Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)"

Transcription

1 Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

2

3 Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product of two sets 5 2. The empty set 6 3. Subsets 7 4. Relations 7 5. Functions 8 6. Injective and surjective functions A paradox in naive set theory Semester II: Numbers Few words about mathematical logic Equivalence relations Small sets and cardinal numbers Projects Semester I: Structures Operations Monoids 22 3

4

5 2009 Semester I: Elements One of the standard answers to the question What is mathematics? is Mathematics is a science which studied mathematical objects. But then one may ask what kind of objects are the mathematical objects? Of course, mathematical objects should include numbers, geometric objects like a triangle or a circle, functions, etc. A simpler and more precise answer is: mathematical objects are sets. Then, numbers are special kinds of sets, geometric objects are other kinds of sets, functions are also certain kinds of sets, and so on (details will be given later on). In other words, everything is a set. The aim of this semester is to learn to work with sets, almost like in the school we learn how to work with numbers. 1. Cartesian product of two sets Definition 1. Let x and y be two sets. Then the pair (x, y) is the set (x, y) = {{x, y}, {x}}. Lemma 1. For any two pairs (x, y) and (a, b), we have if and only if we have (x, y) = (a, b) x = a and y = b. Proof. Suppose first (x, y) = (a, b). According to the definition of a pair, this means {{x, y}, {x}} = {{a, b}, {a}}. (1) These two sets are equal to each other means that every element of one set is also an element of the other set, and vice versa. So {x, y} is an element of {{a, b}, {a}}. Then either we have {x, y} = {a, b} or {x, y} = {a}. If {x, y} = {a}, then again, since we have equality of two sets, we conclude that these sets have the same elements, so this forces x = a = y. To finish treating the case {x, y} = {a}, it remains to show y = b. Indeed, if {x, y} = {a} then by (1) we should have {x} = {a, b}, which itself implies a = x = b. This, together with the previously obtained equalities obviously gives b = a = y. The case {x, y} = {a, b} can be treated in an analogous way (see Exercise 1). Now suppose we have x = a and y = b. Then we have {x, y} = {a, b} and {x} = {a}, which gives (1). Therefore, (x, y) = (a, b). Definition 2. Let X and Y be two sets. Then the cartesian product X Y of X and Y is a new set X Y = {(x, y) x X, y Y }. In other words, X Y is the set of all pairs (x, y) where x is an element of X and y is an element of Y. 5

6 SEMESTER I: ELEMENTS Thus, for instance, if X has exactly three elements x, y, z (i.e. X = {x, y, z}, with x y, x z and y z) and Y has exactly two elements a, b, then the elements of the set X Y are the following six pairs: That is, (x, a), (x, b), (y, a), (y, b), (z, a), (z, b). X Y = {(x, a), (x, b), (y, a), (y, b), (z, a), (z, b)}. Note: above, the order in which we list the pairs is irrelevant, since the elements in a set are not ordered. Thus, for instance, {x, y} = {y, x}. Notice also the distinction between the set {x, y} and the pair (x, y), where in the latter case we would have (x, y) = (y, x) if only if x = y (as this follows from Lemma 1). Exercise 1. Complete the proof of Lemma 1. Exercise 2. If X has exactly n elements and Y has m elements, then how many elements does X Y have? (Hint: if you find it hard to work with general numbers n and m, first try to answer the question for a specific n and m, e.g. n = 2 and m = 3.) Exercise 3. Let X and Y be any two sets. Then is it true that X Y = Y X? If not always, then when is this true? 2. The empty set In order to be able to speak about sets, it seems natural that we must first begin with specifying certain objects, and then we can start constructing sets out of those objects. For instance, we can begin with the objects being all natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4,... Then, we can form, for example, the following sets: {1, 2, 3}, {4, 5}, {1, 5}, {{4}, {3, 5}}, {{{1}}}. For instance, the last set is a set which has just one element x, where x is itself a set with just one element y, where y is the set with the only element 1. But it turns out, we do not need to begin with anything. In other words, we can begin with nothing. What is nothing? It is when we do not have any objects. Can we form a set out of it? Yes we can it is the empty set, which we will denote by. Thus, is the set which does not have elements. Now we see that we actually got something out of nothing; indeed, for is something, and we can use it to construct other sets, like we used 1, 2, 3,... For example, we can construct the following sets out of it: { }, {, { }}, {{ }}, {{{ }}}. Lemma 2. Prove that for any set X, we have X = = X. Proof. The set X is defined as the set of all pairs (x, y) where x is an element of X and y is an element of. But has no elements, so there is no such pair, which means that X also does not have any elements and therefore it is the empty set. Similar argument can be used to show X =.

7 4. RELATIONS 7 3. Subsets Definition 3. A set X is said to be a subset of a set Y, written as X Y, if every element x of X also happens to be an element of Y. Obviously, every set is a subset of itself. Lemma 3. A set X is a subset of every set if and only if X =. Proof. The empty set is a subset of any other set Y since every element of the empty set is trivially an element of Y, as there are no elements in the empty set. Conversely, if X is a subset of every set, than in particular X must be a subset of, which can only happen when X itself is the empty set (if X has at least one element x, then since x is not an element of the empty set, X cannot be a subset of ). So, this something which we created out of nothing is actually part of everything, and it is the only thing that is such. Exercise 4. Prove that if X X and Y Y then X Y X Y. Exercise 5. Prove that if X Y and Y Z, then X Z. Exercise 6. Prove that if X Y and Y X, then X = Y. Exercise 7. For a set X, the power set of X, written as P(X), is defined as the set of all subsets of X. (a) Does there exist a set X for which P(X) =? (b) If X has n number of elements, then how many elements does P(X) have? 4. Relations A relation R from a set X to a set Y, is a subset R X Y. In particular, if R =, then R is called the empty relation. We sometimes depict a relation from X to Y as an arrow of the form X Y, and then we write or R : X Y X R Y to indicate that R is a relation from X to Y. Note that the same set R could be a relation between possibly different pairs of sets (X, Y ) and (X, Y ). For instance, let R X Y and suppose X X, Y Y. Then also R X Y. In order to avoid this (since we want each relation R to remember who is X and who is Y ), we refine the definition of a relation as follows: Definition 4. A relation is a pair (R, (X, Y )), where X and Y are sets, and R is a subset R X Y. We often use the same letter R to denote the set R in the pair (R, (X, Y )), and the whole relation (R, (X, Y )) itself. The set X is said to be the domain of the relation R and the set Y is said to be the codomain of R. Given two relations X R S Y Z their composite S R is a relation S R : X Z defined by S R = {(x, z) y Y [(x, y) R (y, z) S]}

8 SEMESTER I: ELEMENTS where y Y [(x, y) R (y, z) S] means: there exists an element y in Y such that (x, y) R and (y, z) S. For a relation R, we will often use the notation xry to mean (x, y) R. Thus, xs Rz if and only if xsyrz for some y Y. For a relation R : X Y by R we denote a relation R : Y X defined by We call R the opposite relation of R. yr x xry. Remark 1. Above, the symbol stands for if and only if. Also, we will write for implies. Exercise 8. For this question we assume that we have already defined what real numbers are (we will define them later in the notes). Let R be a relation from the set R of real numbers to itself, i.e. R : R R, defined by xry x 2 + y 2 = 1. And let S be a relation S : R R defined by Then, describe the composite S R. xsy x 2 + y 2 = 2. Exercise 9. Let R be a relation from a set X to itself, i.e. we have R : X X. Show that the following conditions are equivalent to each other: (a) R R ; (b) R R; (c) R = R ; (d) For all x, y X we have xry yrx. A relation R : X X satisfying these conditions is called a symmetric relation. 5. Functions Definition 5. A function f from a set X to a set Y, written as f : X Y, is a relation f : X Y having the following property: for every element x X there exists exactly one element y Y such that (x, y) f. When f is a function f : X Y, for each x X we use the special notation f(x) for the unique element f(x) = y Y such that (x, y) f. We will use the following obvious lemma very often, when we want to establish equality of two functions: Lemma 4. Let f, g : X Y be functions from a set X to a set Y. Then f = g if and only if for each x X we have f(x) = g(x). Thus, specifying / constructing / defining a function f : X Y amounts to saying what is f(x) for each x X. Given two functions X f g Y Z we can compose them as relations to get a function X g f Y

9 5. FUNCTIONS 9 Lemma 5. Let f and g be as above. Then for each x X, the composite g f satisfies (g f)(x) = g(f(x)). Proof. By the definition of composition of relations, we have This is the same as to have g f = {(x, z) y Y [(x, y) f (y, z) g]}. g f = {(x, z) y Y [y = f(x) z = g(y)]}. So, to show (g f)(x) = g(f(x)) is the same as to show that there exists y Y such that y = f(x) and g(f(x)) = g(y). But such y clearly exists take y = f(x). Lemma 6. Composition of functions is associative; that is, for any three functions W f X g h Y Z we have h (g f) = (h g) f. Proof. By Lemma 5 we have: for each w W, (h (g f))(w) = h((g f)(x)) = h(g(f(x))). Similarly, for each w W we have ((h g) f)(w) = h(g(f(x))). So (h (g f))(w) = (h g) f)(w) for all w W and hence we can apply Lemma 4 to conclude h (g f) = (h g) f. For a set X by 1 X we denote the function 1 X : X X defined by 1 X (x) = x. Lemma 7. For any function f : X Y we have Exercise 10. Prove Lemma 7. 1 Y f = f = f 1 X. Exercise 11. Show that for any four functions V e W f X g Y the following composites are all equal to each other: h (g (f e)) ((h g) f) e h ((g f) e) (h g) (f e) (h (g f)) e Exercise 12. State and prove associativity of composition of relations. Exercise 13. (a) Prove Lemma 7. (b) State and prove the generalization of Lemma 7, which replaces the function f : X Y with a relation R : X Y. h Z

10 SEMESTER I: ELEMENTS 6. Injective and surjective functions Definition 6. A function f : X Y is said to be injective if for any x 1, x 2 X we have f(x 1 ) = f(x 2 ) x 1 = x 2. We say that f is surjective if for any y Y there exists x X such that f(x) = y. Finally, f is said to be bijective if it is both injective and surjective. Put simply, f is injective if it carries different elements to different elements; f is surjective if f fills up its codomain; and f is bijective if it defines a one-to-one correspondence between its domain and codomain. Lemma 8. A function f : X Y is injective if and only if f f = 1 X. Proof. By the definition of composition of relations, the relation f f consists of all those pairs (x, z) X X such that there exists y with f(x) = y and y = f(z). In other words, it consists of all those pairs (x, z) X X such that f(x) = f(z). So f f 1 X if and only if f is injective. Now, we always have 1 X f f. Hence, f f = 1 X if and only if f is injective. Lemma 9. A function f : X Y is surjective if and only if f f = 1 Y. Lemma 10. A function f : X Y is bijective if and only if its inverse relation f : Y X is itself a function. These three lemmas give an important characterization of bijective functions as those functions f : X Y for which there exists a function g : Y X such that f g = 1 Y and g f = 1 X. Then g is necessarily unique and it coincides with f (see Exercise 15). We call g the inverse of f. Definition 7. The image of a function f : X Y, is defined as the following set: Im(f) = {y x X f(x) = y}. Theorem 1. Any function f : X Y can be presented as a composite f = g h of a surjective function h followed by an injective function g. Proof. Define a function g : Im(f) Y by g(y) = y, and define h : X Im(f) by h(x) = f(x). Then it is trivial to check that f = g h. Exercise 14. Prove Lemmas 9 and 10. Exercise 15. Conclude from Lemmas 8, 9 and 10 that a function f : X Y is bijective if and only if there exists a function g : Y X such that f g = 1 Y and g f = 1 X. Show that when such g exists, it is necessarily unique (i.e. there is only one g satisfying the above two equalities). Exercise 16. (a) Consider a function π 1 : X Y X defined by π 1 ((x, y)) = x. When is π 1 surjective? (b) Consider a function : X X X defined by (x) = (x, x). When is injective? What is the image of?

11 7. A PARADOX IN NAIVE SET THEORY 11 Exercise 17. Complete the proof of Theorem 1. Exercise 18. (a) Prove that a composite f g is injective/surjective/bijective as soon as both f and g are injective/surjective/bijective. (b) Prove that if f g is injective then necessarily g is injective. (c) Prove that if f g is surjective then necessarily f is surjective. 7. A paradox in naive set theory Naive set theory is when one thinks of sets simply as collections of objects, and then one wants to regard sets as being themselves objects. It turns out that this leads to a paradox, for we can then say: consider the set V of all those sets Y such that Y / Y (i.e. Y is not an element of itself); if we believe that all sets are objects, then since an arbitrary collection of objects is a set, nothing is strange about the construction of V. Now, we argue: if V V then, by the definition of V, we should have V / V ; however, if V / V, then, again by the definition of V, we should have V V. So we get V V V / V which is clearly a contradiction. Thus, we should not assume that every set is itself an object. If we think of object as those things which are real, then we can say: not every set is real! In particular, the set of all real sets might not be a real set. Thus, we can only form sets of real things, and only some of these sets will turn out to be real themselves. Then the above argument merely proves that the set V of all real sets Y such that Y / Y, cannot be real (for if it is, we get a paradox). In fact, according to our intuition about sets, all real sets Y should satisfy Y / Y, so that V becomes the set of all real sets. So, indeed, the set of all real sets is not a real set. We can model the relationship between sets and real sets inside the world of real sets as follows: let X be a real set, and call its elements very real sets. Then P(X) is the set of all sets of very real sets. Elements of P(X) are real sets. The question is: can it happen that every real set is a very real set? If this can happen, then we will get that P(X) is a subset of X. In other words, we will have an injective function f : P(X) X defined by f(u) = u. But, as we will prove below (see Theorem 2), there cannot exist an injective function (of any kind) from P(X) to X. The proof of this result is in fact an immediate adaption of the argument used to establish the above paradox. All the time in the previous sections we have only been dealing with real sets. But now we should be careful: what if at some point we formed a set which was not real? To make sure this never happened we have to set out rules for constructing real sets. Here are some of these rules, which are sufficient to deduce that all sets we have been constructing in previous sections were indeed real: (a) The empty set is real. (b) If X is a real set, then any set of its elements is a real set. (c) If x and y are real sets, then the set {x, y} is also real. (d) If X and Y are real sets, then the set of all pairs (x, y) where x X and y Y, is a real set. (e) If X is a real set, then the set of all subsets of X is a real set.

12 SEMESTER I: ELEMENTS But how do we know that these rules are really correct and do not give rise to any paradoxes? We could try to invent new type of mathematics in which we would be able to prove that the above rules do not give rise to any paradoxes, but then, how would we know that this new mathematics will not have any paradoxes? Well, we could repeat the procedure and develop yet another mathematics for showing that there are no paradoxes in the previous mathematics, but then we face the same question again for the newer mathematics. Since this process continues infinitely, and since we will never be able to do infinite number of things in finite time, we will never know whether the above rules yield any paradoxes or not, unless of course we accidently discover them. Henceforth, as in previous sections, when we say set we will mean real set. Theorem 2. Let X be any set. There does not exist an injective function f : P(X) X, from the set P(X) of all subsets of X to X. Proof. Let f be a function f : P(X) X. We will find u, v such that f(u) = f(v) and u v, hence proving that f is not injective. Take v = {y X u P(X) ([f(u) = y] [y / u])}. (Here u P(X) means for any u P(X) such that....) Now, take y = f(v). Then y / v, since if y v, then we would get a contradiction with how v is defined: if y v, then, because f(v) = y, we should have y / v (set u = v above). But if y / v, then there should exist u P(X) different from v for which f(u) = f(v) = y, since otherwise, if v is the only element in P(X) with the property f(v) = y, then by definition of v we would have y v, which we already showed that cannot be true. This completes the proof.

13 2009 Semester II: Numbers The aim of this chapter is to construct natural numbers within set theory. We start by investigating a special class of relations, called equivalence relations, which will serve as a toolkit for constructing numbers. But even before this we have to say 8. Few words about mathematical logic Mathematical reasoning has very precise and strict rules, which ensures that the validity of it does not depend on the opinion of a particular person. This makes mathematics the most precise science. To study these rules is the purpose of mathematical logic. In particular, mathematical logic proposes a fixed meaning to the connectives like and, or, if... then..., etc., and then it becomes more convenient to introduce symbolic representations for them. In this section we introduce these symbols and explain their precise meaning. Throughout the section capital letters A, B,... will be used to represent arbitrary sentences, and small letters x, y,... will be used to represent sets. We will write A[x 1,..., x n ] if A is a sentence involving distinct symbols x 1,..., x n which represent arbitrary sets. Then A(y 1,..., y n ) is a new sentence obtained from A by replacing each occurrence of the symbol x i in A with the symbol y i. In this process, the symbols y 1,..., y n need not be distinct. Here is an example: if then A[x 1, x 2 ] expresses x 1 is a subset of x 2 A(y, y) expresses y is a subset of y. Clearly, the sentence A[x 1, x 2 ] is true for some pairs of sets x 1, x 2 and false for some other pairs of sets (for instance, it is false if x 2 = and x 1 = { }). While A(y, y) is always true (because any set is a subset of itself) Conjunction. Let A and B be sentences. Then A B is the following sentence obtained from A and B: A B = A and B. Mathematical logic gives us the following rule: the sentence A B is true if and only if both A and B are true. This rule can be summarized by the following table, which is similar to the multiplication table for natural numbers (think of t being 1 and f being 0): t f t t f f f f 13

14 SEMESTER II: NUMBERS Above t and f represent true and false, respectively. The logical operation is called conjunction. Note: a more accepted term for logical operation is logical connective Disjunction. Let A and B be sentences. Then A B is the following sentence obtained from A and B: A B = A or B. Mathematical logic gives us the following rule: the sentence A B is true if and only if at least one of A, B is true (or both are true). This rule can be summarized by the following table, which is similar to the addition table for natural numbers if we think of t being 1 and f being 0: t f t t t f t f The logical operation is called disjunction Negation. Let A be a sentence. Then A is the following sentence obtained from A: A = not A. The sentence A is true if and only if A is false. This rule can be exhibited by the following table: The operation is called negation. A A t f f t Exercise 19. Show that A B is true if and only if (A B) is true. Is there a similar relationship between A B and (A B)? 8.4. Implication. Let A and B be sentences. Then A B is the following sentence obtained from A and B: A B = A implies B. The sentence A B is true if and only if ( A) B is true. exhibited by the following table: This rule can be t f t t f f t f The logical operation is called implication. In other words, A B has the same meaning as if A then B. Notice that when A is false, this sentence is (by the above rule) always true (it does not depend on B). But when A is true, A B is true if and only if B is true.

15 8. FEW WORDS ABOUT MATHEMATICAL LOGIC Universal quantifier. Let A[x] be a sentence about a set x. Then y A(y) is the following sentence obtained from A: y A(y) = for all y, A(y). The sentence y A(y) is true if and only if A(y) is true for any set y. The quantifier is called the universal quantifier. Exercise 20. Give several examples of sentences A[x] such that y A(y) is true and also give examples when y A(y) is false Existential quantifier. Let A[x] be a sentence about a set x. Then y A(y) is the following sentence obtained from A: y A(y) = there exists y such that A(y). The sentence y A(y) is true if and only if A(y) is true for at least one set y. The quantifier is called the existential quantifier. There are the following relationships between existential and universal quantifiers: y A(y) is true if and only if ( y (A(y))) is true; y A(y) is true if and only if ( y (A(y))) is true Equivalent sentences. Two sentences A and B are said to be equivalent when A is true if and only if B is true. In this case we write A B. Notice that we can regard A B as a sentence, and then becomes a logical operation. It is easy to see that A B is true if and only if (A B) (B A) is true. Above we have given rules which say whether a sentence A made up of sentences B 1,..., B n using the quantifiers, and connectives,,, is true or false, depending on the truth and falsity of B 1,..., B n. In other words, if we know exactly which of the B 1,..., B n is true and which is false, we will know whether A is true or false, and it will not depend on opinion, since our rules are very strict and they cover all possible cases (of truth and falsity of B 1,..., B n ). However, we might not always know if, say, B 1 is true or not. For example, if B is a sentence about a set x saying x =, then we do not know whether B is true or false, since the truth or falsity of B depends on the choice of x: if x is the empty set, then B is true, and if x is nonempty, then B is false. In general we will always have this problem, when B is a sentence about certain sets x 1,..., x n. Note however, that as soon as we take either the sentence C 1 = x (x = ) or the sentence C 2 = x (x = ) this problem disappears: C 1 and C 2 no longer talk about a particular set x. Clearly, C 1 is false (because it is not true that any set is empty) and C 2 is true (since there does indeed exist a set which is empty the empty set itself). To distinguish this situation with the situation we had above for B, we introduce the following concept: Definition 8. A variable x is said to be free in a sentence A if x does not appear in the subscript of either the universal or the existential quantifier. Our first remark now is that when we introduced notation A[x 1,..., x n ] for the case when A is a sentence about distinct sets x 1,..., x n, under the word about we meant that x 1,..., x n are all free variables in A. Indeed, consider the example of C 1. The variable x is not free in C 1. Then, if we still write C 1 as C 1 [x], then we

16 SEMESTER II: NUMBERS are allowed to form a sentence y C 1 (y) which clearly would not make sense since it would be expressing there exists y such that for all y, y =. We make further adjustment in terminology: from now on we will use the term formula instead of a sentence, and we will call sentences only those formulas which do not have free variables. The justification for using the term formula in the case when there are (possibly) free variables is as simple as this: when we have a free variable x, we can assign to it different values, just like in the usual formulas that we know from school. Now it seems that when B is a sentence (i.e. a formula with no free variables) there should no longer be a problem of not being able to determine whether B is true or false. But it turns out that there is still a problem, since the set theory we work with (and hence all of mathematics) is an abstract theory and it might have many difference concrete instances: in certain instances a given sentence might be true, and in certain instances it might be false! It is a difficult task, and too complex at this stage, to give examples of different instances of set theory (and in some sense it is not even possible). So, to be able to understand the above phenomenon let us replace set theory with a simpler theory, say, theory of numbers. Here we have two instances in mind one is the system of real numbers, and another is the system of complex numbers. So now for us, the variables in sentences represent numbers, rather than sets. In the abstract theory of numbers (suitably introduced) we can formulate a sentence B = x y (y 2 = x). Clearly there are no free variables in B, so B is indeed a sentence in the above sense. However, in general we do not know whether B is true or false. Indeed, in the case of the system of real numbers, B is false since for x = 1 there does not exist y such that y 2 = 1. On the other hand, in the system of complex numbers B is true. So we should live with the fact that there might be some sentences which are neither true nor false! Let us give an example of such a sentence for set theory: let B be the sentence stating that there exists a set X such that there are injections N X R (where N is the set of natural numbers and R is the set of real numbers) but X is not bijective either to N or to R. In other words, the sentence says that there is a set which is bigger than the set of natural numbers, but smaller than the set of real numbers (the set of rational numbers turns out to be as big as the set of natural numbers, as we will see in this chapter). This sentence is known in mathematics as continuum hypothesis. 9. Equivalence relations In the definition below we work with any given set X, and variables x, y, z in quantifiers represent elements of X. We could also avoid such remark by writing, say, x X instead of x. We will do so in the future. Definition 9. A relation R : X X is said to be reflexive, if x xrx; symmetric, if x y (xry yrx); transitive, if x y z ([xry yrz] xrz);

17 9. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS 17 an equivalence relation, if it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive at the same time. Exercise 21. (a) Show that the composite of two reflexive/symmetric relations is reflexive/symmetric. (b) Given an example of two transitive relations R and S such that R S is not transitive. (c) Show that if a relation R is transitive, then also R R is transitive. In the future we will abbreviate, say, x X y X as x,y X. Definition 10. A partition P of a set X is a set of subsets of X (i.e. P P(X)) having the following properties: (a) Every element of P is nonempty: U P (U ); (b) Every two different elements of P are disjoint: U,V P [(U V ) (U V = )]; (c) Every element of X is an element of an element of P : x X U P (x U). Lemma 11. For any set P the following conditions are equivalent: (a) P satisfies 10(a) and 10(b); (b) U,V P [(U V ) (U V = )]. Proof. First we prove (a) (b): Suppose P satisfies 10(a) and 10(b). Let U, V P. We must show (U V ) (U V = ), which amounts to showing (U V ) (U V = ) and (U V = ) (U V ). Let us first show (U V ) (U V = ). But this follows trivially from 10(b). Let us now show (U V = ) (U V ). Suppose U V =. If U = V, then U = U V = which contradicts with 10(a). So U V. This completes the proof of (a) (b). The proof of (b) (a) is left as an exercise. Exercise 22. Complete the proof of Lemma 11. Exercise 23. Show that a partition of a set X is empty if and only if X itself is empty. Exercise 24. List all possible partitions of a set X = {x, y, z} where x, y, z are three distinct elements. Let E be an equivalence relation on a set X. For an element x of X we write [x] E to denote the following set: [x] E = {y xey}. This set is called the equivalence class of x (under the equivalence relation E). Exercise 25. Prove the following: x X y X (xey [x] E = [y] E ). Theorem 3. There is a bijection F : Eq(X) Part(X) from the set Eq(X) of all equivalence relations on X, to the set Part(X) of all partitions of X, defined as follows: F (E) = {[x] E x X}.

18 SEMESTER II: NUMBERS The inverse of F is given by F 1 (P ) = {(x, y) U P (x U y U)}. Thus, every equivalence relation produces a partition, and each partition arises in this way from exactly one equivalence relation. This correspondence will provide a very important tool for constructing numbers: we will defined numbers as elements of the partition corresponding to a suitable equivalence relation on a suitable set. Proof of Theorem 3. First of all, let us check that for each equivalence relation E on X, the set F (E) is indeed a partition of X. Note that since [x] E P(X) for each x X, we have F (E) P(X) (recall that P(X) denotes the set of all subsets of X). So to see that F (E) is a partition of X we must check that P = F (E) satisfies conditions (a), (b) and (c) in Definition 10. (a)&(c): Let U F (E). Then U = [x] E for some equivalence relation E on X. By reflexivity of E, we have x [x] E. So U in nonempty. This proves (a). Since x [x] E F (E) for any element x of X, we also get (c). (b): Let U, V F (E). Suppose U = [x] E and V = [y] E have a common element z. Then xez and yez. By symmetry of E, zey, and by transitivity xey. This implies that [x] E = [y] E (see Exercise 25). So if U V then U and V cannot have a common element and hence are disjoint (i.e. U V = ). This proves (b). Thus, the assignment E F (X) indeed defines a function F : Eq(X) Part(X). The rest of the proof is left as an exercise (see Exercise 26). Exercise 26. Complete the proof of Theorem Small sets and cardinal numbers From this point on we assume that in our universe of sets we have a set S having the following properties: S contains the empty set and is closed under formation of products and power sets (i.e. if X, Y S then X Y S and P(X) S). S is closed under all intersections, i.e. for any function f : X S, where X is any set, the set {y x X y f(x)} is an element of S. S is closed under (binary) unions, i.e. if X, Y S, then the set X Y = {x (x X) (x Y )} is also in S. Many things we will do from this point on depends on the choice of such set S, so henceforth we assume to have one such S fixed. We call the elements of this fixed S the small sets. Definition 11. Consider the following relation E on the set of small sets: XEY when there exists a bijection f : X Y ; in this case we say X is bijective to Y. This relation is an equivalence relation, and the elements of the partition corresponding to E (i.e. the equivalence classes for the equivalence relation E) will be called cardinal numbers.

19 11. PROJECTS 19 Exercise 27. Verify that E is an equivalence relation. 11. Projects Project 1. Introduce cardinal arithmetic, i.e. define addition and multiplication of cardinal numbers and establish their basic properties. Project 2. Use the principle of mathematical induction as a definition of natural numbers and establish basic properties of natural numbers. Project 3. Define rational numbers as equivalence class of pairs of natural numbers, for a suitably chosen equivalence relation. Project 4. Define real numbers.

20

21 2010 Semester I: Structures In the previous chapter we defined natural numbers and saw that the arithmetic of natural numbers obeys certain general principles. For example, addition of natural numbers is commutative, i.e. we have n + m = m + n for any two natural numbers n and m. Such general principle is called an axiom on the operation +. The pair (N, +), where N is the set of natural numbers, and + is the operation of addition of natural numbers, is a mathematical structure. In general, a mathematical structure is a system consisting of sets, operations on these sets, relations, etc. Modern mathematics is full of various different kinds of mathematical structures. In this chapter we will look at some of the most important structures. Before we can start learning about mathematical structures, we have to say more precisely what is an operation. 12. Operations Let X and Y be sets. By X Y we denote the set of all functions from X to Y. For a natural number n we write X n to denote X Y where Y = {1,..., n}. In particular, if n = 0 then Y = and hence X 0 has only one element. When n 1, a function f : {1,..., n} X can be represented by an ordered list (in other words, a sequence) f 1,..., f n of elements of X. In particular, f i in this list is simply f(i). Thus, elements of X n are lists of n elements of X (with possibility of repetitions in a list). Definition 12. An n-ary operation on a set X is a function p : X n X. When n = 0, the set X 0 has only one element, so to specify a 0-ary operation amounts to specify an element in X. For example, the natural number 0 can be regarded as a 0-ary operation on the set N of all natural numbers. Similarly, the natural number 1 can be regarded as a 0-ary operation on N. When n = 2, we often write x 1 px 2 instead of p(x 1, x 2 ). For instance, when X = N and p is the addition + of natural numbers, we always write x 1 + x 2 rather than +(x 1, x 2 ). An example of a 1-ary operation is the operation on N defined by the assignment x x + 1. If we denote this operation by s (for successor ), then we can write s(x) = x + 1. Exercise 28. Give examples of operations of various arities on the set of natural numbers. 21

22 SEMESTER I: STRUCTURES We say nullary for 0-ary, unary for 1-ary, binary for 2-ary, ternary for 3-ary. 13. Monoids Definition 13. A monoid is a mathematical structure (X, m, e), where X is a set, m is a binary operation on X and e is an element of X (regarded as a nullary operation on X), such that m is associative, i.e. for all x, y, z X we have m(m(x, y), z) = m(x, m(y, z)), e is a unit for m, i.e. for all x X we have m(x, e) = x = m(e, x). The system (N, +, 0), where N is the set of natural numbers, + is addition of natural numbers (and 0 is usual natural number zero), is of course an example of a monoid. Exercise 29. Give other examples of monoids. Exercise 30. Prove that in any monoid, the following holds: m(m(m(x, y), z), t) = m(x, m(y, m(z, t))). Definition 14. A monoid (X, m, e) is said to be commutative if the operation m is commutative, i.e. m satisfies for all x, y X. m(x, y) = m(y, x) Of course, (N, +, 0) is a commutative monoid. Exercise 31. Let X be any set. Show that the system (X X,, 1 X ), where X is any set (and X X is the set of all functions from X to itself), is the composition of functions and 1 X is the identity function, is a monoid. Show that this monoid is commutative if and only if X is either the empty set or has exactly one element. Exercise 32. Show that all monoids (X, m, e) where X has at most two elements are commutative. Describe all three-element monoids (i.e. all monoids (X, m, e) where X has exactly three elements).

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement. sentential connectives. negation. conjunction. disjunction

Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement. sentential connectives. negation. conjunction. disjunction Copyright & License Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement sentential connectives negation conjunction disjunction implication or conditional antecedant & consequent hypothesis

More information

HANDOUT AND SET THEORY. Ariyadi Wijaya

HANDOUT AND SET THEORY. Ariyadi Wijaya HANDOUT LOGIC AND SET THEORY Ariyadi Wijaya Mathematics Education Department Faculty of Mathematics and Natural Science Yogyakarta State University 2009 1 Mathematics Education Department Faculty of Mathematics

More information

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT)

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT) CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT) MATH 378, CSUSM. SPRING 2009. AITKEN This chapter reviews some of the background concepts needed for Math 378. This chapter is new to the course (added Spring

More information

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10 Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10 Inductive sets (used to define the natural numbers as a subset of R) (1) Definition: A set S R is an inductive

More information

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) VI.1 : Indexed families and set theoretic operations (Halmos, 4, 8 9; Lipschutz, 5.3 5.4) Lipschutz : 5.3 5.6, 5.29 5.32, 9.14 1. Generalize

More information

Analysis 1. Lecture Notes 2013/2014. The original version of these Notes was written by. Vitali Liskevich

Analysis 1. Lecture Notes 2013/2014. The original version of these Notes was written by. Vitali Liskevich Analysis 1 Lecture Notes 2013/2014 The original version of these Notes was written by Vitali Liskevich followed by minor adjustments by many Successors, and presently taught by Misha Rudnev University

More information

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products Chapter 3 Cartesian Products and Relations The material in this chapter is the first real encounter with abstraction. Relations are very general thing they are a special type of subset. After introducing

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Ivan Avramidi New Mexico Institute of Mining and Technology Socorro, NM 87801 June 3, 2004 Author: Ivan Avramidi; File: absmath.tex; Date: June 11,

More information

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant).

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant). Sets and Functions 1. The language of sets Informally, a set is any collection of objects. The objects may be mathematical objects such as numbers, functions and even sets, or letters or symbols of any

More information

Propositional Logic, Predicates, and Equivalence

Propositional Logic, Predicates, and Equivalence Chapter 1 Propositional Logic, Predicates, and Equivalence A statement or a proposition is a sentence that is true (T) or false (F) but not both. The symbol denotes not, denotes and, and denotes or. If

More information

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. MAT 200, Logic, Language and Proof, Fall 2015 Summary Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. Definition. A proposition is a sentence which is either true or false. Truth table for the connective or :

More information

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin Mathematical Logic 1 First-Order Languages. Symbols. All first-order languages we consider will have the following symbols: (i) variables v 1, v 2, v 3,... ; (ii)

More information

Sets. A set is a collection of objects without repeats. The size or cardinality of a set S is denoted S and is the number of elements in the set.

Sets. A set is a collection of objects without repeats. The size or cardinality of a set S is denoted S and is the number of elements in the set. Sets A set is a collection of objects without repeats. The size or cardinality of a set S is denoted S and is the number of elements in the set. If A and B are sets, then the set of ordered pairs each

More information

3. Only sequences that were formed by using finitely many applications of rules 1 and 2, are propositional formulas.

3. Only sequences that were formed by using finitely many applications of rules 1 and 2, are propositional formulas. 1 Chapter 1 Propositional Logic Mathematical logic studies correct thinking, correct deductions of statements from other statements. Let us make it more precise. A fundamental property of a statement is

More information

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory? Chapter 1 Axiomatic set theory 1.1 Why axiomatic set theory? Essentially all mathematical theories deal with sets in one way or another. In most cases, however, the use of set theory is limited to its

More information

Guide to Proofs on Discrete Structures

Guide to Proofs on Discrete Structures CS103 Handout 17 Spring 2018 Guide to Proofs on Discrete Structures In Problem Set One, you got practice with the art of proofwriting in general (as applied to numbers, sets, puzzles, etc.) Problem Set

More information

HOW TO CREATE A PROOF. Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating

HOW TO CREATE A PROOF. Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating HOW TO CREATE A PROOF ALLAN YASHINSKI Abstract We discuss how to structure a proof based on the statement being proved Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating

More information

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SYLVIA DURIAN Abstract. This paper develops the ordinal numbers and transfinite induction, then demonstrates some interesting applications of transfinite induction.

More information

Introduction to Proofs

Introduction to Proofs Introduction to Proofs Notes by Dr. Lynne H. Walling and Dr. Steffi Zegowitz September 018 The Introduction to Proofs course is organised into the following nine sections. 1. Introduction: sets and functions

More information

FOUNDATIONS & PROOF LECTURE NOTES by Dr Lynne Walling

FOUNDATIONS & PROOF LECTURE NOTES by Dr Lynne Walling FOUNDATIONS & PROOF LECTURE NOTES by Dr Lynne Walling Note: You are expected to spend 3-4 hours per week working on this course outside of the lectures and tutorials. In this time you are expected to review

More information

Reading 11 : Relations and Functions

Reading 11 : Relations and Functions CS/Math 240: Introduction to Discrete Mathematics Fall 2015 Reading 11 : Relations and Functions Instructor: Beck Hasti and Gautam Prakriya In reading 3, we described a correspondence between predicates

More information

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Chapter : Logic Topics:. Statements, Negation, and Compound Statements.2 Truth Tables and Logical Equivalences.3

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

MATH 433 Applied Algebra Lecture 14: Functions. Relations.

MATH 433 Applied Algebra Lecture 14: Functions. Relations. MATH 433 Applied Algebra Lecture 14: Functions. Relations. Cartesian product Definition. The Cartesian product X Y of two sets X and Y is the set of all ordered pairs (x,y) such that x X and y Y. The Cartesian

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

Discrete Mathematics. W. Ethan Duckworth. Fall 2017, Loyola University Maryland

Discrete Mathematics. W. Ethan Duckworth. Fall 2017, Loyola University Maryland Discrete Mathematics W. Ethan Duckworth Fall 2017, Loyola University Maryland Contents 1 Introduction 4 1.1 Statements......................................... 4 1.2 Constructing Direct Proofs................................

More information

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005 POL502: Foundations Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University October 10, 2005 Our first task is to develop the foundations that are necessary for the materials covered in this course. 1

More information

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Math/CS 20: Intro. to Math Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Week 5 UCSB 204 The Integers Normally, using the natural numbers, you can easily define

More information

Automata Theory and Formal Grammars: Lecture 1

Automata Theory and Formal Grammars: Lecture 1 Automata Theory and Formal Grammars: Lecture 1 Sets, Languages, Logic Automata Theory and Formal Grammars: Lecture 1 p.1/72 Sets, Languages, Logic Today Course Overview Administrivia Sets Theory (Review?)

More information

Foundations of Mathematics

Foundations of Mathematics Foundations of Mathematics L. Pedro Poitevin 1. Preliminaries 1.1. Sets We will naively think of a set as a collection of mathematical objects, called its elements or members. To indicate that an object

More information

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities Part I Review of Basic Equations Recall that an equation is an expression with an equal sign in the middle. Also recall that, if a question asks you to solve

More information

Logic and Mathematics:

Logic and Mathematics: Logic and Mathematics: Mathematicians in Schools Program Lashi Bandara Mathematical Sciences Institute, Australian National University April 21, 2011 Contents 1 Russell s Paradox 1 2 Propositional Logic

More information

Sets, Functions and Relations

Sets, Functions and Relations Chapter 2 Sets, Functions and Relations A set is any collection of distinct objects. Here is some notation for some special sets of numbers: Z denotes the set of integers (whole numbers), that is, Z =

More information

Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Inverse Functions

Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Inverse Functions Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Inverse Functions Please read this pdf in place of Section 6.5 in the text. The text uses the term inverse of a function and the notation f 1

More information

REVIEW FOR THIRD 3200 MIDTERM

REVIEW FOR THIRD 3200 MIDTERM REVIEW FOR THIRD 3200 MIDTERM PETE L. CLARK 1) Show that for all integers n 2 we have 1 3 +... + (n 1) 3 < 1 n < 1 3 +... + n 3. Solution: We go by induction on n. Base Case (n = 2): We have (2 1) 3 =

More information

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC CHRISTOPHER WILSON Abstract. We present a basic axiomatic development of Zermelo-Fraenkel and Choice set theory, commonly abbreviated ZFC. This paper is aimed in particular

More information

CA320 - Computability & Complexity

CA320 - Computability & Complexity CA320 - Computability & Complexity David Sinclair Overview In this module we are going to answer 2 important questions: Can all problems be solved by a computer? What problems be efficiently solved by

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015)

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015) 18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015) 1. Introduction The goal for this course is to provide a quick, and hopefully somewhat gentle, introduction to the task of formulating

More information

MATH 13 SAMPLE FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

MATH 13 SAMPLE FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS MATH 13 SAMPLE FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS WINTER 2014 Problem 1 (15 points). For each statement below, circle T or F according to whether the statement is true or false. You do NOT need to justify your answers.

More information

RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS

RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS Chapter 1 RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS There is no permanent place in the world for ugly mathematics.... It may be very hard to define mathematical beauty but that is just as true of beauty of any kind, we

More information

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs MAT 1362 Fall 2018 Alistair Savage Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0

More information

CHAPTER THREE: RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS

CHAPTER THREE: RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS CHAPTER THREE: RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS 1 Relations Intuitively, a relation is the sort of thing that either does or does not hold between certain things, e.g. the love relation holds between Kim and Sandy

More information

Introduction to Metalogic

Introduction to Metalogic Philosophy 135 Spring 2008 Tony Martin Introduction to Metalogic 1 The semantics of sentential logic. The language L of sentential logic. Symbols of L: Remarks: (i) sentence letters p 0, p 1, p 2,... (ii)

More information

CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, Boolean algebras

CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, Boolean algebras CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, oolean algebras Guy McCusker 1W2.1 Sets Most of the things mathematicians talk about are built out of sets. The idea of a set is a simple one: a set is just a collection

More information

3 The language of proof

3 The language of proof 3 The language of proof After working through this section, you should be able to: (a) understand what is asserted by various types of mathematical statements, in particular implications and equivalences;

More information

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting Countability 1 Motivation In topology as well as other areas of mathematics, we deal with a lot of infinite sets. However, as we will gradually discover, some infinite sets are bigger than others. Countably

More information

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han Set, functions and Euclidean space Seungjin Han September, 2018 1 Some Basics LOGIC A is necessary for B : If B holds, then A holds. B A A B is the contraposition of B A. A is sufficient for B: If A holds,

More information

Topics in Logic and Proofs

Topics in Logic and Proofs Chapter 2 Topics in Logic and Proofs Some mathematical statements carry a logical value of being true or false, while some do not. For example, the statement 4 + 5 = 9 is true, whereas the statement 2

More information

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets Introduction In this short article, we will describe some basic notions on cardinality of sets. Given two

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

Theorem. For every positive integer n, the sum of the positive integers from 1 to n is n(n+1)

Theorem. For every positive integer n, the sum of the positive integers from 1 to n is n(n+1) Week 1: Logic Lecture 1, 8/1 (Sections 1.1 and 1.3) Examples of theorems and proofs Theorem (Pythagoras). Let ABC be a right triangle, with legs of lengths a and b, and hypotenuse of length c. Then a +

More information

Introduction to Functions

Introduction to Functions Mathematics for Economists Introduction to Functions Introduction In economics we study the relationship between variables and attempt to explain these relationships through economic theory. For instance

More information

Set theory. Math 304 Spring 2007

Set theory. Math 304 Spring 2007 Math 304 Spring 2007 Set theory Contents 1. Sets 2 1.1. Objects and set formation 2 1.2. Unions and intersections 3 1.3. Differences 4 1.4. Power sets 4 1.5. Ordered pairs and binary,amscdcartesian products

More information

Mathematical Preliminaries. Sipser pages 1-28

Mathematical Preliminaries. Sipser pages 1-28 Mathematical Preliminaries Sipser pages 1-28 Mathematical Preliminaries This course is about the fundamental capabilities and limitations of computers. It has 3 parts 1. Automata Models of computation

More information

Selected problems from past exams

Selected problems from past exams Discrete Structures CS2800 Prelim 1 s Selected problems from past exams 1. True/false. For each of the following statements, indicate whether the statement is true or false. Give a one or two sentence

More information

More Books At www.goalias.blogspot.com www.goalias.blogspot.com www.goalias.blogspot.com www.goalias.blogspot.com www.goalias.blogspot.com www.goalias.blogspot.com www.goalias.blogspot.com www.goalias.blogspot.com

More information

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1 MAGIC Set theory lecture 1 David Asperó University of East Anglia 15 October 2014 Welcome Welcome to this set theory course. This will be a 10 hour introduction to set theory. The only prerequisite is

More information

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted Chapter 2 The Structure of R The purpose of this chapter is to explain to the reader why the set of real numbers is so special. By the end of this chapter, the reader should understand the difference between

More information

Lecture 3: the classification of equivalence relations and the definition of a topological space

Lecture 3: the classification of equivalence relations and the definition of a topological space Lecture 3: the classification of equivalence relations and the definition of a topological space Saul Glasman September 12, 2016 If there s a bijection f : X Y, we ll often say that X and Y are in bijection,

More information

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY About the Class Evaluation. Final grade will be based 25%, 25%, 25%, 25%, on homework, midterm 1, midterm 2, final exam. Exam dates. Midterm 1: Oct 4. Midterm 2:

More information

Foundations Revision Notes

Foundations Revision Notes oundations Revision Notes hese notes are designed as an aid not a substitute for revision. A lot of proofs have not been included because you should have them in your notes, should you need them. Also,

More information

LECTURE NOTES DISCRETE MATHEMATICS. Eusebius Doedel

LECTURE NOTES DISCRETE MATHEMATICS. Eusebius Doedel LECTURE NOTES on DISCRETE MATHEMATICS Eusebius Doedel 1 LOGIC Introduction. First we introduce some basic concepts needed in our discussion of logic. These will be covered in more detail later. A set is

More information

Sets, Logic, Relations, and Functions

Sets, Logic, Relations, and Functions Sets, Logic, Relations, and Functions Andrew Kay September 28, 2014 Abstract This is an introductory text, not a comprehensive study; these notes contain mainly definitions, basic results, and examples.

More information

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2017 Lecture 1 Monday July 17, 2017

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2017 Lecture 1 Monday July 17, 2017 Economics 04 Summer/Fall 07 Lecture Monday July 7, 07 Section.. Methods of Proof We begin by looking at the notion of proof. What is a proof? Proof has a formal definition in mathematical logic, and a

More information

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions Sect. 1.1.3: # 2, 3 (Page 7-8 Math 105A HW 1 Solutions 2(a ( Statement: Each positive integers has a unique prime factorization. n N: n = 1 or ( R N, p 1,..., p R P such that n = p 1 p R and ( n, R, S

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009 Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009 Our main goal is here is to do counting using functions. For that, we

More information

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions 6. Let M be a metric space, let C D M. Now we can think of C as a subset of the metric space M or as a subspace of the metric space D (D being a

More information

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 1 Real Numbers In these lectures, we are going to study a branch of mathematics called

More information

Math 280A Fall Axioms of Set Theory

Math 280A Fall Axioms of Set Theory Math 280A Fall 2009 1. Axioms of Set Theory Let V be the collection of all sets and be a membership relation. We consider (V, ) as a mathematical structure. Analogy: A group is a mathematical structure

More information

UMASS AMHERST MATH 300 SP 05, F. HAJIR HOMEWORK 8: (EQUIVALENCE) RELATIONS AND PARTITIONS

UMASS AMHERST MATH 300 SP 05, F. HAJIR HOMEWORK 8: (EQUIVALENCE) RELATIONS AND PARTITIONS UMASS AMHERST MATH 300 SP 05, F. HAJIR HOMEWORK 8: (EQUIVALENCE) RELATIONS AND PARTITIONS 1. Relations Recall the concept of a function f from a source set X to a target set Y. It is a rule for mapping

More information

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS WINTER 2014 Problem 1 (15 points). For each statement below, circle T or F according to whether the statement is true or false. You do NOT need to justify your answers. T F

More information

Topology Math Conrad Plaut

Topology Math Conrad Plaut Topology Math 467 2010 Conrad Plaut Contents Chapter 1. Background 1 1. Set Theory 1 2. Finite and Infinite Sets 3 3. Indexed Collections of Sets 4 Chapter 2. Topology of R and Beyond 7 1. The Topology

More information

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH RICHARD G HECK, JR 1. INTRODUCTION The purpose of this note is to give a simple, easily accessible proof of the existence of the minimal fixed point, and of various maximal fixed

More information

In mathematics there are endless ways that two entities can be related

In mathematics there are endless ways that two entities can be related CHAPTER 16 Relations In mathematics there are endless ways that two entities can be related to each other. Consider the following mathematical statements. 5 < 10 5 5 6 = 30 5 5 80 7 > 4 x y 8 3 a b ( mod

More information

Lecture 1. Econ 2001: Introduction to Mathematical Methods (a.k.a. Math Camp) 2015 August 10

Lecture 1. Econ 2001: Introduction to Mathematical Methods (a.k.a. Math Camp) 2015 August 10 Lecture 1 Econ 2001: Introduction to Mathematical Methods (a.k.a. Math Camp) 2015 August 10 Lecture 1 Outline 1 Logistics: Who, Where, When, What, How, Why, Stuff 2 Methods of Proof 3 Sets 4 Binary Relations

More information

0 Logical Background. 0.1 Sets

0 Logical Background. 0.1 Sets 0 Logical Background 0.1 Sets In this course we will use the term set to simply mean a collection of things which have a common property such as the totality of positive integers or the collection of points

More information

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS TOM CUCHTA 1. Introduction This paper was written as a final project for the 2013 Summer Session of Mathematical Logic 1 at Missouri S&T. We intend to present a short discussion

More information

Chapter 1. Logic and Proof

Chapter 1. Logic and Proof Chapter 1. Logic and Proof 1.1 Remark: A little over 100 years ago, it was found that some mathematical proofs contained paradoxes, and these paradoxes could be used to prove statements that were known

More information

Preliminaries to the Theory of Computation

Preliminaries to the Theory of Computation Preliminaries to the Theory of Computation 2 In this chapter, we explain mathematical notions, terminologies, and certain methods used in convincing logical arguments that we shall have need of throughout

More information

Numbers, sets, and functions

Numbers, sets, and functions Chapter 1 Numbers, sets, and functions 1.1. The natural numbers, integers, and rational numbers We assume that you are familiar with the set of natural numbers the set of integers and the set of rational

More information

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW 1. Sets As a review, we begin by considering a naive look at set theory. For our purposes, we define a set as a collection of objects. Except for certain sets like N, Z,

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31 Contents 1 Lecture 1: Introduction 2 2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction 7 3 Lecture 3: Induction and Well-Ordering Principle 11 4 Lecture 4: Definition of a Group and examples 15

More information

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued)

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued) 2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued) 2.1. New examples of commutative rings. Recall that in the first lecture we defined the notions of commutative rings and field and gave some examples of

More information

1.1 Statements and Compound Statements

1.1 Statements and Compound Statements Chapter 1 Propositional Logic 1.1 Statements and Compound Statements A statement or proposition is an assertion which is either true or false, though you may not know which. That is, a statement is something

More information

Math 10850, fall 2017, University of Notre Dame

Math 10850, fall 2017, University of Notre Dame Math 10850, fall 2017, University of Notre Dame Notes on first exam September 22, 2017 The key facts The first midterm will be on Thursday, September 28, 6.15pm-7.45pm in Hayes-Healy 127. What you need

More information

0 Sets and Induction. Sets

0 Sets and Induction. Sets 0 Sets and Induction Sets A set is an unordered collection of objects, called elements or members of the set. A set is said to contain its elements. We write a A to denote that a is an element of the set

More information

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES NATHANIEL GALLUP 1. Introduction Number theory begins as the study of the natural numbers the integers N = {1, 2, 3,...}, Z = { 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3,...}, and sometimes

More information

Meta-logic derivation rules

Meta-logic derivation rules Meta-logic derivation rules Hans Halvorson February 19, 2013 Recall that the goal of this course is to learn how to prove things about (as opposed to by means of ) classical first-order logic. So, we will

More information

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS BJORN POONEN 1 Some terminology of set theory N := {0, 1, 2, 3, } Z := {, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, } Q := the set of rational numbers R := the set of real numbers C := the set of complex

More information

On the scope of diagonal argument and on contradictory equivalence.

On the scope of diagonal argument and on contradictory equivalence. Daniil Teplitskiy, Russia, Saint Petersburg PSI Co. Ltd. 24JUN2011 To my teachers and good people Isaak Perchenok and Rustem Valeyev. To my friend Aleksey Kiselev whose intellectual paradigm underlies

More information

Part IA Numbers and Sets

Part IA Numbers and Sets Part IA Numbers and Sets Definitions Based on lectures by A. G. Thomason Notes taken by Dexter Chua Michaelmas 2014 These notes are not endorsed by the lecturers, and I have modified them (often significantly)

More information

Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition

Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition Abstract This document contains supplementary material, such as definitions, explanations, examples, etc., to complement that of the text, How to Think

More information

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017 MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017 Definition: A set A is finite if there exists a nonnegative integer c such that there exists a bijection from A

More information

Cartesian Products and Relations

Cartesian Products and Relations Cartesian Products and Relations Definition (Cartesian product) If A and B are sets, the Cartesian product of A and B is the set A B = {(a, b) : (a A) and (b B)}. The following points are worth special

More information

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist CS103 Winter 2019 Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist Cynthia Lee Keith Schwarz Now that we re transitioning to writing proofs about discrete structures like binary relations, functions, and graphs,

More information