Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics"

Transcription

1 Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics Solutions 1. Consider a pure exchange economy with two goods, h = 1,, and two consumers, i =1,, with utility functions u 1 and u respectively, and total endowment, e = (e 1,e ) À 0. Anattainableallocationissaidto be weakly Pareto-efficient if it is impossible to make every agent better off and strongly Pareto-efficient if it is impossible to make some agent better off without making other agents worse off. For each of the following cases, derive an expression for the set of (strongly) Pareto-efficient allocations and illustrate the set graphically. Also, in each case, determine whether the set of weakly Pareto-efficient allocations is different fromthesetof(strongly) Pareto-efficient allocations. If it is different, characterize and illustrate the set of weakly Pareto-efficient allocations. (a) u 1 (x, y) =α ln x +(1 α)lny and u (x, y) =β ln x +(1 β)lny, where α<βand ln x denotes the natural logaritm of x, i.e., log e x. Let x i be the amount of good x agent i is consuming. Define y i similarly. Let us first examine boundary points. Obviously, the two allocations where one of the agents consume the total endowment is strongly efficient. 1 We next show that these two allocations are the only efficient allocations on the boundary of the Edgeworth box. That is, we shall show that any other boundary allocation is not weakly efficient. To this end, assume for some i we have x i > 0 and y i =0(the argument for the case x i =0,y i > 0 is identical). Since x i > 0, we can transfer x i / to consumer j. Thiswillmakej strictly better off. Nowsincej s utility is continuous we could transfer some amount of good y from j to i leaving j still in a better situation than before. Since i s utility is no longer, she is also clearly better off (see figure 1). Thus the only efficient allocations on the 1 Any other attainable allocation would make the individual who is receiving all the endowment worse off. 1

2 boundary (weakly and strongly) are the allocations where one of the agents receives the total endowment of both goods. Agent 's indifference curve Improving direction for both consumers Agent 1's indifference curve Figure 1: Boundary Case Next, let s focus to the interior of the Edgeworth box. Note that both utilities are strongly monotone and continuous, and thus strongly efficient allocations coincide with weakly efficient allocations. Moreover, note that the sufficient conditions for Negishi s Theorem are satisfied. Thus for weights λ (0, 1), wecanfind the interior efficient allocations via max x 1,y 1,x,y λ (α ln x 1 +(1 α)lny 1 )+(1 λ)(β ln x +(1 β)lny ) s.t. x 1 + x = e 1 and y 1 + y = e. Note that solving the maximization above is equivalent to solving the following two problems: and max x 1,x λα ln x 1 +(1 λ) β ln x s.t. x 1 + x = e 1 max y 1,y λ (1 α)lny 1 +(1 λ)(1 β)lny s.t. y 1 + y = e.

3 TheproblemsabovearestandardCobb-Douglasproblems,andthus x 1 = x = y 1 = y = λα λα +(1 λ) β e 1, (1 λ) β λα +(1 λ) β e 1, λ (1 α) λ (1 α)+(1 λ)(1 β) e, (1 λ)(1 β) λ (1 α)+(1 λ)(1 β) e. The equations above are a possible characterization of our Pareto-efficient allocations as a function of λ. Alternatively we can use the first and third equation to write y 1 as a function of x 1 as y 1 =(1 α) e µ Moreover, it can be shown that βx 1 α (1 β) e 1 αx 1 + βx 1 dy 1 > 0 and d y 1 < 0, dx 1 dx 1 that is, y 1 is a strictly increasing, concave function of x 1. Finally, observe that y 1 x 1 = > =. λ (1 α) λα +(1 λ) β λ (1 α)+(1 λ)(1 β) λα (1 α) λα +(1 λ) α λ (1 α)+(1 λ)(1 α) α (1 α) α e = e. (1 α) α e 1 e 1 Hence, agent 1 s consumption bundle lies always above the diagonal of the Edgeworth box. We can thus characterize the set of efficient allocations e e 1 e e 1 3

4 graphically as in figure. Improving directions for agent 1 Improving directions for agent Figure : Pareto-Efficient Allocations (b) For i =1,, u 1 = u is strictly concave, smooth, and homothetic. First, note that the allocations (e 1,e ), (0, 0) and (0, 0), (e 1,e ) are strongly Pareto Efficient. Next, let s show that any allocation (te 1,te ), ((1 t)e 1, (1 t)e ) for t (0, 1) is also strongly Pareto Efficient. Note that the conditions for Negishi are satisfied, and thus for some weight λ>0, the efficient allocations can be found by solving max x 1,y 1,x,y u(x 1,y 1 )+λu(x,y ) s.t. x 1 + x = e 1 and y 1 + y = e. Since u is differentiable and concave, necessary and sufficient conditions for optimality are u(x 1,y1) / u(x 1,y1) x y = u(x,y ) x 4 / u(x,y). y

5 Since u is homothetic and strictly concave, however, in order for the MRS stobeequal,itmustbethat x 1 y 1 = x y = e 1 e, where the second equality follows from the feasibility constraints. Note that for any t (0, 1), the allocation (te 1,te ), ((1 t)e 1, (1 t)e ) satisfies this condition, and thus is strongly Pareto Efficient. Next, note that any other interior, feasible allocation, say x 0 1,y 0 0 1, x,y 0, will not satisfy x0 1 y 0 1 = x0,andthus y 0 u(x 0 1,y1) 0 / u(x0 1,y1) 0 x y 6= u(x0,y 0 ) x / u(x0,y) 0, y again by homotheticity and strict concavity. Since the equality of the MRS s is necessary for optimality of the planner s problem, we can conclude that 0 x 1,y 0 0 1, x,y 0 is not Pareto Efficient. Finally, let s check the remaining boundary points. Consider the feasible point x 00 1,y , x,y 00 00, and assume without loss of generality that x 1 =0 and y 00 1 > 0. Bystrictconcavity,wecanfind an >0and δ>0such that both agents are stictly better off under the allocation, y 00 1 δ, x 00, y 00 + δ, and thus these boundary allocations cannot be Pareto Efficient. See figure 3 for a graphical representation. 5

6 Improving directions for agent Improving directions for agent 1 Figure 3: Homothetic Utility Functions (c) For i =1,, u i (x, y) =x+g (y), whereg is an increasing and strictly concave function. Again, continuity and monotonicity imply equivalence of strong efficiency and weak efficiency. Hence, to find the efficient allocations we can solve the following Negishi problem: max λ (x 1 + g (y 1 )) + (1 λ)(e 1 x 1 + g (e y 1 )) x 1,y 1 s.t. 0 x 1 e 1 and 0 y 1 e. As in part (a), the problem can be separated into the following two problems: and max x 1 λx 1 +(1 λ)(e 1 x 1 ) s.t. 0 x 1 e 1 max y 1 λg (y 1 )+(1 λ) g (e y 1 ) s.t. 0 y 1 e. 6

7 For the first problem, if λ<1/ then x 1 =0,ifλ>1/ then x 1 =1and if λ =1/ then x 1 [0, 1]. For the second problem, if λ =0then y 1 =0and if λ =1then y 1 = e.if λ =1/, then the strict concavity of g implies that the solution is y 1 = e /. Since g is increasing in y and continuous, then for λ (0, 1/), thereexists auniquey 1 (0,e /) that solves the maximization problem, and similarly for λ (1/, 1). Moreover, by the continuity of g, the optimal set for y 1 (as a function of λ [0, 1]) isonto[0,e ]. Consequently, the efficient allocations are: x 1 =0, y 1 [0,e /) for some λ [0, 1/); x 1 [0, 1], y 1 = e / for λ =1/; and x 1 =1, y 1 (e /,e ] for some λ (1/, 1]. See figure 4 for a graphical representation. Improving directions for consumer 1 Improving directions for consumer Figure 4: Quasi-linear Utility Functions (d) u 1 (x, y) =min{x, y}, u (x, y) =min{x, y} and e 1 = e. To find the Pareto-efficient allocations for this problem, we will investigate four cases: Case 1: x 1 < y 1 and x >y Such an allocation is not weakly Pareto-efficient. To see this, let δ>0 and ε>0 be such that x 1 + δ<(y 1 ε) and (x δ) >y + ε. 7

8 It follows that u 1 (x 1 + δ, y 1 ε) =min{x 1 + δ, (y 1 ε)} = x 1 +δ>x 1 =min{x 1, y 1 } = u 1 (x 1,y 1 ) and u (x δ, y + ε) =min{(x δ),y + ε} = y +ε>y =min{x,y } = u (x,y ). Improving Direction for both agents Figure 5: Case 1 Case : x 1 > y 1 and x <y Such an allocation is not weakly Pareto-efficient. To see this, let δ>0 and ε>0 be such that But then we have x 1 δ>(y 1 + ε) and (x + δ) <y ε. u 1 (x 1 δ, y 1 + ε) =min{x 1 δ, (y 1 + ε)} =(y 1 + ε) > y 1 =min{x 1, y 1 } = u 1 (x 1,y 1 ) and u (x + δ, y ε) =min{(x + δ),y ε} =(x + δ) > x =min{x,y } = u (x,y ). 8

9 Improving direction for both agents Figure 6: Case Case 3: x 1 y 1 and x y Such an allocation is strongly Pareto-efficient. To see this, note that to increase the utility of either consumer you ll have to give her more of good y, but this will decrease the utility of the other consumer. Improving directions for agent 1 Improving directions for agent Figure 7: Case 3 Case 4: x 1 y 1 and x y Such an allocation is strongly Pareto-efficient. To see this, note that to increase the utility of either consumer you ll have to give her more of good x, but this will decrease the utility of the other consumer. 9

10 Improving directions for agent 1 Improving directions for agent Figure 8: Case 4 (e) u 1 (x, y) =max{x, y}, u (x, y) =max{x, y} and e 1 = e. Firstnotethattheallocation(x 1,y 1 )=(0,e), (x,y )=(e, 0) gives the maximum possible utility for both consumers. Since it s impossible to increase the utility of any of the two consumers, this allocation is trivially strongly Pareto-efficient. Moreover, there is no other strongly efficient allocation: any other allocation will give less than maximum utility to at least one of the consumers. Moreover, note that if y 1 = e it is impossible to increase the utility of consumer 1, so all these allocations are weakly Pareto-efficient. Similarly, allocations where x = e are also weakly Pareto-efficient. Finally it s clear that no other allocation can be weakly Pareto-efficient, since we always have the opportunity to move to (0, e), (e, 0) and make both consumers better off. 10

11 So we can represent the set of efficient allocations as strongly Pareto-efficient weakly Pareto-efficient Figure 9: Max Utility 5. Consider a pure exchange economy with two goods, h =1,, andtwo consumers, i =1,, with utility functions u 1 and u respectively, and total endowment, e =(e 1,e ) À 0. For each of the following cases, determine which of the Pareto-efficient allocations can be decentralized as competitive equilibrium with lump sum transfers. Briefly describe the equilibrium prices and transfers for each Pareto-efficient allocation. (a) u 1 (x, y) =α ln x +(1 α)lny and u (x, y) =β ln x +(1 β)lny, where α<βand ln x denotes the natural logaritm of x, i.e., log e x. In this case, for any Pareto-efficient allocation (x 1,y 1), (x,y ), weknow that at least one of the two agents is consuming a positive amount of the two goods, say agent i. Sowecanchoosep x, p y such that p x p y = u i (x i,y i ) / x u i (x i,y i ) / y. Observe that if the allocation is interior we have p x p y = α 1 α y1 x 1 11 = β 1 β y x.

12 So the first order conditions for the utility maximization problem of both consumers are being satisfied at the given bundles and prices. If we are at one of the corner allocations, since both prices are positive the consumer who has no wealth is optimally consuming nothing. By construction p x,p y are chosen so that the first order conditions for the problem of the other consumer are satisfied. Finally, let e i x be the endowment of good x consumer i is receiving. Define e i y in a similar way. Clearly the transfers that make the prices and allocations above an equilibrium are t 1 = p x x 1 + p y y 1 p x e 1 x p y e 1 y and t = p x x + p y y p x e x p y e y. (b) For i =1,, u 1 = u is strictly concave, smooth, and homothetic. Again we know that at least one of the consumers is consuming a positive amount of both goods, say consumer i. Sowecanchoosep x, p y such that p x p y = u i (x i,y i ) / x u i (x i,y i ) / y. But in this case, because of the homotheticity of u, we also know that p x = u j x j,yj / x = u(e 1,e ) / x p y u j x j,yj / y u(e 1,e ) / y. The transfers are the same as in (a). (c) For i =1,, u i (x, y) =x+g (y), whereg is an increasing and strictly concave function. 1

13 For simplicity, let s assume that g is differentiable. Recall that at least one of the agents consumes a positive amount of both goods, say consumer 1. Sowecanchoosep x, p y such that p x p y = u 1 (x 1,y 1) / x u 1 (x 1,y 1) / y. We can thus write the expression above in a simplified way as p x p y = 1 min {g 0 (y 1),g 0 (y )}. Therefore, the ratio of prices can be written as p x p y 1 g 0 (y 1),withequalityifx 1 > 0. So, if we have y >y 1, which implies that p x p y > 1 g 0 (y 1),wemusthavex 1 =0, and thus our price vector is giving us the correct allocations, even for the boundary cases. Again, the transfers are the same as in (a). (d) u 1 (x, y) =min{x, y}, u (x, y) =min{x, y} and e 1 = e. If p x,p y > 0 it s clear that in a solution of the problem of consumer 1 we will have x 1 =y1, and similarly we will have x = y in the problem of consumer. So in order to support an efficient allocation where one of the previous conditions is not true, we ll have to set one of the prices to zero. In fact, if p x =0,andp y > 0 we can support all efficient allocations such that x 1 y1 and x y.andifp x > 0 and p y =0we can support any efficient allocation such that x 1 y1 and x y. If we set p x,p y > 0, the only equilibrium with transfers will be the allocation (x 1,y 1)= µ 3 e, 1 3 e and (x,y )= where e := e 1 = e. Again, the transfers are the same as in (a). µ 1 3 e, 3 e, (e) u 1 (x, y) =max{x, y}, u (x, y) =max{x, y} and e 1 = e. 13

14 It s clear that if p x,p y > 0 both consumers will consume only one of the goods. If one the two prices is equal to zero, the consumers will want to consume an infinite amount of one of the goods, so there is no equilibrium in this case. So the only allocation that we can support as an equilibrium with transfers is (x 1,y1)=(0,e), (x,y)=(e, 0). To support this allocation we only need prices that make consumer 1 want to buy good y and makes consumer want to buy good x. Asufficient condition for this to happen is p x p y p x. Again, the transfers are the same as in (a). 6. Consider a pure exchange economy with two goods, h =1,, andtwo consumers, i =1,, with consumption sets X i = R +, endowments e 1 =(1, 0) and e =(1, 1), and utility functions u 1 (x 11,x 1 )=(x 11 ) 1/ +(x 1 ) 1/ and u (x 1,x )=min{x 1,x } respectively. Show that the initial endowment can be decentralized as a quasiequilibrium, that is, there exists a price vector p such that (p,x )=(p,e) is a quasi-equilibrium. Is (p,x ) a competitive equilibrium (with or without transfers)? Explain your answer with reference to the assumptions of the second theorem of welfare economics. Let p 1 = 0 and p > 0. For consumer 1 we have that p 1 1+p 0 = 0. So, since the cost of the bundle (1, 0) is the minimum possible, the condition for a quasi-equilibrium is trivially satisfied - any allocation increeasing consumer 1 s utility must cost at least 0. For consumer, any bundle such that u (x 1,x ) >u (1, 1) must satisfy x > 1 and, therefore, is more expensive than (1, 1), and thus the condition for a quasi-equilibrium is also satisfied for consumer. We shall now show that endowments cannot be a part of an equilibrium with transfers. Since marginal utility of good for consumer 1 is at e 1, 14

15 then consumer 1 could optimally choose e 1 only if she has no positive wealth. But since she has 1 unit of good one, this is possible only if p 1 =0. But whenever p 1 =0, she would choose x 11 =. The condition we are missing here is the condition that there exists a cheaper bundle than the quasi-equilibrium bundles for both consumers. In the above depicted quasi-equilibrium, this condition is not satisfied for player Consider a pure exchange economy with two consumers i =1, and two commodities, h =1,. The consumers have consumption sets R + and endowments e 1 =(4, 0) and e =(0, 3). Consumer has preferences represented by the utility function u (x,y )=min{x + y,x +y }.Illustrate a typical indifference curve for consumer. Consider the following possible utility functions for consumer 1: u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=min{x 1, y 1 }; u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{x 1, 3y 1 }; u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{x 1,y 1 }; u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{min{x 1,y 1 },min{x 1, y 1 }}. In each case, illustrate the Pareto-efficient allocations in an Edgeworth Box diagram and find the set of Pareto-efficient allocations that can be supported as an equilibrium with transfers. Let s first study consumer s preferences. Note that preferences are strictly monotonic and if x >y,thenu (x,y )=x +y,ifx <y, then u (x,y )=x + y and if x = y,thenu (x,y )=3x. Consumer s indifference curves are as depicted below: 15

16 Figure 10: Consumer s Indifference Curves (a) u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=min{x 1, y 1 }. Any Strongly Pareto Efficient allocation must satisfy x 1 =y 1. If x 1 > y 1, for instance, we could transfer ε of x 1 to consumer and δ of y to consumer 1 to make both consumers strictly better off. All of the points such that x 1 =y 1 are Strongly Pareto Efficient - to improve consumer 1, we must increase his consumption of either x 1 or y 1 (or both), which would decrease consumer s utility. Conversely, from the convexity of consumer s preferences, we must decrease 1 s utility in order to increase consumer s welfare (see the graph below). Moreover, allocations (e 1,y 1 ), (0,e y 1 ) for y 1 are (trivially) Weakly Pareto Efficient since consumer 1 cannot be made better off. 16

17 Figure 11: u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=min{x 1, y 1 } Every Strongly Pareto Efficient ³ point ³ can be decentralized. If x 1, equilibrium can be supported at x 1, x 1, e 1 x 1,e x 1 with prices p = ³ ³ (α, α) for any α>0, andif <x 1 4, then x 1, x 1, e 1 x 1,e x 1 canbesupportedwithpricesp =(α, α) for any α>0. Asinquestion5, the transfers are and t 1 = p x x 1 + p y y 1 p x e 1 x p y e 1 y (b) u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{x 1, 3y 1 }. t = p x x + p y y p x e x p y e y. Clearly, any interior point is inefficient - if 0 <x 1 <y 1 <e,thenwe could transfer x 1 to consumer and δ of y to consumer 1 to make both agents strictly better. Moreover, allocations (x 1, 0), (e 1 x 1,e ) (along the bottom of the Edgeworth Box) are not Weakly Pareto Efficient since we can make both consumers strictly better off with the allocation 0, x ε, e 1,e x ε. 17

18 Allocations such as (e 1,y 1 ), (0,e y 1 ) (along the right of the Edgeworth Box) are not Weakly Pareto Efficient either since the point ³ 0, max{ e ³ 1 3,y 1}, e 1,e max{ e 1 3,y 1} is preferred by both consumers. Allocations (0,y 1 ), (e 1,e y 1 ) (alongtheleftoftheedgeworthbox)are Strongly Pareto Efficient. Clearly, to improve consumer we would have to reduce consumer 1 s utility. To improve consumer 1, we either need to increase his consumption of y 1 (which would reduce consumer s utility) or set x 1 > 3y 1 (which would reduce consumer s utility and in some cases would not be feasible). Finally, allocations (x 1,e ), (e 1 x 1, 0) (along the top of the Edgeworth Box) are (trivially) weakly Pareto Efficient since e 1 < 3e. Figure 1: u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{x 1, 3y 1 } All of the Strongly Pareto Efficient points can be decentralized. For consumer 1 to be maximizing at (0,y 1), itmustbethatp 3p 1 ; otherwise, consumer 1 could afford strictly more than 3y 1 of the first commodity. Therefore, the price vector p =(α, α) for any α>0 will support decentralization of the allocations (0,y 1), (e 1,e y 1). The weakly Pareto Efficient allocations, however, cannot be supported, as for any price vector, consumer 1 would maximize his utility by consuming either only the first commodity or the second commodity. The corresponding transfers are identical to part (a). 18

19 (c) u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{x 1,y 1 }. As in (b), all interior points are inefficient. Moreover, allocations such as (0,y 1 ), (e 1,e y 1 ) (along the left of the Edgeworth Box) are not Weakly Pareto Efficient, as the allocation (y 1 + ε, 0), (e 1 (y 1 + ε),e ) is a strict improvement for both consumers. Allocations such as (x 1,e ), (e 1 x 1, 0) (along the top of the Edgeworth Box) are not Weakly Pareto Efficient either, since (e + ε, 0), (e 1 (e + ε),e ) is a strict improvement for both consumers. Points such as (x 1, 0), (e 1 x 1,e ) (along the bottom of the Edgeworth Box) are Strongly Pareto Efficient. To increase consumer s utility, we clearly need to increase x, which would reduce consumer 1 s utility. To increase consumer 1 s utility, we would either need to increase x 1 or set y 0 1 >x 1, both of which would decrease consumer s utility. Finally, the points (e 1,y 1 ), (0,e y 1 ) (along the right of the Edgeworth Box) are (trivially) Weakly Pareto Efficient since e 1 >e. Figure 13: u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{x 1,y 1 } The only decentralizable allocations are (x 1, 0), (e 1 x 1,e ) when x 1 1. As in (b), the Weakly Pareto Efficient allocations cannot be supported. The 19

20 Strongly Pareto Efficient points are maximal for consumer 1 if p 1 p - otherwise, he would purchase only commodity. When x 1 1, the prices p =(α, α) for any α>0 will clearly constitute an equilibrium. When 1 < x 1 4, however, in order for consumer to be maximizing at (e 1 x 1,e ), it must be that p =(α, α) for some α>0 (otherwise, he would be able to afford a better bundle). Clearly, p 1 >p in this region, and thus equilibrium cannot be sustained. The corresponding transfers are identical to part (a). (d) u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{min{x 1,y 1 },min{x 1, y 1 }}. First, let s get a handle on consumer 1 s preferences. If x 1 > y 1,then u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=y 1,ify 1 > x 1,thenu 1 (x 1,y 1 )=x 1 and if x 1 y 1 and y 1 x 1 then u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{x 1,y 1 }. Graphically, we have: Figure 14: Consumer 1 s Indifference Curves Now let s examine the Pareto Efficient points. Clearly, allocations (x 1, 0), (e 1 x 1,e ) and (0,y 1 ), (e 1,e y 1 ) (along the bottom and left of the Edgeworth Box) are not Weakly Pareto Efficient since consumer 1 receives zero utility (we can 0

21 simply move to the interior to improve both agents). Moreover, allocations (x 1,e ), (e 1 x 1, 0) (along the top of the Edgeworth Box) are not Weakly Pareto Efficient either since the allocation µ x 1 + ε, x 1 + ε, µ e 1 (x 1 + ε),e is an strict improvement for both consumers. µ x1 + ε In the interior, the only (strongly and weakly) Pareto Efficient allocations are when x 1 =y 1 as in part (a). If x 1 > y 1, then transferring ε of x 1 to consumer and δ of y to consumer 1 will be a strict improvement for both. If y 1 > x 1,thenmovingto µ x 1 + ε, x 1 + ε µ, e 1 (x 1 + ε),e µ x1 + ε will improve both consumers (see the figure below). Finally, if x 1 y 1 and y 1 >x 1, then the allocations µ max{x 1,y 1 } + ε, max{x 1,y 1 } + ε µ, e 1 (max{x 1,y 1 } + ε),e will increase the utility of both consumers (again, see the figure below). The allocations (e 1,y 1 ), (0,e y 1 ) for y 1 are weakly Pareto efficient, as consumer 1 cannot be made better off. Thus the Pareto points are identical to part (a). µ max{x1,y 1 } + ε Figure 15: u 1 (x 1,y 1 )=max{min{x 1,y 1 },min{x 1, y 1 }} 1

22 The only decentralizable allocations are x 1, x 1, e1 x 1,e x 1 when x 1. For these allocations, consumer is maximizing his utility if prices are such that p =(α, α) for any α>0 Under these prices, it is clear that consumer 1 is maximizing her utility. The Strongly Pareto Efficient allocations such that <x 1 4, however, are not decentralizable. At these allocations, prices must be such that p =(α, α) for some α>0in order for consumer to be maximizing over her budget set. Under these prices, however, consumer 1 can increase her utility by purchasing less of good 1 and more of good. Consequently, these points cannot be decentralized. The corresponding transfers are identical to part (a).

Market Equilibrium and the Core

Market Equilibrium and the Core Market Equilibrium and the Core Ram Singh Lecture 3-4 September 22/25, 2017 Ram Singh (DSE) Market Equilibrium September 22/25, 2017 1 / 19 Market Exchange: Basics Let us introduce price in our pure exchange

More information

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ. 805 Winter 00 Prof. James Peck Homework Set Questions and Answers. Consider the following pure exchange economy with two consumers and two goods.

More information

Second Welfare Theorem

Second Welfare Theorem Second Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2015 Lecture 18, November 2 Outline 1 Second Welfare Theorem From Last Class We want to state a prove a theorem that says that any Pareto optimal allocation is (part

More information

First Welfare Theorem

First Welfare Theorem First Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 17, October 31 Outline 1 First Welfare Theorem 2 Preliminaries to Second Welfare Theorem Past Definitions A feasible allocation (ˆx, ŷ) is Pareto optimal

More information

Lecture Notes October 18, Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I.

Lecture Notes October 18, Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I. Lecture Notes October 18, 2012 Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I. Economic General Equilibrium Partial and General Economic Equilibrium PARTIAL EQUILIBRIUM S k (p o ) = D k k (po

More information

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics Ram Singh Lecture 6 September 29, 2015 Ram Singh: (DSE) General Equilibrium Analysis September 29, 2015 1 / 14 First Fundamental Theorem The First Fundamental

More information

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions 1. For each of the following propositions, state whether the proposition is true or false. If true, provide a proof (or at least indicate how a proof could

More information

1 General Equilibrium

1 General Equilibrium 1 General Equilibrium 1.1 Pure Exchange Economy goods, consumers agent : preferences < or utility : R + R initial endowments, R + consumption bundle, =( 1 ) R + Definition 1 An allocation, =( 1 ) is feasible

More information

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy Andrew McLennan October 28, 2014 Economics 7250 Advanced Mathematical Techniques for Economics Second Semester 2014 Lecture 15 The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy I. Introduction A. The material discussed

More information

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems The Fundamental Welfare Theorems The so-called Fundamental Welfare Theorems of Economics tell us about the relation between market equilibrium and Pareto efficiency. The First Welfare Theorem: Every Walrasian

More information

4 Lecture Applications

4 Lecture Applications 4 Lecture 4 4.1 Applications We now will look at some of the applications of the convex analysis we have learned. First, we shall us a separation theorem to prove the second fundamental theorem of welfare

More information

Introduction to General Equilibrium

Introduction to General Equilibrium Introduction to General Equilibrium Juan Manuel Puerta November 6, 2009 Introduction So far we discussed markets in isolation. We studied the quantities and welfare that results under different assumptions

More information

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice http://selod.ensae.net/m1 Paris School of Economics (selod@ens.fr) September 27, 2007 Notations Consider an individual (agent) facing a choice set X. Definition (Choice set, "Consumption set") X is a set

More information

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 19, November 7 Outline 1 Welfare Theorems in the differentiable case. 2 Aggregate excess

More information

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework. Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework. Economy: I consumers, i = 1,...I. J firms, j = 1,...J. L goods, l = 1,...L Initial Endowment of good l in the economy: ω l 0, l = 1,...L. Consumer i : preferences

More information

Lecture Notes for January 8, 2009; part 2

Lecture Notes for January 8, 2009; part 2 Economics 200B Prof. R. Starr UCSD Winter 2009 Lecture Notes for January 8, 2009; part 2 Integrating Production and Multiple Consumption Decisions: A2 2 2 Model Competitive Equilibrium: Production and

More information

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5 EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5 Leonardo Felli 32L.LG.04 27 October, 207 Pareto Efficient Allocation Recall the following result: Result An allocation x is Pareto-efficient if and only

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction Microeconomic Theory -- Introduction. Introduction. Profit maximizing firm with monopoly power 6 3. General results on maximizing with two variables 8 4. Model of a private ownership economy 5. Consumer

More information

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations We ve shown that any Walrasian equilibrium allocation (any WEA) is in the core, but it s obvious that the converse is far from

More information

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3 Microeconomics II MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3 Problem 1 Consider an economy 1 1, with one firm (or technology and one consumer (firm owner, as in the textbook (MWG section 15.C. The set of

More information

Economics 200A part 2 UCSD Fall quarter 2011 Prof. R. Starr Mr. Troy Kravitz1 FINAL EXAMINATION SUGGESTED ANSWERS

Economics 200A part 2 UCSD Fall quarter 2011 Prof. R. Starr Mr. Troy Kravitz1 FINAL EXAMINATION SUGGESTED ANSWERS Economics 200A part 2 UCSD Fall quarter 2011 Prof. R. Starr Mr. Troy Kravitz1 FINAL EXAMINATION SUGGESTED ANSWERS This exam is take-home, open-book, open-notes. You may consult any published source (cite

More information

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision: 0-0 1 Demand Lecture Last Revised: 2007-01-12 16:19:03-0800 (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision: 67) a demand correspondence is a special kind of choice correspondence where the set of alternatives is X = { x

More information

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties In this lecture we consider a general model of a private ownership economy, i.e., a market economy in which a consumer s wealth is derived from endowments

More information

Economics 201b Spring 2010 Solutions to Problem Set 1 John Zhu

Economics 201b Spring 2010 Solutions to Problem Set 1 John Zhu Economics 201b Spring 2010 Solutions to Problem Set 1 John Zhu 1a The following is a Edgeworth box characterization of the Pareto optimal, and the individually rational Pareto optimal, along with some

More information

General Equilibrium and Welfare

General Equilibrium and Welfare and Welfare Lectures 2 and 3, ECON 4240 Spring 2017 University of Oslo 24.01.2017 and 31.01.2017 1/37 Outline General equilibrium: look at many markets at the same time. Here all prices determined in the

More information

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018) Recitation #2 (August 1st, 2018) 1. [Checking properties of the Cobb-Douglas utility function.] Consider the utility function u(x) = n i=1 xα i i, where x denotes a vector of n different goods x R n +,

More information

Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an exchange economy

Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an exchange economy Microeconomic Teory -1- Equilibrium and efficiency Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an excange economy 1. Efficient economies 2 2. Gains from excange 6 3. Edgewort-ox analysis 15 4. Properties of a

More information

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata General Equilibrium Equilibrium in Consumption GE begins (1/3) 2-Individual/ 2-good Exchange economy (No production, no transaction costs, full information..) Endowment (Nature): e Private property/ NO

More information

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions.

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions. Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 3: Optimization - interior optima 1 Session: 11-12 Aug 2015 (Thu/Fri) 10:00am 1:00pm I. Optimization: introduction Decision-makers (e.g. consumers,

More information

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses. Microeconomic Theory Summer 206-7 Mid-semester Exam 2 There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.. Consider the following 2 2 economy. The utility functions are: u (.) = x x 2

More information

Note on social choice allocation in exchange economies with Cobb-Douglas preferences

Note on social choice allocation in exchange economies with Cobb-Douglas preferences Note on social choice allocation in exchange economies with Cobb-Douglas preferences Takeshi Momi Department of Economics, Doshisha University April, 2011 Abstract In this note we show that in a pure exchange

More information

Competitive Market Mechanisms as Social Choice Procedures

Competitive Market Mechanisms as Social Choice Procedures Competitive Market Mechanisms as Social Choice Procedures Peter J. Hammond 1 Department of Economics, Stanford University, CA 94305-6072, U.S.A. 1 Introduction and outline 1.1 Markets and social choice

More information

Notes on General Equilibrium

Notes on General Equilibrium Notes on General Equilibrium Alejandro Saporiti Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 1 / 42 General equilibrium Reference: Jehle and Reny, Advanced Microeconomic Theory, 3rd ed., Pearson

More information

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018 EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 018 Show all your work clearly and make sure you justify all your answers. NAME 1. Consider the market for smart pencil in which only one firm (Superapiz) enjoys a

More information

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S. In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 1 44715 (1396-97 1 st term) - Group 1 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 10: Competitive Markets

More information

The Existence of Equilibrium in. Infinite-Dimensional Spaces: Some Examples. John H. Boyd III

The Existence of Equilibrium in. Infinite-Dimensional Spaces: Some Examples. John H. Boyd III The Existence of Equilibrium in Infinite-Dimensional Spaces: Some Examples John H. Boyd III April 1989; Updated June 1995 Abstract. This paper presents some examples that clarify certain topological and

More information

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Tsun-Feng Chiang* *School of Economics, Henan University, Kaifeng, China November 2, 2014 1 / 28 Primitive Notions 1.1 Primitive Notions Consumer

More information

Simon Fraser University, Department of Economics, Econ 201, Prof. Karaivanov FINAL EXAM Answer key

Simon Fraser University, Department of Economics, Econ 201, Prof. Karaivanov FINAL EXAM Answer key Simon Fraser University, Department of Economics, Econ 01, Prof. Karaivanov 017 FINAL EXAM Answer key I. TRUE or FALSE (5 pts each). [The answers below are just examples of correct answers, other possible

More information

ANSWERS TO ODD NUMBERED EXERCISES IN CHAPTER 3

ANSWERS TO ODD NUMBERED EXERCISES IN CHAPTER 3 John Riley 5 Setember 0 NSWERS T DD NUMERED EXERCISES IN CHPTER 3 SECTIN 3: Equilibrium and Efficiency Exercise 3-: Prices with Quasi-linear references (a) Since references are convex, an allocation is

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium Advanced Microeconomic Theory Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium Outline Partial Equilibrium Analysis General Equilibrium Analysis Comparative Statics Welfare Analysis Advanced Microeconomic Theory

More information

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice Economics 101 Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice 1 Uncle Léon The canonical model of exchange in economics is sometimes referred to as the Walrasian Model, after the early economist Léon

More information

Competitive Equilibrium

Competitive Equilibrium Competitive Equilibrium Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 16, October 26 Outline 1 Pareto Effi ciency 2 The Core 3 Planner s Problem(s) 4 Competitive (Walrasian) Equilibrium Decentralized vs. Centralized Economic

More information

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics Public Economics: Chapter 9 1 Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics Objectives of this chapter Public Economics: Chapter 9 2 Read Atkinson & Stiglitz (1980,

More information

Regularity of competitive equilibria in a production economy with externalities

Regularity of competitive equilibria in a production economy with externalities Regularity of competitive equilibria in a production economy with externalities Elena del Mercato Vincenzo Platino Paris School of Economics - Université Paris 1 Panthéon Sorbonne QED-Jamboree Copenhagen,

More information

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses Carlos Hervés-Beloso RGEA. Universidad de Vigo. e-mail: cherves@uvigo.es Emma Moreno-García Universidad de Salamanca. e-mail: emmam@usal.es

More information

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad Unlinked llocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One ad Chiaki Hara Faculty of Economics and Politics, University of Cambridge Institute of Economic Research, Hitotsubashi University pril 16,

More information

CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES. Likewise, we may define the higher order derivatives. f(x, y, z) = xy 2 + e zx. y = 2xy.

CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES. Likewise, we may define the higher order derivatives. f(x, y, z) = xy 2 + e zx. y = 2xy. April 15, 2009 CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES In this chapter D denotes an open subset of R n. 1. Introduction Definition 1.1. Given a function f : D R we define the second partial derivatives as

More information

Firms and returns to scale -1- John Riley

Firms and returns to scale -1- John Riley Firms and returns to scale -1- John Riley Firms and returns to scale. Increasing returns to scale and monopoly pricing 2. Natural monopoly 1 C. Constant returns to scale 21 D. The CRS economy 26 E. pplication

More information

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A December, 2016, Ted Bergstrom, UCSB I asked students to try to answer any 7 of the 8 questions. I intended the exam to have some relatively easy parts and

More information

Adding Production to the Theory

Adding Production to the Theory Adding Production to the Theory We begin by considering the simplest situation that includes production: two goods, both of which have consumption value, but one of which can be transformed into the other.

More information

ANSWER KEY. University of California, Davis Date: June 22, 2015

ANSWER KEY. University of California, Davis Date: June 22, 2015 ANSWER KEY University of California, Davis Date: June, 05 Department of Economics Time: 5 hours Microeconomic Theory Reading Time: 0 minutes PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION FOR THE Ph.D. DEGREE Please answer four

More information

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712 Prof. Peck Fall 20 Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 872. (0 points) The following economy has two consumers, two firms, and three goods. Good is leisure/labor.

More information

Firms and returns to scale -1- Firms and returns to scale

Firms and returns to scale -1- Firms and returns to scale Firms and returns to scale -1- Firms and returns to scale. Increasing returns to scale and monopoly pricing 2. Constant returns to scale 19 C. The CRS economy 25 D. pplication to trade 47 E. Decreasing

More information

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0). . (a) (8 points) What does it mean for observations x and p... x T and p T to be rationalized by a monotone utility function? Notice that this is a one good economy. For all t, p t x t function. p t x

More information

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501 Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501 1. [Checking properties of preference relations-i]. For each of the following preference relations in the consumption of two goods (1 and 2): describe the upper contour

More information

Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality)

Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality) Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality) 1 Definitions and notation Recall some of our definitions and notation for preference orderings. Let X be a set (the set of alternatives); we have the

More information

Utility Maximization Problem

Utility Maximization Problem Demand Theory Utility Maximization Problem Consumer maximizes his utility level by selecting a bundle x (where x can be a vector) subject to his budget constraint: max x 0 u(x) s. t. p x w Weierstrass

More information

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations 14.452 Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations Daron Acemoglu MIT November 20, 2018 Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Economic Growth Lecture 8 November 20, 2018 1 / 46 Growth with Overlapping Generations

More information

i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly.

i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly. Bocconi University PhD in Economics - Microeconomics I Prof. M. Messner Problem Set 3 - Solution Problem 1: i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult

More information

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score. Economics 200B Part 1 UCSD Winter 2014 Prof. R. Starr, Ms. Isla Globus-Harris Final Exam 1 Your Name: SUGGESTED ANSWERS Please answer all questions. Each of the six questions marked with a big number counts

More information

3. THE EXCHANGE ECONOMY

3. THE EXCHANGE ECONOMY Essential Microeconomics -1-3. THE EXCHNGE ECONOMY Pareto efficient allocations 2 Edgewort box analysis 5 Market clearing prices 13 Walrasian Equilibrium 16 Equilibrium and Efficiency 22 First welfare

More information

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume Duality for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume Headwords: CONVEXITY, DUALITY, LAGRANGE MULTIPLIERS, PARETO EFFICIENCY, QUASI-CONCAVITY 1 Introduction The word duality is

More information

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais Microeconomics Fall 2016 Primitive notions There are four building blocks in any model of consumer choice. They are the consumption set, the feasible set, the preference relation, and the behavioural assumption.

More information

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ). University of California, Davis Date: August 24, 2017 Department of Economics Time: 5 hours Microeconomics Reading Time: 20 minutes PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION FOR THE Ph.D. DEGREE Please answer any three

More information

A : a b c d a : B C A E B : d b c a b : C A B D E C : d c a c : E D B C D : a d b d : A D E B C E : a b d. A : a b c d a : B C A D E

A : a b c d a : B C A E B : d b c a b : C A B D E C : d c a c : E D B C D : a d b d : A D E B C E : a b d. A : a b c d a : B C A D E Microeconomics II( ECO 50) Questions on the comprehensive exam will be chosen from the list below( with possible minor variations) CALCULATORS ARE ALLOWED Matching. Consider the Gale-Shapley marriage problem

More information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information Contracts under Asymmetric Information 1 I Aristotle, economy (oiko and nemo) and the idea of exchange values, subsequently adapted by Ricardo and Marx. Classical economists. An economy consists of a set

More information

1 Second Welfare Theorem

1 Second Welfare Theorem Econ 701B Fall 018 University of Pennsylvania Recitation : Second Welfare Theorem Xincheng Qiu (qiux@sas.upenn.edu) 1 Second Welfare Theorem Theorem 1. (Second Welfare Theorem) An economy E satisfies (A1)-(A4).

More information

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory Chapter 9 Nathan Smooha Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory 9.1 Introduction In this chapter, we briefly discuss some topics in the framework of general equilibrium theory, namely

More information

September Math Course: First Order Derivative

September Math Course: First Order Derivative September Math Course: First Order Derivative Arina Nikandrova Functions Function y = f (x), where x is either be a scalar or a vector of several variables (x,..., x n ), can be thought of as a rule which

More information

No Equilibrium in Infinite Economies: Two Examples*

No Equilibrium in Infinite Economies: Two Examples* JOURNAL OF ECONOMIC THEORY 34, 180-186 (1984) No Equilibrium in Infinite Economies: Two Examples* AHMET ALKAN Bogaripi Universitesi, Istanbul, Turkey Received December 20, 1982; revised October 14. 1983

More information

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1 dvanced Microeconomics Problem Set László Sándor Central European University Pareto optima With Cobb-Douglas utilities u x ; x 2 ; x 3 = 0:4 log x 2 + 0:6 log x 3 and u x ; x 2 ; x 3 = log x 2 + log x

More information

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution) Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution) 1. Checking properties of the Cobb-Douglas utility function. Consider the utility function u(x) Y n i1 x i i ; where x denotes a vector of n di erent goods x 2 R n +,

More information

(ii) An input requirement set for this technology is clearly not convex as it

(ii) An input requirement set for this technology is clearly not convex as it LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS Department of Economics Leonardo Felli 32L.4.02; 7525 Solutions to Assignment 5 EC487 Advanced Microeconomics Part I 1. Sketch of the answers: (i) The map of isoquants for this

More information

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Answers Econ 805

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Answers Econ 805 Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Answers Econ 805 Prof. James Peck Winter 0. (0 points) Consider the following pure-exchange economy with two consumers and two goods. Consumer

More information

Econ 401A: Economic Theory Mid-term. Answers

Econ 401A: Economic Theory Mid-term. Answers . Labor suly Econ 40: Economic Theory Mid-term nswers (a) Let be labor suly. Then x 4 The key ste is setting u the budget constraint. x w w(4 x ) Thus the budget constraint can be rewritten as follows:

More information

Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1

Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1 Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1 Session: 15 Aug 2015 (Mon), 10:00am 1:00pm I. Optimization with

More information

Lecture Notes MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS

Lecture Notes MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS Lecture Notes MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS A. Neyman Fall 2006, Jerusalem The notes may/will be updated in few days. Please revisit to check for the updated version. Please email comments to aneyman@math.huji.ac.il

More information

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

Can everyone benefit from innovation? Can everyone benefit from innovation? Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi June 16, 2017 Abstract We study a resource allocation problem with variable technologies, and ask if there is an allocation

More information

PhD Qualifier Examination

PhD Qualifier Examination PhD Qualifier Examination Department of Agricultural Economics July 26, 2013 Instructions The exam consists of six questions. You must answer all questions. If you need an assumption to complete a question,

More information

Preferences and Utility

Preferences and Utility Preferences and Utility How can we formally describe an individual s preference for different amounts of a good? How can we represent his preference for a particular list of goods (a bundle) over another?

More information

Other-Regarding Preferences in General Equilibrium

Other-Regarding Preferences in General Equilibrium Review of Economic Studies (2011) 78, 613 639 doi: 10.1093/restud/rdq026 The Author 2011. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of The Review of Economic Studies Limited. Advance access publication

More information

Overview. Producer Theory. Consumer Theory. Exchange

Overview. Producer Theory. Consumer Theory. Exchange Overview Consumer Producer Exchange Edgeworth Box All Possible Exchange Points Contract Curve Overview Consumer Producer Exchange (Multiplicity) Walrasian Equilibrium Walrasian Equilibrium Requirements:

More information

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems The Fundamental Welfare Theorems The so-called Fundamental Welfare Theorems of Economics tell us about the relation between market equilibrium and Pareto efficiency. The First Welfare Theorem: Every Walrasian

More information

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis 1 Convex sets Both convex sets and functions have general importance in economic theory, not only in optimization. Given two points x; y 2 R n and 2 [0; 1]; the weighted

More information

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2 Microeconomics, Block I Part 2 Piero Gottardi EUI Sept. 20, 2015 Piero Gottardi (EUI) Microeconomics, Block I Part 2 Sept. 20, 2015 1 / 48 Pure Exchange Economy H consumers with: preferences described

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Leonardo Felli EC441: Room D.106, Z.332, D.109 Lecture 8 bis: 24 November 2004 Monopoly Consider now the pricing behavior of a profit maximizing monopolist: a firm that is the only

More information

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018 NAME: Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018 Instructions. Show all your work clearly and make sure you justify all your answers. 1. Question 1 [10 Points]. Discuss and provide examples of

More information

Notes on Alvarez and Jermann, "Efficiency, Equilibrium, and Asset Pricing with Risk of Default," Econometrica 2000

Notes on Alvarez and Jermann, Efficiency, Equilibrium, and Asset Pricing with Risk of Default, Econometrica 2000 Notes on Alvarez Jermann, "Efficiency, Equilibrium, Asset Pricing with Risk of Default," Econometrica 2000 Jonathan Heathcote November 1st 2005 1 Model Consider a pure exchange economy with I agents one

More information

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability Chapter 7 Nathan Smooha Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability 7.1 Introduction Brouwer s Fixed Point Theorem. Let X be a non-empty, compact, and convex subset of R m. If

More information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KYOTO INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH Discussion Paper No.992 Intertemporal efficiency does not imply a common price forecast: a leading example Shurojit Chatterji, Atsushi

More information

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 4, September 7 Outline 1 Structural Properties of Utility Functions 1 Local Non Satiation 2 Convexity 3 Quasi-linearity

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Ordinal preference theory Harald Wiese University of Leipzig Harald Wiese (University of Leipzig) Advanced Microeconomics 1 / 68 Part A. Basic decision and preference theory 1 Decisions

More information

Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods

Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods Michael Florig Jorge Rivera Cayupi First version November 2001, this version May 2005 Abstract We study an economy where all goods entering

More information

1 Jan 28: Overview and Review of Equilibrium

1 Jan 28: Overview and Review of Equilibrium 1 Jan 28: Overview and Review of Equilibrium 1.1 Introduction What is an equilibrium (EQM)? Loosely speaking, an equilibrium is a mapping from environments (preference, technology, information, market

More information

Alp Simsek (MIT) Recitation Notes: 1. Gorman s Aggregation Th eorem2. Normative Representative November 9, Household Theorem / 16

Alp Simsek (MIT) Recitation Notes: 1. Gorman s Aggregation Th eorem2. Normative Representative November 9, Household Theorem / 16 14.452 Recitation Notes: 1. Gorman s Aggregation Theorem 2. Normative Representative Household Theorem 3. Representative Firm Theorem (Recitation 2 on November 6, 2009) (Reference: "Introduction to Modern

More information

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009 Department of Agricultural Economics PhD Qualifier Examination May 009 Instructions: The exam consists of six questions. You must answer all questions. If you need an assumption to complete a question,

More information

Alfred Marshall s cardinal theory of value: the strong law of demand

Alfred Marshall s cardinal theory of value: the strong law of demand Econ Theory Bull (2014) 2:65 76 DOI 10.1007/s40505-014-0029-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE Alfred Marshall s cardinal theory of value: the strong law of demand Donald J. Brown Caterina Calsamiglia Received: 29 November

More information

3.2 THE FUNDAMENTAL WELFARE THEOREMS

3.2 THE FUNDAMENTAL WELFARE THEOREMS Essential Microeconomics -1-3.2 THE FUNDMENTL WELFRE THEOREMS Walrasian Equilibrium 2 First welfare teorem 3 Second welfare teorem (conve, differentiable economy) 12 Te omotetic preference 2 2 economy

More information

Preferences and Utility

Preferences and Utility Preferences and Utility This Version: October 6, 2009 First Version: October, 2008. These lectures examine the preferences of a single agent. In Section 1 we analyse how the agent chooses among a number

More information