ON ARTHUR FINE'S INTERPRETATION QUANTUM MECHANICS

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "ON ARTHUR FINE'S INTERPRETATION QUANTUM MECHANICS"

Transcription

1 ALLEN STAIRS ON ARTHUR FINE'S INTERPRETATION QUANTUM MECHANICS OF The no-hidden-variable proofs of von Neumann, Jauch and Piron and Kochen and Specker have left many workers in the foundations of quantum mechanics unconvinced. Nonetheless, it is probably fair to say that most are convinced by the Bell-Wigner argument that local hidden variables are impossible. A notable exception is Arthur Fine, who insists that the Bell-Wigner result has nothing to do with locality, and who defends a point of view which, while not described as a hidden variable theory, claims that quantum mechanics can be understood as "... an essentially statistical account of a well-defined and localized domain. ''~ By "well-defined", Fine means that every magnitude has a definite value and that classical logic is preserved. In this paper, I attempt to throw cold water on Fine's hopes for a classical understanding of quantum theory by focussing on his treatment of the problem of joint distributions. I will begin with an earlier paper, 'Probability and the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics '2, which provides important background, and then proceed to 'On the Completeness of Quantum Mechanics' in which the above thesis is defended. The main point of the earlier paper is to argue that no violations of our ordinary concepts of probability and logic are involved in the fact that quantum mechanics does not provide joint distributions for every set of magnitudes. The programme of that paper involves introducing a family L of propositions each of the form quantity Q is confined to Borel set A (abbreviated as o[a]) and forming the language/s generated by L by the usual closure under ( v, ^ - ). Fine then attempts to establish the following two claims. I. /S admits of bivalent valuations consistent with QM. II. /S-plus-valuations admits of just those probability assignements that QM does in fact make. (pp ) Synthese 42 (1979) /79] $ Copyright 1979 by D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht, Holland, and Boston, U.S.A.

2 92 ALLEN STAIRS The bivalent valuations are restricted by the following 'regularity requirements'. (a) To each state ~b there corresponds a function ~,+ from i onto {0,1} (b) If P~[A] = 1, then v~[a]= 1 [where P~[A] is the QM probability assigned to Q[A] by ~b] (c) If v~[a] = 1 and A---< B, then v~[b] = 1 (d) If ~. is the complement of A, the v~[a] = 1 only if v~[a] = 0. (e) If P~ is the operator projecting on the closed subspace M then v~[{l}] = 1 iff ~b E M. (p.18) (Condition (e) results from Fine's interpretation of v~[{1}] = 1 as asserting that the state lies in M.) These five requirements do not guarantee that every magnitude has a definite value, and indeed, Fine considers valuations such that for some quantities Q, every proposition Q[A], is false. These will not concern us here, however. Fine also considers valuations satisfying the following condition. (f) To every quantity Q and state ~b there corresponds some real number x such that v~[{x}] = 1. Valuations satisfying (f) are called atomic valuations. Fine maintains that such valuations are possible without contradicting the requirements of the theory. Although it would be worth considering his defence of this claim, we shall not do so here, since our main concern is with probability. Fine notes that if magnitudes are represented as random variables over a common phase space, there will be a joint distribution for each pair of magnitudes. He concludes, therefore, that the phase space is too restrictive a setting for quantum theory and proposes instead the following approach. Simply introduce for each state ~b and quantity Q a probability measure P~ on the Borel sets... It may happen that certain quantities are interpretable as compounds of other quantities. In such cases this way of using probability will assign probability to the corresponding compound events. When this happens, of course, it will be a result of the theory. It will not follow from some extra-theoretical prescription for how to use

3 ON FINE ON QM 93 probability; for example, the prescription that quantities be construed as random variables over a common phase space. (p. 13) It is important to note that, having introduced this general setting for probability and having defined a family of atomic valuations, Fine does not simply assume that "/7,-plus-valuations admits of just those probability assignments that QM does in fact make." Rather, he attempts to justify this claim, beginning with the following obser- vations: If one has in mind the intuitive picture of a valuation as specifying a possible state of the world, then one might try to connect the valuations with probability by requiring that the probability (in $) for an event (= proposition) be measured by the proportion of those states of the world in which the event occurs (i.e. of those valuations v* in which the proposition is true). Since in general there will be too many states to measure by simple proportions, this idea amounts to forming a classical probability space out of the valuations themselves and then transferring the measure on this space to the quantum mechanical probability for the event in question. (pp ) Fine does not regard this programme as feasible for all quantities, since it runs into difficulties with condition (e) on admissible valuations. 3 His solution is to treat projection operators and non-projection operators differently. The probabilities for the former are (roughly speaking) to be obtained directly from Hilbert space, but the latter are associated with a classical probability space. Specifically for the non-idempotents, let V * be the set of valuations associated with the state ~b and F* be the smallest o--algebra of subsets of V s. For Q non-idempotent, define P~{v*Iv~[A] = l} = P~[A] where P(~[A] is the quantum mechanical probability in 4) of Q[A]. p4, can be extended in a variety of ways to a measure on all of F ~. It would seem to be a consequence of this approach that joint distributions could be introduced for arbitrary pairs of Q~, Q: of nonidempotent magnitudes. One would simply use the following rule P(~I,Q2[AxB] = e~[{v~:v~l[a] = v~:b = 1}] However, this would yield more joint distributions than quantum mechanics itself provides. Consequently, Fine requires a principle

4 94 ALLEN STAIRS which will distinguish between those functions P~,o2 which represent genuine quantum mechanical joint distributions and those which do not. Therefore, Fine introduces the following constraint. Let [: RXR~be a Borel function. In order that P~.Q2 be interpretable as a joint distribution in QM we require that there exist a quantity f(q~, Qz) such that for all states 4~ PI(Q,.Q2)[ A] = P~,, Q2[/-!(A)] (jd) (p. 30) A pair of Q1, Q2 quantum mechanical magnitudes will only satisfy jd if Q~ commutes with Q2. Therefore in the context of the phase space, jd instructs us to interpret P~,o2 as a joint distribution only when Q1 and Q2 represent magnitudes where associated operators commute. What Fine did not realize at the time of writing the earlier paper is that there is no measure on the phase space which will reproduce the correct joint distributions even for commuting quantities. 3 It was this realization which lead him to the programme of 'On the Completeness of Quantum Theory'. The aim of the later paper is... to make simultaneous assignments of values to all the quantities of the theory in satisfaction of the" Spectrum Rule. Completeness requires... that these values be the very ones found in measurement, and good sense then directs that they should be distributed according to the probabilities of the theory... (p. 281) Hidden variable theories, as Fine characterizes them, attempt to achieve this aim by introducing a classical phase space and representing quantities as random varibles on the space. A natural constraint on hidden variable theories would seem to be that for all commuting A,B (JD) P~,B = P~A],[B] where the left side is the quantum mechanical joint distribution of A and B and the right side is the phase space joint distribution of the corresponding random variables.the case of two spin-1/2 particles in the singlet state, considered by Bell, shows that JD cannot be satisfied in the phase space (and hence that jd, understood as above, cannot either). Label the two particles S and S'. Let {si} be the spin magnitudes of S and {S~} be the the spin magnitudes of S'. Each Si com-

5 ON FINE ON QM 95 mutes with each SI, and so for all such pairs, the QM joint distribution is well-defined. The Bell-Wigner argument shows that there is a small finite set of such magnitudes whose quantum mechanical joint distributions cannot be reproduced on a phase space. Fine comments on this situation and what he says is interesting. The failure of JD shows...that we cannot fulfill both of these aims. We cannot construe the measured values as merely revealing what is there all along and have the statistics of what is there all along coincide with the probabilities of the theory. (p. 280) In spite of the impression which this passage creates however, Fine is not saying that it is impossible to conceive of quantum mechanical systems as having definite values, revealed by measurement and, roughly speaking, occurring with frequencies corresponding to the quantum mechanical probabilities. As Fine sees it, the problem is really that... the pairs of values that turn up in simultaneous measurements of commuting observables do not distribute according to phase space rules; they are distributed according to the different rules of quantum theory. (p. 280, emphasis mine) In other words, Fine sees the failure of JD merely as indicating a problem with the way in which hidden variable theories represent probabilities (i.e. by means of a phase space). Fine's solution is to drop the phase space and substitute the following approach. For each state ~b, let V ~ be the set of all functions x which assign each magnitude an eigenvalue with non-zero probability. Let Q(x) (x E V 6) be the value which x assigns to Q. To accommodate the statistics, associate with each Q a probability space in the following manner. Let and and V'~(Q) = {Q(x)lx E V 4'} B~ = the Borel subsets of V*(Q) P~ = the probability measure which th associates with Q according to quantum theory. This gives us for each Q a classical probability space S~ = < V*(Q),

6 96 ALLEN STAIRS B~, P~ >. Initially, then, no joint distributions are derivable. They are introduced only when the magnitudes in question commute, thus satisfying jd. If A and B commute, their joint distribution will be a measure on the Borel subsets of V*(A)xV~(B), corresponding to the appropriate quantum mechanical joint distribution. Formally, this approach solves all the problems. The derivation of the Bell-Wigner result involves expressions for the probabilities of simultaneous values of non-commuting quantities. Since these probabilities are not defined in the approach just described, the Bell-Wigner result seems to be circumvented. However, there is no interesting mathematical difference between this way of doing things and the method of representing probabilities in the earlier paper, according to which one simply introduces for each quantity a probability measure on B(R). In that paper, Fine took considerable pains to attempt a justification of the claim that the valuations and probabilities fit together in a suitable way. In the later paper no such attempt is made. What I will now argue is that no satisfactory justification could be given. The best way to see this is to begin with the situation which Wigner 4 considers in his reconstruction of Bell. Let S and S ~ be a pair of systems in the singlet state as above. Let A, B, C be three directions in physical space and, by abuse of notation, let A, B, C be the corresponding S-spin magnitudes and A ~, B ~, C ~ be the corresponding S~-spin magnitudes. For the sake of definiteness, let A, B, C be coplanar directions with OAc = 120, 0AB = OBC = 60 - On Wigner's view the assumption of locality amounts to associating each local spin magnitude, which is a non-maximal magnitude for the composite system represented by H2@H 2, with a unique random variable on the phase space, rather than with a different representative for each maximal magnitude with which it is associated. The joint event 'M = x and N ~ = y' is then simply the intersection of the phase space element which represents 'M = x' and that which represents 'N ~ = y', and this element is an element in the sub-algebra corresponding to M(~)N ~. Fine denies that this has anything to do with locality (for reasons which we will not discuss here) and he rejects the phase space. He does nonetheless associate each of the local magnitudes with a unique 'statistical variable' and thus accepts what is really the crucial step in

7 ON FINE ON QM 97 Wigner's argument. A further requirement which Fine could hardly fail to accept is that the statistics be confirmable in principle. Since all experiments involve observations of only a finite number of systems, however, this means that Fine must allow that the statistics of a finite set of magnitudes be realizable to an arbitrary degree of precision in some possible finite ensemble. Indeed, if this were not possible, then the claim that the statistics are nonetheless correct would seem not even to make sense, let alone be confirmable. Let us inquire, then, if this is possible in the case under consideration. The problem can be seen more clearly if we first ask what it would mean for the statistics to be realized exactly in a finite ensemble. We note that each of the six local magnitudes has two values which we will denote by + and -. Let mr (m~) represent 'M takes value + (-)' and let m~(m~) represent 'M 1 takes value + (-)'. The statistics of the singlet state (which we will denote by ~) are such that for any pair M, M ~ of spin magnitudes corresponding to a single direction, (1) P.(m~ & m~-) = P.(m~ & me) = 0 (2) P.(m~- & m~)= P~,(m~ &m~) = 1/2 In general for M, N ~ (3) and P.(m~ & n~) = P.(m~ & n~) = ½sin E 10MN (4) P.(m~ & n~) = P.(m? & n~) = ~cos 2 10MN For the directions A, B, C, it follows that (5) P,v(a~ & c~) = ½sin260 = 3/8 (6) P.(a~- & 53) = P(b~ & c~) = 1/8 The question which Fine must answer, then, is whether there could exist a finite ensemble of pairs of particles in the singlet state, sucb that (i) each particle has a definite value for spin in each direction A. B, C, (ii) in which no pair consists of two particles with the same value of spin in a single direction, and (iii) in which the probabilities of (5) and (6) are matched exactly by the proportions of pairs in the

8 98 ALLEN STAIRS ensemble which fit the relevant descriptions. In a word, the answer is ~'No '~" To see this, we simply apply an argument virtually identical in ~ structure to Wigner's. If the probabilities of were realized exactly in a finite ensemble, no pair would satisfy nor (mt & mf) (mt & md Let 'N(mT & n~-)' denote the number of pairs of which '(mt & n~)' is true, and let '(+ + - ;- + +)' stand for '(at & btc7 & a~ & b~ & c~)' and so on. From what has just been said, it follows that an expression such as (+ + + ; + + +) is not satisfied by any pair in the ensemble. Therefore (7) N(aT&c~)=N(+ +-;--+)+N(+--;- + +) (8) N(aT & b~-) = N(+ - + ;- + -)+N(+ - - ;- + +) (9) N(bt & c~)=n(+ + -;- + +)+N(- + -;+ - +) Hence, using 'prop? as shorthand for 'proportion of pairs such that..' we have (10) prop(at & c~)-<prop(at & b~)+ prop(b~ & c~-) for any finite ensemble which realizes the statistics exactly. But in the case considered, this is impossible, since 3/8 ~ 1/8 + 1/8. The fact thatqm does not provide a distribution for such expressions as (at & b;... c~) is irrelevant. If quantum mechanical ensembles were as Fine describes them, then in any finite ensemble of pairs in the singlet state there must be a definite number of pairs of which such an expression is true. All that the failure of the existence of a th6oretical distribution could mean is that in any particular case, one could have no

9 ON FINE ON QM 99 well founded expectations about the percentage of the ensemble in which such expressions would be satisfied. So far, we have shown that the statistics could not be satisfied exactly in a finite ensemble. If one dropped the requirement of exactness, then (7) to (9) would become, schematically, (7') (8') prop (a~ & c~) = A + B + e prop (a~- & b~-) = C + B + e' (9') prop (b ~ & c ~ = A + D + e" where each epsilon is the sum of 14 terms. We can no longer derive the inequality, but this changes things very little. It still must be possible, if the probabilities are to be realizable, to describe a finite ensemble in which (7') is arbitrarily close to 3/8, (8') and (9') are each arbitrarily close to 1/8 and each summand of each epsilon (and hence, each epsilon) is arbitrarily close to zero. It is easy to see that this is not possible. I conclude then, that Fine has not succeeded in avoiding Bell's result. The real significance of the Bell-Wigner argument is that no system of the sort which Fine contemplates could possibly exhibit the properties of a quantum mechanical system in the singlet state. The phase space is really just an acknowledgement of the fact that ensembles of such classical systems can be thought of as sets with well-defined subsets corresponding to the various properties countenanced by the theory. Fine could, of course, preserve his belief in the classical nature of quantum mechanical systems by positing a non-local effect to. account for the observed frequencies. But this would be to deny that the quantum mechanical joint distribution of M and N j simply tells us the probabilities of conjunctions of propositions of the forms 'M= x' and 'N ~= y', and consequently to accept a crucial feature of the Bell-Wigner characterization of locality. If what I have said here is correct, there is a sense in which it really amounts to pointing out the obvious. The underlying point, however, is not trivial. There is no merely accidental connection between classical logic and the apparatus of the classical phase space. I

10 100 ALLEN STAIRS suggest in the same vein that it is no mere accident that the classical probability space is not the device used to represent probabilities in quantum mechanics. Dalhousie University and University of Western Ontario NOTES J Fine (1974), p Fine (1973). 3 In particular, if Q is a projection operator onto a one-dimensional subspace spanned by ~b', and if 0 </(~b,~b')12 < 1, then {v~lv~[{1}] = 1} = A and hence has probability = 0. But QM tells us that this probability is non-zero (see p. 28 of Fine [1974]). 4 Wigner (1970). REFERENCES Bell, J. S., 'On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox', Physics 1 (1964), Fine, A., 'On the Completeness of Quantum Theory', In P. Suppes (ed.), Logic and Probability in Quantum Mechanics, Reidel, Dordrecht, Fine, A., 'Probability and the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24 (1973), Wigner, E., 'On Hidden Variables and Quantum Mechanical Probabilities', American Journal of Physics 38 (1970),

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM Michele Caponigro ISHTAR, Bergamo University Abstract From conceptual point of view, we argue about the nature of reality inferred from EPR

More information

Notes on Quantum Logic

Notes on Quantum Logic Notes on Quantum Logic Version 1.0 David B. Malament Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of California, Irvine dmalamen@uci.edu Contents 1 Formal (sentential) quantum logic 2 2 The

More information

A Classification of Hidden-Variable Properties

A Classification of Hidden-Variable Properties A Classification of Hidden-Variable Properties Joint work with Adam Brandenburger Noson S. Yanofsky Brooklyn College and The Graduate Center, CUNY noson@sci.brooklyn.cuny.edu Quantum Logic Inspired by

More information

MGP versus Kochen-Specker condition in hidden variables theories

MGP versus Kochen-Specker condition in hidden variables theories arxiv:quant-ph/0211049v2 29 Jan 2004 MGP versus Kochen-Specker condition in hidden variables theories Claudio Garola Abstract Hidden variables theories for quantum mechanics are usually assumed to satisfy

More information

Hidden Variables and Commutativity in Quantum Mechanics

Hidden Variables and Commutativity in Quantum Mechanics Hidden Variables and Commutativity in Quantum Mechanics Benjamin Feintzeig Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science, University of California, Irvine bfeintze@uci.edu January 1, 2013 Abstract This

More information

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Incompatibility Paradoxes Chapter 22 Incompatibility Paradoxes 22.1 Simultaneous Values There is never any difficulty in supposing that a classical mechanical system possesses, at a particular instant of time, precise values of

More information

Singlet State Correlations

Singlet State Correlations Chapter 23 Singlet State Correlations 23.1 Introduction This and the following chapter can be thought of as a single unit devoted to discussing various issues raised by a famous paper published by Einstein,

More information

Comments on There is no axiomatic system for the. quantum theory. Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) J.

Comments on There is no axiomatic system for the. quantum theory. Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) J. Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Comments on There is no axiomatic system for the quantum theory J. Acacio de Barros the date of receipt and acceptance should be inserted later Abstract

More information

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage C. S. Unnikrishnan Fundamental Interactions Laboratory Tata Institute

More information

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality Iñaki San Pedro Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of the Basque Country, UPV/EHU inaki.sanpedro@ehu.es Abstract

More information

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 2 Jun 2010

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 2 Jun 2010 arxiv:1006.0499v1 [quant-ph] 2 Jun 2010 Von Neumann s No Hidden Variables Proof: A Re-Appraisal Jeffrey Bub Philosophy Department and Institute for Physical Science and Technology University of Maryland,

More information

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 1 Real Numbers In these lectures, we are going to study a branch of mathematics called

More information

Quantum measurements and Kolmogorovian probability theory

Quantum measurements and Kolmogorovian probability theory Quantum measurements and Kolmogorovian probability theory D.A.Slavnov arxiv:quant-ph/0301027v1 8 Jan 2003 Department of Physics, Moscow State University, Moscow 119992, Russia. E- mail: slavnov@goa.bog.msu.ru

More information

ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* I. Introduction

ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* I. Introduction Physics Vol. 1, No. 3, pp. 195 200, 1964 Physics Publishing Co. Printed in the United States ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* J. S. BELLt Department of Physics, University of Wisconsin, Madison,

More information

Computability Crib Sheet

Computability Crib Sheet Computer Science and Engineering, UCSD Winter 10 CSE 200: Computability and Complexity Instructor: Mihir Bellare Computability Crib Sheet January 3, 2010 Computability Crib Sheet This is a quick reference

More information

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued)

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued) 2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued) 2.1. New examples of commutative rings. Recall that in the first lecture we defined the notions of commutative rings and field and gave some examples of

More information

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) 1. The Copenhagen Interpretation Bohr interpreted quantum theory as showing that there is a fundamental partition in nature, between the microphysical

More information

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction Chapter 25 Hardy s Paradox 25.1 Introduction Hardy s paradox resembles the Bohm version of the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox, discussed in Chs. 23 and 24, in that it involves two correlated particles,

More information

Stochastic Quantum Dynamics I. Born Rule

Stochastic Quantum Dynamics I. Born Rule Stochastic Quantum Dynamics I. Born Rule Robert B. Griffiths Version of 25 January 2010 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Born Rule 1 2.1 Statement of the Born Rule................................ 1 2.2 Incompatible

More information

Classical Bell s Inequalities. Vesselin C. Noninski

Classical Bell s Inequalities. Vesselin C. Noninski Classical Bell s Inequalities Vesselin C. Noninski vesselin.noninski@verizon.net Abstract An example of a classical system violating Bell s inequalities is discussed. Existence of a classical system violating

More information

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1 Logic One reason for studying logic is that we need a better notation than ordinary English for expressing relationships among various assertions or hypothetical states of affairs. A solid grounding in

More information

Chapter 2 Classical Probability Theories

Chapter 2 Classical Probability Theories Chapter 2 Classical Probability Theories In principle, those who are not interested in mathematical foundations of probability theory might jump directly to Part II. One should just know that, besides

More information

CAT L4: Quantum Non-Locality and Contextuality

CAT L4: Quantum Non-Locality and Contextuality CAT L4: Quantum Non-Locality and Contextuality Samson Abramsky Department of Computer Science, University of Oxford Samson Abramsky (Department of Computer Science, University CAT L4: of Quantum Oxford)

More information

PATRICK SUPPES** Stanford University

PATRICK SUPPES** Stanford University Reprinted from the Philosophy of Science Vol. 33 - Nos. 1-2 - March - June 1966 TI;eE PROBABILISTIC ARGUMENT FOR A NON-CLASSICAL LQGIC OF QUANTUM MECHANICS" PATRICK SUPPES** Stanford University The aim

More information

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities Chapter 24 EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities 24.1 Bohm Version of the EPR Paradox Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen (EPR) were concerned with the following issue. Given two spatially separated quantum systems

More information

CHAPTER 4 CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL SEMANTICS

CHAPTER 4 CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL SEMANTICS CHAPTER 4 CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL SEMANTICS 1 Language There are several propositional languages that are routinely called classical propositional logic languages. It is due to the functional dependency

More information

The Integers. Peter J. Kahn

The Integers. Peter J. Kahn Math 3040: Spring 2009 The Integers Peter J. Kahn Contents 1. The Basic Construction 1 2. Adding integers 6 3. Ordering integers 16 4. Multiplying integers 18 Before we begin the mathematics of this section,

More information

Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem. Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem. Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics by Christoph Saulder 19. 12. 2007 Interpretations of quantum mechanics Copenhagen interpretation the wavefunction has no

More information

Linear Algebra. Preliminary Lecture Notes

Linear Algebra. Preliminary Lecture Notes Linear Algebra Preliminary Lecture Notes Adolfo J. Rumbos c Draft date May 9, 29 2 Contents 1 Motivation for the course 5 2 Euclidean n dimensional Space 7 2.1 Definition of n Dimensional Euclidean Space...........

More information

LINEAR ALGEBRA: THEORY. Version: August 12,

LINEAR ALGEBRA: THEORY. Version: August 12, LINEAR ALGEBRA: THEORY. Version: August 12, 2000 13 2 Basic concepts We will assume that the following concepts are known: Vector, column vector, row vector, transpose. Recall that x is a column vector,

More information

Foundations of non-commutative probability theory

Foundations of non-commutative probability theory Foundations of non-commutative probability theory Daniel Lehmann School of Engineering and Center for the Study of Rationality Hebrew University, Jerusalem 91904, Israel June 2009 Abstract Kolmogorov s

More information

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox Katsuaki Higashi Abstract According to a conventional view, there exists no common-cause model of quantum correlations satisfying locality

More information

NON HILBERTIAN QUANTUM MECHANICS ON THE FINITE GALOIS FIELD

NON HILBERTIAN QUANTUM MECHANICS ON THE FINITE GALOIS FIELD 1 BAO HUYNH 12524847 PHYSICS 517 QUANTUM MECHANICS II SPRING 2013 TERM PAPER NON HILBERTIAN QUANTUM MECHANICS ON THE FINITE GALOIS FIELD 2 Index table Section Page 1. Introduction 3 2. Algebraic construction

More information

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem PHYS419 Lecture 0 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem 1 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem As first shown by Bell (1964), the force of the arguments

More information

ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* ]. S. BELLt Department of Physics, University of Wisconsin, Madison, Wisconsin

ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* ]. S. BELLt Department of Physics, University of Wisconsin, Madison, Wisconsin Physics Vol. 1, No. 3, pp. 195-290, 1964 Physics Publishing Co. Printed in the United States ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* ]. S. BELLt Department of Physics, University of Wisconsin, Madison,

More information

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions James M. Robins, Tyler J. VanderWeele Departments of Epidemiology and Biostatistics, Harvard School of Public Health Richard

More information

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015)

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015) 18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015) 1. Introduction The goal for this course is to provide a quick, and hopefully somewhat gentle, introduction to the task of formulating

More information

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem PHYS419 Lecture 0 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem 1 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem As first shown by Bell (1964), the force of the arguments

More information

Spanning, linear dependence, dimension

Spanning, linear dependence, dimension Spanning, linear dependence, dimension In the crudest possible measure of these things, the real line R and the plane R have the same size (and so does 3-space, R 3 ) That is, there is a function between

More information

Report 1 The Axiom of Choice

Report 1 The Axiom of Choice Report 1 The Axiom of Choice By Li Yu This report is a collection of the material I presented in the first round presentation of the course MATH 2002. The report focuses on the principle of recursive definition,

More information

Popper's Propensity Interpretation of Probability and Quantum Mechanics

Popper's Propensity Interpretation of Probability and Quantum Mechanics -----JEFFREY BUB----- Popper's Propensity Interpretation of Probability and Quantum Mechanics This paper is a critique of Popper's interpretation of quantum mechanics and the claim that the propensity

More information

In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization

In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization Franz Huber Department of Philosophy University of Toronto Please do not cite! December 31, 2013 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Weisberg s Paradox 3 3 Jeffrey Conditionalization

More information

Notes on Bell s Theorem

Notes on Bell s Theorem Notes on Bell s Theorem Version 1.0 David B. Malament Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of California, Irvine dmalamen@uci.edu Contents 1 Bell s Theorem 2 2 The Geometric Interpretation

More information

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH RICHARD G HECK, JR 1. INTRODUCTION The purpose of this note is to give a simple, easily accessible proof of the existence of the minimal fixed point, and of various maximal fixed

More information

Logic and Propositional Calculus

Logic and Propositional Calculus CHAPTER 4 Logic and Propositional Calculus 4.1 INTRODUCTION Many algorithms and proofs use logical expressions such as: IF p THEN q or If p 1 AND p 2, THEN q 1 OR q 2 Therefore it is necessary to know

More information

(January 6, 2006) Paul Garrett garrett/

(January 6, 2006) Paul Garrett  garrett/ (January 6, 2006)! "$# % & '!)( *+,.-0/%&1,3234)5 * (6# Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ To communicate clearly in mathematical writing, it is helpful to clearly express

More information

Locality and the Hardy theorem

Locality and the Hardy theorem 1 Locality and the Hardy theorem ARTHUR FINE But this conclusion [nonlocality] needs careful discussion in order to clarify what is going on. (Redhead 1987, p. 3) Within the foundations of physics in recent

More information

J = L + S. to this ket and normalize it. In this way we get expressions for all the kets

J = L + S. to this ket and normalize it. In this way we get expressions for all the kets Lecture 3 Relevant sections in text: 3.7, 3.9 Total Angular Momentum Eigenvectors How are the total angular momentum eigenvectors related to the original product eigenvectors (eigenvectors of L z and S

More information

3 The language of proof

3 The language of proof 3 The language of proof After working through this section, you should be able to: (a) understand what is asserted by various types of mathematical statements, in particular implications and equivalences;

More information

RUNS: A_B, A_B', A'_B,

RUNS: A_B, A_B', A'_B, A. Fine, 2013 THE BELL THEOREM The Bell theorem is a demonstration that a plausible way of picturing (or modeling) how the results of measurements occur, when made precise, leads to definite relations

More information

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist Pierre Uzan University Paris-Diderot, laboratory SPHERE, History and Philosophy of Science pierre.uzan@paris7.jussieu.fr Abstract Non-local correlations

More information

A Reexamination on Bell s Theorem

A Reexamination on Bell s Theorem A Reexamination on Bell s Theorem Tianrong Tan Department of Physics, Qingdao University, Qingdao, Shandong 266071, China, Ttr359@126.com Abstract: It is proved that Bell s inequality can be traced back

More information

Linear Algebra. Preliminary Lecture Notes

Linear Algebra. Preliminary Lecture Notes Linear Algebra Preliminary Lecture Notes Adolfo J. Rumbos c Draft date April 29, 23 2 Contents Motivation for the course 5 2 Euclidean n dimensional Space 7 2. Definition of n Dimensional Euclidean Space...........

More information

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION: QUANTUM PHILOSOPHY PCES 4.41 Perhaps the most difficult things to understand about QM are (i) how to reconcile our common sense ideas about physical reality with phenomena such as entanglement, & (ii)

More information

First-Degree Entailment

First-Degree Entailment March 5, 2013 Relevance Logics Relevance logics are non-classical logics that try to avoid the paradoxes of material and strict implication: p (q p) p (p q) (p q) (q r) (p p) q p (q q) p (q q) Counterintuitive?

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

The Integers. Math 3040: Spring Contents 1. The Basic Construction 1 2. Adding integers 4 3. Ordering integers Multiplying integers 12

The Integers. Math 3040: Spring Contents 1. The Basic Construction 1 2. Adding integers 4 3. Ordering integers Multiplying integers 12 Math 3040: Spring 2011 The Integers Contents 1. The Basic Construction 1 2. Adding integers 4 3. Ordering integers 11 4. Multiplying integers 12 Before we begin the mathematics of this section, it is worth

More information

Logic and Propositional Calculus

Logic and Propositional Calculus CHAPTER 4 Logic and Propositional Calculus 4.1 INTRODUCTION Many algorithms and proofs use logical expressions such as: IF p THEN q or If p 1 AND p 2, THEN q 1 OR q 2 Therefore it is necessary to know

More information

To Infinity and Beyond

To Infinity and Beyond To Infinity and Beyond 25 January 2012 To Infinity and Beyond 25 January 2012 1/24 The concept of infinity has both fascinated and frustrated people for millenia. We will discuss some historical problems

More information

ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF

ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF CHAPTER 4 ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. SECTION 4.6 Indirect Argument: Contradiction and Contraposition Copyright Cengage Learning. All

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm Franz Huber Department of Philosophy University of Toronto franz.huber@utoronto.ca http://huber.blogs.chass.utoronto.ca/ July 7, 2014; final

More information

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds 236 My God, He Plays Dice! Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds Many Worlds 237 Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds Hugh Everett III was one of John Wheeler s most famous graduate students. Others included Richard

More information

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm Franz Huber Abstract: Weisberg (2009) introduces a phenomenon he terms perceptual undermining He argues that it poses a problem for Jeffrey

More information

1. Characterization and uniqueness of products

1. Characterization and uniqueness of products (March 16, 2014) Example of characterization by mapping properties: the product topology Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ [This document is http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/m/mfms/notes

More information

Chapter 4: Classical Propositional Semantics

Chapter 4: Classical Propositional Semantics Chapter 4: Classical Propositional Semantics Language : L {,,, }. Classical Semantics assumptions: TWO VALUES: there are only two logical values: truth (T) and false (F), and EXTENSIONALITY: the logical

More information

INTRODUCTORY NOTES ON QUANTUM COMPUTATION

INTRODUCTORY NOTES ON QUANTUM COMPUTATION INTRODUCTORY NOTES ON QUANTUM COMPUTATION Keith Hannabuss Balliol College, Oxford Hilary Term 2009 Notation. In these notes we shall often use the physicists bra-ket notation, writing ψ for a vector ψ

More information

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL THOMAS HOFWEBER PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL 1. PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AND HILBERT S PROGRAM Hilbert s program in the philosophy of mathematics comes in two parts. One part is a

More information

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH ) Contents 1 Sets 1 2 The Real Numbers 9 3 Sequences 29 4 Series 59 5 Functions 81 6 Power Series 105 7 The elementary functions 111 Chapter 1 Sets It is very convenient to introduce some notation and terminology

More information

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument? arxiv:1808.03762v1 [quant-ph] 11 Aug 2018 Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument? Andrei Khrennikov International Center for Mathematical Modeling in Physics, Engineering, Economics, and Cognitive

More information

MAT2342 : Introduction to Applied Linear Algebra Mike Newman, fall Projections. introduction

MAT2342 : Introduction to Applied Linear Algebra Mike Newman, fall Projections. introduction MAT4 : Introduction to Applied Linear Algebra Mike Newman fall 7 9. Projections introduction One reason to consider projections is to understand approximate solutions to linear systems. A common example

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object.

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object. 1.10. BASICS CONCEPTS OF SET THEORY 193 1.10 Basics Concepts of Set Theory Having learned some fundamental notions of logic, it is now a good place before proceeding to more interesting things, such as

More information

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy Bradford Skow Abstract A recent theory of metaphysical indeterminacy says that metaphysical indeterminacy is multiple actuality. That is, we have a case of metaphysical

More information

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction Tutorial on Mathematical Induction Roy Overbeek VU University Amsterdam Department of Computer Science r.overbeek@student.vu.nl April 22, 2014 1 Dominoes: from case-by-case to induction Suppose that you

More information

Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University

Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University Bell s Theorem Ben Dribus Louisiana State University June 8, 2012 Introduction. Quantum Theory makes predictions that challenge intuitive notions of physical reality. Einstein and others were sufficiently

More information

Published as: Aerts, D., 1994, Quantum structures, separated physical entities and probability, Found. Phys., 24,

Published as: Aerts, D., 1994, Quantum structures, separated physical entities and probability, Found. Phys., 24, Published as: Aerts, D., 1994, Quantum structures, separated physical entities and probability, Found. Phys., 24, 1227-1258. Quantum structures, separated physical entities and probability. Diederik Aerts*

More information

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality Rohan French Abstract In Wehmeier (2004) we are presented with the subjunctive modal language, a way of dealing with the expressive inadequacy of modal logic by marking

More information

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ NICOLAS FORD Abstract. The goal of this paper is to present a proof of the Nullstellensatz using tools from a branch of logic called model theory. In

More information

A General Overview of Parametric Estimation and Inference Techniques.

A General Overview of Parametric Estimation and Inference Techniques. A General Overview of Parametric Estimation and Inference Techniques. Moulinath Banerjee University of Michigan September 11, 2012 The object of statistical inference is to glean information about an underlying

More information

Linear Algebra, Summer 2011, pt. 2

Linear Algebra, Summer 2011, pt. 2 Linear Algebra, Summer 2, pt. 2 June 8, 2 Contents Inverses. 2 Vector Spaces. 3 2. Examples of vector spaces..................... 3 2.2 The column space......................... 6 2.3 The null space...........................

More information

(Refer Slide Time: 0:21)

(Refer Slide Time: 0:21) Theory of Computation Prof. Somenath Biswas Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology Kanpur Lecture 7 A generalisation of pumping lemma, Non-deterministic finite automata

More information

(v, w) = arccos( < v, w >

(v, w) = arccos( < v, w > MA322 Sathaye Notes on Inner Products Notes on Chapter 6 Inner product. Given a real vector space V, an inner product is defined to be a bilinear map F : V V R such that the following holds: For all v

More information

Boolean Subalgebras of Orthomodular Posets

Boolean Subalgebras of Orthomodular Posets Boolean Subalgebras of Orthomodular Posets Harding, Heunen, Lindenhovius and Navara New Mexico State University www.math.nmsu.edu/ JohnHarding.html jharding@nmsu.edu Chapman, September 2018 Overview For

More information

Quantum Information Types

Quantum Information Types qitd181 Quantum Information Types Robert B. Griffiths Version of 6 February 2012 References: R. B. Griffiths, Types of Quantum Information, Phys. Rev. A 76 (2007) 062320; arxiv:0707.3752 Contents 1 Introduction

More information

Lecture 29 Relevant sections in text: 3.9

Lecture 29 Relevant sections in text: 3.9 Lecture 29 Relevant sections in text: 3.9 Spin correlations and quantum weirdness: Spin 1/2 systems Consider a pair of spin 1/2 particles created in a spin singlet state. (Experimentally speaking, this

More information

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States Chapter 8 Quantum Entanglement 8.1 Introduction In our final chapter on quantum mechanics we introduce the concept of entanglement. This is a feature of two-particle states (or multi-particle states) in

More information

Building Infinite Processes from Finite-Dimensional Distributions

Building Infinite Processes from Finite-Dimensional Distributions Chapter 2 Building Infinite Processes from Finite-Dimensional Distributions Section 2.1 introduces the finite-dimensional distributions of a stochastic process, and shows how they determine its infinite-dimensional

More information

Nested Epistemic Logic Programs

Nested Epistemic Logic Programs Nested Epistemic Logic Programs Kewen Wang 1 and Yan Zhang 2 1 Griffith University, Australia k.wang@griffith.edu.au 2 University of Western Sydney yan@cit.uws.edu.au Abstract. Nested logic programs and

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

Approximations of Modal Logic K

Approximations of Modal Logic K WoLLIC 2005 Preliminary Version Approximations of Modal Logic K Guilherme de Souza Rabello 2 Department of Mathematics Institute of Mathematics and Statistics University of Sao Paulo, Brazil Marcelo Finger

More information

The assertional versus Tarskian methods

The assertional versus Tarskian methods The assertional versus Tarskian methods Uri Abraham May 12, 2014 Abstract In this lecture we analyze Peterson s well known two-process criticalsection protocol [3] and prove that the mutual exclusion property

More information

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008 Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008 Closed sets We have been operating at a fundamental level at which a topological space is a set together

More information

To Infinity and Beyond. To Infinity and Beyond 1/43

To Infinity and Beyond. To Infinity and Beyond 1/43 To Infinity and Beyond To Infinity and Beyond 1/43 Infinity The concept of infinity has both fascinated and frustrated people for millennia. We will discuss some historical problems about infinity, some

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Introduction to Metalogic 1

Introduction to Metalogic 1 Philosophy 135 Spring 2012 Tony Martin Introduction to Metalogic 1 1 The semantics of sentential logic. The language L of sentential logic. Symbols of L: (i) sentence letters p 0, p 1, p 2,... (ii) connectives,

More information

Spanning and Independence Properties of Finite Frames

Spanning and Independence Properties of Finite Frames Chapter 1 Spanning and Independence Properties of Finite Frames Peter G. Casazza and Darrin Speegle Abstract The fundamental notion of frame theory is redundancy. It is this property which makes frames

More information

DEEP METAPHYSICAL INDETERMINACY

DEEP METAPHYSICAL INDETERMINACY The Philosophical Quarterly June 2010 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2010.672.x The Scots Philosophical Association and the University of St Andrews DEEP METAPHYSICAL INDETERMINACY BY BRADFORD SKOW A recent

More information

Does the ψ-epistemic view really solve the measurement problem?

Does the ψ-epistemic view really solve the measurement problem? Does the ψ-epistemic view really solve the measurement problem? Shan Gao Institute for the History of Natural Sciences, Chinese Academy of Sciences, Beijing 100190, China. E-mail: gaoshan@ihns.ac.cn. September

More information

FREE PROBABILITY THEORY

FREE PROBABILITY THEORY FREE PROBABILITY THEORY ROLAND SPEICHER Lecture 4 Applications of Freeness to Operator Algebras Now we want to see what kind of information the idea can yield that free group factors can be realized by

More information