Classifying Categories The Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak Theorems for Abelian Categories

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Classifying Categories The Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak Theorems for Abelian Categories"

Transcription

1 U.U.D.M. Project Report 2018:5 Classiying Categories The Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak Theorems or belian Categories Daniel hlsén Examensarbete i matematik, 30 hp Handledare: Volodymyr Mazorchuk Examinator: Denis Gaidashev Juni 2018 Department o Mathematics Uppsala University

2

3 Classiying Categories The Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak theorems or abelian categories Daniel hlsén Uppsala University June 2018 bstract The Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak theorems classiy inite groups, either as direct sums o indecomposables or by composition series. This thesis deines abelian categories and extends the aorementioned theorems to this context. 1

4 Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 Preliminaries Basic Category Theory Subobjects and Quotients belian Categories dditive Categories belian Categories Structure Theory o belian Categories Exact Sequences The Subobject Lattice Classiication Theorems The Jordan-Hölder Theorem The Krull-Schmidt-Remak Theorem

5 1 Introduction Category theory was developed by Eilenberg and Mac Lane in the , as a part o their research into algebraic topology. One o their aims was to give an axiomatic account o relationships between collections o mathematical structures. This led to the deinition o categories, unctors and natural transormations, the concepts that uniy all category theory, Categories soon ound use in module theory, group theory and many other disciplines. Nowadays, categories are used in most o mathematics, and has even been proposed as an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a oundation o mathematics.[law66] Due to their general nature, little can be said o an arbitrary category. Instead, mathematical theory must ocus on a speciic type o category, the choice o which is largely dependent on ones interests. In this work, the categories o choice are abelian categories. These categories were independently developed by Buchsbaum[Buc55] and Grothendieck[Gro57]. Grothendieck s work was especially groundbreaking, as he uniied the cohomology theories or groups and or sheaves, which had similar properies but lacked a ormal connection. This showed that abelian categories was the basis o general ramework or cohomology theories, a powerul incentive or research. belian categories are highly structured, possessing both a matrix calculus and various generalizations o the isomorphism theorems. This gives rise to a reined structure theory, which is the topic o this thesis. O special interest here is the structure o subobjects to an object in an abelian category, since this structure contains a lot o inormation about the objects themselves. The ultimate aim o a structure theory is to provide theorems that classiy some collection o objects up to isomorphism. Here, two results pertaining to such theorems are presented. The irst is the Jordan-Hölder theorem, which classiies objects by maximal chains o subobjects. The second is the Krull-Schmidt-Remak theorem, which gives a classiication o objects by linearly independent components. These theorems do not provide a universal classiication theorem or all abelian categories. The problem with the Jordan-Hölder theorem is that not all objects in an abelian category has a maximal chain o subobjects, while the problem or the Krull- Schmidt-Remak theorem is that is requires that the endomorphisms o certain objects are o a particular orm, which is not true or alla objects in an abelian category. 3

6 Fortunately, one can show that every object that can be classiied using Jordan-Hölder can also be classiied using Krull-Schmidt-Remak. The extent to which Krull-Schmidt- Remak can be extended is not discussed urther. The thesis is divided into our chapters, each divided into two sections. The irst chapter covers the basics o category theory and deines subobjects and quotients in general categories. The aim is to set up the the coming chapters, and ix terminology etc. The second chapter deines additive categories, and gives an account o the matrix calculus it contains. Then, abelian categories are deined and some undamental properties are proven, so as to set up the third chapter, which urther develops the theory. In the third chapter, the ocus is on developing the theory o exact sequences, an important tool in the study o abelian categories, and to urther deepen our understanding the subobject structure o abelian categories. In the ourth and inal chapter, the theory is used to prove the Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak theorems. 4

7 2 Preliminaries Categories is a general ramework or studying mathematical structures and how they relate to one another. 2.1 Basic Category Theory This section covers the basics o category theory, in order to ix terminology and notation. Proos and detailed examples are omitted. The interested reader should consider the introductory chapter in Leinster s book Basic Category Theory[Lei14]. Deinition 2.1. category C consists o a class o objects and a class o morphisms Hom C (,B) or every object and B in C, subject to the ollowing constraints. (i) For each in Hom C (,B) and g in Hom C (B,C) there is a morphism g in Hom C (,C), called the composition o and g. (ii) For all in Hom C (,B), g in Hom C (B,C) and h in Hom C (C,D), we have h (g ) = (h g). In other words, the composition is associative. (iii) For all objects in C, there is an morphism id in Hom C (,), called the identity on, such that id = and id g = g or all morphisms and g. The composition g is written as g most o the time, and one usually writes Hom instead o Hom C. morphism in Hom(,) is called an endomorphism, and the collection o endomorphisms on is denoted End(). Composition turns End() into a monoid, with the identity as unit object. I is a morphism in End(), the morphism n is the endomorphism on deined by By convention, 0 = id.. } {{ } n times 5

8 Deinition 2.2. Let be a morphism in Hom(,B) in some category. Then is called the domain o, while B is called the codomain o, written : B. Example 2.3. (i) Set is the category o all sets and unctions under composition. (ii) Vect K is the category o all vector spaces and linear transormations (over a ield K) under composition. (iii) R-Mod is the category o all R-modules and module morphisms (over a ring R) under composition. (iv) Grp is the category o all groups and group morphisms under composition. The deinition o category does not assume that the collections o objects and morphisms are sets. In some circumstances this can be problematic. For details, consider [ML98] or [Lei14]. From old categories, new ones arise. Deinition 2.4. Let C and D be categories. The product category C D o C and D is the category such that (i) the objects o C D are the pairs (,B) with rom C and B rom D. (ii) the morphisms rom (,B) to (,B ) are pairs o morphisms (,g) rom C and D, with : and g : B B. (iii) the identity morphisms id (,B) are (id,id B ). (iv) the composition o morphisms (,g) and (,g ) is (,g g). Deinition 2.5. Let C be a category. The opposite category C op o C is the category such that (i) the objects o C op are the objects in C. (ii) or every morphism : B, there is a morphism op : B. (iii) the identity morphisms id are id. (iv) the composition o morphisms op : B and g op : B C in C op is the morphism ( g) op : C. The opposite category is also called the dual category. For any property o morphisms and objects in a category, there is a corresponding dual property in the dual category where the morphisms are reversed. So, i a property holds in a category, then the dual property holds in the dual category. Since any category is the dual category o its dual category, this means that i a property holds or all categories, the dual property holds or all categories. In particular, or every theorem, there is a dual theorem that holds in the dual categories (see [ML98, p.33-35] or a more complete discussion o this). 6

9 Some caution is needed. I a property holds or a category, the dual property holds or the dual category. This does not mean that dual property hold or the original category! Since there is no guarantee that categories and dual categories have similar properties, this limits the scope o the duality principle. In an arbitrary category, morphisms are not unctions. Thus, there is no concept o surjective, injective or bijective morphisms. Instead, one uses a dierent terminology. Deinition 2.6. morphism is (i) an epimorphism i g = h implies g = h, or all morphisms g,h. Then is called epic. (ii) a monomorphism i g = h implies g = h, or all morphisms g,h. Then is called monic. (iii) an isomorphism i there is a morphism g such that g = id B and g = id. Then, and B are isomorphic, denoted B. n isomorphism rom an object to itsel is called an automorphism. Note that epimorphisms and monomorphisms are dual concepts: a monomorphism in a category is an epimorphism in the dual category and vice versa. Isomorphisms are dual to themselves: isomorphisms are isomorphisms in the dual category as well. Remark. Not all epimorphisms are surjective, nor are all monomorphisms injective. lso, bijective morphisms and isomorphisms do not coincide in general. See [IB68, p.3-7] and [Lei14, p.12] or details. The ollowing acts will be used liberally throughout the thesis. Proposition 2.7. Let : B and g : B C be morphisms in a category. (i) I and g are epic, so is g. (ii) I g is epic, so is g. (iii) I and g are monic, so is g. (iv) I g is monic, so is. (v) I and g are isomorphisms, so i g. (vi) ll isomorphisms are epic and monic. Remark. The converse o (vi) is not true: there are morphisms that are not isomorphisms, yet still epic and monic.[lei14, p.12] Maps between categories that preserve composition are called unctors. Deinition 2.8. Let C and D be categories. covariant unctor F : C D is an assignment o objects in C to D and morphisms in C to morphisms in D such that 7

10 (i) or all and B in C and : B, we have F( ) : F() F(B). (ii) or all in C, we have F(id ) = id F(). (iii) or all : B and g : B C, we have F(g ) = F(g) F( ). contravariant unctor rom C to D is a covariant unctor rom C op to D. Deinition 2.9. biunctor on a category C is a unctor rom C C to C. Functors are assignments between categories, and can be composed pointwise on objects and morphisms. This composition has an identity and is associative. Hence, the collection o categories and unctors behaves like a category. Functors are maps between categories - natural transormations are maps between unctors. Deinition Let C and D be categories and F and G unctors rom C to D. natural transormation rom F to G assigns a morphism η : F() G() in D or all in C, such a that i is a morphism in C between and B, the diagram F() η G() F( ) G( ) F(B) η B G(B) commutes, i.e η B F( ) = G( )η. I η is an isomorphism or every, then η is a natural isomorphism, denoted F G. Just as with unctors, natural transormations can be composed pointwise. Once again, the composition o two natural transormations is a natural transormation and the composition is associative. Two objects in a category are isomorphic to each other i there are invertible morphisms between them. There is a natural analogue to this condition or categories. Deinition Two categories C and D are isomorphic i there are unctors F : C D and G : D C such that FG = id D and GF = id C. Two categories are isomorphic i and only i they are isomorphic as objects in the category o categories. However, isomorphic categories rarely occur in practice. Instead, a weaker notion is used. Deinition Two categories C and D are equivalent i there are unctors F : C D and G : D C such that FG id D and GF id C. 8

11 Deinition unctor F rom a category C to a category D is aithul i the induced map rom Hom(,B) to Hom(F(),F(B)) deined by mapping to F( ) is injective. ull i the induced map rom Hom(,B) to Hom(F(),F(B)) deined by mapping to F( ) is surjective. dense i all objects in D is isomorphic to F() or some in C. Proposition unctor is an equivalence i and only i it is aithul, ull and dense. 2.2 Subobjects and Quotients This thesis is concerned with classiies objects in a category using subobjects. But how can one speak o subobjects without sets? The idea to deine a subobject o an object as an equivalence class o morphisms. Let Mono() denote the class o monomorphisms with codomain. Mono(), the domain o i is denoted i. I i lies in Deinition Let be an object in a category, and suppose that i and j are morphisms in Mono(). Then i contains j via a morphism, denoted j i, i there is a morphism such that the diagram i i j j commutes, i.e i i = j. I i and j contain each other, they are equivalent, denoted i j. Otherwise, the containment is proper, denoted j < i. Proposition Suppose that i and j are monomorphisms in Mono() and that i contains j via. Then is a monomorphism, and i satisy i = j, then =. Proo. I i = j = i, cancel i on both sides and obtain =. That is monic ollows rom (iv) in Proposition 2.7. Proposition Let be an object in a category and suppose that i and j are morphisms in Mono(). Then i and j are equivalent i and only there is an isomorphism such that i contains j via. 9

12 Proo. I there is such an isomorphism, then i = j and i = j 1, so i and j are equivalent. I i and j are equivalent, there are morphisms 1 and 2 such that i = j 2 and j = i 1. Thus, i = i 1 2 id i = 1 2 j = j 2 1 id i = 2 1, so 1 and 2 are isomorphisms. preorder is a transitive and relexive relation on a class o objects. partial order is preorder which is antisymmetric. ny preorder induces an equivalence relation on its underlying set via x y i and only i x y and y x. The set o equivalence classes o is partially ordered by comparing representatives using. Proposition The relation is a preorder on Mono() or every object Proo. To show that any object is contained in itsel, take to be the identity. For transitivity, suppose that i, j and k in Mono() satisy i j and j k. By assumption, there are morphisms and g be such that k = j and j = ig. Then g satisies ig = j = k, and so i is contained in k. By deinition, is the equivalence relation induced by the preorder. Deinition subobject o an object is an equivalence class o Mono() under the relation. The class o subobjects o an object is denoted S. By previous remarks, S is partially ordered by. The dual to a subobject is a quotient. s with subobjects, quotients are deined as equivalence classes o morphisms. I is an object, let Epi() denote the class o epimorphisms out o. Deinition Let be an object in a category, and suppose that p and q are epimorphisms in Epi(). Then p contains q, denoted q p, i there is a morphism such that the diagram q p commutes, i.e i p = q. I p and q contain each other, they are equivalent, denoted p q, otherwise it is proper, denoted q < p p q 10

13 Quotients are entirely dual to subobjects, so the ollowing proos are omitted. Proposition Suppose that p and q are epimorphisms in Epi() and that i contains j via. Then is an epimorphism, and i satisy p = q, then =. Proposition Let be an object in a category and suppose that p and q are morphisms in Epi(). Then p and q are equivalent i and only there is an isomorphism such that p contains q via. Proposition Let be an object in a category. Then is a preorder on Epi(). Deinition quotient object o an object is an equivalence class o Epi() under the relation. The class o quotients o is denoted Q. Remark. Every object has at least one subobject and quotient, represented by the identity morphism. This subobject is identiied with itsel, so that one may speak o as a subobject and quotient o itsel. s a subobject, it contains every subobject and as a quotient object it is contained in every quotient object. In other words, is a lowest upper bound in S and a greatest lower bound in Q. Example Every subgroup o the abelian group Z is o the orm nz = { 2n, n,0,n,2n, } or some unique natural number n. The inclusions j n : nz Z are deined by j n (x) = x. Each subobject o Z is an equivalence class o monomorphisms into Z. Each class contains precisely one o the morphisms j n. Moreover, j m contains j n i and only i there is a morphism : nz mz so that j m = j n, i.e m (x) = nx or all integers x in Z. This happens only when m divides n, in which case is deined via (x) = (n/m)x. Hence, j n j m m n and S Z is isomorphic as a partial order to Z under the reversed divisibility order. What about quotients? Let p : Z G be a surjective group homomorphism. Then G = im(p) Z/ ker(p). The kernel o p is a subgroup o Z, and so there is a natural number n such that ker(p) nz. Consequently, G is isomorphic to C n = Z/nZ, the cyclic group on n elements. Thus every quotient o Z is represented by a unique epimorphism p n : Z C n, deined by p n (x) = x + nz Suppose that the quotient object p n : Z C n contains another quotient p m : Z C m. Then there is an epimorphism : C n C m, so that p n = p m, i.e (p n (x)) = p m (x) (x + nz) = x + mz. 11

14 This holds i and only i m divides n, and so p m p n m n and Q Z is isomorphic as a partial order to Z under the divisibility order. Notice that S Z and Q Z are order isomorphic up to reversal o the order. This is not coincidental: it is a special case o Proposition

15 3 belian Categories belian categories are additive categories with additional structure. 3.1 dditive Categories dditive categories can be seen as the most general type o category that retains a kind o matrix calculus. Deinition 3.1. n object in a category C is (i) initial i or every object B in C there is exactly one morphism rom to B. (ii) terminal i or every object B in C there is exactly one morphism rom B to. (iii) null i it is both initial and terminal. Proposition 3.2. Initial, terminal and null objects are unique up to a unique isomorpism. Proo. By deinition, the only endomorphism on an initial object is the identity morphism. Let I and J be initial objects. Then, there are unique morphisms : I J and g : J I, and g = id J and g = id I, so I and J are isomorphic. The proos or terminal and null objects are dual. Example 3.3. (i) In Set, the empty set is an initial object and singleton set is a terminal object. There is no null object. (ii) In Grp, the trivial group is a null object. Similarly, the zero module is a null object in R-Mod. Deinition 3.4. Let 0 be a null object in a category and and B be objects in the same category. The null morphism between and B is the unique morphism given by the composition o the morphisms 0 and 0 B. Example 3.5. In Grp, the null morphism between two groups G and H is the morphism rom G to H deined by mapping every element in G to 1 H. 13

16 Deinition 3.6. category is preadditive i it has a null object and every set o morphisms between two objects orm an abelian group, such that composition is biadditive. That is, (g + h) = g + h and ( + g)h = h + gh or all morphisms. In a preadditive category, the set o endomorphisms on an object is a ring, with morphism addition as addition and composition as the ring multiplication. The endomorphism ring is a Z-bimodule, via n times (i n is negative.) n = n = + + n times (i n is positive.) 0 (i n is 0.) Proposition 3.7. In preadditive categories, the ollowing are equivalent or an object : (i) is initial. (ii) is terminal. (iii) id is the additive identity in the endomorphism ring. (iv) The endomorphism ring is trivial. Proo. See [ML98, p.194]. When there is a null object in a category, the null morphism 0 : B and the additive identity in Hom(,B) coincide, since 0 is the composition o the additive identity in Hom(,0) and Hom(0,). Deinition 3.8. direct sum o objects 1,..., n in a preadditive category is an object S along with morphisms k i k S p l l such that and n i k p k = id S. k=1 id p l i k = δ lk = k i l = k 0 otherwise. The morphisms i k are called injection morphisms, while the morphisms p l are called projection morphisms. The objects 1,..., n are called direct summands o S, and the 14

17 collection o objects 1,..., n, S along with the morphisms is called a direct sum system. direct sum is trivial i every summand is isomorphic to either or the zero object, and nontrivial otherwise. Every direct summand is a subobject o the direct sum, and a proper one i and only i the direct sum is nontrivial. Not all subobjects are direct summands. For example, Z cannot be written as a non-trivial direct sum, but has a lot o subobjects. Direct sums are sel-dual, since every direct sum system gives rise to a direct sum system in the dual category, by switching projection and injection morphisms. Proposition 3.9. ny direct sum in a preadditive category is unique up to isomorphism. Proo. Let S and S be direct sums o 1,..., n, and p k, i k, p k and i k the corresponding injection and projection morphisms. Deine rom S to S by and g rom S to S by Then and g = g = n i j p j j=1 n i j p j j=1 k=1 = g = n i k p k k=1 n i k p k. k=1 n n n n i k p k = i j p ji k p k = i k p k = id S n i k p k = k=1 Hence, S and S are isomorphic. j=1 k=1 n j=1 k=1 n i j p j i k p k = k=1 n i k p k = id S. The above proposition allows us talk about the direct sum o 1,..., n, denoted j. Note that the isomorphism between two direct sums is not unique. k=1 Deinition category is additive i it is preadditive and every set o objects has a direct sum. Example I R is a ring, the category R-Mod is additive. The null object is the zero module, and direct sum is cartesian product. Direct sums extends to morphisms. 15

18 Proposition Let 1,..., n and 1,..., n be objects in an additive category with corresponding projection and injection morphisms p k, i k, p k and i k. Suppose j is a morphism rom j to j, or every j = 1,...,n. Then there is a unique morphism, denoted j, rom j to j, such that the diagram j j j p k k k k p k commutes or every k. Proo. Let Then p k j = n i j jp j. j=1 ) n ( j = p k i j jp j = j=1 n p k i j jp j = k p k or all k. To prove uniqueness, suppose that p j g = jp j = p j g or all j. Then or all j. Summing over j gives n n n i j p j g = i j p j j=1 j=1 j=1 i j p j i j p j g = i j p j n g = j=1 j=1 i j p j id S g = id S g =. Remark. There is an dual deinition o j, where one replaces the projection morphisms with the injection morphisms in the opposite direction, resulting in the diagrams j i k j i k j k k k and equations ( j ) ik = k i k. 16

19 The process o constructing morphisms between direct sums rom morphisms between the summands can be inverted. Deinition Suppose 1,..., n and 1,..., m are objects in an additive category, and that is a morphism rom j to k. The component jk o is the morphism rom j to k deined by jk = p k i j. The matrix o is the matrix 11 1m [ ] =..... n1 nm. Example Let be the direct sum o objects 1,..., n in an additive category. Then id p 1 id i 1 p n id i 1 [id ] =..... = 0 id p 1 id i n p n id i n id n Similarly, the matrices o the injection and projection morphisms are [i j ] = [ 0 0 id j 0 0 ] and [p k ] = [ 0 0 id k 0 0 ] T. Matrices o morphisms can be seen as elements o the abelian group n j=1 k=1 m Hom( j, k ) with addition deined componentwise. The identity o this group given by the matrix whose entries are all zero morphism. Proposition Let 1,..., n and 1,..., m be objects in an additive category. Then as abelian groups. Hom ( ) n j, k j=1 k=1 m Hom( j, k ). 17

20 Proo. Deine ϕ : Hom ( ) n j, k j=1 k=1 by mapping the morphism : j k to its matrix 11 1m ϕ( ) = [ ] =..... n1 nm. m Hom( j, k ). I = 0, then jk = 0 or all j and k, and hence ϕ preserves the zero matrix. Moreover, i and g are morphisms rom j to k, then ( + g) jk = p k ( + g)i j = p k i j + p k gi j = jk + g jk, so ϕ is a group morphism. Next, deine the map by ψ : n m j=1 k=1 Hom( j, k ) Hom( ) j, k g 11 g 1m n m ψ..... = i j g jkp k. g n1 g nm, j=1 k=1 Let be a morphism rom j to k. Then 11 1m p 1 i 1 p m i 1 ψ(ϕ( )) = ψ..... = ψ..... n1 nm, p 1 i = n p m i n, n m m n = i j p j i kp k = i j p j i k p k =. j=1 k=1 Similarly, one can show that ψ(ϕ([ jk ])) = [ jk ] or all matrices, which establishes that ϕ is an isomorphism. The above proposition shows that every morphism in an additive can be viewed as a matrix. It turns out that composition can be transered as well. Proposition Let 1,..., n, 1,..., m, and 1,..., p be objects in an additive category, with morphisms : j j=1 k=1 k and g : k l. 18

21 Then, the matrix o the composition is given by the matrix where or all i and j. g : j l h 11 h 1p [g ] =..... h n1 h np h ij = m g ki jk Proo. By deinition, ik = p k i i and g kj = p j gi k. Thus, (g ) ij = p j g i i = ( m m m p j g) i k p k ( i i) = p j gi k p k i i = g kj ik. k=1 k=1 k=1 k=1 Not only is there a matrix calculus in additive categories, the direct sum is also unctorial. Proposition Let j, k and l be three n-tuples o objects in an additive category, and j : j j and j : j j two n-tuples o morphisms. Then ( ) ( ) ( j j = j ) j and j=1 id j = id j. Proo. Straightorward calculation gives ( ) ( ) n n j j = i j j p j i k kp k = and = n j=1 k=1 i j ( j j)p j = id j = n ( j j). n i j p j = id j. j=1 n j=1 k=1 i j j p j i k kp k = 19

22 The above result shows that in an additive category C, are unctors or every n, deined by and n : C n C n ( 1,..., n ) = n ( 1,..., n ) = n i=1 i n i. Since the composition o two unctors is a unctor, iteration yields a myriad o unctors that purports to be the direct sum o n. Even i one restricts onesel to iteration o the biunctor 2, the number o dierent direct sum unctors o n variables is (2n)! (n + 1)!n!, each corresponding to a unique bracketing o n variables. Can any sense be made o this? The answer is yes - one can show that the direct sum is a monoidal product on C. Such categories are subject to a coherence theorem, which essentially states that it does not matter how one places the brackets in a direct sum. detailed treatment o these issues is beyond the scope o this thesis, and the reader is reerred to [ML98, p ]. From now on, all direct sums o the same objects and morphisms are treated as equal, and it is assumed that no problems can arise due to bracketing o direct summands. i=1 3.2 belian Categories Every morphism between two modules can be described uniquely by its kernel and image. It is desirable to ind a similar decomposition or additive categories. For this to work, the concept o kernel and image must be redeined using morphisms. It turns out that, even with a proper account o these concepts, a morphism in additive category does not necessarily have a kernel or an image. dditive categories that do are called abelian categories. Deinition Let C be a category with a null object and null morphism 0. kernel o an morphism : B is a morphism k : K such that k = 0, and or every 20

23 h : C such that hk = 0, there is a unique h : C K such that h = kh. K k=0 h k h B. C h=0 Example Suppose that : B is a morphism o abelian group, and let k : K be the inclusion o the preimage o identity. Clearly, k = 0. I k : K satisies k = 0, then the image o k is contained (as a set) in the image o k. Since inclusions are injective, each g in the image o k has a unique preimage k 1 (g), such that k(k 1 (g)) = g. Deine h : K K by Then i.e kh = k. Thus k is the kernel o. h(x) = k 1 (k (x)). (kh)(x) = k(k 1 (k (x))) = k (x), Deinition Let C be a category with a null object and null morphism 0. cokernel o an morphism : B is an object C and morphism c : C C such that c = 0, and or every h : B D such that ch = 0, there is a unique h : C D such that h = h c. c =0 C B c h h =0 h D Example Let : V W be a linear transormation, and let c : V W / im( ) be deined by c(v) = v + im( ). Then i.e the composition c is 0. c (v) = c( (v)) = (v) + im( ) = im( ) = 0, Moreover, i c rom B to C satisies c = 0, deine h : W / im( ) C by h(v + im( )) = c (v). 21

24 To show that this is well deined, suppose that v and w lie in the same equivalence class o the quotient W / im( ). Then there is some u in V such that (u) = v w, and hence c (v) c (w) = c (v w) = c ( (u)) = 0 since c = 0 by assumption. Clearly c = hc, and so c is the cokernel o. Remark. Kernels and cokernels are duals: the kernel o a morphism is the cokernel o the dual morphism and vice versa. Proposition Kernels are monic and cokernels are epic. Proo. Let k be a kernel o a morphism and suppose that g = kg 1 = kg 2. By deinition g = 0, and the diagram. K k=0 g 2 g 1 k g B C g=0 commutes. The uniqueness condition guarantees that g 1 = g 2 and so k is monic. The proo that cokernels are epic is dual. Proposition Kernels and cokernels are unique up to a unique isomorphism. Proo. Let k and k be kernels o. Then k and k are both 0, and so there are morphisms h and h such that kh = k and k h = k. Consequently, k = kh = k h h and k = k h = khh and since k is monic one can cancel on both sides and ind that h and h are isomorphisms. The proo or cokernels is dual. Since kernels and cokernels are unique, one speaks o the kernel and cokernel o a morphism : B, denoted ker( ) and cok( ) respectively. One way o thinking about the kernel o is as the largest subobject o the domain that is mapped to zero by. Dually, one can think o the cokernel as the smallest quotient that maps to zero. Deinition n additive category is abelian i (i) every morphism in the category has a kernel and cokernel. (ii) every monomorphism is a kernel and every epimorphism is a cokernel. 22

25 Since direct sums are sel-dual, and kernels and monomorphisms are dual to cokernels and epimorphisms, respectively, the dual o an abelian category is also abelian. Hence, every theorem or general abelian categories has a dual theorem, obtained by reversing the morphisms and substituting monic or epic and kernel or cokernel, and vice versa. Proposition Let be a morphism in an abelian category. Then (i) ker( ) = 0 i and only i is monic. (ii) i g is a monomorphism, then ker(g ) = ker( ). (iii) cok( ) = 0 i and only i is epic. (iv) i is epic and g is a morphism, then cok(g ) = cok(g). Proo. (i) Suppose satisy ker( ) = 0 and that two morphisms g and h satisy g = h. Let l = g h. Then l = (g h) = g h = 0. Thus, there is a morphism h such that g h = h 0 = 0. Thus g = h, so is monic. Conversely, suppose that is monic. Let k satisy k = 0 = 0. Since is monic, cancellation yields k = 0, so ker( ) = 0. (ii) Suppose that g is monic. Then g k = 0 g k = g0 k = 0. or all morphisms k, so ker(g ) = ker( ). The proos or (iii) and (iv) are dual. In abelian categories, kernel and cokernels induces maps between the class o subobjects and the class o quotients o an object. Proposition Let be an object in an abelian category. (i) I i and j in Mono() are equivalent, so are cok(i) and cok(j). (ii) I p and q in Epi() are equivalent, so are ker(p) and ker(q). Proo. I i and j are equivalent there is an isomorphism such that i = j, and hence cok(i) = cok(j ) = cok(j) by Proposition 2.7. The second point is done similarly. Deine ker : Q S and cok : S Q, by mapping p and i to ker(p) and cok(i) respectively. 23

26 Proposition The unctions ker and cok are mutually inverse and order reversing. Proo. Let i and j be subobjects o, such that i j via a morphism. Let c 1 be the cokernel o i and c 2 be the cokernel o j. Then c 2 i = c 2 j = 0, so there is a morphism g such that gc 2 = c 1. In other words, cok(j) cok(i). That ker is order reversing is proved similarly. Let i be a monomorphism in Mono(). Then it is the kernel o some map. Let c be the cokernel o i and k the kernel o c. By assumption i = 0, and hence there is a map g such that gc =. lso, ci = 0, so there is a map h 1 such that kh 1 = i. Finally, so there is a map h 2 such that ih 2 = k. k = gck = 0, i c C h 2 h 1 g K Thus i and k are equivalent and represent the same subobject, and thus k B i = k = ker(c) = ker(cok(i)) as subobjects. The other direction is proved is similarly. The above proposition generalize Example the subobject and quotient structure o an objects are mirror images o each other. Proposition morphism in an abelian category is an isomorphism i and only i it is monic and epic. Proo. Let be a morphism that is both monic and epic. Since is monic, the kernel o is zero. Hence, a cokernel o ker( ) is the identity. However, Proposition 3.27 assures us that is a cokernel o ker( ). Hence, there is a morphism g such that g is the identity. The exact same reasoning gives that the kernel o the cokernel o is the identity, and that there exists a morphism h such that h is the identity. So is both right and let invertible, and hence an isomorphism. The other direction is (vi) in Proposition

27 Cokernels can be extended to subobjects. Proposition Let i, i, j and j be monomorphisms, such that i i and j j via isomorphisms ϕ i and ϕ j, respectively. Suppose that the subobject represented by i and i is contained in the subobject represented by j and j via monomorphisms and. Then the codomains o cok( ) and cok( ) are isomorphic. Proo. Consider the diagram i ϕ i i i i j j j ϕ j j. The assumptions that i i and j j imply that ϕ i and ϕ j are isomorphisms and the upper and lower triangle commute. The assumption that i is contained in j means that and are monomorphisms and that the let and right triangle commute. Hence, and i = i ϕ i = j ϕ i i = j = j ϕ j. Equating these expressions and cancelling j yields ϕ i = ϕ j. Let c and c be the cokernels o and respectively. Then and c ϕ j = c ϕ i = 0ϕ i = 0 cϕj 1 = c ϕi 1 = 0ϕi 1 = 0. Hence there are morphisms h and h so that the diagram i j c C ϕ i ϕ j h i j c C h commutes. Thus, h c ϕ j = c h hc = c hcϕj 1 = c hh c = c h h = id C hh = id C. 25

28 Deinition Let i and j be two subobjects with domains i and j, such that i is contained in j via a morphism. The quotient o j by i, denoted j / i, is the codomain o the cokernel o. In abelian categories, all morphisms can be decomposed into monomorphisms and epimorphisms. Proposition Let be a morphism in an abelian category. Then = me or an epimorphism e and monomorphism m. Moreover, m is the kernel o the cokernel o and e is the cokernel o the kernel o. K k e D m B c C Proo. Let be a morphism in an abelian category. Let c be the cokernel o and let m to be the kernel o c. By deinition, c = 0, and since m is the kernel o c there is a morphism e such that = me. By Proposition 3.22, e is epic and m is monic. Moreover, since m is monic. e = cok(ker(e)) = cok(ker(me)) = cok(ker( )) The canonical decomposition transers to morphisms. Proposition Consider the commutative square B g h B in an abelian category, and let = me and = m e be a canonical decomposition. Then there is a unique ϕ such that diagram commutes. g e D m ϕ B e D m B h 26

29 Proo. Let,, g and h be given as above. By Proposition 3.31, there are decompositions = me and = m e. Let u be the kernel o. By deinition h u = 0, and thus m e gu = 0. Since m is monic, e gu = 0, and since e is the cokernel o u, there is a unique morphism ϕ such that e g = ϕe. K u e g D ϕ m B e D m B. h Moreover, and since e is epic, m ϕ = hm. m ϕe = m e g = hme, Proposition The canonical decomposition o a morphism in an abelian category is unique up to a unique isomorphism. Proo. pply Proposition 3.32 to the square to ind the isomorphism ϕ. id e D m ϕ B e D m B Deinition Let be a morphism in an abelian category, and = me its canonical decomposition. The image o, denoted im( ) is the monomorphism m. The coimage o, denoted coim( ), is the epimorphism e. Since the coimage and image o a morphism are unique up to a unique isomorphism, they deine a quotient and a subobject o and B respectively. Deinition span into an object in a category is a pair o morphisms with common codomain. cospan rom an object B is a pair o morphisms with common domain B. id B 27

30 Deinition Let and g be a span into. pullback o and g is a cospan and g such that g = g, with the property that i and g is a cospan such that g = g, then there is a unique morphism h such that = h and g = g h. g D h D Deinition Let h and k be a cospan rom. pushout o h and k is a span h and k such that k h = h k, with the property that i h and k is a span that satisy hk = kh, then there is a unique morphism p such that ph = h and pk = k. h B k D g k B C p g D k C h h Pullbacks and pushout are dual to each other, as are span and cospans. Proposition Pullbacks and pushouts are unique up to a unique isomorphism. Proo. Suppose that there are two pullbacks o the same span. Then there are unique maps h and h such that the diagram P commutes. Hence = hh and g = ghh, and the diagram P h h h h g g P P g g B C B g C g 28

31 commutes. I one replaces h h by id P, the diagram still commutes and thus the uniqueness criterion implies that h h = id P. Similarly, hh = id P, and so h is an isomorphism. Pullbacks and pushouts can be composed. Proposition Suppose that the diagram C g E u B u D g F. u commute. Then (i) i the two inner squares are pullback/pushouts, then so is the outer square. (ii) i the inner let-hand square is a pushout, the outer square is a pushout i and only i the inner right-hand square is a pushout. (iii) i the inner right-hand square is a pullback, the outer square is a pullback i and only i the inner let-hand square is a pullback. Proo. (i) Suppose that the two inner square are pushouts. Suppose that h and h satisies h u = hg. Since the let-hand square is a pushout, there is a unique morphism ϕ so that ϕ = h and ϕu = hg. Since the right-hand square is a pushout as well, there is a unique ψ so that ψg = ϕ and ψu = h. But then ψg = ϕ = h. Since ψ is unique, this mean that the outer square is a pushout. The proo or pullbacks is dual. (ii) Suppose that the inner let-hand and the outer squares are pushouts. Let h and h be such that h u = hg. Then hg = h u = h u and since the outer square is a pushout, there is a unique ϕ so that ϕg = h and ϕu = h. Then ϕg u = h u = hg and ϕu g = hg = ϕg u = h u. 29

32 So there is a pushout C hg u B u D h ϕg ϕg P and uniqueness implies that ϕg = h, so the right-hand square is a pushout. The other implication is proved in (i). (iii) Dual to (ii). Proposition In an abelian category, every span have a pullback and every cospan have a pushout. Proo. Let and g be a span with domains B and C and common codomain. Consider the direct sum system B i p B C and let h = p gq. Let k be the kernel o h. Since k is the kernel o h, 0 = hk = ( p gq)k = pk gqk, i.e pk = gqk. Moreover, i g and are such that g = g, let h = ig j. Then hh = ( p gq)(ig j ) = g g = 0, and since k is the kernel o h there is a unique map h such that kh = ig j. q j C g K h K k p B i B C h j C q g This yields pkh = g and qkh = g, which shows that pk and qk is the pullback o and g. 30

33 For the pushout, suppose that and g has common domain and codomains B and C respectively. Let h = i jg and c be the cokernel o h. One can show, using a similar argument as above, that ci and cj is the pushout o and g. 31

34 4 Structure Theory o belian Categories The topic o chapter is the structure theory o abelian categories, a preparation or the proos o the Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak theorems. 4.1 Exact Sequences Exact sequences are the bread and butter o abelian categories. Deinition 4.1. sequence o morphisms 2 d 2 1 d 1 0 d 0 1 d 1 in an abelian category is exact at n i im(d n ) = ker(d n 1 ). sequence is exact i it is exact at every object in the sequence. Many properties o morphisms are characterized via exact sequences. Proposition 4.2. Let 0 B g C 0 be a sequence o morphisms. Then (i) 0 B is exact i and only i is monic. (ii) 0 B C is exact i and only i is the kernel o g. (iii) B 0 is exact i and only i is epic. (iv) B C 0 is exact i and only i g is the cokernel o. (v) 0 B 0 is exact i and only i is an isomorphism. (vi) 0 B C 0 is exact i and only i is the kernel o g and g is the cokernel o. 32

35 Observe that i a sequence o morphisms is exact, the dual o that sequence is also exact. Deinition 4.3. n exact sequence o the orm 0 0 B g C 0 0 is called a short exact sequence. The simplest examples o short exact sequences are o the orm 0 i B p B 0 where p and i are the projection and injection maps. They are characterized thus. Proposition 4.4 (Splitting lemma). For all exact sequences 0 B g C 0 the ollowing statements are equivalent. (i) The middle object B is a direct sum o and C, such that is an injection morphism and g a projection morphism. (ii) There is a morphism l (called a let split) rom B to such that l = id. (iii) There is a morphism r (called a right split) rom C to B such that gr = id C Proo. (i) In a direct sum system, injection morphisms and projection morphism is are right/let splits respectively. (ii) Suppose that an exact sequence 0 B g C 0 has a right split r such that gr = id C. Let p = id B rg. By deinition, gp = g grg = g g = 0. Since is the kernel o g, there is a morphism l, such that l = p, i.e l = id B rg. Thus l +rg = id B. Since gr = id C by assumption, it suices to prove that l = id and lr = 0 to show that B is the direct sum o and C. Yet and since is monic, l = id. lso, l = (id B rg) = rg = 0 =, lr = (id B rg)r = r rgr = r r = 0, and since is monic lr = 0. This shows that l, r, and g orm a direct sum system or C. 33

36 (iii) Dual to (ii). Remark. The splitting lemma implies that i g is such that h = g is an automorphism, then is a direct summand o. For i c is the cokernel o, the sequence 0 c B 0 is exact, and h 1 g, is a let split o, i.e B. Pullbacks and pushouts in abelian categories can be described in terms o exact sequences. Proposition 4.5. Consider the diagram C g B g D. and the direct sum system B i p B C q j C. Let t = j + ig and s = p gq. Then (i) the square commutes i and only i st = 0. (ii) the square is a pullback i and only i 0 t B C s D is exact, i.e t is the kernel o s. (iii) the square is a pushout i and only i t B C s D 0 is exact, i.e s is the cokernel o t. Proo. Note that pt = g and qt =, and si = and sj = g. 34

37 (i) The square is commutative i and only i 0 = g g = sipt + sjqt = s(ip + jq)t = st. (ii) ssume that the square is a pullback. Suppose that k is such that sk = 0. Then 0 = sk = s(ip + jq)k = sipk + sjqk = pk gqk, i.e pk = gqk. Since the square is a pullback, there is a unique morphism h such that h = qk and g h = pk. Hence qth = qk and pth = pk, and so th = (jq + ip)th = jqth + ipth = jqk + ipk = (jq + ip)k = k. This shows that t is a kernel o s, so the sequence is exact. Conversely, suppose that t is the kernel o s and that there are morphism and g such that g = g. Deine r = ig + j. Then pr = g, qr =, and sr = ( p gq)(ig + j ) = pig gqj = g g = 0. Since t is the kernel o s, there is a unique m : U such that tm = r, so ptm = pr and qtm = qr, i.e g m = g and m =. This shows that the square is a pullback. (iii) Dual to the proo above. Proposition 4.6. Consider the pullback P g B C. g in an abelian category. I is monic, so is, and i is epic, so is. Proo. Suppose that is monic. Let h and h be morphisms rom P to P, such that h = h. Then g h = g h, and since the diagram commutes g h = g h. Since is monic, g h = g h. Since the diagram is a pullback, the uniqueness property guarantees that h = h. Suppose that is epic and consider the direct sum system B i p B C q j C. 35

38 In the proo o Proposition 3.40, it was shown that i k is the kernel o h = p gq, then = qk and g = pk. Suppose that uh = 0 or some morphism u. Then 0 = uh = uhi = u( p gq)i = u pi = u and since is epic, u = 0. Thus, h is epic as well. Thus, the sequence 0 P k B C h 0 is exact, i.e h is the cokernel o k. Suppose that u = 0 or some morphism u. Then 0 = u = uqk and hence there is morphism u such that uq = u h. Thus Since is epic, u is 0, and 0 = uqi = u hi = u ( p gq)i = u pi = u. uq = u h = 0. Since q is epic u = 0, which shows that is epic. The nine lemma is a generalization o the isomorphism theorems. The ollowing proo is due to Popescu [Pop73] and [Fre64]. Proposition 4.7. Consider the commutative diagram g C h 0 B g D h E such that the bottom row is exact. The square is a pullback i and only i the sequence is exact, i.e g is the kernel o h. 0 g C h E Proo. Suppose that the square is a pullback. Since the diagram is commutative and the bottom row is exact, h g = hg = 0. Let s be a morphism such that h s = 0. Since the bottom row is exact, g is the kernel o h. Since h s = 0 by assumption, there is a unique morphism t so that s = g t. 36

39 Moreover, since the square is a pullback, there is a unique r so that gr = s. Thus, g is the kernel o h. Conversely, suppose that g is the kernel o h. Let s and t be morphisms such that s = g t. Since the diagram is commutative, h s = hg t = 0, and since g is the kernel o h, there is a unique morphism r so that s = gr. U s t r g C 0 B g h D h E The diagram is commutative, so g r = gr = s = g t and since g is monic, cancellation yields t = r. This shows that the square is a pullback. Proposition 4.8. Consider the commutative diagram g C p E 0 0 B g D p s F 0 such that the right square is a pullback and the rows are exact. Then s is monic. I is epic then s is an isomorphism. Proo. Let r be such that sr = 0. Let u and v be the pullback o p and r. Since the right square is a pullback and the bottom row is exact, Proposition 4.7 implies that g is the kernel o p. Moreover, p v = spv = sru = 0. 37

40 Hence, there is a map t so that gt = v. U u K t g C v p E r 0 0 B g D p s F 0 Thus, ru = pv = pgt = 0 since p is the cokernel o g. Moreover, the morphism p is epic, and thus u is epic, so r = 0, which show that s is monic. I is epic, the composition p = sp is epic, and so s is epic. Since s is always monic, s is an isomorphism. Proposition 4.9. Consider the commutative diagram h D k G 0 B h E k H g g 0 C h F 0 with exact columns and exact middle row. Then the upper row is exact i and only i the bottom row is exact (i.e h is monic). Proo. Suppose that the upper row is exact. The right column is exact, the diagram commutes and is monic, so h = ker(k) = ker( k) = ker( k ). 38

41 Hence, Proposition 4.7 implies that the square h D B h E is a pullback. Thus, the diagram 0 B g C 0 h 0 D E h g F h has exact rows, with the right square being a pullback diagram. Thus h is monic and the bottom row is exact. Conversely, suppose that the bottom row is exact, i.e h is monic. Then, so the sequence = ker(g) = ker(h g) = ker(g h ), 0 B g h F is exact. Thus, the top right square is a pullback. Let r be a morphism such that kr = 0. Then k r = kr = 0, and since the middle row is exact, h is the kernel o k, and and there is a unique morphism t such that h t = t. Since the top right square is a pullback, there is a unique morphism s so that hs = r, which show that h is the kernel o k and the top row is exact. 39

42 Proposition 4.10 (Nine lemma). Consider the commutative diagram D 0 B E 0 C F G H I with exact columns and exact middle row. Then the top row is exact i and only i the bottom row is exact. Proo. Direct application o Proposition 4.9 and its dual yields the conclusion. The strength o the nine lemma is evident in ease o which it proves the second isomorphism theorem. Proposition 4.11 (Second isomorphism theorem). Suppose that i and j represent subobjects o, so that i contains j via a morphism : j i. Then exists there a commutative diagram 0 i i c / i 0 u 0 i / j k u / j p u (/ j )/( i / j ) 0 such that the rows are exact, u is an isomorphism, and u and u are the cokernels o and j respectively. Moreover, the morphisms k and p are unique with this property. Proo. Let u = cok( ), u = cok(j) and c = cok(i). By assumption, j = i. Hence u i = uj = 0, and since u is the cokernel o, there is a unique morphism k so that u i = ku. Let p be the cokernel o k. Then u i = ku implies that pu i = pku = 0, 40

43 and hence there is a unique morphism u that satisies u p = pu. Thus, the diagram j i u i / j 0 id 0 j j i k u / j / i c u (/ j )/( i / j ) p is commutative. By assumption, the columns and the middle and upper rows are exact. Hence the lowest is exact as well, and u is an isomorphism. 4.2 The Subobject Lattice Subobjects and quotients were deined or general categories in Section 2.2. It is time to return to topic in the case o abelian categories. But irst, some order theory is required. Until urther notice, reers to an arbitrary partial order on some underlying set. Deinition Let x and y be objects in a partial order. greatest lower bound o x and y is an element z such that z x and z y, with the property that i w satisy w x and w y, then w z. Dually, a lowest upper bound o x and y is an element z so that x z and y z, with the property that i w satisy x w and y w, then z w. Deinition lattice is a partial order in which every pair o elements have a greatest lower bound and lowest upper bound. The greatest lower bound and lowest upper bound o two elements x and y are unique i they exist, and are denoted x y and x y, respectively. The symbols and are known as meet and join, respectively. Example The power set o a set is a lattice, where the meet is intersection and the join is union. 41

44 Lattices have been studied extensively by Birkho in [Bir67]. In the introduction, proos can be ound o the ollowing three propositions. Proposition In any lattice, the meet and join satisies (i) x x = x and x x = x. (ii) x y = y x and x y = y x. (iii) x (y z) = (x y) z and x (y z) = (x y) z. (iv) x (x y) = x (x y) = x or all lattice elements x,y and z. Moreover, x y is equivalent to each o the conditions x y = x and x y = y. Proposition For all elements x,y and z in a lattice, i y z, then x y x z and x y x z. Proposition 4.17 (Modular inequality). For all elements x,y and z in a lattice, i x z, then x (y z) (x y) z. Remark. In a lattice, the meet and the join can be seen as binary operations. Indeed, lattices can be characterized as a set with two binary operations that satisy (i)-(iv) o Proposition 4.15.[Bir67, p.10] Deinition lattice is modular i x z implies that or all lattice elements x, y and z. x (y z) = (x y) z. The term modular lattice comes rom module theory: the set o submodules o a module is a modular lattice. Deinition n element in a lattice is called a top i x or every element x in the lattice. n element is a bot i x or every x in the lattice. lattice with a top and bot is called bounded. Example The lattice o subsets o a set S has both a top and bot, given by = S and =. The top and bot are unique i they exist. Every element x in such lattices satisy x = x, x =, x = x and x =. Deinition complement o an element x in a bounded lattice is an element c such that x c = and x c =. 42

1 Categories, Functors, and Natural Transformations. Discrete categories. A category is discrete when every arrow is an identity.

1 Categories, Functors, and Natural Transformations. Discrete categories. A category is discrete when every arrow is an identity. MacLane: Categories or Working Mathematician 1 Categories, Functors, and Natural Transormations 1.1 Axioms or Categories 1.2 Categories Discrete categories. A category is discrete when every arrow is an

More information

University of Cape Town

University of Cape Town The copyright o this thesis rests with the. No quotation rom it or inormation derived rom it is to be published without ull acknowledgement o the source. The thesis is to be used or private study or non-commercial

More information

HSP SUBCATEGORIES OF EILENBERG-MOORE ALGEBRAS

HSP SUBCATEGORIES OF EILENBERG-MOORE ALGEBRAS HSP SUBCATEGORIES OF EILENBERG-MOORE ALGEBRAS MICHAEL BARR Abstract. Given a triple T on a complete category C and a actorization system E /M on the category o algebras, we show there is a 1-1 correspondence

More information

GENERAL ABSTRACT NONSENSE

GENERAL ABSTRACT NONSENSE GENERAL ABSTRACT NONSENSE MARCELLO DELGADO Abstract. In this paper, we seek to understand limits, a uniying notion that brings together the ideas o pullbacks, products, and equalizers. To do this, we will

More information

Joseph Muscat Categories. 1 December 2012

Joseph Muscat Categories. 1 December 2012 Joseph Muscat 2015 1 Categories joseph.muscat@um.edu.mt 1 December 2012 1 Objects and Morphisms category is a class o objects with morphisms : (a way o comparing/substituting/mapping/processing to ) such

More information

Descent on the étale site Wouter Zomervrucht, October 14, 2014

Descent on the étale site Wouter Zomervrucht, October 14, 2014 Descent on the étale site Wouter Zomervrucht, October 14, 2014 We treat two eatures o the étale site: descent o morphisms and descent o quasi-coherent sheaves. All will also be true on the larger pp and

More information

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths.

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths. CATEGORY THEORY PROFESSOR PETER JOHNSTONE Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths. Definition 1.1. A category C consists

More information

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/monomorphism 1 of 3 24/11/2012 02:01 Monomorphism From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In the context of abstract algebra or

More information

THE SNAIL LEMMA ENRICO M. VITALE

THE SNAIL LEMMA ENRICO M. VITALE THE SNIL LEMM ENRICO M. VITLE STRCT. The classical snake lemma produces a six terms exact sequence starting rom a commutative square with one o the edge being a regular epimorphism. We establish a new

More information

LIMITS AND COLIMITS. m : M X. in a category G of structured sets of some sort call them gadgets the image subset

LIMITS AND COLIMITS. m : M X. in a category G of structured sets of some sort call them gadgets the image subset 5 LIMITS ND COLIMITS In this chapter we irst briely discuss some topics namely subobjects and pullbacks relating to the deinitions that we already have. This is partly in order to see how these are used,

More information

Category Theory. Course by Dr. Arthur Hughes, Typset by Cathal Ormond

Category Theory. Course by Dr. Arthur Hughes, Typset by Cathal Ormond Category Theory Course by Dr. Arthur Hughes, 2010 Typset by Cathal Ormond Contents 1 Types, Composition and Identities 3 1.1 Programs..................................... 3 1.2 Functional Laws.................................

More information

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA These are notes for our first unit on the algebraic side of homological algebra. While this is the last topic (Chap XX) in the book, it makes sense to

More information

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS BRIAN OSSERMAN Last quarter, we introduced the closed diagonal condition or a prevariety to be a prevariety, and the universally closed condition or a variety to be complete.

More information

Category Theory. Categories. Definition.

Category Theory. Categories. Definition. Category Theory Category theory is a general mathematical theory of structures, systems of structures and relationships between systems of structures. It provides a unifying and economic mathematical modeling

More information

GENERALIZED ABSTRACT NONSENSE: CATEGORY THEORY AND ADJUNCTIONS

GENERALIZED ABSTRACT NONSENSE: CATEGORY THEORY AND ADJUNCTIONS GENERALIZED ABSTRACT NONSENSE: CATEGORY THEORY AND ADJUNCTIONS CHRIS HENDERSON Abstract. This paper will move through the basics o category theory, eventually deining natural transormations and adjunctions

More information

The Clifford algebra and the Chevalley map - a computational approach (detailed version 1 ) Darij Grinberg Version 0.6 (3 June 2016). Not proofread!

The Clifford algebra and the Chevalley map - a computational approach (detailed version 1 ) Darij Grinberg Version 0.6 (3 June 2016). Not proofread! The Cliord algebra and the Chevalley map - a computational approach detailed version 1 Darij Grinberg Version 0.6 3 June 2016. Not prooread! 1. Introduction: the Cliord algebra The theory o the Cliord

More information

Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013)

Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013) Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013) Navid Alaei September 17, 2013 1 Lattice Basics There are, in general, two equivalent approaches to defining a lattice; one is rather

More information

Math 248B. Base change morphisms

Math 248B. Base change morphisms Math 248B. Base change morphisms 1. Motivation A basic operation with shea cohomology is pullback. For a continuous map o topological spaces : X X and an abelian shea F on X with (topological) pullback

More information

Math 216A. A gluing construction of Proj(S)

Math 216A. A gluing construction of Proj(S) Math 216A. A gluing construction o Proj(S) 1. Some basic deinitions Let S = n 0 S n be an N-graded ring (we ollows French terminology here, even though outside o France it is commonly accepted that N does

More information

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal semigroup rings and formal power series rings We next want to explore the notion of a (formal) power series ring in finitely

More information

Categories and Natural Transformations

Categories and Natural Transformations Categories and Natural Transormations Ethan Jerzak 17 August 2007 1 Introduction The motivation or studying Category Theory is to ormalise the underlying similarities between a broad range o mathematical

More information

Tangent Categories. David M. Roberts, Urs Schreiber and Todd Trimble. September 5, 2007

Tangent Categories. David M. Roberts, Urs Schreiber and Todd Trimble. September 5, 2007 Tangent Categories David M Roberts, Urs Schreiber and Todd Trimble September 5, 2007 Abstract For any n-category C we consider the sub-n-category T C C 2 o squares in C with pinned let boundary This resolves

More information

12. Projective modules The blanket assumptions about the base ring k, the k-algebra A, and A-modules enumerated at the start of 11 continue to hold.

12. Projective modules The blanket assumptions about the base ring k, the k-algebra A, and A-modules enumerated at the start of 11 continue to hold. 12. Projective modules The blanket assumptions about the base ring k, the k-algebra A, and A-modules enumerated at the start of 11 continue to hold. 12.1. Indecomposability of M and the localness of End

More information

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS BRIAN OSSERMAN The notions o separatedness and properness are the algebraic geometry analogues o the Hausdor condition and compactness in topology. For varieties over the

More information

Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009

Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009 MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 18.726 Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. 18.726: Algebraic Geometry

More information

Exercises on chapter 0

Exercises on chapter 0 Exercises on chapter 0 1. A partially ordered set (poset) is a set X together with a relation such that (a) x x for all x X; (b) x y and y x implies that x = y for all x, y X; (c) x y and y z implies that

More information

BASIC GROUP THEORY : G G G,

BASIC GROUP THEORY : G G G, BASIC GROUP THEORY 18.904 1. Definitions Definition 1.1. A group (G, ) is a set G with a binary operation : G G G, and a unit e G, possessing the following properties. (1) Unital: for g G, we have g e

More information

A Krull-Schmidt Theorem for Noetherian Modules *

A Krull-Schmidt Theorem for Noetherian Modules * A Krull-Schmidt Theorem for Noetherian Modules * Gary Brookfield Department of Mathematics, University of California, Riverside CA 92521-0135 E-mail: brookfield@math.ucr.edu We prove a version of the Krull-Schmidt

More information

School of Mathematics and Statistics. MT5824 Topics in Groups. Problem Sheet I: Revision and Re-Activation

School of Mathematics and Statistics. MT5824 Topics in Groups. Problem Sheet I: Revision and Re-Activation MRQ 2009 School of Mathematics and Statistics MT5824 Topics in Groups Problem Sheet I: Revision and Re-Activation 1. Let H and K be subgroups of a group G. Define HK = {hk h H, k K }. (a) Show that HK

More information

THE HOMOTOPY THEORY OF EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS

THE HOMOTOPY THEORY OF EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS THE HOMOTOPY THEORY OF EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS FINNUR LÁRUSSON Abstract. We give a detailed exposition o the homotopy theory o equivalence relations, perhaps the simplest nontrivial example o a model structure.

More information

UMS 7/2/14. Nawaz John Sultani. July 12, Abstract

UMS 7/2/14. Nawaz John Sultani. July 12, Abstract UMS 7/2/14 Nawaz John Sultani July 12, 2014 Notes or July, 2 2014 UMS lecture Abstract 1 Quick Review o Universals Deinition 1.1. I S : D C is a unctor and c an object o C, a universal arrow rom c to S

More information

CATEGORIES. 1.1 Introduction

CATEGORIES. 1.1 Introduction 1 CATEGORIES 1.1 Introduction What is category theory? As a irst approximation, one could say that category theory is the mathematical study o (abstract) algebras o unctions. Just as group theory is the

More information

0 Sets and Induction. Sets

0 Sets and Induction. Sets 0 Sets and Induction Sets A set is an unordered collection of objects, called elements or members of the set. A set is said to contain its elements. We write a A to denote that a is an element of the set

More information

EXTENSIONS OF GR O U P S AND M O D U L E S

EXTENSIONS OF GR O U P S AND M O D U L E S M A T -3 9 M A S T E R S T H E S I S I N M A T H E M A T I C S EXTENSIONS OF GR O U P S AND M O D U L E S CatalinaNicole Vintilescu Nermo May, 21 FACULTY OF SCIENCE AND T ECH N OL O G Y Department of Mathematics

More information

1.1 Definition. A monoid is a set M together with a map. 1.3 Definition. A monoid is commutative if x y = y x for all x, y M.

1.1 Definition. A monoid is a set M together with a map. 1.3 Definition. A monoid is commutative if x y = y x for all x, y M. 1 Monoids and groups 1.1 Definition. A monoid is a set M together with a map M M M, (x, y) x y such that (i) (x y) z = x (y z) x, y, z M (associativity); (ii) e M such that x e = e x = x for all x M (e

More information

A TALE OF TWO FUNCTORS. Marc Culler. 1. Hom and Tensor

A TALE OF TWO FUNCTORS. Marc Culler. 1. Hom and Tensor A TALE OF TWO FUNCTORS Marc Culler 1. Hom and Tensor It was the best of times, it was the worst of times, it was the age of covariance, it was the age of contravariance, it was the epoch of homology, it

More information

A COURSE IN HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA CHAPTER 11: Auslander s Proof of Roiter s Theorem E. L. Lady (April 29, 1998)

A COURSE IN HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA CHAPTER 11: Auslander s Proof of Roiter s Theorem E. L. Lady (April 29, 1998) A COURSE IN HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA CHAPTER 11: Auslander s Proof of Roiter s Theorem E. L. Lady (April 29, 1998) A category C is skeletally small if there exists a set of objects in C such that every object

More information

Math 754 Chapter III: Fiber bundles. Classifying spaces. Applications

Math 754 Chapter III: Fiber bundles. Classifying spaces. Applications Math 754 Chapter III: Fiber bundles. Classiying spaces. Applications Laurențiu Maxim Department o Mathematics University o Wisconsin maxim@math.wisc.edu April 18, 2018 Contents 1 Fiber bundles 2 2 Principle

More information

TCC Homological Algebra: Assignment #3 (Solutions)

TCC Homological Algebra: Assignment #3 (Solutions) TCC Homological Algebra: Assignment #3 (Solutions) David Loeffler, d.a.loeffler@warwick.ac.uk 30th November 2016 This is the third of 4 problem sheets. Solutions should be submitted to me (via any appropriate

More information

Introduction to modules

Introduction to modules Chapter 3 Introduction to modules 3.1 Modules, submodules and homomorphisms The problem of classifying all rings is much too general to ever hope for an answer. But one of the most important tools available

More information

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS JEROEN SIJSLING

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS JEROEN SIJSLING ALGEBRAIC GROUPS JEROEN SIJSLING The goal of these notes is to introduce and motivate some notions from the theory of group schemes. For the sake of simplicity, we restrict to algebraic groups (as defined

More information

Span, Cospan, and Other Double Categories

Span, Cospan, and Other Double Categories ariv:1201.3789v1 [math.ct] 18 Jan 2012 Span, Cospan, and Other Double Categories Susan Nieield July 19, 2018 Abstract Given a double category D such that D 0 has pushouts, we characterize oplax/lax adjunctions

More information

Review of category theory

Review of category theory Review of category theory Proseminar on stable homotopy theory, University of Pittsburgh Friday 17 th January 2014 Friday 24 th January 2014 Clive Newstead Abstract This talk will be a review of the fundamentals

More information

REPRESENTATION THEORY WEEK 9

REPRESENTATION THEORY WEEK 9 REPRESENTATION THEORY WEEK 9 1. Jordan-Hölder theorem and indecomposable modules Let M be a module satisfying ascending and descending chain conditions (ACC and DCC). In other words every increasing sequence

More information

Abstract Algebra II Groups ( )

Abstract Algebra II Groups ( ) Abstract Algebra II Groups ( ) Melchior Grützmann / melchiorgfreehostingcom/algebra October 15, 2012 Outline Group homomorphisms Free groups, free products, and presentations Free products ( ) Definition

More information

CATEGORICAL GROTHENDIECK RINGS AND PICARD GROUPS. Contents. 1. The ring K(R) and the group Pic(R)

CATEGORICAL GROTHENDIECK RINGS AND PICARD GROUPS. Contents. 1. The ring K(R) and the group Pic(R) CATEGORICAL GROTHENDIECK RINGS AND PICARD GROUPS J. P. MAY Contents 1. The ring K(R) and the group Pic(R) 1 2. Symmetric monoidal categories, K(C), and Pic(C) 2 3. The unit endomorphism ring R(C ) 5 4.

More information

Direct Limits. Mathematics 683, Fall 2013

Direct Limits. Mathematics 683, Fall 2013 Direct Limits Mathematics 683, Fall 2013 In this note we define direct limits and prove their basic properties. This notion is important in various places in algebra. In particular, in algebraic geometry

More information

A GLIMPSE OF ALGEBRAIC K-THEORY: Eric M. Friedlander

A GLIMPSE OF ALGEBRAIC K-THEORY: Eric M. Friedlander A GLIMPSE OF ALGEBRAIC K-THEORY: Eric M. Friedlander During the first three days of September, 1997, I had the privilege of giving a series of five lectures at the beginning of the School on Algebraic

More information

ELEMENTS IN MATHEMATICS FOR INFORMATION SCIENCE NO.14 CATEGORY THEORY. Tatsuya Hagino

ELEMENTS IN MATHEMATICS FOR INFORMATION SCIENCE NO.14 CATEGORY THEORY. Tatsuya Hagino 1 ELEMENTS IN MTHEMTICS FOR INFORMTION SCIENCE NO.14 CTEGORY THEORY Tatsuya Haino haino@sc.keio.ac.jp 2 Set Theory Set Theory Foundation o Modern Mathematics a set a collection o elements with some property

More information

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS.

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS. FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS. Let A be a ring, for simplicity assumed commutative. A filtering, or filtration, of an A module M means a descending sequence of submodules M = M 0

More information

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA 23

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA 23 MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA 23 6.4. Homotopy uniqueness of projective resolutions. Here I proved that the projective resolution of any R-module (or any object of an abelian category

More information

NOTES ON SPLITTING FIELDS

NOTES ON SPLITTING FIELDS NOTES ON SPLITTING FIELDS CİHAN BAHRAN I will try to define the notion of a splitting field of an algebra over a field using my words, to understand it better. The sources I use are Peter Webb s and T.Y

More information

3 3 Lemma and Protomodularity

3 3 Lemma and Protomodularity Ž. Journal o Algebra 236, 778795 2001 doi:10.1006jabr.2000.8526, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on 3 3 Lemma and Protomodularity Dominique Bourn Uniersite du Littoral, 220 a. de l Uniersite,

More information

1 Fields and vector spaces

1 Fields and vector spaces 1 Fields and vector spaces In this section we revise some algebraic preliminaries and establish notation. 1.1 Division rings and fields A division ring, or skew field, is a structure F with two binary

More information

Solutions to some of the exercises from Tennison s Sheaf Theory

Solutions to some of the exercises from Tennison s Sheaf Theory Solutions to some of the exercises from Tennison s Sheaf Theory Pieter Belmans June 19, 2011 Contents 1 Exercises at the end of Chapter 1 1 2 Exercises in Chapter 2 6 3 Exercises at the end of Chapter

More information

Category Theory. Travis Dirle. December 12, 2017

Category Theory. Travis Dirle. December 12, 2017 Category Theory 2 Category Theory Travis Dirle December 12, 2017 2 Contents 1 Categories 1 2 Construction on Categories 7 3 Universals and Limits 11 4 Adjoints 23 5 Limits 31 6 Generators and Projectives

More information

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories PART I Abstract algebraic categories It should be observed first that the whole concept of category is essentially an auxiliary one; our basic concepts are those of a functor and a natural transformation.

More information

CONTINUITY. 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits. Suppose that F : J C and R: C D are functors. Consider the limit diagrams.

CONTINUITY. 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits. Suppose that F : J C and R: C D are functors. Consider the limit diagrams. CONTINUITY Abstract. Continuity, tensor products, complete lattices, the Tarski Fixed Point Theorem, existence of adjoints, Freyd s Adjoint Functor Theorem 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits.

More information

GALOIS CATEGORIES MELISSA LYNN

GALOIS CATEGORIES MELISSA LYNN GALOIS CATEGORIES MELISSA LYNN Abstract. In abstract algebra, we considered finite Galois extensions of fields with their Galois groups. Here, we noticed a correspondence between the intermediate fields

More information

Categories and functors

Categories and functors Lecture 1 Categories and functors Definition 1.1 A category A consists of a collection ob(a) (whose elements are called the objects of A) for each A, B ob(a), a collection A(A, B) (whose elements are called

More information

Thus we get. ρj. Nρj i = δ D(i),j.

Thus we get. ρj. Nρj i = δ D(i),j. 1.51. The distinguished invertible object. Let C be a finite tensor category with classes of simple objects labeled by a set I. Since duals to projective objects are projective, we can define a map D :

More information

Properties of Triangular Matrix and Gorenstein Differential Graded Algebras

Properties of Triangular Matrix and Gorenstein Differential Graded Algebras Properties of Triangular Matrix and Gorenstein Differential Graded Algebras Daniel Maycock Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy chool of Mathematics & tatistics Newcastle University

More information

Exercises on chapter 1

Exercises on chapter 1 Exercises on chapter 1 1. Let G be a group and H and K be subgroups. Let HK = {hk h H, k K}. (i) Prove that HK is a subgroup of G if and only if HK = KH. (ii) If either H or K is a normal subgroup of G

More information

The basics of frame theory

The basics of frame theory First version released on 30 June 2006 This version released on 30 June 2006 The basics o rame theory Harold Simmons The University o Manchester hsimmons@ manchester.ac.uk This is the irst part o a series

More information

Symbol Index Group GermAnal Ring AbMonoid

Symbol Index Group GermAnal Ring AbMonoid Symbol Index 409 Symbol Index Symbols of standard and uncontroversial usage are generally not included here. As in the word index, boldface page-numbers indicate pages where definitions are given. If a

More information

Variations on a Casselman-Osborne theme

Variations on a Casselman-Osborne theme Variations on a Casselman-Osborne theme Dragan Miličić Introduction This paper is inspired by two classical results in homological algebra o modules over an enveloping algebra lemmas o Casselman-Osborne

More information

Graduate Preliminary Examination

Graduate Preliminary Examination Graduate Preliminary Examination Algebra II 18.2.2005: 3 hours Problem 1. Prove or give a counter-example to the following statement: If M/L and L/K are algebraic extensions of fields, then M/K is algebraic.

More information

Lie Algebra Cohomology

Lie Algebra Cohomology Lie Algebra Cohomology Carsten Liese 1 Chain Complexes Definition 1.1. A chain complex (C, d) of R-modules is a family {C n } n Z of R-modules, together with R-modul maps d n : C n C n 1 such that d d

More information

MATH 101A: ALGEBRA I PART C: TENSOR PRODUCT AND MULTILINEAR ALGEBRA. This is the title page for the notes on tensor products and multilinear algebra.

MATH 101A: ALGEBRA I PART C: TENSOR PRODUCT AND MULTILINEAR ALGEBRA. This is the title page for the notes on tensor products and multilinear algebra. MATH 101A: ALGEBRA I PART C: TENSOR PRODUCT AND MULTILINEAR ALGEBRA This is the title page for the notes on tensor products and multilinear algebra. Contents 1. Bilinear forms and quadratic forms 1 1.1.

More information

Derived Categories. Mistuo Hoshino

Derived Categories. Mistuo Hoshino Derived Categories Mistuo Hoshino Contents 01. Cochain complexes 02. Mapping cones 03. Homotopy categories 04. Quasi-isomorphisms 05. Mapping cylinders 06. Triangulated categories 07. Épaisse subcategories

More information

VALUATIVE CRITERIA FOR SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS

VALUATIVE CRITERIA FOR SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS VALUATIVE CRITERIA FOR SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS BRIAN OSSERMAN Recall that or prevarieties, we had criteria or being a variety or or being complete in terms o existence and uniqueness o limits, where

More information

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS J. WARNER

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS J. WARNER ALGEBRAIC GROUPS J. WARNER Let k be an algebraically closed field. varieties unless otherwise stated. 1. Definitions and Examples For simplicity we will work strictly with affine Definition 1.1. An algebraic

More information

Projective modules: Wedderburn rings

Projective modules: Wedderburn rings Projective modules: Wedderburn rings April 10, 2008 8 Wedderburn rings A Wedderburn ring is an artinian ring which has no nonzero nilpotent left ideals. Note that if R has no left ideals I such that I

More information

An Introduction to Topos Theory

An Introduction to Topos Theory An Introduction to Topos Theory Ryszard Paweł Kostecki Institute o Theoretical Physics, University o Warsaw, Hoża 69, 00-681 Warszawa, Poland email: ryszard.kostecki % uw.edu.pl June 26, 2011 Abstract

More information

LECTURE 3: RELATIVE SINGULAR HOMOLOGY

LECTURE 3: RELATIVE SINGULAR HOMOLOGY LECTURE 3: RELATIVE SINGULAR HOMOLOGY In this lecture we want to cover some basic concepts from homological algebra. These prove to be very helpful in our discussion of singular homology. The following

More information

CHOW S LEMMA. Matthew Emerton

CHOW S LEMMA. Matthew Emerton CHOW LEMMA Matthew Emerton The aim o this note is to prove the ollowing orm o Chow s Lemma: uppose that : is a separated inite type morphism o Noetherian schemes. Then (or some suiciently large n) there

More information

are additive in each variable. Explicitly, the condition on composition means that given a diagram

are additive in each variable. Explicitly, the condition on composition means that given a diagram 1. Abelian categories Most of homological algebra can be carried out in the setting of abelian categories, a class of categories which includes on the one hand all categories of modules and on the other

More information

COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA LECTURE 1: SOME CATEGORY THEORY

COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA LECTURE 1: SOME CATEGORY THEORY COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA LECTURE 1: SOME CATEGORY THEORY VIVEK SHENDE A ring is a set R with two binary operations, an addition + and a multiplication. Always there should be an identity 0 for addition, an

More information

A NOTE ON SHEAVES WITHOUT SELF-EXTENSIONS ON THE PROJECTIVE n-space.

A NOTE ON SHEAVES WITHOUT SELF-EXTENSIONS ON THE PROJECTIVE n-space. A NOTE ON SHEAVES WITHOUT SELF-EXTENSIONS ON THE PROJECTIVE n-space. DIETER HAPPEL AND DAN ZACHARIA Abstract. Let P n be the projective n space over the complex numbers. In this note we show that an indecomposable

More information

VALUATIVE CRITERIA BRIAN OSSERMAN

VALUATIVE CRITERIA BRIAN OSSERMAN VALUATIVE CRITERIA BRIAN OSSERMAN Intuitively, one can think o separatedness as (a relative version o) uniqueness o limits, and properness as (a relative version o) existence o (unique) limits. It is not

More information

The category of linear modular lattices

The category of linear modular lattices Bull. Math. Soc. Sci. Math. Roumanie Tome 56(104) No. 1, 2013, 33 46 The category of linear modular lattices by Toma Albu and Mihai Iosif Dedicated to the memory of Nicolae Popescu (1937-2010) on the occasion

More information

(C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets. Contents. 1 The characterizing results

(C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets. Contents. 1 The characterizing results (C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets We know that both Q and R are something special. When we think about about either o these we usually view it as a ield, or at least some kind o

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.ac] 31 Oct 2015

arxiv: v1 [math.ac] 31 Oct 2015 MESOPRIMARY DECOMPOSITION OF BINOMIAL SUBMODULES CHRISTOPHER O NEILL arxiv:1511.00161v1 [math.ac] 31 Oct 2015 Abstract. Recent results of Kahle and Miller give a method of constructing primary decompositions

More information

Algebraic Geometry

Algebraic Geometry MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 18.726 Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. 18.726: Algebraic Geometry

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

STABLE MODULE THEORY WITH KERNELS

STABLE MODULE THEORY WITH KERNELS Math. J. Okayama Univ. 43(21), 31 41 STABLE MODULE THEORY WITH KERNELS Kiriko KATO 1. Introduction Auslander and Bridger introduced the notion of projective stabilization mod R of a category of finite

More information

120A LECTURE OUTLINES

120A LECTURE OUTLINES 120A LECTURE OUTLINES RUI WANG CONTENTS 1. Lecture 1. Introduction 1 2 1.1. An algebraic object to study 2 1.2. Group 2 1.3. Isomorphic binary operations 2 2. Lecture 2. Introduction 2 3 2.1. The multiplication

More information

h M (T ). The natural isomorphism η : M h M determines an element U = η 1

h M (T ). The natural isomorphism η : M h M determines an element U = η 1 MODULI PROBLEMS AND GEOMETRIC INVARIANT THEORY 7 2.3. Fine moduli spaces. The ideal situation is when there is a scheme that represents our given moduli functor. Definition 2.15. Let M : Sch Set be a moduli

More information

An introduction to toposes. Richard Pettigrew Department of Philosophy University of Bristol

An introduction to toposes. Richard Pettigrew Department of Philosophy University of Bristol n introduction to toposes Richard Pettigrew Department of Philosophy University of Bristol Contents 1 Motivating category theory 1 1.1 The idea behind category theory.................. 1 2 The definition

More information

Algebra. Travis Dirle. December 4, 2016

Algebra. Travis Dirle. December 4, 2016 Abstract Algebra 2 Algebra Travis Dirle December 4, 2016 2 Contents 1 Groups 1 1.1 Semigroups, Monoids and Groups................ 1 1.2 Homomorphisms and Subgroups................. 2 1.3 Cyclic Groups...........................

More information

Derivations and differentials

Derivations and differentials Derivations and differentials Johan Commelin April 24, 2012 In the following text all rings are commutative with 1, unless otherwise specified. 1 Modules of derivations Let A be a ring, α : A B an A algebra,

More information

A Primer on Homological Algebra

A Primer on Homological Algebra A Primer on Homological Algebra Henry Y Chan July 12, 213 1 Modules For people who have taken the algebra sequence, you can pretty much skip the first section Before telling you what a module is, you probably

More information

Morava K-theory of BG: the good, the bad and the MacKey

Morava K-theory of BG: the good, the bad and the MacKey Morava K-theory of BG: the good, the bad and the MacKey Ruhr-Universität Bochum 15th May 2012 Recollections on Galois extensions of commutative rings Let R, S be commutative rings with a ring monomorphism

More information

A Little Beyond: Linear Algebra

A Little Beyond: Linear Algebra A Little Beyond: Linear Algebra Akshay Tiwary March 6, 2016 Any suggestions, questions and remarks are welcome! 1 A little extra Linear Algebra 1. Show that any set of non-zero polynomials in [x], no two

More information

ALGEBRA QUALIFYING EXAM PROBLEMS LINEAR ALGEBRA

ALGEBRA QUALIFYING EXAM PROBLEMS LINEAR ALGEBRA ALGEBRA QUALIFYING EXAM PROBLEMS LINEAR ALGEBRA Kent State University Department of Mathematical Sciences Compiled and Maintained by Donald L. White Version: August 29, 2017 CONTENTS LINEAR ALGEBRA AND

More information

COHEN-MACAULAY RINGS SELECTED EXERCISES. 1. Problem 1.1.9

COHEN-MACAULAY RINGS SELECTED EXERCISES. 1. Problem 1.1.9 COHEN-MACAULAY RINGS SELECTED EXERCISES KELLER VANDEBOGERT 1. Problem 1.1.9 Proceed by induction, and suppose x R is a U and N-regular element for the base case. Suppose now that xm = 0 for some m M. We

More information

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07)

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07) P. J. Šafárik University, Faculty of Science, Košice Project 2005/NP1-051 11230100466 Basic information Extent: 2 hrs lecture/1 hrs seminar per week. Assessment: Written tests during the semester, written

More information

MADE-TO-ORDER WEAK FACTORIZATION SYSTEMS

MADE-TO-ORDER WEAK FACTORIZATION SYSTEMS MADE-TO-ORDER WEAK FACTORIZATION SYSTEMS EMILY RIEHL The aim o this note is to briely summarize techniques or building weak actorization systems whose right class is characterized by a particular liting

More information

The real root modules for some quivers.

The real root modules for some quivers. SS 2006 Selected Topics CMR The real root modules for some quivers Claus Michael Ringel Let Q be a finite quiver with veretx set I and let Λ = kq be its path algebra The quivers we are interested in will

More information

Math 530 Lecture Notes. Xi Chen

Math 530 Lecture Notes. Xi Chen Math 530 Lecture Notes Xi Chen 632 Central Academic Building, University of Alberta, Edmonton, Alberta T6G 2G1, CANADA E-mail address: xichen@math.ualberta.ca 1991 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary

More information