DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )"

Transcription

1 Contents 1 Sets 1 2 The Real Numbers 9 3 Sequences 29 4 Series 59 5 Functions 81 6 Power Series The elementary functions 111

2 Chapter 1 Sets It is very convenient to introduce some notation and terminology from set theory. A set is just a collection of objects which will usually be certain mathematical objects, such as numbers, points in the plane, functions or some such. If A denotes some given set and x denotes an object belonging to A, then this fact is indicated by the expression x A to be read as x belongs to A, or x is a member of A, or x is an element of A. If x denotes some object which does not belong to the set A, then this is indicated by the symbolism x / A and is read as x does not belong to A, or x is not a member of A, or x is not an element of A. To say that the sets A and B are equal is to say that they have the same elements. In other words, to say that A = B is to say both that if x A then also x B and if y B then also y A. We can write this as { x A = x B A = B is the same as y B = y A. The verification that given sets A and B are equal is made up of two parts. The first is the verification that every element of A is also an element of B and the second part is the verification that every element of B is also an element of A. We list a few examples of sets and also introduce some notation. 1

3 2 Chapter 1 Examples The set consisting of the three integers 2, 3, 4. We write this as { 2, 3, 4 }. 2. The set of natural numbers { 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6,... } (i.e., all strictly positive integers). This set is denoted by N. Notice that 0 / N. 3. The set of all real numbers, denoted by R. For example, 8, 11, 0, 5, 1 2, 1 3, π are elements of R. 4. The set of complex numbers is denoted by C. 5. The set of all integers (positive, negative and including zero) is denoted by Z. 6. The set of all rational numbers (all real numbers of the form m n for integers m, n with n 0) is denoted by Q. For example, the real numbers 3 4, 17 9, 0, 78, 3 belong to Q, but 2 / Q. 7. The set of even natural numbers { 2, 4, 6, 8,... }. This could also be written as { n N : n = 2m for some m N }. (The colon : stands for such that (or with the property that ), so this can be read as the set of all n in N such that n = 2m for some m in N.) 8. The set { x R : x > 1 } is the set of all those real numbers strictly greater than The set { z C : z = 1 } is the set of complex numbers with absolute value equal to 1. This is the unit circle in C ( the circle with centre at the origin and with radius equal to 1). Certain sets of real numbers, so-called intervals, are given a special notation with the use of round and square brackets. Let a R and b R and suppose that a < b. { x R : a x b } is denoted [ a, b] (closed interval) { x R : a < x < b } is denoted (a, b) (open interval) { x R : a x < b } is denoted [ a, b) (closed-open interval) { x R : a < x b } is denoted (a, b] (open-closed interval) { x R : x a } is denoted (, a] { x R : x < a } is denoted (, a) { x R : a x } is denoted [ a, ) { x R : a < x } is denoted (a, ). Department of Mathematics

4 Sets 3 It is important to realize that all this is just notation a useful visual short-hand. In particular, the symbol is used in four of the cases. This in no way is meant to imply that represents a real number it positively, absolutely, certainly is not. is not a real number. There is no such real number as. Given sets A and B, we say that A is a subset of B if every element of A is also an element of B, i.e., x A = x B. If this is the case, we write A B read A is a subset of B. By virtue of our earlier discussion of the equality A = B, we can say that A = B is equivalent to if and only if We have N R, Q R, N Z. both A B and B A. Definition 1.2. Suppose that A and B are given sets. The union of A and B, denoted by A B, is the set with elements which belong to either A or B (or both); A B = { x : x A or x B } read A union B equals.... Note that the usage of the word or allows both. In non-mathematical language, the union A B is obtained by bundling together everything in A and everything in B. Clearly, by construction, A A B and also B A B. Example 1.3. Suppose that A = { 1, 2, 3 } and B = { 3, 6, 8 }. Then we find that A B = { 1, 2, 3, 6, 8 }. Definition 1.4. The intersection of A and B, denoted by A B, is the set with elements which belong to both A and B; read A intersect B equals.... A B = { x : x A and x B } In non-mathematical language, the intersection A B is got by selecting everything which belongs to both A and B. Clearly, by construction, we see that A B A and also A B B. King s College London

5 4 Chapter 1 Example 1.5. With A = { 1, 2, 3 } and B = { 3, 6, 8 }, as in the example above, we see that A B = { 3 }. If A and B have no elements in common then their intersection A B has no elements at all. It is convenient to provide a symbol for this situation. We let denote the set with no elements. is called the empty set. Then A B = if A and B have no common elements. In such a situation, we say that A and B are disjoint. Example 1.6. Let A and B be the intervals in R given as A = (1, 4] and B = (4, 6). Then A B = and A B = (1, 6). Remark 1.7. Let A and B be given sets and consider the truth, or otherwise, of the statement A B. This fails to be true precisely when A possesses an element which is not a member of B. Now suppose that A =. The statement B is false provided that there is some nuisance element of which is not an element of B. However, has no elements at all, so there can be no such nuisance element. In other words, the statement B cannot be false and consequently must be true; obeys B for any set B. This might seem a bit odd, but is just a logical consequence of the formalism. Theorem 1.8. For sets A, B and C, we have (1) A (B C) = (A B) (A C). (2) A (B C) = (A B) (A C). Proof. (1) We must show that lhs rhs and that rhs lhs. First, we shall show that lhs rhs. If lhs =, then we are done, because is a subset of any set. So now suppose that lhs and let x lhs = A (B C). Then x A or x (B C) (or both). (i) Suppose x A. Then x A B and also x A C and therefore x (A B) (A C), that is, x rhs. (ii) Suppose that x (B C). Then x B and x C and so x A B and also x A C. Therefore x (A B) (A C), that is, x rhs. So in either case (i) or (ii) (and at least one these must be true), we find that x rhs. Since x lhs is arbitrary, we deduce that every element of the left hand side is also an element of the right hand side, that is, lhs rhs. Now we shall show that rhs lhs. If rhs =, then there is no more to prove. So suppose that rhs. Let x rhs. Then x (A B) and x (A C). Case (i): suppose x A. Then certainly x A (B C) and so x lhs. Case (ii): suppose x / A. Then since x (A B), it follows that x B. Also x (A C) and so it follows that x C. Hence x B C and so x A (B C) which tells us that x lhs. Department of Mathematics

6 Sets 5 We have seen that every element of the right hand side also belongs to the left hand side, that is, rhs lhs. Combining these two parts, we have lhs rhs and also rhs lhs and so it follows that lhs = rhs, as required. (2) This is left as an exercise. The notions of union and intersection extend to the situation with more than just two sets. For example, A 1 A 2 A 3 = { x : x A 1 or x A 2 or x A 3 } = { x : x belongs to at least one of the sets A 1, A 2, A 3 } = { x : x A i for some i = 1 or 2 or 3 } = { x : x A i for some i { 1, 2, 3 } }. More generally, for n sets A 1, A 2,..., A n, we have A 1 A 2 A n = { x : x A i for some i { 1, 2,..., n } }. This union is often denoted by n A i which is somewhat more concise than i=1 the alternative A 1 A 2 A n. Let Λ denote the index set { 1, 2,..., n }. This is just the set of labels for the collection of sets we are considering. Then the above can be conveniently written as A i = { x : x A i for some i Λ }. i Λ This all makes sense for any non-empty index set. Indeed, suppose that we have some collection of sets indexed (that is, labelled,) by a set Λ. Suppose the set with label λ Λ is denoted by A λ. The union of all the A λ s is defined to be A λ = { x : x A λ for some λ Λ }. λ Λ If Λ = N, one often writes Examples 1.9. i=1 A i for λ Λ 1. Suppose that Λ = { 1, 2, 3,..., 57, 58 } and A j = [j, j + 1] for each j Λ. (So, for example, with j = 7, A 7 = [7, 7 + 1] = [7, 8].) Then 58 j=1 A λ. A j = [1, 59]. King s College London

7 6 Chapter 1 2. Suppose that Λ = N and A j = [1, j + 1] for j N. Then A j = [1, ). j=1 To see this, suppose that x j=1. Then x is an element of at least one of the A j s, that is, there is some j 0, say, in N such that x A j0. This means that x [1, j 0 + 1], that is, 1 x j and so certainly x [1, ). It follows that lhs rhs. Now suppose that x [1, ). Then, in particular, x 1. Let N be any natural number satisfying N > x. Then certainly x satisfies 1 x N + 1 which means that x A N and so x j=1 A j. Hence rhs lhs and the equality lhs = rhs follows. 3. Suppose that Λ is the interval (0, 1) and, for each λ (0, 1), A λ is given by A λ = { (x, y) R 2 : x = λ }. In other words, A λ is the vertical line x = λ in the plane R 2. Then A λ = { (x, y) R 2 : 0 < x < 1 } λ Λ which is the vertical strip in R 2 with boundary edges given by the lines with x = 0 and x = 1, respectively. Note that these lines (boundary edges) are not part of the union of the A λ s. 4. Let Λ be the interval [3, 5] and for each λ [3, 5] let A λ = { λ }. In other words, A λ consists of just one point, the real number λ. Then A λ = [3, 5] λ Λ which just says that the interval [3, 5] is the union of all its points (as it should be). A similar discussion can be made regarding intersections. A 1 A 2 A 3 = { x : x A 1 and x A 2 and x A 3 } = { x : x belongs to every one of the sets A 1, A 2, A 3 } = { x : x A i for all i = 1 or 2 or 3 } = { x : x A i for all i { 1, 2, 3 } }. In general, if { A λ } Λ is any collection of sets indexed by the (non-empty) set Λ, then the intersection of the A λ s is A λ = { x : x A λ for all λ Λ }. λ Λ Department of Mathematics

8 Sets 7 If Λ = { 1, 2,..., n }, we usually write we usually write Examples i=1 A i for λ Λ A λ. n i=1 A i for λ Λ A λ and if Λ = N, then 1. Suppose that Λ = N and for each j Λ = N, let A j = [0, j]. Then A j = [0, 1]. j N 2. Let Λ = N and set A j = [j, j + 1] for j N. Then A j =. j=1 3. Let Λ = N and set A j = [j, ) for j N. Then A j =. j=1 To see this, note that x j=1 provided that x belongs to every A j. This means that x satisfies j x j + 1 for all j N. But clearly this fails whenever j is a natural number strictly greater than x. In other words, there are no real numbers which satisfy this criterion. 4. Suppose that Λ = N and for each k N let A k be the interval given by A k = [0, 1/k). Then, in this case, A k = { 0 }. k=1 This follows because the only non-negative real number which is smaller than every 1/k (where k N) is zero. 5. Let Λ = N and let A k = [0, 1 + 1/k] for k N. Then A k = [0, 1]. k=1 Indeed, [0, 1] A k for every k and if x / [0, 1] then x must fail to belong to some A k. King s College London

9 8 Chapter 1 Theorem Suppose that A and B λ, for λ Λ, are given sets. Then (1) A ( ) B λ = (A B λ ). λ Λ λ Λ (2) A ( ) B λ = (A B λ ). λ Λ λ Λ Proof. (1) Suppose that x A ( λ Λ B λ). If x A, then x A Bλ for all λ and so x λ Λ (A B λ). If x / A, then it must be the case that x λ Λ B λ, in which case x B λ for all λ and so x λ Λ (A B λ). We have shown that A ( λ Λ B ) λ λ Λ (A B λ). To establish the reverse inclusion, suppose that x λ Λ (A B λ). Then x A B λ for every λ Λ. If x A, the certainly x A ( λ Λ B λ). If x / A, then we must have that x B λ for every λ, that is, x λ Λ B λ. But then it follows that x A ( λ Λ B λ). Hence λ Λ (A B λ) A ( λ Λ B λ) and so the equality follows. A ( ) B λ = (A B λ ) λ Λ λ Λ (2) The proof of this proceeds along similar lines to part (1). Department of Mathematics

10 Chapter 2 The Real Numbers In this chapter, we will discuss the properties of R, the real number system. It might well be appropriate to ask exactly what a real number is? It is the job of mathematics to set out clear descriptions of the objects within its scope, so it is not at all unreasonable to expect an answer to this. One must start somewhere. For example, in geometry, one might take the concept of point as a basic undefined object. Lines are then specified by pairs of points the line passing through them. Beginning with the natural numbers, N, one can construct Z and from Z one constructs the rationals, Q. Finally from Q it is possible to construct the real numbers R. We will not do this here, but rather we will take a close look at the structure and special properties of R. Of course, everybody knows that numbers can be added and multiplied and even subtracted and it makes sense to divide one number by another (as long as the latter, the denominator, is not zero). We can also compare two numbers and discuss which is the larger. It is precisely these properties (or axioms) that we wish to isolate and highlight. Arithmetic To each pair of real numbers a, b R, there corresponds a third, denoted a + b. This pairing, denoted + and called addition obeys (A1) a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c, for all a, b, c R. (A2) a + b = b + a, for all a, b R. (A3) There is a unique element, denoted 0, in R such that a + 0 = a, for any a R. (A4) For any a R, there is a unique element (denoted a) in R such that a + ( a) = 0. The properties (A1) (A4) say that R is an abelian group with respect to the binary operation +. 9

11 10 Chapter 2 Next, we consider multiplication. To each pair a, b R, there is a third, denoted a.b, the product of a and b. The operation., called multiplication, obeys (A5) a.(b.c) = (a.b).c, for any a, b, c R. (A6) a.b = b.a, for any a, b R. (A7) There is a unique element, denoted 1, in R, with 1 0 and such that a.1 = a, for any a R. (A8) For any a R with a 0, there is a unique element in R, written a 1 or 1 a, such that a.a 1 = 1. The element a 1 is called the (multiplicative) inverse, or reciprocal, of a. (A9) a.(b + c) = a.b + a.c, for all a, b, c R. Remarks is not defined. The element 0 has no reciprocal. Such an object simply does not exist in R. 1/0 has no meaning. 2. Subtraction is given by a b = a + ( b), for a, b R. 3. Division is defined via a b = a.(b 1 ) ( = a. 1 b = a/b) provided b 0. If it should happen that b = 0, then the expression a/b has no meaning. 4. It is usual to omit the dot and write just ab for the product a.b. There is almost never any confusion from this. All the familiar arithmetic results are consequences of the above properties (A1) (A9). Examples For any x R, x.0 = 0. Proof. By (A3), = 0 and so x.(0 + 0) = x.0. x.0 + x.0 = x.0. Adding (x.0) to both sides gives Hence, by (A9), (x.0 + x.0) + ( (x.0)) = x.0 + ( (x.0)) = 0, by (A4). Hence, by (A1), x.0 + (x.0 + ( (x.0)) = 0 and so, using property (A4) again, we get x = 0. However, by (A3), x = x.0 and so by equating these last two expressions for x we obtain x.0 = 0, as required. Department of Mathematics

12 The Real Numbers For any x, y R, x.( y) = (x.y). Proof. (x.y) + x.( y) = x.(y + ( y)), = x.0, by (A4), by (A9), = 0, by the previous result. By (A4) (uniqueness), (x.y) must be the same as x.( y). 3. For any x R, ( x) = x. Proof. We have as required. x = x + 0, by (A3), = x + (( x) + ( ( x))), by (A4), = (x + ( x)) + ( ( x)), by (A1), = 0 + ( ( x)), by (A4), = ( x), by (A3) 4. For any x, y R, x.y = ( x).( y). Proof. By example 2, above, α.( β) = (α, β) for any α, β R. If we now choose α = x and β = y, we get and we are done. ( x).( y) = (( x).y) = (y.( x)), by (A6), = ( (y.x)), by example 2, above, = ( (x.y)), by (A6), = x.y by example 3, above, King s College London

13 12 Chapter 2 Order properties Here we formalize the idea of one number being greater than another. We can order two numbers by thinking of the larger as being the higher in order. More precisely, there is a relation < (read less than ) between elements of R satisfying the following: (A10) For any a, b R, exactly one of the following is true: a < b, b < a or a = b (trichotomy). The notation u > a (read u is greater than a ) means that a < u. (A11) If a < b and b < c, then a < c. (A12) If a < b, then a + c < b + c, for any c R. (A13) If a < b and γ > 0, then aγ < bγ. Notation We write a b to signify that either a < b is true or else a = b is true. In view of (A10), we can say that a b means that it is false that a > b. The notation x w is used to mean that w x and as already noted above, x > w is used to mean w < x. By (A10), if x 0, then either x > 0 or else x < 0. If x > 0, then x is said to be (strictly) positive and if x < 0, we say that x is (strictly) negative. Thus, if x is not zero, then it is either positive or else it is negative. It is quite common to call a number x positive if it obeys x 0 or negative if it obeys x 0. Should it be necessary to indicate that x is not zero, then one adds the adjective strictly. Examples For any x R, we have x > 0 ( x) < 0. Proof. Using (A12), we have 0 < x = 0 + ( x) < x + ( x) (adding ( x) to both sides), = ( x) < 0 since rhs = 0, by (A4). Conversely, again from (A12), ( x) < 0 = ( x) + x < 0 + x and the result follows. = 0 < x by (A2), (A3) and (A4) (adding x to both sides), Department of Mathematics

14 The Real Numbers For any x 0, we have x 2 > 0. Proof. Since x 0, we must have either x > 0 or x < 0, by (A10). If x > 0, then by (A13) we have x 2 > 0 (take a = 0, b = γ = x). On the other hand, if x < 0, then x > 0 by the example above. Hence, by (A13) (with a = 0, b = γ = ( x)), it follows that ( x)( x) > 0. But we know (from the arithmetic properties) that ( α)( β) = α β, for any α, β R and so we have as required. x 2 = x x = ( x)( x) > 0 The number 1 was introduced in (A7). If we set x = 1 here, then we see that 1 = 1 2 > 0, i.e., 1 > 0. We have deduced that the number 1 is positive. Nobody would doubt this, but we see explicitly that this is a consequence of our set-up. Note that it follows from this, by (A12), that a < a + 1, for any a R. 3. If a, b R with a b, then a b. Proof. If a = b then certainly a = b, so we need only consider the case when a < b. a < b = a + ( a) < b + ( a) and the result follows. = 0 < b + ( a) by (A12), = b < ( b) + b + ( a) by (A12) and (A4), = b < a by (A1), (A2) and (A4) From now on, we will work with real numbers and inequalities just as we normally would and will not follow through a succession of steps invoking the various listed properties as required as we go. Suffice it to say that we could do so if we wished. Next, we introduce a very important function, the modulus or absolute value. King s College London

15 14 Chapter 2 Definition 2.4. For any x R, the modulus (or absolute value) of x is the number x defined according to the rule { x, if x 0, x = x, if x < 0. For example, 5 = 5, 0 = 0, 3 = 3 and 1 2 = 1 2. Note that x is never negative. We also see that x = max{ x, x }. Let f(x) = x and g(x) = x. Then x = f(x) when x 0 and x = g(x) when x < 0. Now, we know what the graphs of y = f(x) = x and y = g(x) = x look like and so we can sketch the graph of the function x. It is made up of two straight lines, meeting at the origin. x y = x y = x x 0 Figure 2.1: The absolute value function x. The basic properties of the absolute value are contained in the following two propositions. They are used time and time again in analysis and it is absolutely essential to be fluent in their use. Proposition 2.5. (i) For any a, b R, we have ab = a b. (ii) For any a R and r > 0, the inequality a < r is equivalent to the pair of inequalities r < a < r. Proof. (i) We just consider the various possibilities. If either a or b is zero, then so is the product ab. Hence ab = 0 and at least one of a or b is also zero. Therefore ab = 0 = a b. If both a > 0 and b > 0, then ab > 0 and we have ab = ab, a = a and b = b and so ab = a b in this case. Now, if a > 0 but b < 0, then ab < 0 so we have a = a, b = b and ab = ab = a b. The case a < 0 and b > 0 is similar. Finally, suppose that both a < 0 and b < 0. Then ab > 0 and we have ab = ab, a = a and b = b. Hence, ab = ab = ( a)( b) = a b. Department of Mathematics

16 The Real Numbers 15 (ii) Suppose that a < r. Then max{ a, a } < r and so both a < r and a < r. In other words, a < r and r < a which can be written as r < a < a. On the other hand, if r < a < r, then both a < r and a < r so that max{ a, a } < r. That is, a < r, as required. Remark 2.6. Putting b = 1 in (i), above, and using the fact that 1 = 1, we see that a = a. Proposition 2.7. For any real numbers a and b, (i) a + b a + b. (ii) a b a + b. (iii) a b a b. Proof. (i) We have a + b a + b and (a + b) = a b a + b. Hence a + b = max{ a + b, (a + b) } a + b. (ii) Let c = b and apply (i) to the real numbers a and c to get the inequality a + c a + c. But then this means that a b a + b. (iii) We have a = (a b) + b a b + b by part (i) (with (a b) replacing a). This implies that a b a b. Swapping around a and b, we have ( a b ) = b a b a = a b and therefore as required. a b = max{ a b, ( a b ) } a b If a and b are real numbers, how far apart are they? For example, if a = 7 and b = 11 then we might say that the distance between a and b is 4. If, on the other hand, a = 10 and b = 6, then we would say that the distance between them is 16. In either case, we notice that the distance is given by a b. It is extremely useful to view a b as the distance between the numbers a and b. For example, to say that a b is very small is to say that a and b are close to each other. King s College London

17 16 Chapter 2 Proposition 2.8. Let a, b R be given and suppose that for any given ε > 0, a and b obey the inequality a < b + ε. Then a b. In particular, if x < ε for all ε > 0, then x 0. Proof. We know that either a b or else a > b. Suppose the latter were true, namely, a > b. Set ε 1 = a b. Then ε 1 > 0 and a = b + ε 1. Taking ε = ε 1, we see that this conflicts with the hypothesis that a < b + ε for every ε > 0 (it fails for the choice ε = ε 1 ). We conclude that a > b must be false and so a b. For the last part, simply set a = x and b = 0 to get the desired conclusion. We have listed a number of properties obeyed by the real numbers: (A1)... (A9) arithmetic (A10)... (A13) order. Is this it? Are there any more to be included? We notice that all of these properties are satisfied by the rational numbers, Q. Are all real numbers rational, i.e., is it true that Q = R? Or do we need to consider yet further properties which distinguish between Q and R? Consider an apparently unrelated question. Do all numbers have square roots? Since a 2 is positive for any a R, it is clear that no negative number can have a square root in R. (Indeed, it is the consideration of C, the complex numbers, which allows for square roots of negative numbers.) So we ask, does every positive real number have a square root? Does every natural number n have a square root in R? In particular, is there such a real number as the square root of 2? It would be nice to think that there is such a real number. In fact, according to Pythagoras Theorem, this should be the length of the diagonal of a square whose sides have unit length. The following proposition tells us that there is certainly no such rational number. Proposition 2.9. There are no integers m, n N satisfying m 2 = 2n 2. In particular, 2 is not a rational number. Proof. To say that 2 is rational is to say that there are integers m and n (with n 0) such that m/n = 2. This means that m 2 /n 2 = 2 and so m 2 = 2n 2 for m, n N. (By replacing m or n by m or n, if necessary, we may assume that m and n in this last equality are both positive.) So the fact that 2 / Q is a consequence of the first part of the proposition. Consider the equality m 2 = 2n 2 ( ) To show that m 2 = 2n 2 is impossible for any m, n N, suppose the contrary, namely that there are numbers m and n in N obeying ( ). We will show that this leads to a contradiction. Department of Mathematics

18 The Real Numbers 17 Indeed, if m 2 = 2n 2, then m 2 is even. The square of an odd number is odd and so it follows that m must also be even. This means that we can express m as m = 2k for some suitable k N. But then (2k) 2 = m 2 = 2n 2 which means that 2k 2 = n 2 and so n 2 is even. Arguing as above, we deduce that n can be expressed as n = 2j for some j N. Substituting, we see that k and j also obey ( ), namely, k 2 = 2j 2. This tells us that m/2 and n/2 are integers also obeying ( ). Repeating this whole argument with m = m/2 and n = n/2, we find that both m /2 and n /2 belong to N and also satisfy ( ). In other words, m/2 2 and n/2 2 belong to N and obey ( ). We can keep repeating this argument to deduce that m/2 j and n/2 j are integers obeying ( ). In particular, m/2 j N implies that m/2 j 1 and so m 2 j. But this holds for any j N and we can take j as large as we wish. We can take j so large that 2 j > m. This leads to a contradiction, as we wanted it to. We finally conclude that there are no natural numbers m and n obeying ( ) and as a consequence, there is no element of Q whose square is equal to 2, that is, 2 is not a rational number. Remark A somewhat similar argument can be used to show that many other numbers do not have square roots in Q. For example, 3 / Q. In fact, one can show that if n N, then either n N, that is, n is a perfect square, or else n / Q. For example, 16 = 4 N but 17 / Q. Returning to the discussion of the defining properties of R, we still have to pinpoint the extra property that R has which is not shared by Q. First we need some terminology. Definition A non-empty subset S of R is said to be bounded from above if there is some M R such that a M for all a S. Any such number M is called an upper bound for the set S. Evidently, if M is an upper bound for S, then so is any number greater than M. We say that a non-empty subset S of R is bounded from below if there is some m R such that m a for all a S. Any such number m is called a lower bound for the set S. If m is a lower bound for S, then so is any number less than m. If S is both bounded from above and from below, then S is said to be bounded. King s College London

19 18 Chapter 2 Example Consider the set A = ( 6, 4]. Then A is bounded because any x A obeys 6 x 4. (In fact, any x A obeys the inequalities 6 < x 4.) Any real number greater than or equal to 4 is an upper bound for A and any real number less than or equal to 6 is a lower bound for A. The set A has a maximal element, namely 4, but A does not have a minimal element. Let B = (1, 3 2 ) (2, 5 2 ) (3, 7 2 ) = (k, k ). Then the set B is bounded from below (the number 1 is clearly a lower bound for B). However, B contains k for every k N and so B is not bounded from above (so B is not bounded). We also see that B does not have a minimal element. Remark What does it mean to say that a set S is not bounded from above? Consider the inequality x M. Now, given S and some particular real number M, the inequality ( ) may hold for some elements x in S but may fail for other elements of S. To say that S is bounded from above is to say that there is some M such that ( ) holds for all elements x S. If S is not bounded from above, then it must be the case that whatever M we try, there will always be some x in S for which ( ) fails, that is, for any given M there will be some x S such that x > M. In particular, if we try M = 1, then there will be some element (many, in fact) in S greater than 1. Let us pick any such element and label it as x 1. Then we have x 1 S and x 1 > 1. We can now try M = 2. Again, ( ) must fail for at least one element in S and it could even happen that x 1 > 2. To ensure that we get a new element from S, let M = max{ 2, x 1 }. Then there must be at least one element of S greater than this M. Let x 2 denote any such element. Then we have x 2 S and x 2 > 2 and x 2 x 1. Now setting M = max{ 3, x 1, x 2 }, we may say that there is some element in S, which we choose to denote by x 3, such that x 3 > 3 and x 3 x 1 and x 3 x 2. We can continue to do this and so we see that if S is not bounded from above, then there exist elements x 1, x 2, x 3,..., x n,... (which are all different) such that x n > n for each n N. k=1 The following concepts play an essential rôle. ( ) Department of Mathematics

20 The Real Numbers 19 Definition Suppose that S is a non-empty subset of R which is bounded from above. The number M is the least upper bound (lub) of S if (i) a M for all a S (i.e., M is an upper bound for S). (ii) If M is any upper bound for S, then M M. If S is a non-empty subset of R which is bounded from below, then the number m is the greatest lower bound (glb) of S if (i) m a for all a S (i.e., m is a lower bound for S). (ii) If m is any lower bound for S, then m m. Note that the least upper bound and the greatest lower bound of a set S need not themselves belong to S. They may or they may not. The least upper bound is also called the supremum (sup) and the greatest lower bound is also called the infimum (inf). The ideas are illustrated by some examples. Examples Let S be the following set consisting of 4 elements, S = { 3, 1, 2, 5 }. Then clearly S is bounded from above and from below. The least upper bound is 5 and the greatest lower bound is Let S be the interval S = ( 6, 4]. Then lub S = 4 and glb S = 6. Note that 4 S whereas 6 / S. 3. Let S = (1, ). S is not bounded from above and so has no least upper bound. S is bounded from below and we see that glb S = 1. Note that glb S / S in this case. Remark Suppose that M is the lub for a set S. Let δ > 0. Then M δ < M and since any upper bound M for S has to obey M M, we see that M δ cannot be an upper bound for S. But this means that it is false that a M δ for all a S. In other words, there must be some a S which satisfies M δ < a. Since M is an upper bound for S, we also have a M and so a obeys M δ < a M. So no matter how small δ may be, there will always be some element a S (possibly depending on δ and there may be many) such that M δ < a M, where M = lub S. For any δ > 0, there is a S such that lub S δ < a lub S. King s College London

21 20 Chapter 2 Now suppose that m = glb S. Then for any δ > 0 (however small), we note that m < m + δ and so m + δ cannot be a lower bound for S (because all lower bounds for S must be less than or equal to m). Hence, there is some a S such that a < m + δ, which means that m a < m + δ. For any δ > 0, there is a S such that glb S a < glb S + δ. Remark As already noted above, lub S and glb S may or may not belong to the set S. If it should happen that lub S S, then in this case lub S (or sup S) is the maximum element of S, denoted max S. If glb S S, then glb S (or inf S) is the minimum element of S, denoted min S. For example, the interval S = ( 2, 5] is bounded and, by inspection, we see that sup S = 5 and inf S = 2. Since sup S = 5 S, the set S does indeed have a maximum element, namely, 5 = sup S. However, inf S / S and so S has no minimum element. We are now in a position to discuss the final property satisfied by R and it is precisely this last property which distinguishes R from Q. (A14) (The completeness property of R) Any non-empty subset of R which is bounded from above possesses a least upper bound. Any non-empty subset of R which is bounded from below possesses a greatest lower bound. These statements might appear self-evident, but as we will see, they have far-reaching consequences. We note here that these two statements are not independent, in fact, each implies the other, that is, they are equivalent. Remark It is very convenient to think of R as the set of points on a line (the real line). Indeed, this is standard procedure when sketching graphs of functions where the coordinate axes represent the real numbers. Department of Mathematics

22 The Real Numbers 21 Imagine now the following situation. } {{ } A )( R }{{} B Figure 2.2: The real line has no gaps. The set A consists of all points on the line (real numbers) to the left of the arrow and B comprises all those points to the right. Numbers are bigger the more they are to the right. The arrow points to the least upper bound of A (which is also the greatest lower bound of B). The completeness property (A14) ensures the existence of the real number in R that the arrow supposedly points to. There are no gaps or missing points on the real line. We can think of the integers Z or even the rationals Q as collections of dots on a line, but it is property (A14) which allows us to visualize R as the whole unbroken line itself. The next result is so obvious that it seems hardly worth noting. However, it is very important and follows from property (A14). Theorem 2.19 (Archimedean Property). For any given x R, there is some n N such that n > x. Proof. Let x R be given. We use the method of proof by contradiction so suppose that there is no n N obeying n > x. This means that n x for all n N, that is, x is an upper bound for N in R. By the completeness property, (A14), N has a least upper bound, α, say. Then α is an upper bound for N so that n α ( ) for all n N. Since α is the least upper bound, α 1 cannot be an upper bound for N and so there must be some k N such that α 1 < k. But we can rewrite this as α < k + 1 which contradicts ( ) since k + 1 N. We conclude that there is some n N obeying n > x, as claimed. Corollary (i) For any given δ > 0, there is some n N such that 1 n < δ. (ii) For any α > 0, β > 0, there is n N such α n < β. Proof. (i) Let δ > 0 be given. By the Archimedean Property, there is some n N such that n > 1/δ. But then this gives 1/n < δ, as required. (ii) For given α > 0 and β > 0, set δ = β/α. By (i), there is n N such that 1/n < δ = β/α and so α/n < β. King s College London

23 22 Chapter 2 The next result is no surprise either. Theorem For any a R, there is a unique integer n Z such that n a < n + 1. Proof. Let S = { k Z : k > a }. By theorem 2.19, S is not empty and is bounded below (by a). Hence, by the completeness property (A14), S has a greatest lower bound α, say, in R. We have a α k for all k S. (The inequality a α follows because a is a lower bound and α is the greatest lower bound and the inequality α k follows because α is a lower bound of S.) Since α is the greatest lower bound, α + 1 cannot be a lower bound of S and so there is some m S such that m < α + 1, that is, m 1 < α. m 1 = n a m = n + 1 Figure 2.3: The integer part of a. Now, α is a lower bound for S and m 1 < α and so m 1 / S. But then, by the defining property of S, this means that it is false that m 1 > a. In other words, we have m 1 a. But m S and so m > a and so m satisfies m 1 a < m. Putting n = m 1, we get n Z and n satisfies the required inequalities n a < n + 1. To show the uniqueness of such n Z, suppose that also n Z obeys n a < n +1. Suppose that n < n. Then n+1 n and so the inequalities n a and a < n + 1 give n a < n + 1 n giving n < n which is impossible. Similarly, the assumption that n < n would lead to the impossible inequality n < n. We conclude that n = n which is to say that n is unique. Remark For x R, let n Z be the unique integer obeying the inequalities n x < n+1. Set r = x n. Then we see that 0 x n = r < 1 and so x = n + r with n Z and where 0 r < 1. The unique integer n here is called the integer part of the real number x and is denoted by [x] (or sometimes by x ). R Department of Mathematics

24 The Real Numbers 23 Theorem Between any pair of real numbers a < b, there are infinitelymany rational numbers and also infinitely-many irrational numbers. Proof. First, we shall show that there is at least one such rational, that is, we shall show that for any given a < b in R, there is some q Q such that a < q < b. The idea of the proof is as follows. If there is an integer between a and b, then we are done. In any case, we note that since the integers are spread one unit apart, there should certainly be at least one integer between a and b if the distance between a and b is greater than 1. If the distance between a and b is less than 1, then we can open up the gap between them by multiplying both by a sufficiently large (positive) integer, n, say. The gap between na and nb is n(b a). Clearly, if n is large enough, this value is greater than 1. Then there will be some integer m, say, between na and nb, i.e., na < m < nb. But then we see (since n is positive) that a < m/n < b and q = m/n is a rational number which does the job. We shall now write this argument out formally. Let n N be sufficiently large that n(b a) > 1 so that na + 1 < nb and let m = [na] + 1. Since [na] na < [na] + 1, it follows that [na] na < [na] + 1 na + 1 < nb }{{} m and so na < m < nb and hence a < m/n < b. (Note that n > 0, so this last step is valid.) Setting q = m/n, we have that q Q and q obeys a < q < b, as required. To see that there are infinitely-many rationals between a and b, we just repeat the above argument but with, say, q and b instead of a and b. This tells us that there is a rational, q 2, say, obeying q < q 2 < b. Once again, repeating this argument, there is a rational, q 3, say, obeying q 2 < q 3 < b. Continuing in this way, we see that for any n N, there are n rationals, q, q 2,..., q n obeying a < q < q 2 < q 3 < < q n < b. Hence it follows that there are infinitely-many rationals between a and b. To show that there are infinitely-many irrational numbers between a and b, we use a trick together with the observation that if r is rational, then r/ 2 is irrational. The trick is simply to apply the first part to the numbers a 2 and b 2 to deduce that for any n N there are rational numbers r 1, r 2,..., r n obeying a 2 < r 1 < r 2 < < r n < b 2. Now let µ j = r j / 2 for j = 1, 2,..., n. Then each µ j is irrational and we have a < µ 1 < µ 2 < < µ n < b and the result follows. King s College London

25 24 Chapter 2 As a further application of the Completeness Property of R, we shall show that any positive real number has a positive n th root. Theorem Let x 0 and n N be given. Then there is a unique s 0 such that s n = x. The real number s is called the (positive) n th root of x and is denoted by x 1/n. Proof. If x = 0, then we can take s = 0, so suppose that x > 0. Let A be the set A = { t 0 : t n < x }. Then 0 A and so A is not empty and, by the Archimedean Property, there is some integer K with K > x. But then every t A must obey t < K because otherwise we would have t K and therefore t n K n K > x, which is not possible for any t A. This means that A is bounded from above. By the Completeness Property of R, A has a least upper bound, lub A = s, say. Note now that, since x > 0, by the Archimedean Property there is some m N such that m > 1/x. Hence m n m > 1/x which implies that 1/m n < x so that 1/m n A. This means that s 1/m n. In particular, s > 0. Now, exactly one of the statements s n = x, s n < x or s n > x is true. We claim that s n = x and to show this we shall show that the last two statements must be false. Indeed, suppose that s n < x. For k N, let s k = s(1 + 1 k ). Then evidently s k > s and we will show that s n k < x for suitably large k. Let d = x s n. Then d > 0 and x s n k = x sn + s n s n k = d (sn k sn ) = d s n( (1 + 1 k )n 1 ). Now, writing α = (1 + 1 k ) and noting that 1 < α 2, we estimate Hence (1 + 1 k )n 1 = α n 1 = (α 1)(α n 1 + α n ) (α 1)(2 n n ) (α 1) n 2 n = 1 k n 2n. s n k sn = s n( (1 + 1 k )n 1 ) sn n 2 n. k For sufficiently large k, the right hand side of this inequality is less than d and so x s n k = x sn + s n s n k = d (sn k sn ) > 0. It follows that if k is large enough, then s k A. But s k > s which means that s cannot be the least upper bound of A and we have a contradiction. Hence it must be false that s n < x. Department of Mathematics

26 The Real Numbers 25 Suppose now that s n > x and let δ = s n x. For given k N, let t k = s(1 1 k ). Writing β = 1 1 k and noting that 0 β 1, we estimate that It follows that 1 (1 1 k )n = 1 β n = (β n 1) = (β 1)(β n 1 + β n ) = (1 β)(β n 1 + β n ) (1 β) n = 1 k n. s n t n k = sn (1 (1 1 k )n ) 1 k sn n < δ for sufficiently large k. But then this means that t n k x = tn k sn + s n x = δ (s n t n k ) > 0 for large k. However, t k < s and since s = lub A, it follows that t k is not an upper bound for A. In other words, there is some τ A such that τ > t k and therefore τ n x > t n k x > 0. However, τ A means that τ n < x which is a contradiction and so it is false that s n > x. We have now shown that s n < x is false and also that s n > x is false and so we conclude that it must be true that s n = x, as required. We have established the existence of some s 0 such that s n = x and so, finally, we must prove that such an s is unique. If x = 0, then s = 0 obeys s n = 0 = x. No s 0 can obey s n = 0 because s n (1/s) n = 1 0, so s = 0 is the only solution to s n = 0. Now let s > 0 and t > 0. If s > t, then s/t > 1 so that (s/t) n > 1 and we find that s n > t n. Interchanging the rôles of s and t, it follows that if s < t, then s n < t n. We conclude that if s n = x = t n then both s < t and s > t are impossible and so s = t. The proof is complete. King s College London

27 26 Chapter 2 Principle of induction Suppose that, for each n N, P (n) is a statement about the number n such that (i) P (1) is true. (ii) For any k N, the truth of P (k) implies the truth of P (k + 1). Then P (n) is true for all n. Example For any n N, n 2 = Proof. For n N, let P (n) be the statement that n 2 = Then P (1) is the statement that n(n + 1)(2n + 1) 6 n(n + 1)(2n + 1) (1 + 1)(2 + 1) = 6 which is true. Now suppose that k N and that P (k) is true. We wish to show that P (k + 1) is also true. Since we are assuming that P (k) is true, we see that k 2 + (k + 1) 2 k(k + 1)(2k + 1) = + (k + 1) 2, 6 using the truth of P (k), k(k + 1)(2k + 1) + (k + 1)(6k + 6) = 6 = (k + 1)(2k2 + k + 6k + 6) 6 (k + 1)(k + 2)(2k + 3) = 6 which is to say that P (k + 1) is true. By the principle of induction, we conclude that P (n) is true for all n N. We can rephrase the principle of induction as follows. Let T be the set given by T = { k N : P (k) is true }, so k T if and only if P (k) is true. In particular, P (1) is true if and only if 1 T. Hence the principle of induction may be rephrased as follows. Let T be a set of natural numbers such that 1 T and such that if T contains k then it also contains k + 1. Then T = N... Department of Mathematics

28 The Real Numbers 27 Principle of induction (2nd form) Suppose that Q(n) is a statement about the natural number n such that (i) Q(1) is true. (ii) For any k N, the truth of all Q(1), Q(2),..., Q(k) implies the truth of Q(k + 1). Then Q(n) is true for all n. In a nutshell: Suppose that: Q(1) is true and Q(1) true Q(2) true Q(3) true = Q(k +1) true. Q(k) true Conclusion: Q(n) is true for all n N. This follows from the usual form of the principle. To see this, let S = { m N : Q(m) is true }. We shall use the usual form of induction to show that the hypotheses above imply that S = N. For any n N, let P (n) be the statement { 1, 2,..., n } S. Now, by hypothesis, Q(1) is true and so 1 S. Hence { 1 } S which is to say that P (1) is true. Next, suppose that the truth of P (k) implies that of P (k+1) and assume that P (k) is true. This means that { 1, 2,..., k } S, that is, each of Q(1), Q(2),..., Q(k) is true. But then by the 2nd part of the hypothesis above, Q(k + 1) is true, that is to say, k + 1 S. Hence { 1, 2,... k, k + 1 } S. But this just tells us that P (k + 1) is true. By induction (usual form), it follows that P (n) is true for all n N. This means that { 1, 2,..., n } S for all n. In particular, n S for every n N, that is, Q(n) is true for all n N which is the content of the 2nd form of the principle. King s College London

29 28 Chapter 2 Department of Mathematics

30 Chapter 3 Sequences A sequence of real numbers is just a listing a 1, a 2, a 3,... of real numbers labelled by N, the set of natural numbers. Thus, to each n N, there corresponds a real number a n. Not surprisingly, a n is called the n th term of the sequence. a 1, a 2, a 3,..., a k, a k+1,... labelled by N k th term Figure 3.1: The sequence (a n ) n N. Whilst it may seem a trivial comment, it is important to note that the essential thing about a sequence is that it has a notion of direction it makes sense to talk about one term being further down the sequence than another. For example, a 101 is further down the sequence than, say, a 45. It is convenient to denote the above sequence by (a n ) n N or even simply by (a n ). Note that there is no requirement that the terms be different. It is quite permissible for a j to be the same as a n for different j and n. Indeed, one could have a n = α, say, for all n. This is just a sequence with constant terms (all equal to α) a somewhat trivial sequence, but a sequence nonetheless. Remark 3.1. On a more formal level, one can think of a sequence of real numbers to be nothing but a function from N into R. Indeed, we can define such a function f : N R by setting f(n) = a n for n N. Conversely, any f : N R will determine a sequence of real numbers, as above, via the assignment a n = f(n). One might wish to consider a finite sequence such as, say, the four term sequence a 1, a 2, a 3, a 4. We will use the word sequence to mean an infinite sequence and simply include the adjective finite when this is meant. 29

31 30 Chapter 3 Examples , 4, 9, 16,... Here the general term a n is given by the simple formula a n = n , 3/2, 4/3, 5/4, 6/5,... The general term is a n = (n + 1)/n. 3. 2, 0, 2, 0, 2, 0,... { 0, if n is even Here a n = 2, if n is odd. This can also be expressed as a n = 1 ( 1) n. 4. Let a n be defined by the prescription a 1 = a 2 = 1 and a n = a n 1 + a n 2 for n 3. The sequence (a n ) is then 1, 1, 2, 3, 5, 8, 13,... These are known as the Fibonacci numbers. We are usually interested in the long-term behaviour of sequences, that is, what happens as we look further and further down the sequence. What happens to a n when n gets very large? Do the terms settle down or do they get sometimes big, sometimes small,..., or what? In examples and 3.2.4, the terms just get huge. In example 3.2.2, we see, for example, that a 99 = 100/99, a = 10001/10000, a = ( )/10 20,..., so it looks as though the terms become close to 1. In example 3.2.3, the terms just keep oscillating between the two values 0 and 2. In example 3.2.2, we would like to say that the sequence approaches 1 as we go further and further down it. Indeed, for example, the difference between a and 1 is that between ( )/10 10 and 1, that is, How can we formulate this idea of convergence of a sequence precisely? We might picture a sequence in two ways, as follows. The first is as the graph of the function n a n. (Notice that we do not join up the dots.) a 1 a a 3 a 4... a n n Figure 3.2: A sequence as a graph. N Department of Mathematics

32 Sequences 31 The second way is just to indicate the values of the sequence on the real line. a4 a2 a1 a3 R Figure 3.3: Plot the values of the sequence on the real line. The example above, would then be pictured either as a 1 a 3 a 5 a 2 a 4 a N Figure 3.4: Graph with values 0 or 2. or as 0 a2 a 4. 2 a1 a 3. R Figure 3.5: The values of a n are either 0 or 2. King s College London

33 32 Chapter 3 Returning to the general situation now, how should we formulate the idea that a sequence (a n ) converges to α? According to our first pictorial description, we would want the plotted points of the sequence (the graph) to eventually become very close to the line y = α. y = α Figure 3.6: The graph gets close to the line y = α. In terms of the second pictorial description, we would simply demand that the values of the sequence eventually cluster around the value x = α. x = α Figure 3.7: The values of (a n ) cluster around x = α. If we think of the index n as representing time, then we can think of a n as the value of the sequence at the time n. The sequence can be considered to have some property eventually provided we are prepared to wait long enough for it to become established. It is very convenient to use this word eventually, so we shall indicate precisely what we mean by it. We say that a sequence eventually has some particular property if there is some N N such that all the terms a n after a N (i.e., all a n with n > N) have the property under consideration. (The number N can be thought of as some offered time after which we are guaranteed that the property under consideration will hold and will continue to hold.) As an example of this usage, let (a n ) be the sequence given by the prescription a n = 100 n, for n N. Then a 1 = 99, a 2 = 98,... etc. It is clear that a n is negative whenever n is greater than 100. Thus, we can say that this sequence (a n ) is eventually negative. Now we can formulate the notion of convergence of a sequence. The idea is that (a n ) converges to the number α if eventually it is as close to α as desired. That is to say, given some preassigned tolerance ε, no matter how small, we demand that eventually (a n ) is close to within ε of α. In Department of Mathematics R R

34 Sequences 33 other words, the distance between a n and α (as points on the real line) is eventually smaller than ε. Definition 3.3. We say that the sequence (a n ) n N of real numbers converges to the real number α if for any given ε > 0, there is some natural number N N such that a n α < ε whenever n > N. α is called the limit of the sequence. In such a situation, we write a n α as n or alternatively lim n a n = α. The use of the symbol is just as part of a phrase and it has no meaning in isolation. There is no real number. Remark 3.4. The positive number ε is the assigned tolerance demanded. Typically, the smaller ε is, so the larger we should expect N to have to be. For example, consider the sequence (a n ) where a n = 1/n. We would expect that a n 0 as n. To see this, let ε > 0 be given. (We are not able to choose this. It is given to us and its actual value is beyond our control.) It will be true that a n 0 < ε provided n > 1/ε. So after some contemplation, we proceed as follows. We are unable to influence the choice of ε given to us, but once it is given then we can (and must) base our tactics on it. So let N be any natural number larger than 1/ε. If n > N, then n > N > 1/ε and so 1/n < ε. That is, if n > N, then a n 0 = 1/n < ε and so, according to our definition, we have shown that a n 0 as n. Notice that the smaller ε is, the larger N has to be. Note that the statement can also be written as or also as if n > N then a n α < ε a n α < ε whenever n > N n > N = a n α < ε. Also, we should note that the inequality a n α < ε telling that the distance between the real numbers a n and α is less than ε can also be expressed by the pair of inequalities ε < a n α < ε or equivalently by the pair α ε < a n < α + ε. This simply means that a n lies on the real line somewhere between the two values α ε and α + ε. This must happen eventually if the sequence is to be convergent (to α). King s College London

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 1 Real Numbers In these lectures, we are going to study a branch of mathematics called

More information

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers Chapter The Real Numbers.. Some Preliminaries Discussion: The Irrationality of 2. We begin with the natural numbers N = {, 2, 3, }. In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend

More information

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers Chapter 1 The Real Numbers 1.1. Some Preliminaries Discussion: The Irrationality of 2. We begin with the natural numbers N = {1, 2, 3, }. In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need

More information

MA103 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Second part, Analysis and Algebra

MA103 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Second part, Analysis and Algebra 206/7 MA03 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Second part, Analysis and Algebra Amol Sasane Revised by Jozef Skokan, Konrad Swanepoel, and Graham Brightwell Copyright c London School of Economics 206

More information

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Chapter One. The Real Number System Chapter One. The Real Number System We shall give a quick introduction to the real number system. It is imperative that we know how the set of real numbers behaves in the way that its completeness and

More information

Structure of R. Chapter Algebraic and Order Properties of R

Structure of R. Chapter Algebraic and Order Properties of R Chapter Structure of R We will re-assemble calculus by first making assumptions about the real numbers. All subsequent results will be rigorously derived from these assumptions. Most of the assumptions

More information

Chapter 1 The Real Numbers

Chapter 1 The Real Numbers Chapter 1 The Real Numbers In a beginning course in calculus, the emphasis is on introducing the techniques of the subject;i.e., differentiation and integration and their applications. An advanced calculus

More information

2.2 Some Consequences of the Completeness Axiom

2.2 Some Consequences of the Completeness Axiom 60 CHAPTER 2. IMPORTANT PROPERTIES OF R 2.2 Some Consequences of the Completeness Axiom In this section, we use the fact that R is complete to establish some important results. First, we will prove that

More information

3 The language of proof

3 The language of proof 3 The language of proof After working through this section, you should be able to: (a) understand what is asserted by various types of mathematical statements, in particular implications and equivalences;

More information

Analysis I. Classroom Notes. H.-D. Alber

Analysis I. Classroom Notes. H.-D. Alber Analysis I Classroom Notes H-D Alber Contents 1 Fundamental notions 1 11 Sets 1 12 Product sets, relations 5 13 Composition of statements 7 14 Quantifiers, negation of statements 9 2 Real numbers 11 21

More information

Supremum and Infimum

Supremum and Infimum Supremum and Infimum UBC M0 Lecture Notes by Philip D. Loewen The Real Number System. Work hard to construct from the axioms a set R with special elements O and I, and a subset P R, and mappings A: R R

More information

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued)

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued) 2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued) 2.1. New examples of commutative rings. Recall that in the first lecture we defined the notions of commutative rings and field and gave some examples of

More information

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals MATH 02 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS Properties of Real Numbers Some Fundamentals The whole course will be based entirely on the study of sequence of numbers and functions defined on the real

More information

chapter 12 MORE MATRIX ALGEBRA 12.1 Systems of Linear Equations GOALS

chapter 12 MORE MATRIX ALGEBRA 12.1 Systems of Linear Equations GOALS chapter MORE MATRIX ALGEBRA GOALS In Chapter we studied matrix operations and the algebra of sets and logic. We also made note of the strong resemblance of matrix algebra to elementary algebra. The reader

More information

M208 Pure Mathematics AA1. Numbers

M208 Pure Mathematics AA1. Numbers M208 Pure Mathematics AA1 Numbers Note to reader Mathematical/statistical content at the Open University is usually provided to students in printed books, with PDFs of the same online. This format ensures

More information

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi Real Analysis Math 3AH Rudin, Chapter # Dominique Abdi.. If r is rational (r 0) and x is irrational, prove that r + x and rx are irrational. Solution. Assume the contrary, that r+x and rx are rational.

More information

Math Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring

Math Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring Math 135 - Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring - 2013 Created for Math 135, Spring 2008 by Lukasz Grabarek and Michael Joyce Send comments and corrections to lukasz@math.hawaii.edu Contents

More information

MATH 117 LECTURE NOTES

MATH 117 LECTURE NOTES MATH 117 LECTURE NOTES XIN ZHOU Abstract. This is the set of lecture notes for Math 117 during Fall quarter of 2017 at UC Santa Barbara. The lectures follow closely the textbook [1]. Contents 1. The set

More information

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions 1. Suppose k is a positive integer. Use induction to prove the following two statements. (a) For all n N 0, the inequality (k 2 + n)! k 2n holds.

More information

1 Numbers. exponential functions, such as x 7! a x ; where a; x 2 R; trigonometric functions, such as x 7! sin x; where x 2 R; ffiffi x ; where x 0:

1 Numbers. exponential functions, such as x 7! a x ; where a; x 2 R; trigonometric functions, such as x 7! sin x; where x 2 R; ffiffi x ; where x 0: Numbers In this book we study the properties of real functions defined on intervals of the real line (possibly the whole real line) and whose image also lies on the real line. In other words, they map

More information

Some Background Material

Some Background Material Chapter 1 Some Background Material In the first chapter, we present a quick review of elementary - but important - material as a way of dipping our toes in the water. This chapter also introduces important

More information

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10 Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10 Inductive sets (used to define the natural numbers as a subset of R) (1) Definition: A set S R is an inductive

More information

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics An Introductory Single Variable Real Analysis: A Learning Approach through Problem Solving Marcel B. Finan c All Rights

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1.

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1. Chapter 3 Sequences Both the main elements of calculus (differentiation and integration) require the notion of a limit. Sequences will play a central role when we work with limits. Definition 3.. A Sequence

More information

Section 2.5 : The Completeness Axiom in R

Section 2.5 : The Completeness Axiom in R Section 2.5 : The Completeness Axiom in R The rational numbers and real numbers are closely related. The set Q of rational numbers is countable and the set R of real numbers is not, and in this sense there

More information

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents Contents 1 1 Introduction 1 What is proof? 1 Statements, Definitions and Euler Diagrams 1 Statements 1 Definitions Our first proof Euler diagrams 4 3 Logical Connectives 5 Negation 6 Conjunction 7 Disjunction

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005 POL502: Foundations Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University October 10, 2005 Our first task is to develop the foundations that are necessary for the materials covered in this course. 1

More information

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted Chapter 2 The Structure of R The purpose of this chapter is to explain to the reader why the set of real numbers is so special. By the end of this chapter, the reader should understand the difference between

More information

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System 21-355 Principles of Real Analysis I Fall 2004 I. The Real Number System The main goal of this course is to develop the theory of real-valued functions of one real variable in a systematic and rigorous

More information

A Guide to Proof-Writing

A Guide to Proof-Writing A Guide to Proof-Writing 437 A Guide to Proof-Writing by Ron Morash, University of Michigan Dearborn Toward the end of Section 1.5, the text states that there is no algorithm for proving theorems.... Such

More information

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Boolean Algebras Let X be an arbitrary set and let P(X) be the class of all subsets of X (the power set of X). Three natural set-theoretic operations on P(X) are the binary operations of union

More information

The Process of Mathematical Proof

The Process of Mathematical Proof 1 The Process of Mathematical Proof Introduction. Mathematical proofs use the rules of logical deduction that grew out of the work of Aristotle around 350 BC. In previous courses, there was probably an

More information

Sets. 1.1 What is a set?

Sets. 1.1 What is a set? Section 1 Sets 1 Sets After working through this section, you should be able to: (a) use set notation; (b) determine whether two given sets are equal and whether one given set is a subset of another; (c)

More information

We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works.

We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works. Analysis I We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works. Copier s Message These notes may contain errors. In fact, they almost

More information

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets 1 Rational and Real Numbers Recall that a number is rational if it can be written in the form a/b where a, b Z and b 0, and a number

More information

MATH10040: Chapter 0 Mathematics, Logic and Reasoning

MATH10040: Chapter 0 Mathematics, Logic and Reasoning MATH10040: Chapter 0 Mathematics, Logic and Reasoning 1. What is Mathematics? There is no definitive answer to this question. 1 Indeed, the answer given by a 21st-century mathematician would differ greatly

More information

Calculus (Real Analysis I)

Calculus (Real Analysis I) Calculus (Real Analysis I) (MAT122β) Department of Mathematics University of Ruhuna A.W.L. Pubudu Thilan Department of Mathematics University of Ruhuna Calculus (Real Analysis I)(MAT122β) 1/172 Chapter

More information

Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008

Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008 Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008 October 29, 2008 1 Introduction into proof August 20, 2008 First we will go through some simple proofs to learn how one writes a rigorous proof. Let start

More information

* 8 Groups, with Appendix containing Rings and Fields.

* 8 Groups, with Appendix containing Rings and Fields. * 8 Groups, with Appendix containing Rings and Fields Binary Operations Definition We say that is a binary operation on a set S if, and only if, a, b, a b S Implicit in this definition is the idea that

More information

Due date: Monday, February 6, 2017.

Due date: Monday, February 6, 2017. Modern Analysis Homework 3 Solutions Due date: Monday, February 6, 2017. 1. If A R define A = {x R : x A}. Let A be a nonempty set of real numbers, assume A is bounded above. Prove that A is bounded below

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

2.1 Convergence of Sequences

2.1 Convergence of Sequences Chapter 2 Sequences 2. Convergence of Sequences A sequence is a function f : N R. We write f) = a, f2) = a 2, and in general fn) = a n. We usually identify the sequence with the range of f, which is written

More information

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets 2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets NOTE: AS OF 2008, SOME OF THIS STUFF IS A BIT OUT- DATED AND HAS A FEW TYPOS. I WILL REVISE THIS MATE- RIAL SOMETIME. In this lecture we discuss two

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 3

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 3 EECS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 014 Anant Sahai Note 3 Induction Induction is an extremely powerful tool in mathematics. It is a way of proving propositions that hold for all

More information

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31 Contents 1 Lecture 1: Introduction 2 2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction 7 3 Lecture 3: Induction and Well-Ordering Principle 11 4 Lecture 4: Definition of a Group and examples 15

More information

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. IAN KIMING 1. Motivation. It will not come as a big surprise to anyone when I say that we need the real numbers in mathematics. More to the point, we need to be able to

More information

Advanced Calculus: MATH 410 Real Numbers Professor David Levermore 5 December 2010

Advanced Calculus: MATH 410 Real Numbers Professor David Levermore 5 December 2010 Advanced Calculus: MATH 410 Real Numbers Professor David Levermore 5 December 2010 1. Real Number System 1.1. Introduction. Numbers are at the heart of mathematics. By now you must be fairly familiar with

More information

Law of Trichotomy and Boundary Equations

Law of Trichotomy and Boundary Equations Law of Trichotomy and Boundary Equations Law of Trichotomy: For any two real numbers a and b, exactly one of the following is true. i. a < b ii. a = b iii. a > b The Law of Trichotomy is a formal statement

More information

2 Arithmetic. 2.1 Greatest common divisors. This chapter is about properties of the integers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}.

2 Arithmetic. 2.1 Greatest common divisors. This chapter is about properties of the integers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}. 2 Arithmetic This chapter is about properties of the integers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}. (See [Houston, Chapters 27 & 28]) 2.1 Greatest common divisors Definition 2.16. If a, b are integers, we say

More information

Lecture Notes in Real Analysis Anant R. Shastri Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology Bombay

Lecture Notes in Real Analysis Anant R. Shastri Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology Bombay Lecture Notes in Real Analysis 2010 Anant R. Shastri Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology Bombay August 6, 2010 Lectures 1-3 (I-week) Lecture 1 Why real numbers? Example 1 Gaps in the

More information

1 Basic Combinatorics

1 Basic Combinatorics 1 Basic Combinatorics 1.1 Sets and sequences Sets. A set is an unordered collection of distinct objects. The objects are called elements of the set. We use braces to denote a set, for example, the set

More information

Chapter 5. Number Theory. 5.1 Base b representations

Chapter 5. Number Theory. 5.1 Base b representations Chapter 5 Number Theory The material in this chapter offers a small glimpse of why a lot of facts that you ve probably nown and used for a long time are true. It also offers some exposure to generalization,

More information

0.Axioms for the Integers 1

0.Axioms for the Integers 1 0.Axioms for the Integers 1 Number theory is the study of the arithmetical properties of the integers. You have been doing arithmetic with integers since you were a young child, but these mathematical

More information

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products Chapter 3 Cartesian Products and Relations The material in this chapter is the first real encounter with abstraction. Relations are very general thing they are a special type of subset. After introducing

More information

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant).

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant). Sets and Functions 1. The language of sets Informally, a set is any collection of objects. The objects may be mathematical objects such as numbers, functions and even sets, or letters or symbols of any

More information

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero Chapter Limits of Sequences Calculus Student: lim s n = 0 means the s n are getting closer and closer to zero but never gets there. Instructor: ARGHHHHH! Exercise. Think of a better response for the instructor.

More information

PRIME NUMBERS YANKI LEKILI

PRIME NUMBERS YANKI LEKILI PRIME NUMBERS YANKI LEKILI We denote by N the set of natural numbers: 1,2,..., These are constructed using Peano axioms. We will not get into the philosophical questions related to this and simply assume

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes Written by Santiago Cañez These are notes which provide a basic summary of each lecture for Math 300, Foundations of Higher

More information

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs MAT 1362 Fall 2018 Alistair Savage Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0

More information

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS Chapter 6 MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS This chapter can be considered enrichment material containing also several more advanced topics and may be skipped in its entirety. You can proceed directly

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Summer 2014 James Cook Note 5

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Summer 2014 James Cook Note 5 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Summer 2014 James Cook Note 5 Modular Arithmetic In several settings, such as error-correcting codes and cryptography, we sometimes wish to work over a

More information

Contribution of Problems

Contribution of Problems Exam topics 1. Basic structures: sets, lists, functions (a) Sets { }: write all elements, or define by condition (b) Set operations: A B, A B, A\B, A c (c) Lists ( ): Cartesian product A B (d) Functions

More information

Sequences of Real Numbers

Sequences of Real Numbers Chapter 8 Sequences of Real Numbers In this chapter, we assume the existence of the ordered field of real numbers, though we do not yet discuss or use the completeness of the real numbers. In the next

More information

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Chapter : Logic Topics:. Statements, Negation, and Compound Statements.2 Truth Tables and Logical Equivalences.3

More information

The Real Number System

The Real Number System MATH 337 The Real Number System Sets of Numbers Dr. Neal, WKU A set S is a well-defined collection of objects, with well-defined meaning that there is a specific description from which we can tell precisely

More information

Numbers, sets, and functions

Numbers, sets, and functions Chapter 1 Numbers, sets, and functions 1.1. The natural numbers, integers, and rational numbers We assume that you are familiar with the set of natural numbers the set of integers and the set of rational

More information

( ε > 0) ( N N) ( n N) : n > N a n A < ε.

( ε > 0) ( N N) ( n N) : n > N a n A < ε. CHAPTER 1. LIMITS OF SEQUENCES 1.1. An Ad-hoc Definition. In mathematical analysis, the concept of limits is of paramount importance, in view of the fact that many basic objects of study such as derivatives,

More information

Handout #6 INTRODUCTION TO ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES: Prof. Moseley AN ALGEBRAIC FIELD

Handout #6 INTRODUCTION TO ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES: Prof. Moseley AN ALGEBRAIC FIELD Handout #6 INTRODUCTION TO ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES: Prof. Moseley Chap. 2 AN ALGEBRAIC FIELD To introduce the notion of an abstract algebraic structure we consider (algebraic) fields. (These should not to

More information

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS Article A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS Juan Pablo Ramírez 0000-0002-4912-2952 Abstract: We present the real number system as a generalization of the natural numbers. First, we prove the co-finite topology,

More information

Math Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring

Math Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring Math 135 - Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring - 2014 Created for Math 135, Spring 2008 by Lukasz Grabarek and Michael Joyce Send comments and corrections to lukasz@math.hawaii.edu Contents

More information

STA2112F99 ε δ Review

STA2112F99 ε δ Review STA2112F99 ε δ Review 1. Sequences of real numbers Definition: Let a 1, a 2,... be a sequence of real numbers. We will write a n a, or lim a n = a, if for n all ε > 0, there exists a real number N such

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2018 Alistair Sinclair and Yun Song Note 6

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2018 Alistair Sinclair and Yun Song Note 6 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2018 Alistair Sinclair and Yun Song Note 6 1 Modular Arithmetic In several settings, such as error-correcting codes and cryptography, we sometimes

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

{x : P (x)} P (x) = x is a cat

{x : P (x)} P (x) = x is a cat 1. Sets, relations and functions. 1.1. Set theory. We assume the reader is familiar with elementary set theory as it is used in mathematics today. Nonetheless, we shall now give a careful treatment of

More information

CHAPTER 3: THE INTEGERS Z

CHAPTER 3: THE INTEGERS Z CHAPTER 3: THE INTEGERS Z MATH 378, CSUSM. SPRING 2009. AITKEN 1. Introduction The natural numbers are designed for measuring the size of finite sets, but what if you want to compare the sizes of two sets?

More information

Continuity. Chapter 4

Continuity. Chapter 4 Chapter 4 Continuity Throughout this chapter D is a nonempty subset of the real numbers. We recall the definition of a function. Definition 4.1. A function from D into R, denoted f : D R, is a subset of

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2013 Vazirani Note 1

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2013 Vazirani Note 1 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 013 Vazirani Note 1 Induction Induction is a basic, powerful and widely used proof technique. It is one of the most common techniques for analyzing

More information

Studying Rudin s Principles of Mathematical Analysis Through Questions. August 4, 2008

Studying Rudin s Principles of Mathematical Analysis Through Questions. August 4, 2008 Studying Rudin s Principles of Mathematical Analysis Through Questions Mesut B. Çakır c August 4, 2008 ii Contents 1 The Real and Complex Number Systems 3 1.1 Introduction............................................

More information

ALGEBRA. 1. Some elementary number theory 1.1. Primes and divisibility. We denote the collection of integers

ALGEBRA. 1. Some elementary number theory 1.1. Primes and divisibility. We denote the collection of integers ALGEBRA CHRISTIAN REMLING 1. Some elementary number theory 1.1. Primes and divisibility. We denote the collection of integers by Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1,...}. Given a, b Z, we write a b if b = ac for some

More information

Maths 212: Homework Solutions

Maths 212: Homework Solutions Maths 212: Homework Solutions 1. The definition of A ensures that x π for all x A, so π is an upper bound of A. To show it is the least upper bound, suppose x < π and consider two cases. If x < 1, then

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

1 The Real Number System

1 The Real Number System 1 The Real Number System The rational numbers are beautiful, but are not big enough for various purposes, and the set R of real numbers was constructed in the late nineteenth century, as a kind of an envelope

More information

One-to-one functions and onto functions

One-to-one functions and onto functions MA 3362 Lecture 7 - One-to-one and Onto Wednesday, October 22, 2008. Objectives: Formalize definitions of one-to-one and onto One-to-one functions and onto functions At the level of set theory, there are

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

Solutions for Homework Assignment 2

Solutions for Homework Assignment 2 Solutions for Homework Assignment 2 Problem 1. If a,b R, then a+b a + b. This fact is called the Triangle Inequality. By using the Triangle Inequality, prove that a b a b for all a,b R. Solution. To prove

More information

Describing the Real Numbers

Describing the Real Numbers Describing the Real Numbers Anthony Várilly Math 25a, Fall 2001 1 Introduction The goal of these notes is to uniquely describe the real numbers by taking certain statements as axioms. This exercise might

More information

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271) Chapter 2 Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271) 2.1 Overview This chapter reviews proof techniques that were probably introduced in Math 271 and that may also have been used in a different way in Phil

More information

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Math/CS 20: Intro. to Math Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Week 5 UCSB 204 The Integers Normally, using the natural numbers, you can easily define

More information

FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES

FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES I FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES 1. The laws of arithmetic The object of the higher arithmetic is to discover and to establish general propositions concerning the natural numbers 1, 2, 3,... of ordinary

More information

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity Math/CS 20: Intro. to Math Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity Week 2 UCSB 204 Sizes of Infinity On one hand, we know that the real numbers contain more elements than the rational

More information

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields 1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields Very informally speaking, a commutative ring is a set in which we can add, subtract and multiply elements so that the usual laws hold. A field is a commutative

More information

UNC Charlotte 2004 Algebra with solutions

UNC Charlotte 2004 Algebra with solutions with solutions March 8, 2004 1. Let z denote the real number solution to of the digits of z? (A) 13 (B) 14 (C) 15 (D) 16 (E) 17 3 + x 1 = 5. What is the sum Solution: E. Square both sides twice to get

More information

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities Part I Review of Basic Equations Recall that an equation is an expression with an equal sign in the middle. Also recall that, if a question asks you to solve

More information

Sets, Structures, Numbers

Sets, Structures, Numbers Chapter 1 Sets, Structures, Numbers Abstract In this chapter we shall introduce most of the background needed to develop the foundations of mathematical analysis. We start with sets and algebraic structures.

More information

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction Tutorial on Mathematical Induction Roy Overbeek VU University Amsterdam Department of Computer Science r.overbeek@student.vu.nl April 22, 2014 1 Dominoes: from case-by-case to induction Suppose that you

More information

Set theory. Math 304 Spring 2007

Set theory. Math 304 Spring 2007 Math 304 Spring 2007 Set theory Contents 1. Sets 2 1.1. Objects and set formation 2 1.2. Unions and intersections 3 1.3. Differences 4 1.4. Power sets 4 1.5. Ordered pairs and binary,amscdcartesian products

More information