Report 1 The Axiom of Choice

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Report 1 The Axiom of Choice"

Transcription

1 Report 1 The Axiom of Choice By Li Yu This report is a collection of the material I presented in the first round presentation of the course MATH The report focuses on the principle of recursive definition, the axiom of choice and its applications. Some proofs which were omitted in the presentations can be found here. 1. Principle of Recursive Definition Theorem 1.1 (Recursive Definition) Let A be a nonempty set, a 0 an element of A. Suppose is a function that assigns, to each function f mapping a section of the positive integers into A, an element of A. Then there exists a unique function h: Z + A satisfying: (1) h(1) = a 0 ; (2) h(i) = (h S i-1 ), for all integers i s.t. i 2. Proof We first prove that: (*) For any positive integer n, there exists a unique function h n : S n A satisfying: (1 ) h n (1) = a 0 ; (2 ) h n (i) = (h n S i-1 ), for all integers i s.t. 2 i n. Step Ⅰ When n = 1, define h 1 : S 1 A as h 1 (1) = a 0. It is immediately clear that h 1 satisfies (1 ) and (2 ), and such h 1 is unique. Step Ⅱ Assume that (*) is true when n=k. Define a function h k+1 : S k+1 A as h k+1 (i) = h k (i) for all integers i s.t. 1 i k, and h k+1 (k+1) = (h k ). By the definition of h k+1, it satisfies (1 ) and (2 ). Hence the existence of such a function when n = k+1 is proved. Let h k+1 : S k+1 A and h k+1 : S k+1 A be two functions satisfying (1 ) and (2 ). Then h k+1 S k and h k+1 S k are functions from S k into A satisfying (1 ) and (2 ). By the assumption of Step Ⅱ, h k+1 S k and h k+1 S k are identical. Hence, h k+1 (k+1) = (h k+1 S k ) = (h k+1 S k ) = h k+1 (k+1). This proves the uniqueness of such a function. Step Ⅲ By mathematical induction, (*) is true. Now define h: Z + A as such that the graph of it is the union of the graphs of h n in (*), where n is a positive integer. By (*), h m (n) = (h m S n )(n) = h n (n) for any positive integers m,n s.t. n<m. Hence h defined above is indeed a function and h(n) = h n (n) = h n+1 (n) = h n+2 (n) = To prove that h satisfies (1), we observe that h(1) = h 1 (1) = a 0. To prove that h satisfies (2), we observe that h(i) = h i (i) = (h i S i-1 ) = (h S i-1 ) for all integers i s.t. i 2. This completes the proof. Q.E.D. 1/7

2 Example We consider a simple case. The function h: Z + Z + s.t. h(n) = n for all positive integers n can be defined by recursive definition as a function h: Z + Z + satisfying h(1) = 1 and h(n) = h(n-1) + 1. We try to look for the in Theorem 1.1 for this recursion. For every function f Sk-1 from S k-1 into Z +, we define (f Sk-1 ) to be f Sk-1 (k-1) + 1, where k is a positive integer s.t. k 2. Then it is clear that h(n) = (h S n-1 ) = h(n-1) + 1, since h S n-1 is a function from S n-1 into Z +. Hence this is the desired in Theorem 1.1. Now we turn to the main part of this report. 2. The Axiom of Choice In this section we introduce the Axiom of Choice and prove the equivalence of different forms of this axiom. Axiom of Choice (AC 1 ) Let A be a set of pairwise disjoint nonempty sets. There exists a set C consisting of exactly one element of each member of A. Example Let A = {Z, Q-Z, R-Q}. It is obvious that A is a set of pairwise disjoint nonempty sets. The axiom of choice guarantees the existence of a set consisting of one and only one element of each of the sets Z, Q-Z, R-Q. C = {0, -1/2, } is an example of such a set. Example The previous example is trivial to some extent. Let us study another example. Let A be a set of pairwise disjoint nonempty sets consisting of two arbitrary elements, i.e. the members of A are doubletons. Is it possible for one to prove that there exists a set consisting of exactly one element of each member of A without referring to the Axiom of Choice, explicitly or implicitly? It seems quite plausible. But this time one cannot give a desired set explicitly, as we did in the previous example, since the members of A are arbitrary. How about choosing the larger element of each member of A? But what does one mean by larger? How about listing the elements of the members of A in the form of {a,b} and choosing the left element? But how does one list the elements, which one is written on the left? If one gives a rule to list these elements, why does he or she bother to list them? He or she may simply make a set consisting of elements that are intended to be written on the left. The axiom of choice justifies the practice of selecting something without explicitly stating the rule governing the selection. When one says let v be a vector which is not in the subspace spanned by, he or she is referring to the Axiom of Choice implicitly. There are quite a lot of circumstances where we refer to the Axiom of Choice in mathematics. To mention some of them: Hahn-Banach Theorem, every field has a unique algebraic closure. The Axiom of Choice can be formulated in different forms. We next 2/7

3 investigate two of them. Definition 2.1 f is a choice function for a set A if and only if f is a function from the set of all nonempty subsets of A into A and for every nonempty subset B of A, f(b) B. Example A choice function f for Z + may be defined as f(s) = the smallest element of S, where S is any nonempty subset of Z +. A choice function g for {Tommy, Jerry} may be defined as g({tommy}) = Tommy, g({jerry}) = Jerry and g({tommy, Jerry}) = Jerry. Intuitively, a choice function for a set is a function which chooses an element from each nonempty subset of the set. Axiom of Choice (AC 2 ) Every nonempty set has a choice function. Theorem 2.1 AC 1 and AC 2 are equivalent. Proof AC 1 => AC 2 ) For any nonempty subset B of A, define S B = {(B, b): b B}. Then define S = {S B : B is nonempty subset of A}. For any distinct nonempty subsets B 1 and B 2 of A, S B1 and S B2 are disjoint since the first components of all elements of S B1 are B 1, whereas those of all elements of S B2 are B 2. Hence by AC 1, there exists a set C consisting of exactly one element of each member of S. By the definition of C, for every nonempty subset B of A, there exists a unique element b B s.t. (B, b) C. Hence there exists a function F from the set of all nonempty subsets of A into A whose graph is C, i.e. F(B) B. This proves what we want. AC 2 => AC 1 ) Let S = {x: x B, for some B A }. By the definition of S, B is contained in S for every member B of A. By AC 2, S has a choice function F. Let C = {F(B): B A}. For any B A, F(B) is an element of B and F(B) C. Assume there exists a set B 0 in A s.t. b 1 and b 2 are distinct elements of B 0 which are also elements of C. Then by the definition of C, there exist sets B 1 and B 2 in A s.t. F(B 1 ) = b 1 and F(B 2 ) = b 2 and hence b 1 B 1 and b 2 B 2. Then b 1 B 1, b 1 B 0, and hence B 1 = B 0, since the members of A are disjoint. Similarly, B 2 = B 0, which implies B 1 = B 2. Hence b 1 = F(B 1 ) = F(B 2 ) = b 2. This contradicts the assertion that b 1 and b 2 are distinct. So we conclude that C consists of exactly one element of each member of A. This proves AC 1. Q.E.D. Axiom of Choice (AC 3 ) Let A be a set of pairwise disjoint nonempty sets. The Cartesian product of the sets in A is nonempty. Theorem 2.2 AC 1 and AC 3 are equivalent. The simple proof of Theorem 2.2 is omitted. 3/7

4 Although the content of the axiom of choice seems intuitively clear, or trivial, as you like, amazing consequences of it can be deduced. The next theorem is rather revealing. Theorem 2.3 (Banach-Tarski Paradox) Given a solid ball in R 3, it is possible to partition it into finitely many pieces and reassemble them to form two solid balls, each identical in size to the first. Idea of the proof Quite a lot of abstract algebra is used. The group of rotations in R 3 is involved and the crucial step of the proof is to apply AC 1 to the set of all cosets of a subgroup of this group. This counterintuitive logical consequence of the Axiom of Choice was first proposed by Banach and Tarski with the intention to reject this axiom. The Banach-Tarski Paradox shows to us that the Axiom of Choice is not as trivial as we once imagined. Unfortunately, there is no elementary proof available. 3. Applications of the Axiom of Choice In this section we study some applications of the Axiom of Choice. We use this axiom to prove two theorems, Hausdorff Maximal Principle and Zorn s Lemma, which are widely referred to in practice, and then indicate that they are actually equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. Definition 3.1 A relation R on a set A is called an order relation if it has the following properties: (1) For every x and y in A for which x y, either xry or yrx; (2) For no x in A does the relation xrx hold; (3) If xry and yrz, then xrz. Example The ordinary less than relation on the set of all real numbers is an order relation. So is the ordinary relation of greater than on the same set. The relation R on the set R R defined as (r 1,r 2 )R(s 1,s 2 ) if r 1 <s 1 or r 1 = s 1 and r 2 <s 2 is an order relation. The inclusion relation on the power set of a set need not be an order relation, since property (1) fails to hold in general. Definition 3.2 Let A be a set and < be an order relation on A. a is said to be the smallest element of a subset X of A if a X and for every x X, a = x or a<x. Definition 3.3 A set A with an order relation < is said to be well-ordered if every nonempty subset of A has a smallest element. Example The set Z + of all positive integers is well-ordered by the ordinary less than relation, as can be easily proved by mathematical induction. In fact, one may show that the Well-ordering Property of Z + implies the Principle of Mathematical Induction. However, the set R of all real numbers is not well-ordered by the ordinary less than relation, since the open interval (a, b), where a<b, does not have a smallest element. It should also be noticed that Z + is not well-ordered by the ordinary greater than relation. Hence, well-orderedness of a set does not depend on the set alone. But we have the following beautiful theorem. Theorem 3.1 (Well-ordering Theorem) If A is a set, then there exists an order relation on A that well-orders A. 4/7

5 Idea of the proof The proof is split into two stages. The first stage is to prove that there exists a well-ordered set of any given size. The second is to construct by transfinite recursion, with the help of the choice function for A, a bijection from A into one of the well-ordered sets, which preserves the order. Example To have a concrete understanding of the proof, let us construct an order relation on Z, which is not well-ordered by the ordinary less than relation. Define f: Z Z + as f(z) = 2z when z 0 and f(z) = -2z-1 when z<0. It is clear that f is a bijection. Define a relation R on Z as z 1 Rz 2 if f(z 1 )<f(z 2 ), the reader may prove without difficulty that R well-orders Z. From the idea of the proof we see that the Well-ordering Theorem is a logical consequence of the Axiom of Choice. An interesting fact is that the inverse is also true, i.e. the Axiom of Choice is derivable from the Well-ordering Theorem. Therefore, the Well-ordering Theorem is said to be equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. Historically, numerous equivalent versions of the Axiom of Choice have been used by mathematicians. The famous and practically important ones are listed without formal proof below. Definition 3.4 A relation R on a set A is called a strict partial order relation if it has the following properties: (1) For no x in A does the relation xrx hold; (2) If xry and yrz, then xrz. Example Note that every order relation on a set is a strict partial order relation. Hence every example following definition 3.1 is an example of strict partial order relation. To differentiate between the two concepts, consider the Cartesian product Z + Z +. Define a relation R on Z + Z + as (m 1,n 1 )R(m 2,n 2 ) if m 1 = m 2 and n 1 <n 2. The reader may easily verify by definition that R is a strict partial order relation on Z + Z +. However, it is neither the case that (1,2)R(2,1) nor (2,1)R(1,2). The first condition of definition 3.1 is not satisfied, so R is not an order relation Z + Z +. The adjective strict indicates that xrx does not hold. It may be omitted without taking the risk of ambiguity in this report. The adjective partial refers to the fact clearly illustrated in the last example, i.e. it is not the case that any two elements are comparable. In this sense, strictly partially ordered sets behave more randomly than well-ordered ones. But patterns can indeed be observed in strictly partially ordered sets, as the next theorem will illustrate. Definition 3.5 Let R be a strict partial order relation on a set A. A subset C of A is said to be a chain in A if R, when restricted to C, is an order relation on C. Definition 3.6 A chain C 0 in a strictly partially ordered set A is said to be a maximal chain if for any chain C in A, it is not the case that C 0 is properly contained in C. Theorem 3.2 (Hausdorff Maximal Principle) Every strictly partially ordered set has a maximal chain. Example Consider the set Z + Z + and the relation R studied above. C = 5/7

6 {(1,n): n Z + } is a chain in Z + Z +, since any two elements in C are comparable with respect to R. For any chain C in Z + Z + which properly contains C, it must have an element whose first component is not 1. This element is not comparable with (1,1), which is in C. This contradicts the assertion that C is a chain. Hence C is a maximal chain in Z + Z +. Idea of the proof Assume there is no maximal chain in a strictly partially ordered set. Then every chain in this set can be extended. Let C be a chain in this set and S C, the set of all chains properly containing C. We may define a function f on the set of all chains by associating every chain C to a chain in S C, which can be done by applying AC 2 to S C, where C goes through all chains in the set considered. This definition can be intuitively understood as to extend the chains. Then we prove that such a function has a fixed point, i.e. f(c) = C for some chain C. This contradicts the construction of the function f, since, by definition, f(c) is a proper extension of C. Now we proceed to Zorn s Lemma. Definition 3.7 Let R be a strict partial order relation on a set A and B, a subset of A. An element x of A is said to be an upper bound of B if for every b in B, either b = x or brx. An element m of A is said to be a maximal element of A if for no a in A does the relation mra hold. It is no harm to define the concepts of lower bound and minimal element, although these concepts will not be used in the following context. The definition is as follows. Definition 3.8 Let R be a strict partial order relation on a set A and B, a subset of A. An element x of A is said to be a lower bound of B if for every b in B, either x = b or xrb. An element m of A is said to be a minimal element of A if for no a in A does the relation arm hold. Theorem 3.3 (Zorn s Lemma) Let A be a strictly partially ordered set. If every chain in A has an upper bound, then A has a maximal element. Example Consider the set Z + of positive integers with the ordinary greater than as the strict partial order. Every chain in Z + has an upper bound, which is the least integer in the chain, and we know that 1 in the maximal element in Z +. Another example which is slightly different may be constructed by considering the Cartesian product (R-R - ) (R-R - ) of nonnegative real numbers and itself, together with a relation R defined as (a,b)r(c,d) if a>c and b = d. Every chain in (R-R - ) (R-R - ) is of the form {(a,b): b = r} for some fixed r in R-R -, and (0,r) is an upper bound of such a chain. Hence, by Zorn s lemma, we know that (R-R - ) (R-R - ) has a maximal element. This time we have infinitely many maximal elements and every element of the form (0,r), where r is a nonnegative real number, is a maximal element. Idea of the proof Let us, again, demonstrate the power of the axiom of choice informally. To prove Theorem 3.3, we define, by transfinite recursion, an increasing (with respect to the strict partial order) transfinite sequence and then prove that there is an element in this sequence which is a maximal element. The 6/7

7 choice function plays an analogous role to the function does in Recursive Definition. The significance of the Axiom of Choice in this proof is that we may state explicitly what the function is when we define something by the Principle of Recursive Definition, while it is not always as easy to find such a function in the general case. An alternative, and probably much simpler, way to prove Zorn s Lemma is to use Hausdoff Maximal Principle. Note that the upper bound of a maximal chain, if exists, must be a maximal element, as the readers may easily verify. By the assumption of Zorn s Lemma, the upper bound of a maximal chain does exist. This proves the theorem. We conclude this section by establishing the equivalence of Hausdorff Maximal Principle and Zorn s Lemma to the Axiom of Choice. Theorem 3.4 Zorn s Lemma and Hausdorff Maximal Principle are equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. 4. Conclusion This report deals with some basic concepts of set theory and the Axiom of Choice. It starts from the Principle of Recursive Definition, then introduces the Axiom of Choice and discusses briefly some applications of this axiom. The Axiom of Choice has been studied in great details by mathematicians. This report only covers a very small part of it, but I hope that it provides the readers with reasonable amount of background knowledge in this area. 7/7

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SYLVIA DURIAN Abstract. This paper develops the ordinal numbers and transfinite induction, then demonstrates some interesting applications of transfinite induction.

More information

Products, Relations and Functions

Products, Relations and Functions Products, Relations and Functions For a variety of reasons, in this course it will be useful to modify a few of the settheoretic preliminaries in the first chapter of Munkres. The discussion below explains

More information

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC CHRISTOPHER WILSON Abstract. We present a basic axiomatic development of Zermelo-Fraenkel and Choice set theory, commonly abbreviated ZFC. This paper is aimed in particular

More information

Relations and Equivalence Relations

Relations and Equivalence Relations Relations and Equivalence Relations In this section, we shall introduce a formal definition for the notion of a relation on a set. This is something we often take for granted in elementary algebra courses,

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) VI.1 : Indexed families and set theoretic operations (Halmos, 4, 8 9; Lipschutz, 5.3 5.4) Lipschutz : 5.3 5.6, 5.29 5.32, 9.14 1. Generalize

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n 10. Algebraic closure Definition 10.1. Let K be a field. The algebraic closure of K, denoted K, is an algebraic field extension L/K such that every polynomial in K[x] splits in L. We say that K is algebraically

More information

9 RELATIONS. 9.1 Reflexive, symmetric and transitive relations. MATH Foundations of Pure Mathematics

9 RELATIONS. 9.1 Reflexive, symmetric and transitive relations. MATH Foundations of Pure Mathematics MATH10111 - Foundations of Pure Mathematics 9 RELATIONS 9.1 Reflexive, symmetric and transitive relations Let A be a set with A. A relation R on A is a subset of A A. For convenience, for x, y A, write

More information

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products Chapter 3 Cartesian Products and Relations The material in this chapter is the first real encounter with abstraction. Relations are very general thing they are a special type of subset. After introducing

More information

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma Any indexed family of sets A ={Ai: i I} may be conceived as a variable set, to wit, as a set varying over the index set I. Each Ai is then the value of the variable

More information

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han Set, functions and Euclidean space Seungjin Han September, 2018 1 Some Basics LOGIC A is necessary for B : If B holds, then A holds. B A A B is the contraposition of B A. A is sufficient for B: If A holds,

More information

EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS (NOTES FOR STUDENTS) 1. RELATIONS

EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS (NOTES FOR STUDENTS) 1. RELATIONS EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS (NOTES FOR STUDENTS) LIOR SILBERMAN Version 1.0 compiled September 9, 2015. 1.1. List of examples. 1. RELATIONS Equality of real numbers: for some x,y R we have x = y. For other pairs

More information

MATH 433 Applied Algebra Lecture 14: Functions. Relations.

MATH 433 Applied Algebra Lecture 14: Functions. Relations. MATH 433 Applied Algebra Lecture 14: Functions. Relations. Cartesian product Definition. The Cartesian product X Y of two sets X and Y is the set of all ordered pairs (x,y) such that x X and y Y. The Cartesian

More information

Properties of the Integers

Properties of the Integers Properties of the Integers The set of all integers is the set and the subset of Z given by Z = {, 5, 4, 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, }, N = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, }, is the set of nonnegative integers (also called

More information

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c.

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c. Properties of the Integers The set of all integers is the set and the subset of Z given by Z = {, 5, 4, 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, }, N = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, }, is the set of nonnegative integers (also called

More information

Axioms for Set Theory

Axioms for Set Theory Axioms for Set Theory The following is a subset of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms for set theory. In this setting, all objects are sets which are denoted by letters, e.g. x, y, X, Y. Equality is logical identity:

More information

The Axiom of Choice. Contents. 1 Motivation 2. 2 The Axiom of Choice 2. 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4. 4 Zorn s Lemma 5. 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6

The Axiom of Choice. Contents. 1 Motivation 2. 2 The Axiom of Choice 2. 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4. 4 Zorn s Lemma 5. 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6 The Axiom of Choice Contents 1 Motivation 2 2 The Axiom of Choice 2 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4 4 Zorn s Lemma 5 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6 6 More equivalences of AC 11 7 Consequences of the Axiom of

More information

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY About the Class Evaluation. Final grade will be based 25%, 25%, 25%, 25%, on homework, midterm 1, midterm 2, final exam. Exam dates. Midterm 1: Oct 4. Midterm 2:

More information

Week 4-5: Generating Permutations and Combinations

Week 4-5: Generating Permutations and Combinations Week 4-5: Generating Permutations and Combinations February 27, 2017 1 Generating Permutations We have learned that there are n! permutations of {1, 2,...,n}. It is important in many instances to generate

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

Real Analysis. Jesse Peterson

Real Analysis. Jesse Peterson Real Analysis Jesse Peterson February 1, 2017 2 Contents 1 Preliminaries 7 1.1 Sets.................................. 7 1.1.1 Countability......................... 8 1.1.2 Transfinite induction.....................

More information

Section 0.7. The Axiom of Choice, Order, and Zorn s Lemma

Section 0.7. The Axiom of Choice, Order, and Zorn s Lemma 0.7. The Axiom of Choice, Order, and Zorn s Lemma 1 Section 0.7. The Axiom of Choice, Order, and Zorn s Lemma Note. In this section, we state the Axiom of Choice and two statements equivalent to it (Zorn

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10 Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10 Inductive sets (used to define the natural numbers as a subset of R) (1) Definition: A set S R is an inductive

More information

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Math/CS 20: Intro. to Math Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Week 5 UCSB 204 The Integers Normally, using the natural numbers, you can easily define

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination Answer Key 1 1. [25 points] Let X be a set with 2 or more elements. Show that there are topologies U and V on X such that the identity map J : (X, U)

More information

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008 Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008 Closed sets We have been operating at a fundamental level at which a topological space is a set together

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

= ϕ r cos θ. 0 cos ξ sin ξ and sin ξ cos ξ. sin ξ 0 cos ξ

= ϕ r cos θ. 0 cos ξ sin ξ and sin ξ cos ξ. sin ξ 0 cos ξ 8. The Banach-Tarski paradox May, 2012 The Banach-Tarski paradox is that a unit ball in Euclidean -space can be decomposed into finitely many parts which can then be reassembled to form two unit balls

More information

ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS

ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS KEITH CONRAD 1. Introduction Zorn s lemma is a result in set theory that appears in proofs of some non-constructive existence theorems throughout mathematics. We will

More information

Standard forms for writing numbers

Standard forms for writing numbers Standard forms for writing numbers In order to relate the abstract mathematical descriptions of familiar number systems to the everyday descriptions of numbers by decimal expansions and similar means,

More information

The Axiom of Choice and the Banach-Tarski Paradox

The Axiom of Choice and the Banach-Tarski Paradox The Axiom of Choice and the Banach-Tarski Paradox Department of Mathematical Sciences Lakehead University March 2011 The Axiom of Choice Axiom of Choice (Suppes 1960) For any set A there is a function

More information

Introduction to Topology

Introduction to Topology Introduction to Topology Randall R. Holmes Auburn University Typeset by AMS-TEX Chapter 1. Metric Spaces 1. Definition and Examples. As the course progresses we will need to review some basic notions about

More information

The Measure Problem. Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN , USA

The Measure Problem. Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN , USA The Measure Problem Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN 47907-2067, USA A problem of Banach is to determine the structure of a nonnegative (countably additive)

More information

VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties

VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties Near the end of Section V I.4 we listed several basic questions about transfinite cardinal numbers, and we shall restate them here for the sake of convenience:

More information

Chapter 1 Preliminaries

Chapter 1 Preliminaries Chapter 1 Preliminaries 1.1 Conventions and Notations Throughout the book we use the following notations for standard sets of numbers: N the set {1, 2,...} of natural numbers Z the set of integers Q the

More information

Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

Cosets and Lagrange s theorem Cosets and Lagrange s theorem These are notes on cosets and Lagrange s theorem some of which may already have been lecturer. There are some questions for you included in the text. You should write the

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem These are notes on cosets and Lagrange s theorem; they go over some material from the lectures again, and they have some new material it is all examinable,

More information

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces Chapter 2 Metric Spaces The purpose of this chapter is to present a summary of some basic properties of metric and topological spaces that play an important role in the main body of the book. 2.1 Metrics

More information

Maths 212: Homework Solutions

Maths 212: Homework Solutions Maths 212: Homework Solutions 1. The definition of A ensures that x π for all x A, so π is an upper bound of A. To show it is the least upper bound, suppose x < π and consider two cases. If x < 1, then

More information

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets Introduction In this short article, we will describe some basic notions on cardinality of sets. Given two

More information

Discrete Mathematics with Applications MATH236

Discrete Mathematics with Applications MATH236 Discrete Mathematics with Applications MATH236 Dr. Hung P. Tong-Viet School of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science University of KwaZulu-Natal Pietermaritzburg Campus Semester 1, 2013 Tong-Viet

More information

0.2 Vector spaces. J.A.Beachy 1

0.2 Vector spaces. J.A.Beachy 1 J.A.Beachy 1 0.2 Vector spaces I m going to begin this section at a rather basic level, giving the definitions of a field and of a vector space in much that same detail as you would have met them in a

More information

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting Countability 1 Motivation In topology as well as other areas of mathematics, we deal with a lot of infinite sets. However, as we will gradually discover, some infinite sets are bigger than others. Countably

More information

HILBERT SPACES AND THE RADON-NIKODYM THEOREM. where the bar in the first equation denotes complex conjugation. In either case, for any x V define

HILBERT SPACES AND THE RADON-NIKODYM THEOREM. where the bar in the first equation denotes complex conjugation. In either case, for any x V define HILBERT SPACES AND THE RADON-NIKODYM THEOREM STEVEN P. LALLEY 1. DEFINITIONS Definition 1. A real inner product space is a real vector space V together with a symmetric, bilinear, positive-definite mapping,

More information

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction (David Ross, UH-Manoa Dept. of Mathematics) 1 Cardinality Recall the following notions: function, relation, one-to-one, onto, on-to-one correspondence,

More information

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT)

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT) CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT) MATH 378, CSUSM. SPRING 2009. AITKEN This chapter reviews some of the background concepts needed for Math 378. This chapter is new to the course (added Spring

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Ivan Avramidi New Mexico Institute of Mining and Technology Socorro, NM 87801 June 3, 2004 Author: Ivan Avramidi; File: absmath.tex; Date: June 11,

More information

Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement. sentential connectives. negation. conjunction. disjunction

Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement. sentential connectives. negation. conjunction. disjunction Copyright & License Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement sentential connectives negation conjunction disjunction implication or conditional antecedant & consequent hypothesis

More information

Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics. October 15, 2018 DRAFT

Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics. October 15, 2018 DRAFT Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics October 15, 2018 2 Contents 1 Basic Set Theory 5 1.1 Basic Set Theory....................................... 5 1.1.1 Union and Intersection of Sets...........................

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

Locally convex spaces, the hyperplane separation theorem, and the Krein-Milman theorem

Locally convex spaces, the hyperplane separation theorem, and the Krein-Milman theorem 56 Chapter 7 Locally convex spaces, the hyperplane separation theorem, and the Krein-Milman theorem Recall that C(X) is not a normed linear space when X is not compact. On the other hand we could use semi

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n 8 CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

The Banach-Tarski paradox

The Banach-Tarski paradox The Banach-Tarski paradox 1 Non-measurable sets In these notes I want to present a proof of the Banach-Tarski paradox, a consequence of the axiom of choice that shows us that a naive understanding of the

More information

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem Tel Aviv University, 2013 Measure and category 30 4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem 4a Vitali set....................... 30 4b No choice....................... 31 4c Dependent choice..................

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

Foundations of algebra

Foundations of algebra Foundations of algebra Equivalence relations - suggested problems - solutions P1: There are several relations that you are familiar with: Relations on R (or any of its subsets): Equality. Symbol: x = y.

More information

Notes on the Dual Ramsey Theorem

Notes on the Dual Ramsey Theorem Notes on the Dual Ramsey Theorem Reed Solomon July 29, 2010 1 Partitions and infinite variable words The goal of these notes is to give a proof of the Dual Ramsey Theorem. This theorem was first proved

More information

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE D-MAXIMAL SETS PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE Abstract. Soare [23] proved that the maximal sets form an orbit in E. We consider here D-maximal sets, generalizations of maximal sets introduced

More information

A CONTINUOUS MOVEMENT VERSION OF THE BANACH TARSKI PARADOX: A SOLUTION TO DE GROOT S PROBLEM

A CONTINUOUS MOVEMENT VERSION OF THE BANACH TARSKI PARADOX: A SOLUTION TO DE GROOT S PROBLEM The Journal of Symbolic Logic Volume 70, Number 3, Sept. 2005 A CONTINUOUS MOVEMENT VERSION OF THE BANACH TARSKI PARADOX: A SOLUTION TO DE GROOT S PROBLEM TREVOR M. WILSON Abstract. In 1924 Banach and

More information

Filters in Analysis and Topology

Filters in Analysis and Topology Filters in Analysis and Topology David MacIver July 1, 2004 Abstract The study of filters is a very natural way to talk about convergence in an arbitrary topological space, and carries over nicely into

More information

CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R

CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R LECTURE NOTES FOR MATH 378 (CSUSM, SPRING 2009). WAYNE AITKEN In the previous chapter we discussed the need for a complete ordered field. The field Q is not complete, so we constructed

More information

Exploring the Exotic Setting for Algebraic Geometry

Exploring the Exotic Setting for Algebraic Geometry Exploring the Exotic Setting for Algebraic Geometry Victor I. Piercey University of Arizona Integration Workshop Project August 6-10, 2010 1 Introduction In this project, we will describe the basic topology

More information

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs MAT 1362 Fall 2018 Alistair Savage Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0

More information

Math 109 September 1, 2016

Math 109 September 1, 2016 Math 109 September 1, 2016 Question 1 Given that the proposition P Q is true. Which of the following must also be true? A. (not P ) or Q. B. (not Q) implies (not P ). C. Q implies P. D. A and B E. A, B,

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Hilbert spaces. 1. Cauchy-Schwarz-Bunyakowsky inequality

Hilbert spaces. 1. Cauchy-Schwarz-Bunyakowsky inequality (October 29, 2016) Hilbert spaces Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ [This document is http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/m/fun/notes 2016-17/03 hsp.pdf] Hilbert spaces are

More information

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2. MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2. This text is based on the following books: Topology by James Dugundgji Fundamental concepts of topology by Peter O Neil Elements of Mathematics: General Topology

More information

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University Sets, Models and Proofs I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University 2000; revised, 2006 Contents 1 Sets 1 1.1 Cardinal Numbers........................ 2 1.1.1 The Continuum

More information

Notes on the Banach-Tarski Paradox

Notes on the Banach-Tarski Paradox Notes on the Banach-Tarski Paradox Donald Brower May 6, 2006 The Banach-Tarski paradox is not a logical paradox, but rather a counter intuitive result. It says that a ball can be broken into a finite number

More information

Topological properties

Topological properties CHAPTER 4 Topological properties 1. Connectedness Definitions and examples Basic properties Connected components Connected versus path connected, again 2. Compactness Definition and first examples Topological

More information

Numbers, sets, and functions

Numbers, sets, and functions Chapter 1 Numbers, sets, and functions 1.1. The natural numbers, integers, and rational numbers We assume that you are familiar with the set of natural numbers the set of integers and the set of rational

More information

Chapter VI. Relations. Assumptions are the termites of relationships. Henry Winkler

Chapter VI. Relations. Assumptions are the termites of relationships. Henry Winkler Chapter VI Relations Assumptions are the termites of relationships. Henry Winkler Studying relationships between objects can yield important information about the objects themselves. In the real numbers,

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

CSCI3390-Lecture 6: An Undecidable Problem

CSCI3390-Lecture 6: An Undecidable Problem CSCI3390-Lecture 6: An Undecidable Problem September 21, 2018 1 Summary The language L T M recognized by the universal Turing machine is not decidable. Thus there is no algorithm that determines, yes or

More information

Lecture 7: Relations

Lecture 7: Relations Lecture 7: Relations 1 Relation Relation between two objects signify some connection between them. For example, relation of one person being biological parent of another. If we take any two people at random,

More information

MA103 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Second part, Analysis and Algebra

MA103 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Second part, Analysis and Algebra 206/7 MA03 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Second part, Analysis and Algebra Amol Sasane Revised by Jozef Skokan, Konrad Swanepoel, and Graham Brightwell Copyright c London School of Economics 206

More information

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET 1. THE AXIOM OF FOUNDATION Early on in the book (page 6) it is indicated that throughout the formal development set is going to mean pure set, or set whose elements,

More information

Guide to Proofs on Discrete Structures

Guide to Proofs on Discrete Structures CS103 Handout 17 Spring 2018 Guide to Proofs on Discrete Structures In Problem Set One, you got practice with the art of proofwriting in general (as applied to numbers, sets, puzzles, etc.) Problem Set

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

On the Properties of Positive Spanning Sets and Positive Bases

On the Properties of Positive Spanning Sets and Positive Bases Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) On the Properties of Positive Spanning Sets and Positive Bases Rommel G. Regis Received: May 30, 2015 / Accepted: date Abstract The concepts of positive

More information

Generating Permutations and Combinations

Generating Permutations and Combinations Generating Permutations and Combinations March 0, 005 Generating Permutations We have learned that there are n! permutations of {,,, n} It is important in many instances to generate a list of such permutations

More information

Sequences of height 1 primes in Z[X]

Sequences of height 1 primes in Z[X] Sequences of height 1 primes in Z[X] Stephen McAdam Department of Mathematics University of Texas Austin TX 78712 mcadam@math.utexas.edu Abstract: For each partition J K of {1, 2,, n} (n 2) with J 2, let

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

0 Sets and Induction. Sets

0 Sets and Induction. Sets 0 Sets and Induction Sets A set is an unordered collection of objects, called elements or members of the set. A set is said to contain its elements. We write a A to denote that a is an element of the set

More information

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability 1 Motivation Up to now we have been mentioning the notion of sequence convergence without actually defining it. So in this section we will

More information

/633 Introduction to Algorithms Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Matroids and Greedy Algorithms Date: 10/31/16

/633 Introduction to Algorithms Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Matroids and Greedy Algorithms Date: 10/31/16 60.433/633 Introduction to Algorithms Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Matroids and Greedy Algorithms Date: 0/3/6 6. Introduction We talked a lot the last lecture about greedy algorithms. While both Prim

More information

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems Logic SEP: Day 1 July 15, 2013 1 Some references Syllabus: http://www.math.wisc.edu/graduate/guide-qe Previous years qualifying exams: http://www.math.wisc.edu/ miller/old/qual/index.html Miller s Moore

More information

Supplement. Algebraic Closure of a Field

Supplement. Algebraic Closure of a Field Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 1 Supplement. Algebraic Closure of a Field Note. In this supplement, we give some background material which is used in the proof of Fraleigh s Theorem 31.17/31.22

More information

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory? Chapter 1 Axiomatic set theory 1.1 Why axiomatic set theory? Essentially all mathematical theories deal with sets in one way or another. In most cases, however, the use of set theory is limited to its

More information

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014 Functions and cardinality (solutions) 21-127 sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014 What follows is a somewhat hastily written collection of solutions for my review sheet. I have omitted some

More information

Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization

Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization Zachary Mesyan March 11, 2018 Abstract The goal of this paper is to generalize the theory of triangularizing matrices to linear transformations of an arbitrary vector

More information