i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly.

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly."

Transcription

1 Bocconi University PhD in Economics - Microeconomics I Prof. M. Messner Problem Set 3 - Solution Problem 1: i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly. So assume that x(p, w) is a function (i.e. not a correspondence). We have to show that if q n = (p n, w n ) q = (p, w) then x n = x(q n ) x(q). For later reference notice that since {q n } converges we know that for any t (0, 1) there must be a N such that B(q n ) B(tp, (1+t)w) for all N > n. Thus, we may see {x n } as a sequence in a compact set. We will proceed in two steps. In a first step we will show that for each y B(q) there is a sequence {y n } such that y n B(q n ) and y n y. In a second step we will use this fact to show the desired result. So fix y B(q) and take any point ŷ such that pŷ < w (i.e. ŷ is in the interior of the set B(q)). Then p n ŷ < w n for n large enough. Now define (for large enough n) y n = t n y + (1 t n )ŷ where t n is the maximal number in [0, 1] such that y n B(q n ) (since ŷ is in the interior of B(q n ) for n large enough, such a t n must exist). We want to show that y n y. Clearly, this can be the case only if t n 1. Now since {t n } is a sequence in the compact set [0, 1] it must have a cluster point t (i.e. there must be a subsequence {t l } such that t l t). We will argue now that there cannot be any cluster point t < 1. If this were the case then we would have for l large enough p l y l = w l and thus lim p l (t l y + (1 t l )ŷ) w l = p(ty + (1 t)ŷ) w = 0. l But since pŷ < w this would imply py > w, which contradicts our starting assumption that y B(q). Hence, the only cluster point of our sequence is t = 1 and thus t n 1. We know now that for an arbitrarily chosen y B(q) there exists a sequence {y n } such that y n B(q n ) and y n y. Then by definition of the demand function we have that x n y n. Since the sequence {x n } is a sequence of elements of a compact set it must have a cluster point x (i.e. there must be a subsequence {x n k } such that x n k x ). p n k x n k w n k implies px w or equivalently x B(q). Since x n k y n k it follows by continuity of that x y. Since y was chosen arbitrarily it follows that we must have x y for all y B(q). Or put differently, any cluster point of {x n } must be at least as good as any y B(q). But since x(q) is by assumption the only such point in B(q) it follows that x n x(q). ii) First of all observe that the second utility function is simply a strictly monotonic transformation of the first one (ũ (x) = ln [u (x)]). Therefore both utility functions represent the same preferences and thus must give rise to identical demand functions. In order to calculate the demand for the Cobb-Douglas utility function, notice first that this function is strictly monotonic everywhere in in the interior of X = R L +. Moreover, for 1

2 any point x in the interior of the consumption set we have that u(x) > u(y) for all vectors y which have at least one component which is equal to zero. These two observations imply that if x solves the consumer s problem for the pair (p, w), then px = w and x l > 0 for all l. We also know that any solution must satisfy the Kuhn-Tucker necessary conditions. Using the previous observations and the fact that u(x)/ x l > 0 for all x in the interior of X, the K-T conditions reduce for some λ > 0. u(x ) = λp px = w It is straightforward to show that this set of equations has a unique solution (which therefore must be the unique solution of the maximization problem) which is given by x l (p, w) = α l I n α. n p l Notice that the demand for good l does not depend on the prices of any of the other goods. Moreover, the share of income which a consumer with Cobb-Douglas preferences spends on good l is a constant (and thus independent of both prices and income; p l x l (p, w)/i = (α l / n α n)). Problem 2: i) We have to show that linear homogeneity of u implies linear homogeneity of the demand in w. The statement of the problem contains assumptions regarding differentiability of u. We will prove the statement without using these assumptions. We just use strict quasi-concavity which implies that x(p, w) is a function. So let x = x (p, w). Notice that since px w it also follows that for any λ > 0, λx is affordable at (p, λw), that is p (λx) λw. Next, observe that if y B(p, λw), then y/λ B(p, w) (py λw p(y/λ) w). Since x is chosen at (p, w) it follows that u ( y λ) < u (x) for all y B(p, λw). By linear homogeneity we have ( y u u (x) u (y) < λu (x) u (y) < u (λx). λ) This means that λx = x (p, λw). As for the indirect utility function simply observe that v (p, λw) = u (x (p, λw)) = u (λx (p, w)) = λu (x (p, w)) = λv (p, w). In the preceding proof we did not at all use differentiability of the utility function. We will now also provide a proof which relies on differentiability arguments. In our argument we will refer to the Kuhn-Tucker (K-T) conditions. We know that if u is differentiable then x = x(p, w) implies that there is some α 0 such that u(x ) αp, x [ u(x ) αp] = 0 px w 0, α(px w) = 0. 2

3 Since u is strictly quasi-concave it follows that there cannot exist any x 0 such that u(x) = 0 = u(0) (why? if there were such an x then for any α (0, 1) we would have by strict quasi-concavity u(αx) > u(x) = u(0) = 0; by linear homogeinity instead we would have (1/α)u(αx) = u(x) > 0, a contradiction). This also means that we either have, u(x) > u(0) = 0 for all x 0 or u(0) > u(x) for all x 0 (if there were two non-zero bundles x and x such that u(x) > 0 and u(x ) < 0 then by continuity - which is implied by differentiability - there would have to exist some convex combination of x and x, x say, such that u(x ) = 0, which, as we have already seen, is impossible). In the second case 0 is the unique optimal solution for all (p, w) and hence we have 0 = x(p, w) = λx(p, w) = x(p, λw) = 0. In the first case instead we must have (by linear homogeneity) that the unique optimal solution lies on the budget line (we know that the optimal solution x satisfies u(x ) > 0; suppose px < w, then there exists some λ > 1 such that p(λx ) = w and u(λx ) = λu(x ) > u(x ), which contradicts optimality of x and thus we must have px = w). Moreover, in that case we must have that that at each x such that u(x) > 0 there must be some l such that u(x)/ x l > 0 (linear homogeneity implies u(x) = l x l( u(x)/ x l )). This implies that the K-T conditions can be satisfied only for a strictly positive Lagrange multiplier, i.e. α > 0. Next observe that by linear homogeneity we know that for all λ > 0 and all x R L + the equation u(λx) = λu(x) holds. Thus also the derivatives wrt x l of both sides of this equation must coincide: λ u(λx) x l = λ u(x) x l. Since λ > 0 this means that the partial derivatives of u are homogeneous of degree zero. But then if (x, α) satisfies the K-T conditions for the price-wealth pair (p, w), then (λx, α) must satisfy the K-T conditions for the price-wealth pair (p, λw): The conditions u(x )/ x l αp l, x l ( u(x )/ x l αp l ) = 0 and px = w are equivalent to the conditions u(λx )/ x l αp l, λx l ( u(λx )/ x l αp l ) = 0 and λpx = λw. Finally, the result that λx(p, w) = x(p, λw) follows by observing that the K-T conditions are not only necessary but also sufficient for an optimum given that the utility function is (strictly) quasi-concave and strictly increasing in some dimension. ii) In order to show that the utility function is linear homogeneous we first argue that the demand function must be linear homogeneous in in w. This is most easily done under the assumption that the indirect utility function is differentiable. Notice that λv(p, w) = v(p, λw) implies v(p, w) v(p, λw) λ = p l p l But then by Roy s Identity it follows that and v(p, w) w x l (p, λw) = v(p, λw)/ p l v(p, λw)/ w = λ v(p, w)/ p l v(p, w)/ w = v(p, λw). w = λx(p, w). 3

4 Next, observe that combining v (p, λw) = u (x (p, λw)) = u (λx (p, w)) with v (p, λw) = λv (p, w) = λu (x (p, w)) implies u (λx (p, w)) = λu (x (p, w)) That is, the condition u(λx) = λu(x) holds at least whenever x is an optimal choice for some (p, w). Finally observe that since u is strictly quasi-concave it follows that for every x there exists some (p, w) such that x = x(p, w). Problem 3: i) Consider two price-wealth pairs (p, w) and (p, w ) such that p 1 = 1, and assume that the respective optimal choises are x and x (remember that by strict convexity of preferences the optimal choices must be unique). We have to show that x = x = (x 1 + w, x 2,..., x L ), where w = w w (i.e. the extra income is entirely spent on commodity 1). We will do so by contraposition. So assume that x x. Then, x x and thus by quasi-linearty ˆx = x ( w, 0,..., 0) x ( w, 0,..., 0) = x. Now since pˆx = p(x ( w, 0,..., 0)) = px w w w = w ˆx it also follows that ˆx belongs to the budget B(p, w). But ˆx B(p, w) and ˆx x contradicts the assumption that x is the unique optimal choice from B(p, w) and so we can conclude that we must have x = x. Remark: Remember that quasi-linearity in commodity one of the preference implies that it is representable by a utility function of the form u(x) = x 1 + η(x 1 ). If we assume that η is differentiable then the above result (x 1 (p, w) is independent of w) may also be shown by using the FOC of the UMP. In order to see this observe that since u is linear in x 1 it follows that x(p, w) must satisfy Walras Law (the budget must always be exhausted). Moreover, linearity of u in x 1 also implies that the constraint optimization problem max (x 1,x 1) R R L 1 + x 1 + η (x 1 ) s.t. x 1 + p 1 x 1 = w is equivalent to (using the budget equation in order to eliminate x 1 from the objective function) The FOC for this problem max (x 1) R L 1 + w p 1 x 1 + η (x 1 ). η xl (x 1 ) p l 0 and x l (η xl (x 1 ) p l ) = 0, l = 2,..., L are clearly independent of w and so we can conclude that the demand x 1 (p, w) (which must satisfy the FOC) must be independent of w. 4

5 ii) We have argued before that the demand x(p, w) must satisfy Walras Law. Thus, if x 1 (p) is the (wealth independent) demand for the commodities l 2 we have that x 1 (p, w) = w p 1 x 1 (p). This implies that the indirect utility at (p, w) is given by v (w, p) = w p 1 x 1 (p) + η (x 1 (p)). Thus, if we define φ(p) = η(x 1 (p)) p 1 x 1 (p) we have v (w, p) = w + φ(p). iii) First of all, observe that strict quasi-concavity of the utility function u implies that the function η must be strictly quasi-concave too. In order to see this take x 2 and x 2 such that x 2 x 2 and η(x 2 ) η(x 2). We have to show that η(x 2 (λ)) > η(x 2 ) for all λ (0, 1), where of course x 2 (λ) = λx 2 + (1 λ)x 2. For any x 1 we have x 1 + η(x 2) x 1 + η(x 2 ). Thus by strict quasi-concavity of u we have λx 1 + (1 λ)x 1 + η(x 2 (λ)) = x 1 + η(x 2 (λ)) > x 1 + η(x 2 ) for all λ (0, 1) and so we are done. Now consider the UMP(p, w) max x 1 + η (x 2 ) s.t. x 1 + p 2 x 2 = w. (x 1,x 2) R 2 + This problem is equivalent to the problem UMP (p, w) given by max w p 2 x 2 + η (x 2 ) s.t. p 2 x 2 w. x 2 R + The non-negativity constraint on x 1 in UMP(p, w) is irrelevant if and only if in UMP (p, w) the constraint p 2 x 2 w is not strictly binding. That is, if and only if the relaxed problem UMP (p, w) defined as max w p 2 x 2 + η (x 2 ) x 2 R + is solved by a point ˆx 2 w/p 2. Since the objective function of this problem is strictly quasi-concave (we know that η(x 2 ) is strictly quasiconcave; you can easily verify that adding the linear term, p 2 x 2, does not affect strict quasi-concavity) we can conclude that ˆx 2 w/p 2 if and only if the objective function is non-increasing at w/p 2, i.e. iff x 2 > w/p 2 implies η(x 2 ) η(w/p 2 ) p 2 x 2 w. If the function η is differentiable then this condition can be expressed as η (w/p 2 ) p 2. Problem 4: In class we have discussed necessary and sufficient conditions for rationalizability. For the first two demand functions given in the text we will not verify these conditions in detail, because it is rather straightforward to directly guess preferences by which they are generated. In the case of the third demand function we will show instead that it violates WARP, which implies that it cannot be the outcome of preference maximization. 5

6 i) Inspecting the demand function x (p, w) = ( 2w 2p 1 + p 2, w 2p 1 + p 2 immediately reveals that the consumer likes to consume the two goods in the fixed proportion 2 : 1. But that simply means that he considers the two goods perfect complements and so we can conclude that his demand can be rationalized by the preference,, defined by x y if min{x 1, 2x 2 } min{y 1, 2y 2 }. ) ii) The demand function x (p, w) = ( ) w p 1, 0 ( ) 1, w p1 p 2 if w p 1 1 else may be obtained by maximizing the preference represented by the utility function u defined as { x1 if x 1 < 1 u(x) = 1 + x 2 if x 1 1. In order to see this just observe that as long as prices and wealth are such that B(p, w) does not contain any x with x 1 1, it is optimal for the consumer to spend his entire wealth on good 1. If instead the consumer can afford a bundle x such that x 1 1 then it is optimal for him to acquire exactly one unit of good 1 and to spend the rest of the income on good 2. iii) If x (p, w) is such that it satisfy the two equations p 2 x 1 (p, w) = p 1 x 2 (p, w) and p 1 x 1 (p, w) + p 2 x 2 (p, w) = w then we must have that p i x i (p, w) = p w. p2 2 This demand function clearly satisfies homogeneity of degree zero. Now consider the two price-wealth pairs (p, w) = (2, 1, 5) and (p, w ) = (1, 2, 5) and observe that x(p, w) = (2, 1) (1, 2) = x(p, w ). Since p x(p, w) = px(p, w ) = = 4 < 5 it follows that x(p, w, ) B(p, w ) and x(p, w ) B(p, w). This of course means that the demand function does not satisfy the WARP and so it violates one of the necessary conditions for rationalizability. Problem 5: i) Consider the EMP min px x R L + s.t. u (x) u 6

7 where p R L ++. Take an arbitrary x Y = {x : u(x) u} (given that the feasible set is non-empty there is always such an element) and consider the set Y = {x : u(x) u} {x : px px }. This set is non-empty (at least x belongs to it). Moreover, since both Y and {x : px px } are closed and {x : px px } is bounded, it follows that Y must be closed and bounded (and thus compact). But then, given that the expenditure is linear (and thus continuous) in x the problem min px s.t. x Y x R L + must have a solution. Denote this solution by x and observe that for all x Y Y we must have px px px. Thus x must also solve the original EMP. ii) Consider the solution set h(p, u) for the EMP(p, u). If h(p, u) is a singleton there is nothing to show. So assume that x, x h(p, u) and x x. We have to show that for all α [0, 1] we have x(α) = αx + (1 α)x h(p, u). First, observe that if is convex, then the utility function u( ) must be quasi-concave. But quasi-concavity of the utility function u( ) implies that x(α) must belong to the feasible set of EMP(p, u). Moreover, px(α) = α(px)+(1 α)px = αe(p, u)+(1 α)e(p, u) = e(p, u). Thus, for all α [0, 1] the bundle x(α) delivers the minimal expenditure and so we can conclude that x(α) h(p, u). If is strictly convex, then u( ) is strictly quasi-concave. Now assume - by contraposition - that h(p, u) is not a singleton. In particular, let again x, x h(p, u) and x(α) = αx+(1 α)x. Then, by strict quasi-concavity we have u(x(α)) > min{u(x), u(x )} u for all α (0, 1). If x(α) yields a strictly larger utility then by continuity there is a t < 1 such that u(tx(α)) u. But if tx(α) is feasible and tpx(α) = t(αpx + (1 α)px < px = px we obtain a contradiction with the assumption that x and x are optimal. So we can conclude that under the assumption of strictly convex preferences h(p, u) must be a singleton. iii) We have to show that if u(λx) = λu(x) for all x and all λ > 0 then x h(p, u) implies λx h(p, λu). So assume that x h(p, u). Then x Y (u) = {x : u(x ) u}. By linear homogeneity of the utility function we have that u(λx) = λu(x) λu. Thus, λx is in the feasible set of EMP(p, λu). Now suppose (by contraposition) that λx does not solve EMP(p, λu), i.e. assume that there is some x Y (λu) = {x : u(x) λu} such that px < pλx. Then since u(x ) λu we have (1/λ)u(x ) u, or equivalently, u(x /λ) u. Hence x /λ is in the feasible set of the EMP(p, u). But since px < pλx we have px /λ < px which contradicts our assumption that x is a solution of EMP(p, u). We can therefore conclude that if x h(p, u) then λx h(p, λu). Linear homogeneity of e(p, u) in u follows immediately from linear homogeneity of h(p, u) in u: If x h(p, u) then λx h(p, λu) and thus λe(p, u) = λpx = p(λx) = e(p, λu). Problem 6: Consider the situation depicted in the following figure. Under budget B the two individuals choose the bundles x 1 and x 2 respectively. The average of these two bundles is represented by the point x. Under budget B, which is obtained by a rotation of the original budget line around x the two chosen bundles are y 1 and y 2, respectively. Notice that we have 7

8 by construction that x B. Moreover observe that consumer two reduces his consumption of good 2 as we move from budget B to B, while consumer one keeps his consumption of good two constant. Thus, the average of the bundles chosen under B must lie somewhere on the new budget line below the level x 2. This in turn implies that ȳ B. But then x and ȳ could never be rationalized as the choices of a preference maximizing consumer since these choices violate the WARP. Now the question is, whether we could rationalize the choices of the two individuals. First of all observe that the choices of the two consumers do not violate the WARP. Consider now consumer 1 who varies only his consumption of good 1. Such a behavior is easily explained as the outcome of the maximization of a preference relation which is quasi-linear in good 1. The behavior of consumer two may be explained as the choices of an individual for whom good two is a strongly inferior good. x 2 B x 2 y 2 x ȳ x 1 y 1 B x 1 8

Utility Maximization Problem

Utility Maximization Problem Demand Theory Utility Maximization Problem Consumer maximizes his utility level by selecting a bundle x (where x can be a vector) subject to his budget constraint: max x 0 u(x) s. t. p x w Weierstrass

More information

Notes on Consumer Theory

Notes on Consumer Theory Notes on Consumer Theory Alejandro Saporiti Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) Consumer Theory 1 / 65 Consumer theory Reference: Jehle and Reny, Advanced Microeconomic Theory, 3rd ed., Pearson 2011: Ch. 1.

More information

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Piero Gottardi EUI Sept. 26, 2016 Piero Gottardi (EUI) Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Sept. 26, 2016 1 / 53 Choice Theory Set of alternatives: X, with generic elements x,

More information

Utility Maximization Problem. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2

Utility Maximization Problem. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2 Demand Theory Utility Maximization Problem Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2 Utility Maximization Problem Consumer maximizes his utility level by selecting a bundle x (where x can be a vector) subject to

More information

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 6, September 14 Outline 1 Applications of Envelope Theorem 2 Hicksian Demand 3 Duality 4 Connections between

More information

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018) Recitation #2 (August 1st, 2018) 1. [Checking properties of the Cobb-Douglas utility function.] Consider the utility function u(x) = n i=1 xα i i, where x denotes a vector of n different goods x R n +,

More information

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision: 0-0 1 Demand Lecture Last Revised: 2007-01-12 16:19:03-0800 (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision: 67) a demand correspondence is a special kind of choice correspondence where the set of alternatives is X = { x

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 2: Demand Theory

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 2: Demand Theory Advanced Microeconomic Theory Chapter 2: Demand Theory Outline Utility maximization problem (UMP) Walrasian demand and indirect utility function WARP and Walrasian demand Income and substitution effects

More information

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais Microeconomics Fall 2016 Indirect utility and expenditure Properties of consumer demand The indirect utility function The relationship among prices, incomes, and the maximised value of utility can be summarised

More information

Consumer Theory. Ichiro Obara. October 8, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, / 51

Consumer Theory. Ichiro Obara. October 8, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, / 51 Consumer Theory Ichiro Obara UCLA October 8, 2012 Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, 2012 1 / 51 Utility Maximization Utility Maximization Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, 2012 2 / 51 Utility

More information

CONSUMER DEMAND. Consumer Demand

CONSUMER DEMAND. Consumer Demand CONSUMER DEMAND KENNETH R. DRIESSEL Consumer Demand The most basic unit in microeconomics is the consumer. In this section we discuss the consumer optimization problem: The consumer has limited wealth

More information

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32 Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Tsun-Feng Chiang* *School of Economics, Henan University, Kaifeng, China November 1, 2015 Week 7: The Consumer

More information

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 4, September 7 Outline 1 Structural Properties of Utility Functions 1 Local Non Satiation 2 Convexity 3 Quasi-linearity

More information

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution) Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution) 1. Checking properties of the Cobb-Douglas utility function. Consider the utility function u(x) Y n i1 x i i ; where x denotes a vector of n di erent goods x 2 R n +,

More information

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts The notes for our course are based on: Mas-Colell, A., M.D. Whinston and J.R. Green (1995), Microeconomic Theory, New York and Oxford: Oxford

More information

u(x) s.t. px w x 0 Denote the solution to this problem by ˆx(p, x). In order to obtain ˆx we may simply solve the standard problem max x 0

u(x) s.t. px w x 0 Denote the solution to this problem by ˆx(p, x). In order to obtain ˆx we may simply solve the standard problem max x 0 Bocconi University PhD in Economics - Microeconomics I Prof M Messner Probem Set 4 - Soution Probem : If an individua has an endowment instead of a monetary income his weath depends on price eves In particuar,

More information

PS4-Solution. Mehrdad Esfahani. Fall Arizona State University. Question 1 Question 2 Question 3 Question 4 Question 5

PS4-Solution. Mehrdad Esfahani. Fall Arizona State University. Question 1 Question 2 Question 3 Question 4 Question 5 PS4-Solution Mehrdad Esfahani Arizona State University Fall 2016 Mehrdad Esfahani PS4-Solution 1 / 13 Part d Part e Question 1 Choose some 1 k l and fix the level of consumption of the goods index by i

More information

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply) Leonardo Felli 30 October, 2002 Microeconomics II Lecture 4 Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply) Define M = m + p ω to be the endowment of the consumer. The Marshallian

More information

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018 EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 018 Show all your work clearly and make sure you justify all your answers. NAME 1. Consider the market for smart pencil in which only one firm (Superapiz) enjoys a

More information

Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1

Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1 Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1 Session: 15 Aug 2015 (Mon), 10:00am 1:00pm I. Optimization with

More information

Microeconomics I Fall 2007 Prof. I. Hafalir

Microeconomics I Fall 2007 Prof. I. Hafalir Microeconomics I Fall 2007 Prof. I. Hafalir Chris Almost Contents Contents 1 1 Demand Theory 2 1.1 Preference relations............................. 2 1.2 Utility functions................................

More information

Preferences and Utility

Preferences and Utility Preferences and Utility How can we formally describe an individual s preference for different amounts of a good? How can we represent his preference for a particular list of goods (a bundle) over another?

More information

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ. 805 Winter 00 Prof. James Peck Homework Set Questions and Answers. Consider the following pure exchange economy with two consumers and two goods.

More information

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions Lecture 2, 1 September Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Outline 1 Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference 2 Equivalence between Axioms and Rationalizable Choices. 3 An Application:

More information

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A December, 2016, Ted Bergstrom, UCSB I asked students to try to answer any 7 of the 8 questions. I intended the exam to have some relatively easy parts and

More information

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018 NAME: Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018 Instructions. Show all your work clearly and make sure you justify all your answers. 1. Question 1 [10 Points]. Discuss and provide examples of

More information

CHAPTER 1-2: SHADOW PRICES

CHAPTER 1-2: SHADOW PRICES Essential Microeconomics -- CHAPTER -: SHADOW PRICES An intuitive approach: profit maimizing firm with a fied supply of an input Shadow prices 5 Concave maimization problem 7 Constraint qualifications

More information

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice Economics 101 Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice 1 Uncle Léon The canonical model of exchange in economics is sometimes referred to as the Walrasian Model, after the early economist Léon

More information

Final Exam - Math Camp August 27, 2014

Final Exam - Math Camp August 27, 2014 Final Exam - Math Camp August 27, 2014 You will have three hours to complete this exam. Please write your solution to question one in blue book 1 and your solutions to the subsequent questions in blue

More information

Competitive Consumer Demand 1

Competitive Consumer Demand 1 John Nachbar Washington University May 7, 2017 1 Introduction. Competitive Consumer Demand 1 These notes sketch out the basic elements of competitive demand theory. The main result is the Slutsky Decomposition

More information

1 General Equilibrium

1 General Equilibrium 1 General Equilibrium 1.1 Pure Exchange Economy goods, consumers agent : preferences < or utility : R + R initial endowments, R + consumption bundle, =( 1 ) R + Definition 1 An allocation, =( 1 ) is feasible

More information

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems The Fundamental Welfare Theorems The so-called Fundamental Welfare Theorems of Economics tell us about the relation between market equilibrium and Pareto efficiency. The First Welfare Theorem: Every Walrasian

More information

On the (Non-)Differentiability of the Optimal Value Function When the Optimal Solution Is Unique

On the (Non-)Differentiability of the Optimal Value Function When the Optimal Solution Is Unique On the (Non-)Differentiability of the Optimal Value Function When the Optimal Solution Is Unique Daisuke Oyama Faculty of Economics, University of Tokyo Hongo, Bunkyo-ku, Tokyo 113-0033, Japan oyama@e.u-tokyo.ac.jp

More information

Properties of Walrasian Demand

Properties of Walrasian Demand Properties of Walrasian Demand Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 5, September 12 Problem Set 2 is due in Kelly s mailbox by 5pm today Outline 1 Properties of Walrasian Demand 2 Indirect Utility Function 3 Envelope

More information

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata General Equilibrium Equilibrium in Consumption GE begins (1/3) 2-Individual/ 2-good Exchange economy (No production, no transaction costs, full information..) Endowment (Nature): e Private property/ NO

More information

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7 Mathematical Foundations -- Constrained Optimization Constrained Optimization An intuitive approach First Order Conditions (FOC) 7 Constraint qualifications 9 Formal statement of the FOC for a maximum

More information

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 8, September 21 Outline 1 Generalized Axiom of Revealed Preferences 2 Afriat s Theorem 3 Production Sets and Production Functions 4 Profits

More information

Second Welfare Theorem

Second Welfare Theorem Second Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2015 Lecture 18, November 2 Outline 1 Second Welfare Theorem From Last Class We want to state a prove a theorem that says that any Pareto optimal allocation is (part

More information

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2)

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2) Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2) Tsun-Feng Chiang *School of Economics, Henan University, Kaifeng, China November 15, 2015 Microeconomic Theory Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory

More information

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 2

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 2 EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 2 Leonardo Felli 32L.LG.04 6 October, 2017 Properties of the Profit Function Recall the following property of the profit function π(p, w) = max x p f (x)

More information

Microeconomic Theory: Lecture 2 Choice Theory and Consumer Demand

Microeconomic Theory: Lecture 2 Choice Theory and Consumer Demand Microeconomic Theory: Lecture 2 Choice Theory and Consumer Demand Summer Semester, 2014 De nitions and Axioms Binary Relations I Examples: taller than, friend of, loves, hates, etc. I Abstract formulation:

More information

Homework 3 Suggested Answers

Homework 3 Suggested Answers Homework 3 Suggested Answers Answers from Simon and Blume are on the back of the book. Answers to questions from Dixit s book: 2.1. We are to solve the following budget problem, where α, β, p, q, I are

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Welfare measures and aggregation October 30, 2012 The plan: 1 Welfare measures 2 Example: 1 Our consumer has initial wealth w and is facing the initial set of market prices p 0. 2 Now he is faced with

More information

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP Prof. Olivier Bochet Room A.34 Phone 3 63 476 E-mail olivier.bochet@vwi.unibe.ch Webpage http//sta.vwi.unibe.ch/bochet Advanced Microeconomics Fall 2 Lecture Note Choice-Based Approach Price e ects, Wealth

More information

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction Microeconomic Theory -- Introduction. Introduction. Profit maximizing firm with monopoly power 6 3. General results on maximizing with two variables 8 4. Model of a private ownership economy 5. Consumer

More information

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3 Microeconomics II MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3 Problem 1 Consider an economy 1 1, with one firm (or technology and one consumer (firm owner, as in the textbook (MWG section 15.C. The set of

More information

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016 Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam # - Answer key Fall 06. [Checking properties of preference relations]. Consider the following preference relation de ned in the positive

More information

1.3 The Indirect Utility Function

1.3 The Indirect Utility Function 1.2 Utility Maximization Problem (UMP) (MWG 2.D, 2.E; Kreps 2.2) max u (x) s.t. p.x w and x 0 hx Xi For a cts preference relation represented by a cts utility fn, u ( ): 1. The UMP has at least one solution

More information

Mathematical Preliminaries for Microeconomics: Exercises

Mathematical Preliminaries for Microeconomics: Exercises Mathematical Preliminaries for Microeconomics: Exercises Igor Letina 1 Universität Zürich Fall 2013 1 Based on exercises by Dennis Gärtner, Andreas Hefti and Nick Netzer. How to prove A B Direct proof

More information

Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics

Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Dirk Bergemann, Spring 2012 Week of 1/29-2/4 1 Lecture 7: Expenditure Minimization Instead of maximizing utility subject to a given income we can also minimize expenditure

More information

Rice University. Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall ECON 501: Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Part A

Rice University. Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall ECON 501: Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Part A Rice University Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall 006 ECON 50: Advanced Microeconomic Theory Part A. Consider the following expenditure function. e (p ; p ; p 3 ; u) = (p + p ) u + p 3 State

More information

3. Neoclassical Demand Theory. 3.1 Preferences

3. Neoclassical Demand Theory. 3.1 Preferences EC 701, Fall 2005, Microeconomic Theory September 28, 2005 page 81 3. Neoclassical Demand Theory 3.1 Preferences Not all preferences can be described by utility functions. This is inconvenient. We make

More information

Econ Slides from Lecture 14

Econ Slides from Lecture 14 Econ 205 Sobel Econ 205 - Slides from Lecture 14 Joel Sobel September 10, 2010 Theorem ( Lagrange Multipliers ) Theorem If x solves max f (x) subject to G(x) = 0 then there exists λ such that Df (x ) =

More information

Introductory Microeconomics

Introductory Microeconomics Prof. Wolfram Elsner Faculty of Business Studies and Economics iino Institute of Institutional and Innovation Economics Introductory Microeconomics The Ideal Neoclassical Market and General Equilibrium

More information

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS Jan Werner University of Minnesota FALL SEMESTER 2017 1 PART I: Producer Theory 1. Production Set Production set is a subset Y of commodity space IR

More information

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 7, September 19 Problem Set 3 is due in Kelly s mailbox by 5pm today Outline 1 Comparative Statics Without Calculus 2 Supermodularity

More information

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009 Department of Agricultural Economics PhD Qualifier Examination May 009 Instructions: The exam consists of six questions. You must answer all questions. If you need an assumption to complete a question,

More information

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics Solutions 1. Consider a pure exchange economy with two goods, h = 1,, and two consumers, i =1,, with utility functions u 1 and u respectively, and total endowment, e = (e

More information

Chapter 1 Consumer Theory Part II

Chapter 1 Consumer Theory Part II Chapter 1 Consumer Theory Part II Economics 5113 Microeconomic Theory Kam Yu Winter 2018 Outline 1 Introduction to Duality Theory Indirect Utility and Expenditure Functions Ordinary and Compensated Demand

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium Advanced Microeconomic Theory Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium Outline Partial Equilibrium Analysis General Equilibrium Analysis Comparative Statics Welfare Analysis Advanced Microeconomic Theory

More information

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 19, November 7 Outline 1 Welfare Theorems in the differentiable case. 2 Aggregate excess

More information

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability Chapter 7 Nathan Smooha Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability 7.1 Introduction Brouwer s Fixed Point Theorem. Let X be a non-empty, compact, and convex subset of R m. If

More information

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais Microeconomics Fall 2016 Primitive notions There are four building blocks in any model of consumer choice. They are the consumption set, the feasible set, the preference relation, and the behavioural assumption.

More information

Solutions to selected exercises from Jehle and Reny (2001): Advanced Microeconomic Theory

Solutions to selected exercises from Jehle and Reny (2001): Advanced Microeconomic Theory Solutions to selected exercises from Jehle and Reny (001): Advanced Microeconomic Theory Thomas Herzfeld September 010 Contents 1 Mathematical Appendix 1.1 Chapter A1..................................

More information

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand KC Border Revised Fall 2011; Winter 2017 Preferences For the purposes of this note, a preference relation

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Homework #2

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Homework #2 Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Homework #2 0..4 Prove that Hicksian demands are homogeneous of degree 0 in prices. We use the relationship between Hicksian and Marshallian demands: x h i

More information

First Welfare Theorem

First Welfare Theorem First Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 17, October 31 Outline 1 First Welfare Theorem 2 Preliminaries to Second Welfare Theorem Past Definitions A feasible allocation (ˆx, ŷ) is Pareto optimal

More information

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem Natalia Lazzati Mathematics for Economics (Part I) Note 8: Nonlinear Programming - The Kuhn-Tucker Problem Note 8 is based on de la Fuente (2000, Ch. 7) and Simon and Blume (1994, Ch. 18 and 19). The Kuhn-Tucker

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6 Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO April 10, 017 Administrative Stuff Homework # is due at the end of class. I will post the solutions on the website later today. The midterm

More information

Microeconomic Analysis

Microeconomic Analysis Microeconomic Analysis Seminar 1 Marco Pelliccia (mp63@soas.ac.uk, Room 474) SOAS, 2014 Basics of Preference Relations Assume that our consumer chooses among L commodities and that the commodity space

More information

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice http://selod.ensae.net/m1 Paris School of Economics (selod@ens.fr) September 27, 2007 Notations Consider an individual (agent) facing a choice set X. Definition (Choice set, "Consumption set") X is a set

More information

= 2 = 1.5. Figure 4.1: WARP violated

= 2 = 1.5. Figure 4.1: WARP violated Chapter 4 The Consumer Exercise 4.1 You observe a consumer in two situations: with an income of $100 he buys 5 units of good 1 at a price of $10 per unit and 10 units of good 2 at a price of $5 per unit.

More information

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Chiaki Hara April 5, 2004 Abstract We give a theorem on the existence of an equilibrium price vector for an excess

More information

Generalized Convexity in Economics

Generalized Convexity in Economics Generalized Convexity in Economics J.E. Martínez-Legaz Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona, Spain 2nd Summer School: Generalized Convexity Analysis Introduction to Theory and Applications JULY 19, 2008 KAOHSIUNG

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Midterm Exam

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Midterm Exam Advanced Microeconomic Analsis Solutions to Midterm Exam Q1. (0 pts) An individual consumes two goods x 1 x and his utilit function is: u(x 1 x ) = [min(x 1 + x x 1 + x )] (a) Draw some indifference curves

More information

Econ 5150: Applied Econometrics Empirical Demand Analysis. Sung Y. Park CUHK

Econ 5150: Applied Econometrics Empirical Demand Analysis. Sung Y. Park CUHK Econ 5150: Applied Econometrics Empirical Analysis Sung Y. Park CUHK Marshallian demand Under some mild regularity conditions on preferences the preference relation x ર z ( the bundle x us weakly preferred

More information

DECISIONS AND GAMES. PART I

DECISIONS AND GAMES. PART I DECISIONS AND GAMES. PART I 1. Preference and choice 2. Demand theory 3. Uncertainty 4. Intertemporal decision making 5. Behavioral decision theory DECISIONS AND GAMES. PART II 6. Static Games of complete

More information

Individual decision-making under certainty

Individual decision-making under certainty Individual decision-making under certainty Objects of inquiry Our study begins with individual decision-making under certainty Items of interest include: Feasible set Objective function (Feasible set R)

More information

EC /11. Math for Microeconomics September Course, Part II Problem Set 1 with Solutions. a11 a 12. x 2

EC /11. Math for Microeconomics September Course, Part II Problem Set 1 with Solutions. a11 a 12. x 2 LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS Professor Leonardo Felli Department of Economics S.478; x7525 EC400 2010/11 Math for Microeconomics September Course, Part II Problem Set 1 with Solutions 1. Show that the general

More information

ECON 255 Introduction to Mathematical Economics

ECON 255 Introduction to Mathematical Economics Page 1 of 5 FINAL EXAMINATION Winter 2017 Introduction to Mathematical Economics April 20, 2017 TIME ALLOWED: 3 HOURS NUMBER IN THE LIST: STUDENT NUMBER: NAME: SIGNATURE: INSTRUCTIONS 1. This examination

More information

1 Preference and choice

1 Preference and choice 1 Preference and choice 1.1 Preference relations is a binary relation on the set of alternatives X. Suppose we have two alternatives x, y X, x y x is at least as good as y. : the strict preference x y

More information

Tutorial 3: Optimisation

Tutorial 3: Optimisation Tutorial : Optimisation ECO411F 011 1. Find and classify the extrema of the cubic cost function C = C (Q) = Q 5Q +.. Find and classify the extreme values of the following functions (a) y = x 1 + x x 1x

More information

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume Duality for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume Headwords: CONVEXITY, DUALITY, LAGRANGE MULTIPLIERS, PARETO EFFICIENCY, QUASI-CONCAVITY 1 Introduction The word duality is

More information

Midterm Examination: Economics 210A October 2011

Midterm Examination: Economics 210A October 2011 Midterm Examination: Economics 210A October 2011 The exam has 6 questions. Answer as many as you can. Good luck. 1) A) Must every quasi-concave function must be concave? If so, prove it. If not, provide

More information

Problem 2: ii) Completeness of implies that for any x X we have x x and thus x x. Thus x I(x).

Problem 2: ii) Completeness of implies that for any x X we have x x and thus x x. Thus x I(x). Bocconi University PhD in Economics - Microeconomics I Prof. M. Messner Problem Set 1 - Solution Problem 1: Suppose that x y and y z but not x z. Then, z x. Together with y z this implies (by transitivity)

More information

Introduction to General Equilibrium

Introduction to General Equilibrium Introduction to General Equilibrium Juan Manuel Puerta November 6, 2009 Introduction So far we discussed markets in isolation. We studied the quantities and welfare that results under different assumptions

More information

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions.

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions. Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 3: Optimization - interior optima 1 Session: 11-12 Aug 2015 (Thu/Fri) 10:00am 1:00pm I. Optimization: introduction Decision-makers (e.g. consumers,

More information

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti Demand Theory Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti Aix-Marseille Université Faculté d Economie et Gestion Aix-Marseille School of Economics October 5, 2018 Table of

More information

Applications I: consumer theory

Applications I: consumer theory Applications I: consumer theory Lecture note 8 Outline 1. Preferences to utility 2. Utility to demand 3. Fully worked example 1 From preferences to utility The preference ordering We start by assuming

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Welfare measures and aggregation October 17, 2010 The plan: 1 Welfare measures 2 Example: 1 Our consumer has initial wealth w and is facing the initial set of market prices p 0. 2 Now he is faced with

More information

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5 EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5 Leonardo Felli 32L.LG.04 27 October, 207 Pareto Efficient Allocation Recall the following result: Result An allocation x is Pareto-efficient if and only

More information

Maximum Value Functions and the Envelope Theorem

Maximum Value Functions and the Envelope Theorem Lecture Notes for ECON 40 Kevin Wainwright Maximum Value Functions and the Envelope Theorem A maximum (or minimum) value function is an objective function where the choice variables have been assigned

More information

Professor: Alan G. Isaac These notes are very rough. Suggestions welcome. Samuelson (1938, p.71) introduced revealed preference theory hoping

Professor: Alan G. Isaac These notes are very rough. Suggestions welcome. Samuelson (1938, p.71) introduced revealed preference theory hoping 19.713 Professor: Alan G. Isaac These notes are very rough. Suggestions welcome. Samuelson (1938, p.71) introduced revealed preference theory hoping to liberate the theory of consumer behavior from any

More information

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis 1 Convex sets Both convex sets and functions have general importance in economic theory, not only in optimization. Given two points x; y 2 R n and 2 [0; 1]; the weighted

More information

Economics th April 2011

Economics th April 2011 Economics 401 8th April 2011 Instructions: Answer 7 of the following 9 questions. All questions are of equal weight. Indicate clearly on the first page which questions you want marked. 1. Answer both parts.

More information

Finite Dimensional Optimization Part I: The KKT Theorem 1

Finite Dimensional Optimization Part I: The KKT Theorem 1 John Nachbar Washington University March 26, 2018 1 Introduction Finite Dimensional Optimization Part I: The KKT Theorem 1 These notes characterize maxima and minima in terms of first derivatives. I focus

More information

ON BEHAVIORAL COMPLEMENTARITY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

ON BEHAVIORAL COMPLEMENTARITY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS ON BEHAVIORAL COMPLEMENTARITY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS CHRISTOPHER P. CHAMBERS, FEDERICO ECHENIQUE, AND ERAN SHMAYA Abstract. We study the behavioral definition of complementary goods: if the price of one

More information

Notes on General Equilibrium

Notes on General Equilibrium Notes on General Equilibrium Alejandro Saporiti Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 1 / 42 General equilibrium Reference: Jehle and Reny, Advanced Microeconomic Theory, 3rd ed., Pearson

More information

Econ 508-A FINITE DIMENSIONAL OPTIMIZATION - NECESSARY CONDITIONS. Carmen Astorne-Figari Washington University in St. Louis.

Econ 508-A FINITE DIMENSIONAL OPTIMIZATION - NECESSARY CONDITIONS. Carmen Astorne-Figari Washington University in St. Louis. Econ 508-A FINITE DIMENSIONAL OPTIMIZATION - NECESSARY CONDITIONS Carmen Astorne-Figari Washington University in St. Louis August 12, 2010 INTRODUCTION General form of an optimization problem: max x f

More information