A Logic of Injectivity

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "A Logic of Injectivity"

Transcription

1 A Logic of Injectivity J. Adámek, M. Hébert and L. Sousa Abstract Injectivity of objects wit respect to a set H of morpisms is an important concept of algebra, model teory and omotopy teory. Here we study te logic of injectivity consequences of H, by wic we understand morpisms suc tat injectivity wit respect to H implies injectivity wit respect to. We formulate tree simple deduction rules for te injectivity logic and for its finitary version were morpisms between finitely ranked objects are considered only, and prove tat tey are sound in all categories, and complete in all reasonable categories. 1 Introduction Recall tat an object A is injective w.r.t. a morpism : P P provided tat every morpism from P to A factors troug. We address te following problem: given a set H of morpisms, wic morpisms are injectivity consequences of H in te sense tat every object injective w.r.t. all members of H is also injective w.r.t.? We denote te injectivity consequence relationsip by H =. Tis is a classical topic in general algebra: te equational logic of Garrett Birkoff [10] is a special case. In fact, an equation s = t is a pair of elements of a free algebra F, and tat pair generates a congruence on F. An algebra A satisfies s = t iff it is injective w.r.t. te canonical epimorpism : F F/. Tus, if we restrict our sets H to regular epimorpisms wit free domains, ten te logic of injectivity becomes precisely te equational logic. However, tere are oter important cases in algebra: recall for example te concept of injective module, were H is te set of all monomorpisms (in te category of modules). To mention an example from omotopy teory, recall tat a Kan complex [14] is a simplicial set injective w.r.t. all te monomorpisms k n n (for n, k N, k n) were n is te complex generated by a single n-simplex and k n is te subcomplex obtained by deleting te k-t 1-simplex and all adjacent faces. We can ask for example weter Kan complexes can be specified by a simpler collection of monomorpisms, as a special case of our injectivity logic. Te tird autor acknowledges financial support by te Center of Matematics of te University of Coimbra and te Scool of Tecnology of Viseu 1

2 Injectivity establises a Galois correspondence between objects and morpisms of a category. Te closed families on te side of objects are called injectivity classes: for every set H of morpisms we obtain te injectivity class InjH, i.e., te class of all objects injective w.r.t. H. In [5] small-injectivity classes in locally presentable categories were caracterized as precisely te full accessible subcategories closed under products, and in [18] tis was sarpened in te following sense. Let us call a morpism λ-ary if its domain and codomain are λ-presentable objects. Injectivity classes wit respect to λ-ary morpisms are precisely te full subcategories closed under products, λ-filtered colimits, and λ-pure subobjects. For injectivity w.r.t. cones or trees of morpisms similar results are in [7] and [15]. In te present paper we study closed sets on te side of morpisms, i.e., we develop a deduction system for te above injectivity consequence relationsip =. It as altogeter tree deduction rules, wic are quite intuitive. Firstly, observe tat every object injective w.r.t. a composite = 2 1 is injective w.r.t. te first morpism 1. Tis gives us te first deduction rule cancellation It is also easy to see tat injectivity w.r.t. implies injectivity w.r.t. any morpism opposite to in a pusout (along an arbitrary morpism), wic yields te rule pusout for every pusout Finally, an object injective w.r.t. two composable morpisms is also injective w.r.t. teir composite. Te same olds for tree, four,... morpisms but also for a transfinite composite as used in omotopy teory. For example, given an ω-cain of morpisms A 0 0 A 1 1 A ten teir ω-composite is te first morpism c 0 : A 0 C of (any) colimit cocone c n : A n C (n N) of te cain. Observe tat c 0 is indeed an injectivity consequence of { i ; i < ω}. For every ordinal λ we ave te concept of a λ-composite of morpisms (see 2.10 below) and te following deduction rule, expressing te fact tat an object injective w.r.t. eac i is injective w.r.t. te transfinite composite: transfinite composition i (i < λ) for every λ-composite of ( i ) i<λ We are going to prove tat te Injectivity Logic based on te above tree rules is sound and complete. Tat is, given a set H of morpisms, ten H = olds for precisely tose morpisms wic can be proved from assumptions in H using te tree deduction rules above. Tis olds in a number of categories, e.g., in (a) every variety of algebras, (b) te category of topological spaces and many nice subcategories (e.g. Hausdorff spaces), and 2

3 (c) every locally presentable category of Gabriel and Ulmer. We introduce te concept of a strongly locally ranked category encompassing (a)-(c) above, and prove te soundness and completeness of our Injectivity Logic in all suc categories. Observe tat te above logic is infinitary, in fact, it as a proper class of deduction rules: one for every ordinal λ in te instance of transfinite composition. We also study, following te footsteps of Grigore Roşu, te completeness of te corresponding Finitary Injectivity Logic: it is te restriction of te above logic to λ finite. Well, all we need to consider are te cases λ = 2, called composition, and λ = 0, called identity: composition 1 0 for = 1 0 identity id A Te resulting finitary deductive system (introduced in [6] as a sligt modification of te deduction system of Grigore Roşu [19]) as four deduction rules; it is clearly sound, and te main result of our paper (Teorem 6.2) says tat it is also complete wit respect to finitary morpisms, i.e., morpisms wit domain and codomain of finite rank. Tis implies te expected compactness teorem: every finitary injectivity consequence of a set H of finitary morpisms is an injectivity consequence of some finite subset of H. Te completeness teorem for Finitary Injectivity Logic will ten be extended to te k-ary Injectivity Logic, defined in te expected way. Ten te full completeness teorem easily follows. Te fact tat te full Injectivity Logic above is complete in strongly locally ranked categories can also be derived from Quillen s Small Object Argument [17], see Remark 3.9 below. However our sarpening to te k-ary logic for every cardinal k cannot be derived from tat paper, and we consider tis to be a major step. Related work Bernard Banascewski and Horst Herrlic sowed tirty years ago tat implications in general algebra can be expressed categorically via injectivity w.r.t. regular epimorpisms, see [9]. A generalization to injectivity w.r.t. cones or even trees of morpisms was studied by Hajnal Andréka, István Németi and Ildikó Sain, see e.g. [7, 8, 15]. To see more precisely ow tat work relates to ours and to classical logic, consider injectivity in te category of all Σ-structures (and Σ-omomorpisms), were Σ is any signature. Ten recall from [4], 5.33 tat tere is a natural way to associate to a (finitary) morpism f : A B a (finitary) sentence f := X( A (X) Y ( B (X, Y ))) (were A (X) and B (X, Y ) are sets of atomic formulas) suc tat an object C satisfies f if and only if it is injective wit respect to f (see 2.22 below for more on tis). Suc sentences are called regular sentences. In tis paper we concentrate on te proof teory for te (finite and infinite) regular logics. As mentioned above, te restriction 3

4 to epimorpisms correspond to considering only te quasi-equations (i.e., no existential quantifiers), and just equations if we impose tey ave projective domains. Recently, Grigore Roşu introduced a deduction system for injectivity, see [19], and e proved tat te resulting logic is sound and complete for epimorpisms wic are finitely presentable, see 3.5, and ave projective domains. A sligt modification of Roşu s system was introduced in [6]: tis is te deduction system 2.4 below. It differs from [19] by formulating pusout more generally and using composition in place of Roşu s union. In [6] completeness is proved for sets of epimorpisms wit finitely presentable domains and codomains. (Tis is sligtly stronger tan requiring te epimorpisms to be finitely presentable, owever, witout te too restrictive assumption of projectivity of te domains te logic fails to be complete for finitely presentable epimorpisms in general, see [6].) In te present paper completeness of te finitary logic is proved for arbitrary morpisms (not necessarily epimorpisms) wit finitely presentable domains and codomains. Te fact tat te assumption of epimorpism is dropped makes te proof substantially more difficult. We present a sort proof in locally presentable categories first, and ten a proof of a more general result for strongly locally ranked categories. We also formulate te appropriate infinitary logic dealing wit arbitrary morpisms. Tere are oter generalizations of Birkoff s equational logic wic are, except for te common motivation, not related to our approac. For example te categorical approac to logic of (ordered) many-sorted algebras of Razvan Diaconescu [11], and te logic of implications in general algebra of Robert Quackenbus [16]. In our joint paper [1] we are taking anoter route to generalize te equational logic: we consider ortogonality of objects to a morpism instead of injectivity. Te deduction system is similar: te rule cancellation as to be weakened, and an additional rule concerning coequalizers is added. We prove te completeness of te resulting logic of ortogonality in locally presentable categories. Te corresponding sentences are te so called limit sentences, X( A (X)!Y ( B (X, Y ))), were!y means tere exists exactly one Y suc tat. 2 Logic of injectivity 2.0. Assumption Trougout te paper we assume tat we are working in a cocomplete category Definition A morpism is called an injectivity consequence of a set of morpisms H, notation H = provided tat every object injective w.r.t. all morpisms in H is also injective w.r.t Examples (1) A composite = 2 1 is an injectivity consequence of { 1, 2 }. (2) Conversely, in every composite = 2 1 te morpism 1 is an injectivity 4

5 consequence of : (3) In every pusout A 1 A 2 A X A A u B v B is an injectivity consequence of : A A u v B B X 2.3. Remark Te above examples are exaustive. More precisely, te following deduction system, introduced in [6], see also [19], (were, owever, it was only applied to epimorpisms) will be proved complete below: 2.4. Definition Te Finitary Injectivity Deduction System consists of one axiom identity id A and tree deduction rules composition cancellation if is defined and pusout if We say tat a morpism is a formal consequence of a set H of morpisms (notation H ) in te Finitary Injectivity Logic if tere exists a proof of from H (wic means a finite sequence 1,..., n = of morpisms suc tat for every i = 1,..., n te morpism i lies in H or is a conclusion of one of te deduction rules wose premises lie in { 1,..., i 1 }). 5

6 2.5. Lemma Te Finitary Injectivity Logic is sound, i.e., if a morpism is a formal consequence of a set of morpisms H, ten is an injectivity consequence of H. Briefly: H implies H =. Te proof follows from Remark Later we define finitary morpisms (as morpisms wose domains and codomains are finitely presentable (Section 3) or of finite rank (Section 5)), and in Section 6 we prove tat te resulting Finitary Injectivity Logic is complete, i.e., tat H = implies H for every set H of finitary morpisms and every finitary Example Te following rule finite coproduct (were for i : A i B i te morpism : A 1 + A 2 B 1 + B 2 is te canonical coproduct morpism) is obviously sound. Here is a proof in te Finitary Injectivity Logic: Using te pusouts 1 A 1 B 1 A 1 + A 2 1 +id A2 B 1 + A 2 2 A 2 B 2 B 1 + A 2 id B1 + 2 B 1 + B 2 we can write id A2 id B via pusout via composition since = (id B1 + 2 ) ( 1 + id A2 ) Example Te following rule finite wide pusout for every wide pusout 1... n 1 2 k 1 k 2 C... n... k n were = k i i is sound. Here is a proof in te Finitary Injectivity Logic: If n = 2 we ave 6

7 1 2 k 2 = k 2 2 via pusout via composition If n = 3 denote by r a pusout of 1, 2, ten a pusout, 3, 1 r 3 2 k 3 k 1 k 2 3 of 3 along r forms a wide pusout of 1, 2 and 3 : k 2 r k 3 = k 3 3 via pusout via composition via pusout via composition Etc Remark We want to define a composition of a cain of λ morpisms for every ordinal λ (see te case λ = ω in te Introduction). Recall tat a λ-cain is a functor A from λ, te well-ordered category of all ordinals i < λ. Recall furter tat λ + denotes te successor ordinal, i.e., te set of all i λ Definition (i) We call a λ-cain A smoot if for every limit ordinal i < λ we ave A i = colim j<i A j wit te colimit cocone of all a ji = A(j i). (ii) A morpism is called a λ-composite of morpisms ( i ) i<λ, were λ is an ordinal, if tere exists a smoot λ + -cain A wit connecting morpisms a ij : A i A j for i j λ suc tat i = a i,i+1 for all i < λ and = a 0,λ Examples λ = 0: No morpism i is given, just an object A 0 ; and = a 0,0 is te identity morpism of A 0. λ = 1: A morpism 0 is given, and we ave = a 0,1 = 0. Tus, a 1-composite of 0 is 0. 7

8 λ = 2: Tis is te usual concept of composition: given morpisms 0, 1, teir 2-composite exists iff tey are composable. Ten 1 0 is te 2-composite. λ = ω: Tis is te case mentioned in te Introduction. Observe tat, unlike te previous cases, an ω-composite is only unique up to isomorpism Lemma A λ-composite of morpisms ( i ) i<λ is an injectivity consequence of tese morpisms. Proof Tis is a trivial transfinite induction on λ. In case λ = 0 tis states tat id A is an injectivity consequence of, etc Definition Te Injectivity Deduction System consists of te deduction rules cancellation pusout for every pusout and te rule sceme (one rule for every ordinal λ) transfinite composition i (i < λ) for every λ-composite of ( i ) i<λ We say tat a morpism is a formal consequence of a set H of morpisms (notation H ) in te Injectivity Logic if tere exists a proof of from H (wic means a cain ( i ) i n of morpisms, were n is an ordinal, suc tat = n, and eac i eiter lies in H, or is a conclusion of one of te deduction rules wose premises lie in { j } j<i ) Lemma Te Injectivity Logic is sound, i.e., if a morpism is a formal consequence of a set H of morpisms, ten is an injectivity consequence of H. Briefly: H implies H =. Te proof (using 2.12) is elementary Remark In 2.13 we can replace transfinite composition by te deduction rule wide pusout, see below, wic makes use of te (obvious) fact tat an object A injective w.r.t. a set { i } i<λ of morpisms aving a common domain is also injective w.r.t. teir wide pusout. Let us note ere tat tis rule does not replace pusout of 2.13 (because in te latter a pusout of along an arbitrary morpism is considered) Definition Te deduction rule wide pusout i (i < λ) for a wide pusout of { i } i<λ applies, for every cardinal λ, to an arbitrary object P and an arbitrary set { i } of λ 8

9 morpisms wit te common domain P and te following wide pusout i P i k i P Q... = k i i (for any i) Remark Again, tis is a sceme of deduction rules: for every cardinal λ we ave one rule λ-wide pusout. Observe tat λ = 0 yields te rule identity Lemma Te Injectivity Deduction System 2.13 is equivalent to te deduction system composition, cancellation, pusout and wide pusout. Proof (1) We can derive wide pusout from For every ordinal number λ we derive te rule i (i < λ) for a wide pusout of { i } i<λ by transfinite induction on te ordinal λ. We are given an object P and morpisms i : P P i (i < λ). Te case λ = 0 is trivial, from λ derive λ + 1 by using pusout, and for limit ordinals λ form te restricted multiple pusouts Q j of morpisms i for i < j, and observe tat tey form a smoot cain wose composite is a multiple pusout of all i s. (2) From te system in 2.17 we can derive te rule λ-composition, were λ is an arbitrary ordinal: te case λ = 0 follows from 0-wide pusout. Te isolated step uses composition: te (λ + 1)-composite of ( i ) i λ is simply λ k were k is te λ-composite of ( i ) i<λ. In te limit case, use te fact tat a composite of ( i ) i<λ is a wide pusout of {k i } i<λ, were k i is a composite of ( j ) j<i Remark For every infinite cardinal k te k-ary Injectivity Deduction System is te system 2.13 were λ ranges troug ordinals smaller tan k. A proof of a morpism from a set H in te k-ary Injectivity Logic is, ten, a proof of lengt n < k using only te deduction rules wit λ restricted as above. Te last lemma can, obviously, be formulated under tis restriction in case we use te sceme λ-wide pusout for all cardinals λ < k Definition Te deduction rule coproduct i (i < λ) i<λ i applies, for every cardinal λ, to an arbitrary collection of λ morpisms i : A i B i. 9

10 2.20. Lemma Te Injectivity Deduction System 2.13 is equivalent to te deduction system of 2.17 wit wide pusout replaced by identity + coproduct Proof (1) coproduct follows from In fact, i<λ i : i<λ A i i<λ B i is a wide pusout of te morpisms k j : i<λ A i i<j A i + B j + j<i<λ A i, were j ranges troug λ, wit components id Ai (i j) and j, and k j is a pusout of j along te j-t coproduct injection of i<λ A i. (2) Conversely, wide pusout follows from identity+coproduct. We obviously need to consider only λ > 1 and ten we use te fact tat given morpisms i : A B i (i < λ), teir wide pusout : A C can be obtained from i<λ i by pusing out along te codiagonal : λ A A: A ` i Bi A C Remark Te deduction system of te last lemma as five rules, but te advantage against te system 2.13 is tat tey are particularly simple to formulate: identity cancellation id A composition if 2 1 is defined pusout given coproduct i (i I) i I i We prove below tat 2.13, and terefore te above equivalent deduction system, is not only sound but (in a number of categories) also complete Remark To relate our deduction rules to te usual ones (of classical logic), let us consider, as in te Introduction, te category of all Σ-structures. Ten any object A can be presented by a set A (X) of atomic formulas wit parameters X in A: for te familiar algebraic structures, tis is just te usual concept of generators and relations. Given a morpism f : A B, and suc presentations A (X) and B o(y ) of A and B, we can also present B by B (X, Y ), wic is te union of B o(y ) and te set of all te 10

11 equations x = t(y ) for wic f(x) = t(y ) (t a Σ-term). Ten for te sentence f := X( A (X) Y ( B (X, Y ))) we ave tat an object C is f-injective iff C = f. Note tat if f is finitary (see te Introduction or 3.4 below), te presentations, and ence f, can be cosen to be finitary (more details in [4], 5.33). Now, we can associate Gentzen-style rules to sets of atomic formulas, generalizing te idea of wat was done (wit more accuracy) in [6] for sets of equations: associating A (X) B (X, Y ) to X( A (X) Y ( B (X, Y ))), te identity axiom is of course A (X) A (X) ; cancellation is a categorical version of te restriction rule A (X) (B (X, Y ) C (X, Y, Z)) A (X) B (X, Y ) ; pusout is essentially te weakening rule A (X) B (X, Y ) (A (X) C (X, Z)) B (X, Y ) ; and composition is a cut rule A (X) B (X, Y ), B (X, Y ) C (X, Y, Z) A (X) C (X, Y, Z). Te usual stronger cut rule corresponds to A (X) B (X, Y ), ((B (X, Y ) C (X, Y, Z)) D (X, Y, Z, U) (A (X) C (X, Y, Z)) D (X, Y, Z, U) wic is proved via A f B, B + C g D A + C g (f+1 C) C, f g f + id C g g (f + 1 C ) pusout composition 11

12 3 Completeness in locally presentable categories 3.1. Assumption In te present section we study injectivity in a locally presentable category A of Gabriel and Ulmer, see [12] or [4]. Tis means tat: (a) A is cocomplete, and (b) tere exists a regular cardinal λ suc tat A as a set of λ-presentable objects wose closure under λ-filtered colimits is all of A. Recall tat an object A is λ-presentable if its om-functor om(a, ) : A Set preserves λ-filtered colimits. Tat is, given a λ-filtered diagram D wit a colimit c i : D i C (i I) in A, ten for every morpism f : A C and (i) a factorization of f troug c i exists for some i I, (ii) factorizations are essentially unique, i.e., given i I and c i g = c i g for some g, g : A D i, tere exists a connecting morpism d ij : D i D j of te diagram wit d ij g = d ij g Examples (see [4]) Sets, preseaves, varieties of algebras and simplicial sets are examples of locally presentable categories. Categories suc as Top (topological spaces) or Haus (Hausdorff spaces) are not locally presentable Remark (a) In te present section we prove tat te Injectivity Logic is complete in every locally presentable category. Te reader may decide to skip tis section since we prove a more general result in Section 6. Bot of our proofs are based on te fact tat for every set H of morpisms te full subcategory InjH (of all objects injective w.r.t. morpisms of H) is weakly reflective. Tat is: every object A A as a morpism r : A A, called a weak reflection, suc tat and (i) A lies in InjH (ii) every morpism from A to an object of InjH factors troug r (not necessarily uniquely). In te present section we will utilize te classical Small Object Argument of D. Quillen [17]: tis tells us tat every object A as a weak reflection r : A A in InjH suc tat r is a transfinite composite of morpisms of te class Ĥ = {k; k is a pusout of a member of H along some morpism}. (b) Te reason for proving te completeness based on te Small Object Argument in te present section is tat te proof is sort and elegant. However, by using a more refined construction of weak reflection in InjH, wic we present in Section 5, we will be 12

13 able to prove te completeness in te so-called strongly locally ranked categories, wic include Top and Haus. Te spirits of te two proofs are quite different. Given an injectivity consequence of a set of morpisms, in tis section we will sow ow to derive a formal proof of from Quillen s construction of te weak reflection; tis construction is linear, forming a transfinite composite. In te next section, a weak reflection will be constructed as a colimit of a filtered diagram wic someow presents simultaneously all te possible formal proofs Definition A morpism is called λ-ary provided tat its domain and codomain are λ-presentable objects. For λ = ℵ 0 we say finitary Remark (a) Te λ-ary morpisms are precisely te λ-presentable objects of te arrow category A. In contrast, M. Hébert introduced in [13] λ-presentable morpisms; tese are te morpisms f : A B wic are λ-presentable objects of te slice category A A. In te present paper we will not use te latter concept. (b) We work now wit te Finitary Injectivity Logic, i.e., te deduction system 2.4 applied to finitary morpisms. We generalize tis to te k-ary logic below Teorem Te Finitary Injectivity Logic is complete in every locally presentable category A. Tat is, given a set H of finitary morpisms in A, ten every finitary morpism wic is an injectivity consequence of H is a formal consequence in te deduction system 2.4. Briefly: H = implies H. Proof Given a finitary morpism : A B wic is an injectivity consequence of H, we prove tat H. (a) Te above object A as a weak reflection r : A A suc tat r is a transfinite composition of morpisms in Ĥ, see 3.3(a). Since H =, it follows tat A is injective w.r.t., wic yields a morpism u forming a commutative triangle r A A u B (b) Consider all commutative triangles as above were r : A A is any α-composite of morpisms in Ĥ for some ordinal α and u is arbitrary. We prove tat te least possible α is finite. Tis finises te proof of H : In case α = 0, we ave tat id = u, and we derive via identity and cancellation. In case α is a finite ordinal greater tan 0, we ave tat r is provable from H using pusout and composition. Consequently, via cancellation, we get. 13

14 Let C be te class of all ordinals α suc tat tere are an α-composite r of morpisms of Ĥ and a morpism u wit r = u. To sow tat te least member γ of C is finite, we prove tat for eac ordinal γ ω in C we can find anoter ordinal in C wic is smaller tan γ. A. Case γ = β + m, wit β a limit ordinal and m > 0 finite. Let a i,i+1 (i < β + m) be te corresponding cain wit r = a 0,β+m. Since a β,β+1 lies in Ĥ, we can express it as a pusout of some morpism k : D D in H: k D A 0 a 01 A 1... a 12 A i a i,i+1 D q p p A i+1 a i+1,i+2 A i+2... a i+2,i+3 A β aβ,β+1 A β+1 v i P i v i+1 v i+2 p i,i+1 P i+1 p i+1,i+2 P i+2 p i+2,i+3 v β... P β We ave a colimit A β = colim i<β A i of a cain of morpisms. Hence, because D is finitely presentable, p factorizes as p = a iβ q for some i < β and some morpism q : D A i. Let v i be a pusout of k along q, and form a sequence v j of pusouts of k along a ij q (j < β) as illustrated in te diagram above (taking colimits at te limit ordinals). Ten it is easily seen, due to p = a iβ q, tat v β = colim j<β v j is a pusout of k along p. Tus, witout loss of generality, P β = A β+1 and v β = a β,β+1. Observe tat, since a j,j+1 lies in Ĥ, pusout implies tat p j,j+1 Ĥ for all i j < β. Also v i Ĥ since it is a pusout of k along q. Consequently, a 0,β+1 is a β-composite of morpisms b j,j+1 (j < β) of Ĥ as follows (were l is te first limit ordinal after i): and b j,j+1 = a j,j+1 for all j < i, b i,i+1 = v i, b j,j+1 = p j 1,j for all i < j < l, b j,j+1 = p j,j+1 for all l j < β. Tus r = a 0,β+m is a (β + (m 1))-composite of morpisms of Ĥ. B. Case γ is a limit ordinal. Te morpism u : B A = colim i<γ A i factors, since B is finitely presentable, troug some a iγ, i < γ: u = a iγ u for some u : B A i. 14

15 Te parallel pair A = A 0 u A i a 0i is clearly merged by te colimit morpism a iγ of A γ = colim i<γ A i. Since A is finitely presentable, om(a, ) preserves tat colimit, consequently (see (ii) in 3.1.b), te parallel pair is also merged by a connecting morpism a ij : A i A j for some i < j < γ: Tis gives us a commutative triangle a ij u = a 0j. a 01 a A 0 12 A 1... Aj a ij u B tus a 0j is a j-composite of morpisms of Ĥ wit j < γ Remark Te above teorem immediatly generalizes to te k-ary Injectivity Logic, i.e., to te deduction system of 2.18 applied to k-ary morpisms. Recall tat for every set of objects in a locally presentable category tere exists a cardinal k suc tat all tese objects are k-presentable. Consequently, for every set H {} of morpisms tere exists k suc tat all members are k-ary. Te proof tat H = implies H is completely analogously to 3.6: We sow tat te least possible α is smaller tan k, tus in Cases A. and B. we work wit γ k Corollary Te Injectivity Logic is sound and complete in every locally presentable category. In fact, given H = find a cardinal k suc tat all members of H {} are k-ary morpisms. Ten is a formal consequence of H by Remark Te above corollary also follows from te Small Object Argument (see 3.3(a)): if : A B is an injectivity consequence of H and if r : A A is te corresponding weak reflection, ten r is clearly a formal consequence of H. Since A is injective w.r.t., it follows tat r factors troug, tus, is a formal consequence of r (via cancellation). 4 Strongly locally ranked categories 4.1. Remark Recall tat a factorization system in a category is a pair (E, M) of classes of morpisms containing all isomorpisms and closed under composition suc tat (a) every morpism f : A B as a factorization f = m e wit e : A C in E and m : C B in M 15

16 and (b) given anoter suc factorization f = m e tere exists a unique diagonal fill-in morpism d making te diagram commutative. A e C e d m C B m Te factorization system is called left-proper if every morpism of E is an epimorpism. In tat case te E-quotients of an object A are te quotient objects of A represented by morpisms of E wit domain A Definition Let (E, M) be a factorization system. We say tat an object A as M-rank λ, were λ is a regular cardinal, provided, tat (a) om(a, ) preserves λ-filtered colimits of diagrams of M-morpisms (i.e., given a λ-filtered diagram D wose connecting morpisms lie in M, ten every morpism f : A colimd factors, essentially uniquely, troug a colimit map of D) and (b) A as less tan λ E-quotients. If λ = ℵ 0 we say tat te object A as finite M-rank Examples (1) For te factorization system (Iso, All), rank λ is equivalent to λ- presentability. (2) In te category Top of topological spaces, coose (E, M) = (Epi, Strong Mono). Here te M-subobjects are precisely te embeddings of subspaces. Every topological space A of cardinality α as M-rank λ wenever λ > 2 2α. In fact, om(a, ) preserves λ-directed unions of subspaces since α < λ. And te amount of quotient objects of A (carried by epimorpisms) is at most β α E βt β were E β is te number of equivalence relations on A of order β and T β is te number of topologies on a set of cardinality β. Since E β and T β are bot 2 2β, we ave β α E βt β α 2 2α 2 2α < λ, tus we conclude tat A as less tan λ quotients Remark Every E-quotient of an object of M-rank λ also as M-rank λ. In fact (a) in 4.2 follows easily by diagonal fill-in, and (b) is obvious Definition A category A is called strongly locally ranked provided tat it as a left-proper factorization system (E, M) suc tat (i) A is cocomplete; (ii) every object as an M-rank, and all objects of te same M-rank form a set up to isomorpism; 16

17 (iii) for every cardinal µ te collection of all objects of M-rank µ is closed under E- quotients and under µ-small colimits, i.e., colimits of diagrams wit less tan µ morpisms; and and (iv) te subcategory of all objects of A and all morpisms of M is closed under filtered colimits in A. Remark Te statement (iv) means tat, given a filtered colimit wit connecting morpisms in M, ten (a) te colimit cocone is formed by morpisms of M (b) every oter cocone of M-morpisms as te unique factorizing morpism in M Examples (1) Every locally presentable category is strongly locally ranked: coose E isomorpisms, M all morpisms. In fact, see [4], 1.9 for te proof of (ii), wereas (iii) and (iv) old trivially. (2) Coose E epimorpisms, M strong monomorpisms. Here categories suc as Top (wic are not locally presentable) are included. In fact, for a space A of cardinality α we ave tat om(a, ) preserves λ-filtered colimits (=unions) of subspaces wenever α < λ. Tus, by coosing a cardinal λ > α bigger tan te number of quotients of A we get an M-rank of A. It is easy to verify (iii) and (iv) in Top. (3) Let B be a full, isomorpism closed, E-reflective subcategory of a strongly locally ranked category A. If B is closed under filtered colimits of M-morpisms in A, ten B is strongly locally ranked. In fact, B is closed under M in te sense tat given m : A B in M wit B B, ten A B. (Indeed, we ave a reflection r A : A A in E and m = m r A for a unique m ; tis implies tat r A E is an isomorpism, tus, A B.) Terefore te restriction of (E, M) to B yields a factorization system. It fulfils (ii)-(iv) of 4.5 because B is closed under filtered colimits of M-morpisms. (4) Te category Haus of Hausdorff spaces is strongly locally ranked: it is an epireflective subcategory of Top closed under filtered unions of subspaces Observation In a strongly locally ranked category te class M is closed under transfinite composition. Tis follows from (iv) Definition A morpism is called k-ary if its domain and codomain ave M-rank k. In case k = ℵ 0 we speak of finitary morpisms. 17

18 4.9. Remark Te name strongly locally ranked was cosen since our requirements are somewat stronger tan tose of [2]: tere a category is called locally ranked in case it is cocomplete, as an (E, M)-factorization, is E-cowellpowered and for every object A tere exists an infinite cardinal λ suc tat om(a, ) preserves colimits of λ-cains of M-monomorpisms. Our definition of rank and te condition 4.5(ii) imply tat te given category is E-cowellpowered. Tus, every strongly locally ranked category is locally ranked. An example of a locally ranked category tat is not strongly locally ranked is te category of σ-semilattices (posets wit countable joins and functions preserving tem): condition 4.5(iv) fails ere. Consider e.g. te ω-cain of te posets exp(n) (were n = {0, 1,..., n 1}), n ω, wit inclusion as order. Te colimit of tis cain is exp(n) ordered by inclusion. If M is te poset of all finite subsets of N wit an added top element, ten te embeddings exp(n) M form a cocone of te cain, but te factorization morpism exp(n) M is not a monomorpism. 5 A construction of weak reflections 5.1. Assumption In te present section A denotes a strongly locally ranked category. For every infinite cardinal k, A k denotes a cosen set of objects of M-rank k closed under E-quotients and k-small colimits. In particular, one may of course coose A k to be a set of representatives of all te objects of M-rank k up to isomorpism. Given a set H M of k-ary morpisms of A k (considered as a full subcategory of A), [2] provides a construction of a weak reflection in Inj H, wic generalizes te Small Object Argument (see 3.3). However, tis does not appear to be sufficient to prove our Completeness Teorem for te finitary case. Te aim of tis section is to present a different, more appropriate construction. We begin wit te case k = ω and come back to te general case at te end of tis section Convention (a) Morpisms wit domain and codomain in A ω are called petty. (b) Given a set H of petty morpisms, let H denote te closure of H under finite composition and pusout in A ω. (Tat is, H is te closure of H {id A ; A A ω } under binary composition and pusout along petty morpisms.) (c) Since H mora ω is a set, we can, for every object B of A ω, index all morpisms of H wit domain B by a set and tat indexing set can be cosen to be independent of B. Tat is, we assume tat a set T is given and tat for every object B A ω, is te set of all morpisms of H wit domain B. { B (t) : B B(t) ; t T } (5.1) 18

19 5.3. Diagram D A For every object A A ω we define a diagram D A in A and later prove tat a weak reflection of A in Inj H is obtained as a colimit of D A. Te domain D of D A, independent of A, is te poset of all finite words ε, M 1, M 1 M 2,..., M 1... M k (k < ω) were ε denotes te empty word and eac M i is a finite subset of T. Te ordering is as follows: M 1... M k N 1... N l iff k l and M 1 N 1,..., M k N k. Observe tat ε is te least element. We denote te objects D A (M 1... M k ) of te diagram D A by A M were M = M 1... M k, and if M 1... M k N 1... N l = N, we denote by a M,N : A M A N te corresponding connecting morpism of D A. We define tese objects and connecting morpisms by induction on te lengt k of te word M = M 1... M k considered. Case k = 0: A ε = A. Induction step: Assume tat all objects A M wit M of lengt less tan or equal to k and all connecting morpisms between tem are defined. For every word M of lengt k + 1 denote by M M te prefix of M of lengt k, and define te object A M as a colimit of te following finite diagram A K AK (t) A K (t) a K,M A M... were K ranges over all words K D wit K M and t ranges over te set M k+1. Tus, A M is equipped wit (te universal cone of) morpisms a M,M : A M A M (connecting morpism of D A ) and d K M(t) : A K (t) A M for all K M, t M k+1, 19

20 forming commutative squares a K,M A M A K AK (t) A K (t) (5.2) a M,M A M d K M (t) Tis defines te objects A M for all words of lengt k + 1. Next we define connecting morpisms a N,M : A N A M for all words N M. If te lengt of N is at most k, ten N M and we define a N,M troug te (already defined) connecting morpism a N,M by composing it wit te above a M,M. If N as lengt k + 1, we define a N,M as te unique morpism for wic te diagrams A K a K,N AK (t) A N A K (t) a N,N d K N (t) A N a N,M a d K N,M M (t) A M (K N, t N k+1 ) (5.3) commute. It is easy to verify tat te morpisms a N,M are well-defined and tat D A : D A preserves composition and identity morpisms Lemma All connecting morpisms of te diagram D A lie in H. Proof We first observe tat, given a finite diagram A i i B i f i C (i I) 20

21 wit all i in H, a colimit i A i B i f i d i C D (i I) (5.4) is obtained by first considering pusouts i of i along f i and ten forming a wide pusout of all i (i I). Consequently, te connecting morpisms of D A are formed by repeating one of te following steps: a finite wide pusout of morpisms in H, a composition of morpisms in H, and a pusout of a morpism in H along a petty morpism. Since H is closed, by 5.2, under te latter, it is closed under te first one in te obvious sense, see te construction of a finite wide pusout described in Example Lemma For every object A M of te diagram D A and every morpism : A M B of H tere exists a connecting morpism a M, N : A M A N of D A wic factors troug. Proof We ave M = M 1... M k and = AM (t) for some t T. Put N = M 1... M k {t}. Ten for K = M te definition of d K N (t) (see (5.2)) gives te following commutative diagram: Consequently, as required. A M id AM (t) A M (t) A M a M,N A N d K N (t) a M,N = d K N(t) AM (t) 5.6. Proposition Let H be a set of petty morpisms wit H M. Ten for every object A A ω a colimit γ M : A M  (M D) of te diagram D A yields a weak reflection of A in Inj H via r A = γ ε : A Â. Proof (1)  is injective w.r.t. H: We want to prove tat given H and f as follows B C f  ten f factors troug. Firstly, since  = colimd A is a directed colimit of H- morpisms (see 5.4) wit H M, and B as finite M-rank (because B A ω ), it follows 21

22 tat om(b, ) preserves te colimit of D A. Tus, tere exists a colimit morpism γ N : A N  troug wic f factors, f = γ N f. B C f f f  γ N A N A N (t) γ M A M a N, M By pusing H out along f we obtain a morpism H. Ten by 5.5 tere exists M N suc tat a N,M = for some : A N (t) A M. Te above commutative diagram proves tat f factors troug. (2) Let B be injective w.r.t. H. For every morpism f : A B we define a compatible cocone f M : A M B of te diagram D A by induction on k = te lengt of te word M suc tat f ε = f. Ten te desired factorization of f is obtained via te (unique) factorization g :  B wit g γ M = f M : in fact, g r A = f. For k k + 1, coose for every word N of lengt k and every t T a morpism f N (t) forming a commutative triangle A N AN (t) A N (t) f N f N (t) B (recalling tat B is H-injective because it is H-injective). Ten for every word M of lengt k+1 we ave a unique factorization f M : A M B making te following diagrams A K AK (t) A K (t) (5.5) a K, M d K M (t) a M,M f K (t) A M A M f M f M commutative for all K M and t M k+1. Let us verify te compatibility f M = f N a M, N for all M N in D. (5.6) Te last diagram yields f M = f M a M, M. Terefore, it is sufficient to prove (5.6) for words M and N of te same lengt k + 1. In order to do tat, we will sow tat f M d K M(t) = f N a M,N d K M(t), for all K M and t M k+1, (5.7) 22 B

23 and Concerning (5.7), we ave f M d K M (t) f M a M,M = f N a M,N a M,M. (5.8) = f K(t) = f N d K N (t), by replacing M by N in (5.5) = f N a M,N d K M (t), by (5.3). As for (5.8), we ave f M a M,M = f M = f N a M,N = f N a N,N a M,N, by replacing M by N in (5.5) = f N a M,N a M,M Convention Generalizing te above construction from ω to any infinite cardinal k, we call te morpisms of A k k-petty. Let us now denote by H k te closure of H under k-composition (2.10) and pusout in A k. Following 2.18, H k is closed under k-wide pusout. We again assume tat a set T is given suc tat, for every object B A k we ave an indexing B (t) : B B(t), t T of all morpisms of H k wit domain B Diagram D A Te poset D of 5.3 is generalized to a poset D k : Let P k T be te poset of all subsets of T of cardinality < k. Te elements of D k are all functions M : λ P k T were λ < k is an ordinal, including te case ε : 0 P k T. Te ordering is as follows: for N : λ P k T put M N iff λ λ and M i N i for all i < λ. We define, for every A A k, te diagram D A : D k A. Te objects D A (M) = A M and te connecting morpisms a M,N : A M A N (M N) are defined by transfinite induction on λ < k. For λ = 0 we ave A ε = A. Te isolated step is precisely as in 5.3, were for M : λ + 1 P k T we denote by M : λ P k T te domain-restriction. Te limit steps are defined via colimits of smoot cains, see 2.10: if λ < k is a limit ordinal and M : λ P k T is given, ten A M is a colimit of te cain A M/i (i < λ), were M/i is te domain restriction of M to i, wit te connecting morpisms a M/i, M/j : A M/i 23

24 A M/j for all i j < λ. Te proof tat tese cains are smoot is an easy transfinite induction. It is also easy to see tat all te above results old: Â = colimd A is an H-injective weak reflection of A, and all connecting morpisms of D A are members of H. Consequently, te proof of te following proposition is analogous to tat of 5.6: 5.9. Proposition Let H be a set of k-petty morpisms wit H k M. Ten for every object A A k a colimit γ M : A M Â of D A yields a weak reflection of A in InjH via r A = γ ε : A Â. 6 Completeness in strongly locally ranked categories 6.1. Assumption Trougout tis section A denotes a strongly locally ranked category. We first prove te completeness of te finitary logic. Recall tat te finitary morpisms are tose were te domain and codomain are of finite M-rank. Let us remark tat wenever te class M is closed under pusout, ten te metod of proof of Teorem 3.6 applies again. However, tis excludes examples suc as Haus (were strong monomorpisms are not closed under pusout) Teorem Te Finitary Injectivity Logic is complete in every strongly locally ranked category. Tat is, given a set H of finitary morpisms, every finitary morpism wic is an injectivity consequence of H is a formal consequence (in te deduction system of 2.4). Sortly: H = implies H Remark We do not need te full strengt of weak local presentation for tis result. We are going to prove te completeness under te following milder assumptions on A: (i) A is cocomplete and as a left-proper factorization system (E, M); (ii) A ω is a set of objects of finite M-rank, closed under finite colimits and E-quotients; (iii) M is closed under filtered colimits in A (see 4.5 (iv)). Te statement we prove is, ten, concerned wit petty morpisms (see 5.2). We sow tat for every set H of petty morpisms we ave H = implies H (for all petty). Te coice of A ω as a set of representatives of all objects of finite M-rank yields te statement of te teorem. Proof of 6.2 and 6.3 Let ten H be a set of petty morpisms, and let H denote te closure of H as in 5.2. (1) We first prove tat te teorem olds wenever H M. Moreover, we will sow tat for every petty injectivity consequence H = we ave a formal proof of from 24

25 assumptions in H suc tat te use of pusout is always restricted to pusing out along petty morpisms. To prove tis, consider, for te given petty injectivity consequence : A B of H, te weak reflection r A : A  in Inj H of 5.6. Te object  is injective w.r.t., tus r A factors troug via some f : B Â: r A A B f A M γ M a N, M  γ N Since B A ω, it as finite M-rank, and 5.4 implies tat om(b, ) preserves te colimit  = colimd A. Ten f factors troug one of te colimit morpisms γ N : A N Â: g A N f = γ N g for some g : B A N. We know tat r A = γ ε is te composite of te connecting morpism a ε, N : A A N of D A and γ N, terefore, γ N a ε, N = r A = γ N g. Tat is, te colimit morpism γ N merges te parallel pair a ε, N, g : A A N. Now te domain A as finite M-rank, tus om(a, ) also preserves  = colimd A. Consequently, by (ii) in 3.1(b) te parallel pair is also merged by some connecting morpism a N, M : A N A M of D A : a N, M a ε, N = a N, M g : A A M. Te left-and side is simply a ε, M, and tis is a morpism of H, see Lemma 5.4. Recall tat te definition of H implies tat every morpism in H can be proved from H using Finitary Injectivity Logic in wic pusout is only applied to pusing out along petty morpisms. Tus, we ave a proof of te rigt-and side a N, M g. Te last step is deriving from tis by cancellation. (2) Assuming H E, ten we prove tat Inj H is a reflective subcategory of A, and for every object A A ω te reflection map r A : A  is a formal consequence of H lying in E: H r A and r A E. In fact, from H E it follows tat H E (since E is closed under composition and pusout). Since A as only finitely many E-quotients, see 4.2, we can form a finite wide pusout, r A : A Â, of all E-quotients of A lying in H. Clearly, H r A, in fact, r A H. Te object  is injective w.r.t. H: given : P P in H and f : P Â, form a pusout of along f. Tis is an E-quotient in H, ten te same is true for 25

26 r A. Consequently, r A factors troug r A, and te factorization, i : B Â, is an epimorpism split by, tus, f = i g : P P f A r A Â Te morpism r A is a weak reflection: given a morpism u from A to an object C of Inj H, ten u factors troug r A because C is injective w.r.t. H and r A H. (3) Let H be arbitrary. We begin our proof by defining an increasing sequence of sets E i E of petty morpisms (i Ord). For every member f : A B of H we denote by f i a reflection of f in Inj E i : r A i A f B Â fi ˆB First step: E 0 = {id A ; A A ω }. Here Inj E 0 = A, tus f 0 = f. Isolated step: For eac f H, let f i = f i f i be te (E, M)-factorization of te reflection f i of f in Inj E i, and put and r B B E i+1 = E i {f i; f H}. Limit step: E j = i<j E i for limit ordinals j. We prove tat for every ordinal i we ave g H f i for every f H (6.1) Inj H = Inj E i Inj{f i } f H. (6.2) For i = 0, (6.1) and (6.2) are trivial (use cancellation for (6.1) and identity for (6.2)). Given i > 0, assuming tat H f j for all j < i, wit f : A B in H, tat is, H E i, we ave, by (2), tat H r B (6.3) were r B is te reflection of B in Inj E i. Tus, H f i r A. Moreover, r A is an epimorpism, terefore te following square A r A Â f i ˆB r A Â f i ˆB id is a pusout, wic proves H f i (via pusout). H f i ten follows by cancellation. 26

27 To prove (6.2), observe tat (6.1) implies Inj H Inj E i, and our previous argument yields Inj H Inj {f i } f H. Tus, it remains to prove te reverse inclusion: every object X injective w.r.t. E i {f i } f H is injective w.r.t. H. In fact, given f : A B in H and a morpism u : A X, ten since X Inj E i we ave a factorization u = v r A, and ten te injectivity of X w.r.t. f i yields te desired factorization of u troug f. A u f B r A X v  ˆB f i r B (4) Since A ω is a small category, tere exists an ordinal j wit We want to apply (1) to te category and te set E j = E j+1. A = Inj E j, A ω = A ω obja. Let us verify tat A satisfies te assumptions (i) (iii) of Remark 6.3 w.r.t. E = E mora and M = M mora. Ad(i): A is cocomplete because it is reflective in A. Moreover, since te reflection maps lie in E, it follows tat (E, M ) is a factorization system: in fact, A is closed under factorization in A. Since E Epi(A), we ave E Epi(A ). Ad(iii): It is sufficient to prove tat A is closed under filtered colimits of M - morpisms in A. In fact, let D be a filtered diagram in A wit connecting morpisms in M, and let c t : C t C (t T ) be a colimit of D in A. Ten C A, i.e., C is injective w.r.t. f j :  E for every f H. Tis follows from  aving finite M-rank (because A A ω implies  A ω due to te fact tat r A : A  is an E-quotient): since om(â, ) preserves te colimit of D, every morpism u :  C factors troug some of te colimit morpisms:  v C t c t C u f j E Since C t A is injective w.r.t. f j, we ave a factorization of v troug f j, and terefore, u also factors troug f j. Tis proves C A. 27

28 Ad(ii): Due to te above, every object of A aving a finite M-rank in A as a finite M -rank in A. Also, a finite colimit of objects of A in A is a reflection (tus, an E-quotient) of te corresponding finite colimit in A. Tus, it lies in A ω. Next we claim tat te set H = {f j ; f H} fulfils H M and H is closed under petty identities, composition, and pusouts along petty morpisms. In fact, in te above (E, M)-factorization of f j : A f B r A  f j f j f j D ˆB r B we know tat f j lies in E j+1 = E j and  is injective w.r.t. E j, tus, f j is a split monomorpism (as well as an epimorpism, since E Epi(A)). Tus, f j is an isomorpism, wic implies f j M. H contains id A for every A A ω because H contains it; H is closed under composition because H is (and f f j is te action of te reflector functor from A to Inj E j ). Finally, H is closed under pusout along petty morpisms. In fact, to form a pusout of f j :  ˆB along u :  C in A = Inj E j, we form a pusout, g, of f along u r A in A, and compose it wit te reflection map r D of te codomain D: A f B r A r B  f j ˆB v ˆv u ˆD ĝ r D C g D Since C lies in A, we can assume r C = id C, and te reflection ĝ = r D g of g in A is ten a pusout of f j along u. Now f H implies g H, and we ave ĝ = g j H. (5) We are ready to prove tat if a petty morpism : A B is an injectivity consequence of H, ten H in A. We write H A for te latter since we work witin two categories: wen we apply (1) to A we use A for formal consequence in A. Analogously wit = A and = A. Let ĥ :  ˆB be a reflection of in A, ten H = A ĥ because every object C A = Inj E j wic is injective w.r.t. H = {f j } f H is, due to (6.2), injective w.r.t. H in A. Ten C is injective w.r.t., and from C A it follows 28

29 easily tat C is injective w.r.t. ĥ. Due to (4) we can apply (1). Terefore, H A ĥ. We tus ave a proof of ĥ from H in A. We modify it to obtain a proof of from H in A. We ave no problems wit a line of te given proof tat uses one of te assumptions f j H : we know from (6.1) tat H A f j, and we substitute tat line wit a formal proof of f j in A. No problem is, of course, caused by te lines using composition or cancellation. But we need to modify te lines using pusout because A is not closed under pusout in A. However, a pusout, g, of a morpism g along a petty morpism u in A u P g Q P g r Q g Q is obtained from a pusout, g, of g along u in A by composing it wit a reflection map r Q of te pusout codomain. Recall tat P, P, Q A ω imply Q A ω. Tus, we can replace te line g of te given proof by using pusout in A (deriving g ), followed by a proof of r Q (recall from (6.3) tat H A r Q ) and an application of composition. We tus proved tat H A ĥ. Since r B = ĥ r A and H A r A (see (6.3)), we conclude H A ĥ r A ; by cancellation ten H A Corollary (Compactness Teorem) Let H be a set of finitary morpisms in a strongly locally ranked category. Every finitary morpism wic is an injectivity consequence of H is an injectivity consequence of a finite subset of H Remark We proceed by generalizing te completeness result from finitary to k- ary, were k is an arbitrary infinite cardinal. Te k-ary logic, ten, deals wit k-ary morpisms (i.e., tose aving bot domain and codomain of M-rank k) and te k-ary Injectivity Deduction System of Teorem Te k-ary Injectivity Logic is complete in every strongly locally ranked category. Tat is, given a set H of k-ary morpisms, ten every k-ary morpism wic is an injectivity consequence of H is a formal consequence (in te k-ary Injectivity Deduction System). Proof Te wole proof is completely analogous to tat of Teorem 6.2. As described in Remark 6.3 we work under te following milder assumptions on te category A: (i) A is cocomplete and as a left-proper factorization system (E, M); (ii) A k is a set of objects of M-rank k, closed under colimits of less tan k morpisms and under E-quotients; 29

MA455 Manifolds Solutions 1 May 2008

MA455 Manifolds Solutions 1 May 2008 MA455 Manifolds Solutions 1 May 2008 1. (i) Given real numbers a < b, find a diffeomorpism (a, b) R. Solution: For example first map (a, b) to (0, π/2) and ten map (0, π/2) diffeomorpically to R using

More information

Monoidal Structures on Higher Categories

Monoidal Structures on Higher Categories Monoidal Structures on Higer Categories Paul Ziegler Monoidal Structures on Simplicial Categories Let C be a simplicial category, tat is a category enriced over simplicial sets. Suc categories are a model

More information

A SHORT INTRODUCTION TO BANACH LATTICES AND

A SHORT INTRODUCTION TO BANACH LATTICES AND CHAPTER A SHORT INTRODUCTION TO BANACH LATTICES AND POSITIVE OPERATORS In tis capter we give a brief introduction to Banac lattices and positive operators. Most results of tis capter can be found, e.g.,

More information

Continuity and Differentiability of the Trigonometric Functions

Continuity and Differentiability of the Trigonometric Functions [Te basis for te following work will be te definition of te trigonometric functions as ratios of te sides of a triangle inscribed in a circle; in particular, te sine of an angle will be defined to be te

More information

Differentiation in higher dimensions

Differentiation in higher dimensions Capter 2 Differentiation in iger dimensions 2.1 Te Total Derivative Recall tat if f : R R is a 1-variable function, and a R, we say tat f is differentiable at x = a if and only if te ratio f(a+) f(a) tends

More information

Combining functions: algebraic methods

Combining functions: algebraic methods Combining functions: algebraic metods Functions can be added, subtracted, multiplied, divided, and raised to a power, just like numbers or algebra expressions. If f(x) = x 2 and g(x) = x + 2, clearly f(x)

More information

Symmetry Labeling of Molecular Energies

Symmetry Labeling of Molecular Energies Capter 7. Symmetry Labeling of Molecular Energies Notes: Most of te material presented in tis capter is taken from Bunker and Jensen 1998, Cap. 6, and Bunker and Jensen 2005, Cap. 7. 7.1 Hamiltonian Symmetry

More information

Math 161 (33) - Final exam

Math 161 (33) - Final exam Name: Id #: Mat 161 (33) - Final exam Fall Quarter 2015 Wednesday December 9, 2015-10:30am to 12:30am Instructions: Prob. Points Score possible 1 25 2 25 3 25 4 25 TOTAL 75 (BEST 3) Read eac problem carefully.

More information

Consider a function f we ll specify which assumptions we need to make about it in a minute. Let us reformulate the integral. 1 f(x) dx.

Consider a function f we ll specify which assumptions we need to make about it in a minute. Let us reformulate the integral. 1 f(x) dx. Capter 2 Integrals as sums and derivatives as differences We now switc to te simplest metods for integrating or differentiating a function from its function samples. A careful study of Taylor expansions

More information

HOMEWORK HELP 2 FOR MATH 151

HOMEWORK HELP 2 FOR MATH 151 HOMEWORK HELP 2 FOR MATH 151 Here we go; te second round of omework elp. If tere are oters you would like to see, let me know! 2.4, 43 and 44 At wat points are te functions f(x) and g(x) = xf(x)continuous,

More information

E E B B. over U is a full subcategory of the fiber of C,D over U. Given [B, B ], and h=θ over V, the Cartesian arrow M=f

E E B B. over U is a full subcategory of the fiber of C,D over U. Given [B, B ], and h=θ over V, the Cartesian arrow M=f ppendix : ibrational teory o L euivalence E E onsider ibrations P, P, and te category Fib[,] o all maps E @E 2 =(, ):@ :: P { P 2 () @ o ibrations; Fib[,] is a ull subcategory o [,] ; see [3]. Fib[,] is

More information

1 The concept of limits (p.217 p.229, p.242 p.249, p.255 p.256) 1.1 Limits Consider the function determined by the formula 3. x since at this point

1 The concept of limits (p.217 p.229, p.242 p.249, p.255 p.256) 1.1 Limits Consider the function determined by the formula 3. x since at this point MA00 Capter 6 Calculus and Basic Linear Algebra I Limits, Continuity and Differentiability Te concept of its (p.7 p.9, p.4 p.49, p.55 p.56). Limits Consider te function determined by te formula f Note

More information

A = h w (1) Error Analysis Physics 141

A = h w (1) Error Analysis Physics 141 Introduction In all brances of pysical science and engineering one deals constantly wit numbers wic results more or less directly from experimental observations. Experimental observations always ave inaccuracies.

More information

Volume 29, Issue 3. Existence of competitive equilibrium in economies with multi-member households

Volume 29, Issue 3. Existence of competitive equilibrium in economies with multi-member households Volume 29, Issue 3 Existence of competitive equilibrium in economies wit multi-member ouseolds Noriisa Sato Graduate Scool of Economics, Waseda University Abstract Tis paper focuses on te existence of

More information

Lecture XVII. Abstract We introduce the concept of directional derivative of a scalar function and discuss its relation with the gradient operator.

Lecture XVII. Abstract We introduce the concept of directional derivative of a scalar function and discuss its relation with the gradient operator. Lecture XVII Abstract We introduce te concept of directional derivative of a scalar function and discuss its relation wit te gradient operator. Directional derivative and gradient Te directional derivative

More information

LIST OF CORRECTIONS LOCALLY PRESENTABLE AND ACCESSIBLE CATEGORIES

LIST OF CORRECTIONS LOCALLY PRESENTABLE AND ACCESSIBLE CATEGORIES LIST OF CORRECTIONS LOCALLY PRESENTABLE AND ACCESSIBLE CATEGORIES J.Adámek J.Rosický Cambridge University Press 1994 Version: June 2013 The following is a list of corrections of all mistakes that have

More information

Introduction to Derivatives

Introduction to Derivatives Introduction to Derivatives 5-Minute Review: Instantaneous Rates and Tangent Slope Recall te analogy tat we developed earlier First we saw tat te secant slope of te line troug te two points (a, f (a))

More information

called the homomorphism induced by the inductive limit. One verifies that the diagram

called the homomorphism induced by the inductive limit. One verifies that the diagram Inductive limits of C -algebras 51 sequences {a n } suc tat a n, and a n 0. If A = A i for all i I, ten A i = C b (I,A) and i I A i = C 0 (I,A). i I 1.10 Inductive limits of C -algebras Definition 1.10.1

More information

4. The slope of the line 2x 7y = 8 is (a) 2/7 (b) 7/2 (c) 2 (d) 2/7 (e) None of these.

4. The slope of the line 2x 7y = 8 is (a) 2/7 (b) 7/2 (c) 2 (d) 2/7 (e) None of these. Mat 11. Test Form N Fall 016 Name. Instructions. Te first eleven problems are wort points eac. Te last six problems are wort 5 points eac. For te last six problems, you must use relevant metods of algebra

More information

How to Find the Derivative of a Function: Calculus 1

How to Find the Derivative of a Function: Calculus 1 Introduction How to Find te Derivative of a Function: Calculus 1 Calculus is not an easy matematics course Te fact tat you ave enrolled in suc a difficult subject indicates tat you are interested in te

More information

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories PART I Abstract algebraic categories It should be observed first that the whole concept of category is essentially an auxiliary one; our basic concepts are those of a functor and a natural transformation.

More information

On convexity of polynomial paths and generalized majorizations

On convexity of polynomial paths and generalized majorizations On convexity of polynomial pats and generalized majorizations Marija Dodig Centro de Estruturas Lineares e Combinatórias, CELC, Universidade de Lisboa, Av. Prof. Gama Pinto 2, 1649-003 Lisboa, Portugal

More information

INJECTIVE AND PROJECTIVE PROPERTIES OF REPRESENTATIONS OF QUIVERS WITH n EDGES. Sangwon Park

INJECTIVE AND PROJECTIVE PROPERTIES OF REPRESENTATIONS OF QUIVERS WITH n EDGES. Sangwon Park Korean J. Mat. 16 (2008), No. 3, pp. 323 334 INJECTIVE AND PROJECTIVE PROPERTIES OF REPRESENTATIONS OF QUIVERS WITH n EDGES Sanwon Park Abstract. We define injective and projective representations of quivers

More information

Copyright c 2008 Kevin Long

Copyright c 2008 Kevin Long Lecture 4 Numerical solution of initial value problems Te metods you ve learned so far ave obtained closed-form solutions to initial value problems. A closedform solution is an explicit algebriac formula

More information

Polynomial Interpolation

Polynomial Interpolation Capter 4 Polynomial Interpolation In tis capter, we consider te important problem of approximatinga function fx, wose values at a set of distinct points x, x, x,, x n are known, by a polynomial P x suc

More information

Click here to see an animation of the derivative

Click here to see an animation of the derivative Differentiation Massoud Malek Derivative Te concept of derivative is at te core of Calculus; It is a very powerful tool for understanding te beavior of matematical functions. It allows us to optimize functions,

More information

Exam 1 Review Solutions

Exam 1 Review Solutions Exam Review Solutions Please also review te old quizzes, and be sure tat you understand te omework problems. General notes: () Always give an algebraic reason for your answer (graps are not sufficient),

More information

Analytic Functions. Differentiable Functions of a Complex Variable

Analytic Functions. Differentiable Functions of a Complex Variable Analytic Functions Differentiable Functions of a Complex Variable In tis capter, we sall generalize te ideas for polynomials power series of a complex variable we developed in te previous capter to general

More information

LIMITS AND DERIVATIVES CONDITIONS FOR THE EXISTENCE OF A LIMIT

LIMITS AND DERIVATIVES CONDITIONS FOR THE EXISTENCE OF A LIMIT LIMITS AND DERIVATIVES Te limit of a function is defined as te value of y tat te curve approaces, as x approaces a particular value. Te limit of f (x) as x approaces a is written as f (x) approaces, as

More information

Numerical Differentiation

Numerical Differentiation Numerical Differentiation Finite Difference Formulas for te first derivative (Using Taylor Expansion tecnique) (section 8.3.) Suppose tat f() = g() is a function of te variable, and tat as 0 te function

More information

Function Composition and Chain Rules

Function Composition and Chain Rules Function Composition and s James K. Peterson Department of Biological Sciences and Department of Matematical Sciences Clemson University Marc 8, 2017 Outline 1 Function Composition and Continuity 2 Function

More information

5.1 We will begin this section with the definition of a rational expression. We

5.1 We will begin this section with the definition of a rational expression. We Basic Properties and Reducing to Lowest Terms 5.1 We will begin tis section wit te definition of a rational epression. We will ten state te two basic properties associated wit rational epressions and go

More information

64 IX. The Exceptional Lie Algebras

64 IX. The Exceptional Lie Algebras 64 IX. Te Exceptional Lie Algebras IX. Te Exceptional Lie Algebras We ave displayed te four series of classical Lie algebras and teir Dynkin diagrams. How many more simple Lie algebras are tere? Surprisingly,

More information

1 Calculus. 1.1 Gradients and the Derivative. Q f(x+h) f(x)

1 Calculus. 1.1 Gradients and the Derivative. Q f(x+h) f(x) Calculus. Gradients and te Derivative Q f(x+) δy P T δx R f(x) 0 x x+ Let P (x, f(x)) and Q(x+, f(x+)) denote two points on te curve of te function y = f(x) and let R denote te point of intersection of

More information

REVIEW LAB ANSWER KEY

REVIEW LAB ANSWER KEY REVIEW LAB ANSWER KEY. Witout using SN, find te derivative of eac of te following (you do not need to simplify your answers): a. f x 3x 3 5x x 6 f x 3 3x 5 x 0 b. g x 4 x x x notice te trick ere! x x g

More information

Polynomial Interpolation

Polynomial Interpolation Capter 4 Polynomial Interpolation In tis capter, we consider te important problem of approximating a function f(x, wose values at a set of distinct points x, x, x 2,,x n are known, by a polynomial P (x

More information

Mathematics 5 Worksheet 11 Geometry, Tangency, and the Derivative

Mathematics 5 Worksheet 11 Geometry, Tangency, and the Derivative Matematics 5 Workseet 11 Geometry, Tangency, and te Derivative Problem 1. Find te equation of a line wit slope m tat intersects te point (3, 9). Solution. Te equation for a line passing troug a point (x

More information

Section 15.6 Directional Derivatives and the Gradient Vector

Section 15.6 Directional Derivatives and the Gradient Vector Section 15.6 Directional Derivatives and te Gradient Vector Finding rates of cange in different directions Recall tat wen we first started considering derivatives of functions of more tan one variable,

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.dg] 4 Feb 2015

arxiv: v1 [math.dg] 4 Feb 2015 CENTROID OF TRIANGLES ASSOCIATED WITH A CURVE arxiv:1502.01205v1 [mat.dg] 4 Feb 2015 Dong-Soo Kim and Dong Seo Kim Abstract. Arcimedes sowed tat te area between a parabola and any cord AB on te parabola

More information

INTRODUCTION AND MATHEMATICAL CONCEPTS

INTRODUCTION AND MATHEMATICAL CONCEPTS INTODUCTION ND MTHEMTICL CONCEPTS PEVIEW Tis capter introduces you to te basic matematical tools for doing pysics. You will study units and converting between units, te trigonometric relationsips of sine,

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.ct] 28 Oct 2017

arxiv: v1 [math.ct] 28 Oct 2017 BARELY LOCALLY PRESENTABLE CATEGORIES arxiv:1710.10476v1 [math.ct] 28 Oct 2017 L. POSITSELSKI AND J. ROSICKÝ Abstract. We introduce a new class of categories generalizing locally presentable ones. The

More information

Gradient Descent etc.

Gradient Descent etc. 1 Gradient Descent etc EE 13: Networked estimation and control Prof Kan) I DERIVATIVE Consider f : R R x fx) Te derivative is defined as d fx) = lim dx fx + ) fx) Te cain rule states tat if d d f gx) )

More information

Generic maximum nullity of a graph

Generic maximum nullity of a graph Generic maximum nullity of a grap Leslie Hogben Bryan Sader Marc 5, 2008 Abstract For a grap G of order n, te maximum nullity of G is defined to be te largest possible nullity over all real symmetric n

More information

The Complexity of Computing the MCD-Estimator

The Complexity of Computing the MCD-Estimator Te Complexity of Computing te MCD-Estimator Torsten Bernolt Lerstul Informatik 2 Universität Dortmund, Germany torstenbernolt@uni-dortmundde Paul Fiscer IMM, Danisc Tecnical University Kongens Lyngby,

More information

3.4 Worksheet: Proof of the Chain Rule NAME

3.4 Worksheet: Proof of the Chain Rule NAME Mat 1170 3.4 Workseet: Proof of te Cain Rule NAME Te Cain Rule So far we are able to differentiate all types of functions. For example: polynomials, rational, root, and trigonometric functions. We are

More information

ch (for some fixed positive number c) reaching c

ch (for some fixed positive number c) reaching c GSTF Journal of Matematics Statistics and Operations Researc (JMSOR) Vol. No. September 05 DOI 0.60/s4086-05-000-z Nonlinear Piecewise-defined Difference Equations wit Reciprocal and Cubic Terms Ramadan

More information

SECTION 3.2: DERIVATIVE FUNCTIONS and DIFFERENTIABILITY

SECTION 3.2: DERIVATIVE FUNCTIONS and DIFFERENTIABILITY (Section 3.2: Derivative Functions and Differentiability) 3.2.1 SECTION 3.2: DERIVATIVE FUNCTIONS and DIFFERENTIABILITY LEARNING OBJECTIVES Know, understand, and apply te Limit Definition of te Derivative

More information

2.8 The Derivative as a Function

2.8 The Derivative as a Function .8 Te Derivative as a Function Typically, we can find te derivative of a function f at many points of its domain: Definition. Suppose tat f is a function wic is differentiable at every point of an open

More information

= 0 and states ''hence there is a stationary point'' All aspects of the proof dx must be correct (c)

= 0 and states ''hence there is a stationary point'' All aspects of the proof dx must be correct (c) Paper 1: Pure Matematics 1 Mark Sceme 1(a) (i) (ii) d d y 3 1x 4x x M1 A1 d y dx 1.1b 1.1b 36x 48x A1ft 1.1b Substitutes x = into teir dx (3) 3 1 4 Sows d y 0 and states ''ence tere is a stationary point''

More information

INTRODUCTION AND MATHEMATICAL CONCEPTS

INTRODUCTION AND MATHEMATICAL CONCEPTS Capter 1 INTRODUCTION ND MTHEMTICL CONCEPTS PREVIEW Tis capter introduces you to te basic matematical tools for doing pysics. You will study units and converting between units, te trigonometric relationsips

More information

Preface. Here are a couple of warnings to my students who may be here to get a copy of what happened on a day that you missed.

Preface. Here are a couple of warnings to my students who may be here to get a copy of what happened on a day that you missed. Preface Here are my online notes for my course tat I teac ere at Lamar University. Despite te fact tat tese are my class notes, tey sould be accessible to anyone wanting to learn or needing a refreser

More information

Bob Brown Math 251 Calculus 1 Chapter 3, Section 1 Completed 1 CCBC Dundalk

Bob Brown Math 251 Calculus 1 Chapter 3, Section 1 Completed 1 CCBC Dundalk Bob Brown Mat 251 Calculus 1 Capter 3, Section 1 Completed 1 Te Tangent Line Problem Te idea of a tangent line first arises in geometry in te context of a circle. But before we jump into a discussion of

More information

Functions of the Complex Variable z

Functions of the Complex Variable z Capter 2 Functions of te Complex Variable z Introduction We wis to examine te notion of a function of z were z is a complex variable. To be sure, a complex variable can be viewed as noting but a pair of

More information

. If lim. x 2 x 1. f(x+h) f(x)

. If lim. x 2 x 1. f(x+h) f(x) Review of Differential Calculus Wen te value of one variable y is uniquely determined by te value of anoter variable x, ten te relationsip between x and y is described by a function f tat assigns a value

More information

NUMERICAL DIFFERENTIATION. James T. Smith San Francisco State University. In calculus classes, you compute derivatives algebraically: for example,

NUMERICAL DIFFERENTIATION. James T. Smith San Francisco State University. In calculus classes, you compute derivatives algebraically: for example, NUMERICAL DIFFERENTIATION James T Smit San Francisco State University In calculus classes, you compute derivatives algebraically: for example, f( x) = x + x f ( x) = x x Tis tecnique requires your knowing

More information

University Mathematics 2

University Mathematics 2 University Matematics 2 1 Differentiability In tis section, we discuss te differentiability of functions. Definition 1.1 Differentiable function). Let f) be a function. We say tat f is differentiable at

More information

Poisson Equation in Sobolev Spaces

Poisson Equation in Sobolev Spaces Poisson Equation in Sobolev Spaces OcMountain Dayligt Time. 6, 011 Today we discuss te Poisson equation in Sobolev spaces. It s existence, uniqueness, and regularity. Weak Solution. u = f in, u = g on

More information

DIGRAPHS FROM POWERS MODULO p

DIGRAPHS FROM POWERS MODULO p DIGRAPHS FROM POWERS MODULO p Caroline Luceta Box 111 GCC, 100 Campus Drive, Grove City PA 1617 USA Eli Miller PO Box 410, Sumneytown, PA 18084 USA Clifford Reiter Department of Matematics, Lafayette College,

More information

A GENERAL CONSTRUCTION OF INTERNAL SHEAVES IN ALGEBRAIC SET THEORY

A GENERAL CONSTRUCTION OF INTERNAL SHEAVES IN ALGEBRAIC SET THEORY A GENERAL CONSTRUCTION OF INTERNAL SHEAVES IN ALGEBRAIC SET THEORY S. AWODEY, N. GAMBINO, P. L. LUMSDAINE, AND M. A. WARREN Abstract. We present a solution to te problem o deining a counterpart in Algebraic

More information

2.11 That s So Derivative

2.11 That s So Derivative 2.11 Tat s So Derivative Introduction to Differential Calculus Just as one defines instantaneous velocity in terms of average velocity, we now define te instantaneous rate of cange of a function at a point

More information

Recall from our discussion of continuity in lecture a function is continuous at a point x = a if and only if

Recall from our discussion of continuity in lecture a function is continuous at a point x = a if and only if Computational Aspects of its. Keeping te simple simple. Recall by elementary functions we mean :Polynomials (including linear and quadratic equations) Eponentials Logaritms Trig Functions Rational Functions

More information

232 Calculus and Structures

232 Calculus and Structures 3 Calculus and Structures CHAPTER 17 JUSTIFICATION OF THE AREA AND SLOPE METHODS FOR EVALUATING BEAMS Calculus and Structures 33 Copyrigt Capter 17 JUSTIFICATION OF THE AREA AND SLOPE METHODS 17.1 THE

More information

WYSE Academic Challenge 2004 Sectional Mathematics Solution Set

WYSE Academic Challenge 2004 Sectional Mathematics Solution Set WYSE Academic Callenge 00 Sectional Matematics Solution Set. Answer: B. Since te equation can be written in te form x + y, we ave a major 5 semi-axis of lengt 5 and minor semi-axis of lengt. Tis means

More information

INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 17

INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 17 INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 17 RAVI VAKIL CONTENTS 1. Were we are 1 1.1. Reined Gysin omomorpisms i! 2 1.2. Excess intersection ormula 4 2. Local complete intersection morpisms 6 Were we re oin, by popular

More information

Integral Calculus, dealing with areas and volumes, and approximate areas under and between curves.

Integral Calculus, dealing with areas and volumes, and approximate areas under and between curves. Calculus can be divided into two ke areas: Differential Calculus dealing wit its, rates of cange, tangents and normals to curves, curve sketcing, and applications to maima and minima problems Integral

More information

Derivatives of Exponentials

Derivatives of Exponentials mat 0 more on derivatives: day 0 Derivatives of Eponentials Recall tat DEFINITION... An eponential function as te form f () =a, were te base is a real number a > 0. Te domain of an eponential function

More information

Math 312 Lecture Notes Modeling

Math 312 Lecture Notes Modeling Mat 3 Lecture Notes Modeling Warren Weckesser Department of Matematics Colgate University 5 7 January 006 Classifying Matematical Models An Example We consider te following scenario. During a storm, a

More information

LATTICE EXIT MODELS S. GILL WILLIAMSON

LATTICE EXIT MODELS S. GILL WILLIAMSON LATTICE EXIT MODELS S. GILL WILLIAMSON ABSTRACT. We discuss a class of problems wic we call lattice exit models. At one level, tese problems provide undergraduate level exercises in labeling te vertices

More information

Quantum Numbers and Rules

Quantum Numbers and Rules OpenStax-CNX module: m42614 1 Quantum Numbers and Rules OpenStax College Tis work is produced by OpenStax-CNX and licensed under te Creative Commons Attribution License 3.0 Abstract Dene quantum number.

More information

THE IMPLICIT FUNCTION THEOREM

THE IMPLICIT FUNCTION THEOREM THE IMPLICIT FUNCTION THEOREM ALEXANDRU ALEMAN 1. Motivation and statement We want to understand a general situation wic occurs in almost any area wic uses matematics. Suppose we are given number of equations

More information

Differential Calculus (The basics) Prepared by Mr. C. Hull

Differential Calculus (The basics) Prepared by Mr. C. Hull Differential Calculus Te basics) A : Limits In tis work on limits, we will deal only wit functions i.e. tose relationsips in wic an input variable ) defines a unique output variable y). Wen we work wit

More information

1watt=1W=1kg m 2 /s 3

1watt=1W=1kg m 2 /s 3 Appendix A Matematics Appendix A.1 Units To measure a pysical quantity, you need a standard. Eac pysical quantity as certain units. A unit is just a standard we use to compare, e.g. a ruler. In tis laboratory

More information

Pre-Calculus Review Preemptive Strike

Pre-Calculus Review Preemptive Strike Pre-Calculus Review Preemptive Strike Attaced are some notes and one assignment wit tree parts. Tese are due on te day tat we start te pre-calculus review. I strongly suggest reading troug te notes torougly

More information

1. Questions (a) through (e) refer to the graph of the function f given below. (A) 0 (B) 1 (C) 2 (D) 4 (E) does not exist

1. Questions (a) through (e) refer to the graph of the function f given below. (A) 0 (B) 1 (C) 2 (D) 4 (E) does not exist Mat 1120 Calculus Test 2. October 18, 2001 Your name Te multiple coice problems count 4 points eac. In te multiple coice section, circle te correct coice (or coices). You must sow your work on te oter

More information

More on generalized inverses of partitioned matrices with Banachiewicz-Schur forms

More on generalized inverses of partitioned matrices with Banachiewicz-Schur forms More on generalized inverses of partitioned matrices wit anaciewicz-scur forms Yongge Tian a,, Yosio Takane b a Cina Economics and Management cademy, Central University of Finance and Economics, eijing,

More information

Topos Theory. Lectures 17-20: The interpretation of logic in categories. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello.

Topos Theory. Lectures 17-20: The interpretation of logic in categories. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello. logic s Lectures 17-20: logic in 2 / 40 logic s Interpreting first-order logic in In Logic, first-order s are a wide class of formal s used for talking about structures of any kind (where the restriction

More information

THE IDEA OF DIFFERENTIABILITY FOR FUNCTIONS OF SEVERAL VARIABLES Math 225

THE IDEA OF DIFFERENTIABILITY FOR FUNCTIONS OF SEVERAL VARIABLES Math 225 THE IDEA OF DIFFERENTIABILITY FOR FUNCTIONS OF SEVERAL VARIABLES Mat 225 As we ave seen, te definition of derivative for a Mat 111 function g : R R and for acurveγ : R E n are te same, except for interpretation:

More information

Characterization of reducible hexagons and fast decomposition of elementary benzenoid graphs

Characterization of reducible hexagons and fast decomposition of elementary benzenoid graphs Discrete Applied Matematics 156 (2008) 1711 1724 www.elsevier.com/locate/dam Caracterization of reducible exagons and fast decomposition of elementary benzenoid graps Andrej Taranenko, Aleksander Vesel

More information

An introduction to locally finitely presentable categories

An introduction to locally finitely presentable categories An introduction to locally finitely presentable categories MARU SARAZOLA A document born out of my attempt to understand the notion of locally finitely presentable category, and my annoyance at constantly

More information

lecture 26: Richardson extrapolation

lecture 26: Richardson extrapolation 43 lecture 26: Ricardson extrapolation 35 Ricardson extrapolation, Romberg integration Trougout numerical analysis, one encounters procedures tat apply some simple approximation (eg, linear interpolation)

More information

Chapter 5 FINITE DIFFERENCE METHOD (FDM)

Chapter 5 FINITE DIFFERENCE METHOD (FDM) MEE7 Computer Modeling Tecniques in Engineering Capter 5 FINITE DIFFERENCE METHOD (FDM) 5. Introduction to FDM Te finite difference tecniques are based upon approximations wic permit replacing differential

More information

What are Iteration Theories?

What are Iteration Theories? What are Iteration Theories? Jiří Adámek and Stefan Milius Institute of Theoretical Computer Science Technical University of Braunschweig Germany adamek,milius @iti.cs.tu-bs.de Jiří Velebil Department

More information

Excursions in Computing Science: Week v Milli-micro-nano-..math Part II

Excursions in Computing Science: Week v Milli-micro-nano-..math Part II Excursions in Computing Science: Week v Milli-micro-nano-..mat Part II T. H. Merrett McGill University, Montreal, Canada June, 5 I. Prefatory Notes. Cube root of 8. Almost every calculator as a square-root

More information

Material for Difference Quotient

Material for Difference Quotient Material for Difference Quotient Prepared by Stepanie Quintal, graduate student and Marvin Stick, professor Dept. of Matematical Sciences, UMass Lowell Summer 05 Preface Te following difference quotient

More information

POLYNOMIAL AND SPLINE ESTIMATORS OF THE DISTRIBUTION FUNCTION WITH PRESCRIBED ACCURACY

POLYNOMIAL AND SPLINE ESTIMATORS OF THE DISTRIBUTION FUNCTION WITH PRESCRIBED ACCURACY APPLICATIONES MATHEMATICAE 36, (29), pp. 2 Zbigniew Ciesielski (Sopot) Ryszard Zieliński (Warszawa) POLYNOMIAL AND SPLINE ESTIMATORS OF THE DISTRIBUTION FUNCTION WITH PRESCRIBED ACCURACY Abstract. Dvoretzky

More information

Continuity and Differentiability Worksheet

Continuity and Differentiability Worksheet Continuity and Differentiability Workseet (Be sure tat you can also do te grapical eercises from te tet- Tese were not included below! Typical problems are like problems -3, p. 6; -3, p. 7; 33-34, p. 7;

More information

Math Spring 2013 Solutions to Assignment # 3 Completion Date: Wednesday May 15, (1/z) 2 (1/z 1) 2 = lim

Math Spring 2013 Solutions to Assignment # 3 Completion Date: Wednesday May 15, (1/z) 2 (1/z 1) 2 = lim Mat 311 - Spring 013 Solutions to Assignment # 3 Completion Date: Wednesday May 15, 013 Question 1. [p 56, #10 (a)] 4z Use te teorem of Sec. 17 to sow tat z (z 1) = 4. We ave z 4z (z 1) = z 0 4 (1/z) (1/z

More information

Derivatives. By: OpenStaxCollege

Derivatives. By: OpenStaxCollege By: OpenStaxCollege Te average teen in te United States opens a refrigerator door an estimated 25 times per day. Supposedly, tis average is up from 10 years ago wen te average teenager opened a refrigerator

More information

SFU UBC UNBC Uvic Calculus Challenge Examination June 5, 2008, 12:00 15:00

SFU UBC UNBC Uvic Calculus Challenge Examination June 5, 2008, 12:00 15:00 SFU UBC UNBC Uvic Calculus Callenge Eamination June 5, 008, :00 5:00 Host: SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY First Name: Last Name: Scool: Student signature INSTRUCTIONS Sow all your work Full marks are given only

More information

Convexity and Smoothness

Convexity and Smoothness Capter 4 Convexity and Smootness 4.1 Strict Convexity, Smootness, and Gateaux Differentiablity Definition 4.1.1. Let X be a Banac space wit a norm denoted by. A map f : X \{0} X \{0}, f f x is called a

More information

Time (hours) Morphine sulfate (mg)

Time (hours) Morphine sulfate (mg) Mat Xa Fall 2002 Review Notes Limits and Definition of Derivative Important Information: 1 According to te most recent information from te Registrar, te Xa final exam will be eld from 9:15 am to 12:15

More information

The derivative function

The derivative function Roberto s Notes on Differential Calculus Capter : Definition of derivative Section Te derivative function Wat you need to know already: f is at a point on its grap and ow to compute it. Wat te derivative

More information

Solution. Solution. f (x) = (cos x)2 cos(2x) 2 sin(2x) 2 cos x ( sin x) (cos x) 4. f (π/4) = ( 2/2) ( 2/2) ( 2/2) ( 2/2) 4.

Solution. Solution. f (x) = (cos x)2 cos(2x) 2 sin(2x) 2 cos x ( sin x) (cos x) 4. f (π/4) = ( 2/2) ( 2/2) ( 2/2) ( 2/2) 4. December 09, 20 Calculus PracticeTest s Name: (4 points) Find te absolute extrema of f(x) = x 3 0 on te interval [0, 4] Te derivative of f(x) is f (x) = 3x 2, wic is zero only at x = 0 Tus we only need

More information

GELFAND S PROOF OF WIENER S THEOREM

GELFAND S PROOF OF WIENER S THEOREM GELFAND S PROOF OF WIENER S THEOREM S. H. KULKARNI 1. Introduction Te following teorem was proved by te famous matematician Norbert Wiener. Wiener s proof can be found in is book [5]. Teorem 1.1. (Wiener

More information

MATH745 Fall MATH745 Fall

MATH745 Fall MATH745 Fall MATH745 Fall 5 MATH745 Fall 5 INTRODUCTION WELCOME TO MATH 745 TOPICS IN NUMERICAL ANALYSIS Instructor: Dr Bartosz Protas Department of Matematics & Statistics Email: bprotas@mcmasterca Office HH 36, Ext

More information

Order of Accuracy. ũ h u Ch p, (1)

Order of Accuracy. ũ h u Ch p, (1) Order of Accuracy 1 Terminology We consider a numerical approximation of an exact value u. Te approximation depends on a small parameter, wic can be for instance te grid size or time step in a numerical

More information

5 Ordinary Differential Equations: Finite Difference Methods for Boundary Problems

5 Ordinary Differential Equations: Finite Difference Methods for Boundary Problems 5 Ordinary Differential Equations: Finite Difference Metods for Boundary Problems Read sections 10.1, 10.2, 10.4 Review questions 10.1 10.4, 10.8 10.9, 10.13 5.1 Introduction In te previous capters we

More information

On the Bott-Chern characteristic classes for coherent sheaves

On the Bott-Chern characteristic classes for coherent sheaves On te Bott-Cern caracteristic classes for coerent seaves Hua Qiang Abstract In te paper [Blo10], Block constructed a dg-category P A 0, (X) using coesive modules wic is a dg-enancement of DCo b (X), te

More information

Subdifferentials of convex functions

Subdifferentials of convex functions Subdifferentials of convex functions Jordan Bell jordan.bell@gmail.com Department of Matematics, University of Toronto April 21, 2014 Wenever we speak about a vector space in tis note we mean a vector

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 13 Jan 2019

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 13 Jan 2019 Adiabatic Limit and Deformations of Complex Structures Dan Popovici ariv:1901.04087v1 [mat.ag] 13 Jan 2019 Abstract. Based on our recent adaptation of te adiabatic limit construction to te case of complex

More information