D i (w; p) := H i (w; S(w; p)): (1)

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "D i (w; p) := H i (w; S(w; p)): (1)"

Transcription

1 EC0 Microeconomic Principles II Outline Answers. (a) Demand for input i can be written D i (w; p) := H i (w; S(w; p)): () where H i is the conditional demand for input i and S is the supply function. From this we nd tha tthe e ect of an output price change i (w; p) (w; q p) @p the e ect of an input price change i (w; p) (w; q ) C iq (w; q )C jq (w; q ) : j C qq (w; q ) where C is the cost function and C iq is short C=@w i. No. Given i (w; q )=@w i must be negative (or zero), equation (3) implies that Di(w; i p) < 0. 3 ii. No. Given i (w; q )=@w j = C ij = C ji j (w; q )=@w i equation (3) implies i =@w j j =@w i. 3 iii. Yes the case of an inferior input in (). (b) Note that the MRS is given by dx = x dx which is decreasing/constant/increasing in x according as < / = / > : so we will only get a conventional interior solution if <

2 i. Given the budget constraint y = px + x the problem is to choose x to maximise x + y px (c) For > consumer maximises utility at either x = 0 or x = 0 (x = y=p): demand is discontinuous. For = any value of x between 0 and y=p is a solution. For < we have the FOC x = p which yields x = [p=] 5 ii. In the case > each individual is indi erent between (0; y) and (y=p; 0). The average behaviour will be indistinguishable from the case = above. 3 i. Relative inequality aversion is constant. 3 ii. The ede income must satisfy which, given =, simpli es to = + 3 = + 3 which implies = :5. 5 (d) See lecture notes, chapter 7. i. Brief explanation of derivation of consumer demand function and supply function of individual rms. Aggregation over agents (point out absence of production externalities) 4 ii. Explain Walras law and the reason for the homogeneity of degree zero of household demand functions and rm supply functions. 4

3 (e) Find all the pure and mixed strategy Nash equilibria of the following game in normal form InII L C R T 3; 0 0; 3 0; M 0; 3 3; 0 0; 0 B ; 0 0; 0 0; 0 Sketched answer: There is one pure strategy equilibrium: (B; R). This involves weakly dominated strategies on the part of both players. Look for mixed strategy equilibria not involving weakly dominated strategies. Let p and p the probabilities for players I on T and M respectively. Let q and q the probabilities for players II on L and C respectively. Player I is indi erent between T and M when 3q = 3( q), q = =. Player II is indi erent between L and C when 3( p) = 3p, p = =. There are no other equilibria. This is because R and B will not be played unless the probability that T and L are played is zero for both (by weak domination). 8 (f) Which strategies survive the process of iterated deletion of strictly dominated strategies in the following game? InII D E F A ; ; 3; B ; ; 4; C 5; ; 7 8; 6 Sketched answer: No strategy is dominated for Player I. Strategy E dominates strategy F for Player II. So, F can be eliminated. After F has been eliminated, both A and B dominate C for Player I. So, C can be eliminated. The strategies A, B, D and E all survive the process of iterated deletion of strictly dominated strategies. Each is a best response (strict) to some strategy of the opponent. 8 (g) Give an example of an extensive form game with complete and perfect information with the following property. If we derive the 3

4 Normal form G corresponding to, there is a Nash equilibrium of G that does not correspond to the backwards induction solution for. Sketched answer: The simplest example would be that of an entry game. In Player I moves rst and can decide to Enter (E), or stay Out (O). If Player I chooses O the payo s are (0; ). If Player I enters, Player II can choose to Fight (F ) or Acquiesce (A). If Player II chooses A then payo s are (; ). If Player II chooses F then payo s are ( ; ). The backwards induction solution is that Player II chooses A and Player I chooses E. The normal form G corresponding to is InII F A E ; ; O 0; 0; Clearly, G has two Nash equilibria: (O; F ) and (E; A). 8 (h) Is the following statement true? Give a reason for your answer. In a duopoly, whether moving rst carries any advantage or not depends on which strategic variables can be chosen by the two rms. Sketched answer: The statement is true. The simplest set-up to refer to is two rms producing a homogeneous product with, say, a linear demand curve, and identical linear cost functions. If the strategic choice variables are quantities clearly there is a rst mover advantage. The Cournot pro t is always smaller than the pro t of a Stackelberg leader. If the strategic choice variables are prices then there is no rstmover advantage. The rst mover can set price equal to marginal cost, in which case both pro ts will be zero. If the rst mover sets any price strictly above marginal cost, then he will be undercut by the second mover. The rst mover s pro t will be zero, while the second mover s pro t will be positive. 8 4

5 Section B. (a) The cost-minimisation problem can be represented as minimising the Lagrangean " # mx mx w i z i + log q i log z i (4) i= where w i is the given price of input i, and is the Lagrange multiplier. Given that the isoquant does not touch the axis we must have an interior solution: rst-order conditions are which imply i= w i i z i = 0; i = ; ; ::; m (5) z i = i ; i = ; ; ::; m (6) w i Now solve for. Using the production function and (6) we get q = my i= z i i = z i i = i i ; i = ; ; ::; m (7) w i A m Y i= w i i ; i = ; ; ::; m (8) where := P m j= j and A := [ Q m i= i i ] = are constants, from which we nd = q = A Q m i= w i i = A [qw w :::wm m ] = : (9) Substituting from (9) into (6) we get the conditional demand function: H i (w; q) = zi = i A [qw w :::wm m ] = (0) w i and minimised cost is mx C (w; q) = w i zi = A [qw w :::wm m ] = () i= = Bq = () 5

6 where B := A [w w :::wm m ] =. It is clear from () that cost is increasing in q and increasing in w i if i > 0 (it is always nondecreasing in w i ). Di erentiating () with respect to q marginal cost is C q (w; q) = Bq (3) Clearly marginal cost falls/stays constant/rises with q as T. 8 (b) Suppose, without loss of generality, that in the short run inputs ; :::; k (k m) remain variable and that the remaining inputs are xed. In the short-run the production function can be written as log q = kx i log z i + log k (4) i= where k := exp mx i=k+ i log z i! (5) and z i is the arbitrary value at which input i is xed; note that B is xed in the short run. The general form of the Lagrangean (4) remains unchanged, but with q replaced by q= k and m replaced by k. So the rst-order conditions and their corollaries (5)-(9) are essentially as before, but and A are replaced by k := kx j (6) j= and A k := is h Qk i =k i= i i. Hence short-run conditional demand ~H i (w; q; z k+ ; :::; z m ) = =k i q A k w w :::w k k (7) w i k and minimised cost in the short run is ~C (w; q; z k+ ; :::; z m ) = kx w i zi + c k i= = k A k q k w w :::w k k =k + c k (8) = k B k q = k + ck (9) 6

7 where c k := mx i=k+ w i z i (0) is the xed-cost component in the short run and B k := A k [w w :::w k k = k] = k. Di erentiating (9) we nd that short-run marginal cost is ~C q (w; q; z k+ ; :::; z m ) = B k q k k () (c) Using the Marginal cost=price condition we nd 6 B k q k k = p () where p is the price of output so that, rearranging () the supply function is p k k q = S (w; p; z k+ ; :::; z m ) = (3) wherever MCAC. The elasticity of (3) is given by B log S (w; p; z k+ ; :::; z m log p = k k > 0 (4) It is clear from (6) that k k k ::: and so the positive supply elasticity in (4) must fall as k falls (a) i. Budget constraint is x = w` + y ii. Substitute the budget constraint into the utility function and transform it by taking U (). Then the problem is equivalent to maximising i h[w` + y] + [ `] First-order condition for an interior maximum is: w [w` + y] [ `] = 0 7

8 and so w` + y w ` = w` + y ` = w where := Therefore we have ` = w y w + w It is clear that this expression is less than given w > 0 and y 0. However, if y were large enough then ` in the above formula would become negative, which is logically impossible. Hence the result. iii. From part (ii) the individual would choose not to work if If ` > 0 then w w := = w + w < 0 So leisure ( `) is increasing in y. 6 (b) If w were higher, would ` and x w w + w = w w y w w + w [w + w] + = w w + w [w + w] w y [w + w] w w y [w + w] = w w + y [w + w] w y [w + w] = w + w y w + y [w + w] = w [ ] + y [w + ] [w + w] 8

9 Work may decrease with the wage rate if < (equivalently < 0) and y is small. Also note that, for given y if some people choose not to work it must be the low-wage people for whom w w. ii. From the budget constraint and part (b): 8 w+y < if y < w +w x = : y otherwise and so, if y < w = [ + w ] [w + y] w [ ] [ + w ] = [ yw ] + w + yw [ + w ] which must be positive. Also note that (c) We know from part y 0 and y = 0, w + y + w > y if w > w. High-ability people have higher money income. 8 < 0 and from part (b), given > 0. Introduction of the bene t is pure income e ect and so decreases `; the tax will decrease the e ective wage and so, for small B it will decrease `. All those with positive hours of work will work less. 6 (a) See chapter 8 of notes. (b) Consider the person s wealth after taking out (partial) insurance cover using the two-state model (no loss;loss). If the person remained uninsured it would be (y 0 ; y 0 L); if he ensures fully it is (y 0 ; y 0 ). So if he ensures a proportion t for the pro-rata premium wealth in the two states will be which becomes ([ t] y 0 + t [y 0 ] ; [ t] [y 0 L] + t [y 0 ]) (y 0 t; y 0 t [ t] L) 9

10 So expected utility is given Eu = [ ] u (y 0 t) + u (y 0 t [ t] L) = [ ] u y (y 0 t) + [L ] u y (y 0 t [ t] L) Consider what happens in the neighbourhood of t = (full insurance). t= = [ ] u y (y 0 ) + [L ] u y (y 0 ) = [L ] u y (y 0 ) We know that u y (y 0 ) > 0 (positive marginal utility of wealth) and, by assumption, L <. Therefore this expression is strictly negative which means that in the neighbourhood of full insurance (t = ) the individual could increase expected utility by cutting down on the insurance cover. 8 (c) For an interior maximum = 0 which means that the optimal t is given as the solution to the equation [ ] u y (y 0 t ) + [L ] u y (y 0 t [ t ] L) = 0 (d) Di erentiating the above equation with respect to y 0 we get [ ] u yy (y 0 0 which gives 6 +[L ] u yy (y 0 t [ t ] = [ ] u yy (y 0 t ) + [L ] u yy (y 0 t [ t ] 0 [ ] u yy (y 0 t ) + [L ] u yy (y 0 t [ t ] L) The denominator of this must be negative: u yy () is everywhere negative and the other terms are positive. The numerator is positive if DARA holds: therefore an increase in wealth reduces the demand for insurance coverage. 6 0

11 5. (a) Using standard notation for net output pro ts are given by = 3X p i y i (5) i= If pro ts are maximised then production must take place on the transformation curve. Therefore, substituting from the production constraint into (5) we get: = p y + p y [y ] + [y ] A (6) To maximise just maximise (6) with respect to y and y. This gives the FOCs: p i A y i = 0 (7) i = ;, and so from which, using (6), pro ts are y = A p (8) y = A p (9) = A [p ] + [p ] : (30) 4 (b) Given that the capitalist utility function is 6 x c x c it is immediate that in the optimum the capitalists spend an equal share of their income on the two consumption goods and so x c i = p i : Worker utility is x w [ x w 3 ] (3)

12 and the budget constraint is p x w x w 3 (3) Maximising (3) subject to (3) is equivalent to maximising The FOC is which gives optimal labour supply as: p [ x w 3 ] [ x w 3 ] : (33) p [ x w 3 ] = 0 (34) x w 3 = p (35) and, from (3), the workers optimal consumption of good is (c) x w = [p ] : (36) 6 i. The economy has no stock of good or good ; workers do not consume good ; so excess demand for the two goods is, respectively: x c + x w y = p + [p ] A p (37) x c y = p A p (38) ii. To nd the equilibrium set each of (37) and (38) equal to zero. This gives p + = A [p ] 3 (39) = A [p ] (40) Substituting in for pro ts from (30) in (40) we have [p ] + [p ] 4 = [p ]

13 and so p p = p 3: (4) Substituting for and p from (30) and (4) into (39) we get p A [p ] + 3 [p ] 4 and, on rearranging, this gives + = A [p ] 3 p = =3 3 (4) A Using (4) for p completes the answer. 4 (d) Using (30), (4) and (4) pro ts in equilibrium are A [p ] = A 3 [p ] = A 3 =3 3 = A =3 A =3 : 3 Given that the price of good 3 is normalised to, using (35)and (4) total labour income in equilibrium is = =3 3 = p A =3 A =3 3 So, workers and capitalists get the same money income in equilibrium. Note that this is una ected by the value of A; so the income distribution remains unchanged by technical progress. 5 3

14 6. Section C Consider the following Stackelberg Duopoly Game. Two quantity-setting rms, and, produce a homogeneous product. Let q and q denote the output of rm and rm respectively, with Q = q + q total output.. The two rms face a (linear) demand curve given by p = a Q, with a >. The cost function of rm is given by C (q ) = q, with C (q ) the total cost of producing output q. The cost function for rm is given by C (q ) = q, with C (q ) the total cost of producing output q. As is standard in a Stackelberg Duopoly Game, rst Firm sets q, then Firm observes q, and then sets its own output q. (a) Find the (unique) Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium of the game. That is, nd the (unique) quantities q and q that constitute a Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium of the Stackelberg Duopoly Game. Sketched answer: The pro t of Firm can be written as q (a q q ) q Therefore (di erentiate wrt q and set equal to zero) Firm s best response function is q = a q Plugging this into the pro t function for Firm we get a q q a q q Di erentiating and setting equal to zero gives and hence q = a q = a 4 4

15 (b) Now suppose that before playing the Stackelberg game the two rms have to decide whether to enter the market or not. Their decisions to enter are taken simultaneously. Entering is an irreversible decision. Before playing the Stackelberg game both rms observe whether the other has entered or not. Entering the Stackelberg game costs F > 0 to Firm and F > 0 to rm. The entry costs are sunk once incurred. For what range of costs F and F will it be the case that both rms strictly prefer to enter? Sketched answer: Plugging q and q into the pro t function of Firm gives (a ) = 8 Plugging q and q into the pro t function of Firm gives = (a ) 6 So both Firms will strictly prefer to enter if F < (a ) 8 and F < (a ) 6 7. [not for resit] A Seller, S, has a an object for sale. The object costs c to the seller. A potential buyer B has a value of v for the object. There is potential surplus from the exchange in the sense that v > c. S and B have to agree on a price p at which to exchange, and will do so according to the Nash Bargaining Solution. S s utility if the object is sold at price p is (p c) with <. B s utility if the object is sold at price p is v p. If no transaction takes place, both S and B have a utility of 0. 0 (a) Find the price at which the object will be traded according to the Nash Bargaining Solution. Call this price p. Sketched answer: The Nash product is (p c) (v p) Di erentiating and setting equal to 0 gives (p c) (v p) = (p c) 5

16 Rearranging and simplifying gives p = + v + + c 5 (b) Is the price p that you found in (a) an increasing or decreasing function of? 5 Sketched answer: Since v > c, clearly p is increasing in 8. [not for resit] Consider the following auction game. A single indivisible object is for sale. There are two bidders, and. Each bidder i = ; can have a valuation of either or 0 for the object. Each bidder s valuation is or 0 with probability =, and their valuations are independent. The bidders are only allowed to bid either or 0. (a) Suppose the auction is a rst-price one. The bidders are only allowed to bid either or 0. The highest bidder wins and pays her bid. Ties are broken randomly, by ipping a fair coin. Show that there is no equilibrium of the game in which both bidders bid when their value is and bid 0 when their value is 0. Sketched answer: Suppose bidder bids if v = and bids 0 if v = 0. Suppose v =. If bidder sets b = he gets an expected payo of ( ) + ) ( ) = 0 This is because of the following. With probability = bidder s valuation is, in which case b =, the bids are tied and wins with probability =. If he wins, he pays, while his value is. With probability = bidder s valuation is 0, in which case b = 0, and wins for sure. If he wins, he pays and his value is. Still assuming that v =, suppose that bidder sets b = 0. Then he gets an expected payo of 0 + ( 0) = 4 This is because of the following. With probability = bidder s valuation is, in which case b =, wins for sure and gets a payo of 0. With probability = bidders s valuation is 0, in which case b = 0, the bids are tied and wins with probability =. If he wins, he pays 0 and his value is. 6

17 So, when v = bidder would like to deviate from the putative equilibrium in which he bids. He gains by bidding 0 in this case. 0 (b) Now consider the same auction game but with a cap on the bids, so that the bidders are only allowed to bid either = or 0. Show that there is an equilibrium for the game in which both bidders bid = when their value is and 0 when their value is 0. Sketched answer: All checks are done from the point of view of bidder. All calculations for bidder are symmetric. Suppose bidder bids = if v = and bids 0 if v = 0. Suppose v =. If bidder sets b = = he gets an expected payo of + = 3 8 This is because of the following. With probability = bidder s valuation is, in which case b = =, the bids are tied and wins with probability =. If he wins, he pays =, while his value is. With probability = bidder s valuation is 0, in which case b = 0, and wins for sure. If he wins, he pays = and his value is. Still assuming that v =, suppose that bidder sets b = 0. Then he gets an expected payo of 0 + ( 0) = 4 This is because of the following. With probability = bidder s valuation is, in which case b = =, wins for sure and gets a payo of 0. With probability = bidders s valuation is 0, in which case b = 0, the bids are tied and wins with probability =. If he wins, he pays 0 and his value is. So, contingent on v = bidder does not want to deviate from the proposed equilibrium. Suppose now that v = 0. If bidder sets b = = he gets an expected payo of = 3 8 This is because of the following. With probability = bidder s valuation is, in which case b = =, the bids are tied and wins with probability =. If he wins, he pays =, while his value is 0. 7

18 With probability = bidder s valuation is 0, in which case b = 0, and wins for sure. If he wins, he pays = and his value is 0. Still assuming that v = 0, suppose that bidder sets b = 0. Then he gets and expected payo of 0 + (0 0) = 0 This is because of the following. With probability = bidder s valuation is, in which case b = =, wins for sure and gets a payo of 0. With probability = bidders s valuation is 0, in which case b = 0, the bids are tied and wins with probability =. If he wins, he pays 0 and his value is 0. So, contingent on v = 0 bidder does not want to deviate from the proposed equilibrium [not for resit] A principal P hires an agent A to carry out a task that requires unobservable non-contractible e ort e [0; ]. A s e ort determines the probability that the task is successful in generating output. Output equals with probability e and 0 with probability e. Output is observable and contractible. First, P o ers a contract to A, then A accepts or rejects it. After a contract is signed, A chooses e. (a) A contract is a pair of reals (w ; w 0 ), with the rst being the wage (in units of output) that P pays A if output is, and the second being the wage if output is 0. Assume that A cannot be paid a negative wage, regardless of output. Both P and A are risk-neutral, and A dislikes e ort which generates disutility ke =, with k > =. Denote by e, w and w 0 the equilibrium values of e, w and w 0. Compute e, w and w 0. Sketched answer: Given w, w 0 and e, the payo to A is e w + ( e) w 0 k e Given w and w 0 he will choose an e that maximizes this. Di erentiating wrt e and setting equal to 0 gives the IC constraint for A. This is w 0 = k e w 8

19 Hence, it must be that w 0 = 0. This is because otherwise we could decrease both w and w 0, keep e constant and increase P s expected pro t. So we know that w 0 = 0 and w = k e Therefore P s expected pro t can be written as e( w ) + ( e)( w 0 ) = e( w ) = e( k e) Di erentiating wrt e and setting equal to 0 gives e = k Substituting back into the IC gives w = 0 7 [resit]a rm is the only employer in a city. This employer can hire workers on the local labor market, where there are two types of workers, low skill and high skill workers. Workers are expected to perform tasks for the employer. Utility of the workers of type i depend on their income, y i, and on the number of tasks they perform, t i, according to the following utility function: u i (y i ; t i ) = y i i d (t i ) ; where d (t i ) denotes the disutility of performing tasks and i is the skill parameter, with ` > h (the disutility to work is multiplied by a larger factor for the low skill agents). If they are not hired by the employer, workers have a reservation income of 0. We also assume that d (t i ) = t i, and that each task yields a pro t of to the rm, that ` = > h = ; and, nally, that there are 400 high skill workers and 00 low skill workers. (a) Suppose that the employer proposes the following contract. Each hired worker can decide the number of tasks shenhe performs and gets a payment of per task shenhe performs. Would workers of type ` accept to be hired? If so, how many tasks would they choose to perform? Would workers of type h accept to be hired? If so, how many tasks would they choose to perform? Is there an incentive compatibility problem? Outline of solution: Workers try to maximize u i (y i ; t i ) = y i i t i under the constraint that y i = t i : Substituting for y i in the utility 9

20 function and taking the derivative yields t i = i so that t ` = and t h = ; and, consequently, y` = and y h = : Workers of both types would accept to be hired at a wage rate of per task. There is no incentive problem, as u` (y ` ; t `) = ` = 4 > u` (yh; t h) = ` () = 0 and u h (y h; t h) = h () = > u h (y ` ; t `) = h = 3 8 : (b) Suppose the employer observes the skill of the workers. What is the pro t maximizing pair of contracts shenhe will propose to low skill and high skill workers, that is, how many tasks will each of them be asked to perform and how much will they be paid? Is there an incentive compatibility problem? Outline of solution: The employer proposes a contract (t h ; y h ) to type-h workers so as to maximize t h y h under the participation constraint u h (y h ; t h ) 0; and proposes a contract (t`; y`) to type-` workers so as to maximize t` y` under the participation constraint u` (y`; t`) 0: This gives us t i = i so that t ` = and t h = ; and, given that the participation constraints are binding, y ` = 4 and yh = : There is now an incentive compatibility constraint, as u h (y h; t h) = h () = 0 < u h (y ` ; t `) = 4 h = 8 : Workers of type h would like to masquerade workers of type ` : this contract can only be enforced if the employer observes the types. (c) Suppose the employer does not observe the skill of the workers. What is the pro t maximizing pair of contracts shenhe will propose to low skill and high skill workers, that is, how many tasks will each of them be asked to perform and how much will they be paid? Who will be better o, who will be worse o, compared to the complete information situation (part (b) of this question)? Outline of solution: Given what we have deduced above, we know that we have to take the incentive constraint of agents of type 0

21 h into account, as well as the participation constraint of agents of type `: As long as those constraints are met, the other two constraints (participation constraint of workers of type h and incentive constraints of agents of type `) are automatically met. The problem becomes that of under the constraints max 400 (t h y h ) + 00 (t` y`) u` (y`; t`) = y` `t ` 0; u h (y h ; t h ) = y h h t h u h (y`; t`) = y` h t `: Deriving with respect to t h ; t`; y h ; y` h = 400 ic ~t h = 00 p ~t` + ic ~t` h = ic = 00 + p ic = 0 where p is the multiplier associated to the participation constraint, and ic that associated to the incentive compatibility constraint and a tilda means an optimal value of the variable. We get ic = 400; therefore, ~t h = ; p = 500; ~t` = : Deriving with 6 respect to p and ic yields the participation constraints (which must be binding), so that ~y` = and 36 ~y` = 37 : Workers of type ` 7 have the same utilitynlevel as before, 0, whereas workers of type h have a strictly positive utility level, 37 7 = and the employer has a lower pro t both in the contract with a worker of type 7 37 h (a pro t of = 35 instead of ) and in the contract with a 7 7 worker of type ` (a pro t of = 5 instead of = = 9 ) [resit] The manager of a rm can exert a high e ort level E h = or a low e ort level E l =. The gross pro t of the rm is either P = 6 or P = P. The manager s choice a ects the probability of a particular pro t outcome occurring. If he chooses E h, then P occurs with probability h = 3, but if he chooses E 4 l then that probability is only l =. The risk neutral owner designs contracts which specify a 4

22 payment y i to the manager contingent on gross pro t P i. The utility function of the manager is u(y; E) = y = E, and his reservation utility u = 0. (a) Solve for the full information rst best contract, rst, if it is optimal to induce the manager to exert a high e ort, and second if it is optimal to induce hernhim to exert a low e ort. Outline of solution: Under the full information, rst best (FIFB) contract, both manager and owner can observe the action of the manager. Thus, we can solve the optimization problem for the owner for both high and low e ort levels separately, and then study which one yields higher expected pro ts. Formally, denoting the expected pro t to the owner under high and low e ort levels by the manager as P h and P l respectively, we have the following optimization problem for the owner, where i fh; lg: max Pi = i (P y ) + ( i )(P y ) y ;y s.t. i u(y ; E i ) + ( i )u(y ; E i ) u = 0 The participation constraint will be binding at the optimum. Furthermore, since the owner can observe the manager s action, and since the manager is risk-averse, the owner will set y = y = yi. Hence, we can solve for yh and y l simply by setting u(y i ; E i ) = 0 y i E i = 0 Using the numerical values given in the question, we obtain y h = 4 y l = which yield expected pro ts to the owner of P h = 8 + P 4 P l = 3 + 3P 4 : (b) Find the threshold value of P above which high e ort is optimal and below which low e ort is optimal. Outline of solution: Thus, the owner would like to induce the manager to take action E h if 8 + P 3 + 3P ; that is, if P

23 (c) Solve for the second-best contracts in the event that the owner cannot observe the manager s action in both cases where either high e ort or low e ort is optimal. Again, nd the threshold value of P: Outline of solution: However, if the manager could convince the owner that he was using E h, and get the owner to pay him yh, while in fact only using E l, his payo would be u(y h; E l ) = y h E l = > 0 and hence the incentive compatibility constraint would be violated. Thus, we now consider the second-best contract, where the owner cannot observe the action of the manager, but can induce him to take the right e ort level. Under the second-best contract, the owner has the choice of inducing the manager to choose either high or low e ort levels. Since there is no incentive compatibility problem with the low e ort level, the rst best solution continues to hold. The interesting case is inducing the manager to take the high e ort level with a second-best contract. Under the secondbest contract, the participation constraint continues to hold. In addition, however, we have an incentive compatibility constraint that guarantees that the manager would choose E h over E l, given the contract. Thus, the owner has to solve the problem such that max Ph = h (P y ) + ( h )(P y ) y ;y h y + ( h )y E h 0; that is, 3y + y 8 h y + ( h )y E h l y + ( l )y E l ; that is, y y Setting up a Lagrangean L in the usual manner, assigning Lagrange multipliers p and ic to the participation and the incentive compatibility constraint respectively, we nd from the rst-order conditions that (6 p + ic )y = 3 (43) ( p ic )y = (44) 3

24 We rst have to determine whether the constraints will be binding, using Kuhn-Tucker conditions 0, 0 and L = L = 0. Consider = 0. By equations 43 and 44, this implies that y = y = and hence that y = y. But this violates the incentive compatibility constraint, as before. Thus, > 0, and, by L = 0, the IC h must bind. But equation 44 implies that >, and hence R h must bind as well. We can now solve for y and y using IC h and R h constraints, and obtain that y = 5 4 y = 4 The expected pro ts associated with this contract are P h = P 4 P l = 3 + 3P 4 : (note that the pro t in the case of a low e ort remains unchanged, as there is no IC problem in that case). High e ort is optimal when 9 + P > 3 + 3P ; that is, when P < 8:5. While it was rational for the owner to bear all the risk under rst best, given that he was risk-neutral while the manager was risk-averse, under the secondbest contract the risk is shared between the owner and manager. This induces the manager to take the action which yields a higher probability of a good outcome. (d) Compare the two threshold values. What can you deduce? Outline of solution: For values of P in the interval [8:5; 0] ; it is optimal to induce the manager to choose a high e ort level if e ort is observable, and it is optimal to induce him to take a low e ort level when e ort is not observable. This is an illustration of the agency cost: it is so costly to enforce a high level of e ort when it is not observable that the owner of the rl has an interest to let the manager choose the low e ort level when e ort is no longer observable. 9 [resit] Answer any two questions from (a)-(c). 4

25 (a) A set of three agents, f; ; 3g, have to choose an alternative in a set of possible options. The problem can be represented as the choice of a point x in the interval [0,]. Agents have singlepeaked preferences over the set of alternatives (that is, each agent i f; ; 3g has a top-ranked alternative in the interval, say t i ; and moving away from that alternative makes hernhim worse o ), but the mechanism designer does not know the preferences of the agents and will have to design a direct revelation mechanism. Show that the following rule is manipulable: let a be a precise point in the interior of the interval: 0<a<. Given the preferences announced by the three agents, if a is e cient, then it is selected, and if a is not e cient, then the selected alternative is the minimum between the three alternatives top-ranked by the agents, min i t i. Outline of solution: In the following graph, the preferences of three agents are represented. Let us assume that these are the true preferences. Given that a is not between the peaks, it is not e cient. Consequently, the rule will select t = min i t i : u i u 3 (a) 6 u 3 (t ) 0 t t t 3 a - But given that u 3 (a) > u 3 (t ) ; agent 3 has an interest to misrepresent his preferences, for instance by pretending that t 0 3 = a: In this case, a becomes e cient, and the rule selects a: (b) A set of two voters, f; g, have to choose an alternative among fx; y; zg : They have strict preferences over the alternatives, but any ranking is possible. Show that the following rule is manipulable. If alternative x is e cient, then it is selected. If alternative x is not e cient, but alternative y is, then y is selected. If neither x nor y is e cient, then z is selected. Outline of solution: One way to solve the problem is by de ning the voting rule extensively. This gives us the following table. 5

26 n xyz xzy yxz yzx zxy zyx xyz x x x x x x xzy x x x x x x yxz x x y y x y yzx x x y y y y zxy x x x y z z zyx x x y y z z One can see that agent, for instance, when she is of type zxy; and is of type yzx; the selected alternative is y; whereas it would be x if she says she has preferences xyz: Therefore, she has an incentive to misrepresent her preferences in that case, and truthtelling is not a dominant strategy. Also, when she is of type yxz; and is of type zxy; the selected alternative is x; whereas it would be y if she says she has preferences yzx: Another way of solving the problem is by thinking directly to the possible ways or pro tably misreprenting one s preferences. If x is agent s top alternative, then it is e cient, and then clearly she does not have any incentive to misrepresent her preferences as she will get x: If y is agent s preferred alternative, then, either x is selected, if it is e cient, or y is selected. If y is selected, then clearly agent has an incentive to tell the truth. If x is e cient, is it possible to still obtain y by misrepresenting her preferences? It must be the case that by announcing x lower in her ranking than what is true, but still having y on top, makes x becomes ine cient, that is, by announcing yzx instead of yxz; x is no longer e cient. Can it be possible? Yes, provided agent has z on top and x is not dominated by y; that is, if agent is of type zxy, so that, by announcing yzx instead of yxz; agent makes x dominated by z: As x is no longer e cient, but y is, y is the new selection. So, agent has an interest to say she is of type yzx when she is actually of type yxz and agent is of type zxy: (c) Two rms, and, have to decide whether or not to undertake some joint investment. The cost of the investment is 0. The bene ts of the investment for each rm, v and v ; are private knowledge. Pro ts are simply bene ts minus payments. The possible values for v are and 7, those for v are 4 and 7. The rms would like to undertake the project if the sum of their values exceed the cost of the project. They agree to use the pivotal mechanism. Compute the amount each rm will have to pay as a function of their announcement. Check that the mechanism 6

27 cannot be manipulated. Check that there will always be enough money if they decide to undertake the project. Outline of solution: The project will be undertaken if (v ; v ) f(7; 4) ; (7; 7)g : Agent is pivotal in the case (; 7) : indeed, agent s valuation is larger than what is, on average, necessary to undertake the project, whereas the project is not undertaken; in this case agent pays P j6=i v j (n ) c =7-5=. She is also pivotal in the case (7; 4) : indeed, agent s valuation is lower than the average cost, whereas P the project is undertaken. In this case, agent pays nc j6=i v j = 0 4 = 6: In the other cases, she pays the average cost. Agent is never pivotal. To sum up, the payments are n 4 7 (0; 0) (; 0) 7 (6; 5) (5; 5) The mechanism cannot be manipulated. Indeed, when agent has valuation, her payo s are n so that telling the truth is dominant. When she has valuation 7, her payo s are n so that truthtelling is, again, a dominant strategy. 7 The relevant tables for agent are n and n when she has valuation 4 and 7 respectively, so that one sees again that truthtelling is a dominant strategy. Finally, the total payments by the agents are in the (7; 4) case, and 0 in the (7; 7) case, so that the cost is always covered. 7

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours.

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours. University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring 2012 EC941: Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Final Exam Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours. 1. Consider

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key EconS 50 - Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam # - Answer Key 1. Revenue comparison in two auction formats. Consider a sealed-bid auction with bidders. Every bidder i privately observes his valuation

More information

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2 EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2 Leonardo Felli 32L.G.06 19 January 2015 Moral Hazard: Consider the contractual relationship between two agents (a principal and an agent) The principal

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE)

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE) EconS 3 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE). Based on MWG 9.B.3 Consider the three-player nite game of perfect information depicted in gure. L R Player 3 l r a b

More information

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 1 Modelling incomplete information So far, we have studied games in which information was complete,

More information

Lecture 7. Simple Dynamic Games

Lecture 7. Simple Dynamic Games Lecture 7. Simple Dynamic Games 1. Two-Stage Games of Complete and Perfect Information Two-Stages dynamic game with two players: player 1 chooses action a 1 from the set of his feasible actions A 1 player

More information

Notes on Mechanism Designy

Notes on Mechanism Designy Notes on Mechanism Designy ECON 20B - Game Theory Guillermo Ordoñez UCLA February 0, 2006 Mechanism Design. Informal discussion. Mechanisms are particular types of games of incomplete (or asymmetric) information

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key EconS 503 - Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key 1. WEAs with market power. Consider an exchange economy with two consumers, A and B, whose utility functions are u A (x A 1 ; x A 2 ) = x A

More information

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version)

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) July 4, 2017 1. Person A lexicographically prefers good x to good y, i.e., when comparing two bundles of x and y, she strictly prefers

More information

Microeconomics CHAPTER 2. THE FIRM

Microeconomics CHAPTER 2. THE FIRM Chapter The Firm Exercise. Suppose that a unit of output can be produced by any of the following combinations of inputs z = 0: 0:5 ; z 0:3 = 0:. Construct the isouant for =. ; z 3 0:5 = 0:. Assuming constant

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design 1. Public Good Provision Imagine that you and your colleagues want to buy a co ee machine for your o ce. Suppose that some of you may

More information

Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model

Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model Yu (Larry) Chen School of Economics, Nanjing University Fall 2015 Principal-Agent Relationship Principal-agent relationship

More information

Moral Hazard. Felix Munoz-Garcia. Advanced Microeconomics II - Washington State University

Moral Hazard. Felix Munoz-Garcia. Advanced Microeconomics II - Washington State University Moral Hazard Felix Munoz-Garcia Advanced Microeconomics II - Washington State University Moral Hazard Reading materials: Start with Prajit Dutta, Chapter 19. MWG, Chapter 14 Macho-Stadler and Perez-Castrillo,

More information

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

Limit pricing models and PBE 1 EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Limit pricing models and PBE 1 1 Model Consider an entry game with an incumbent monopolist (Firm 1) and an entrant (Firm ) who analyzes whether or not to join the

More information

Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanisms

Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanisms Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanisms Jonathan Levin 1 Economics 285 Market Design Winter 2009 1 These slides are based on Paul Milgrom s. onathan Levin VCG Mechanisms Winter 2009 1 / 23 Motivation We consider

More information

Teoria das organizações e contratos

Teoria das organizações e contratos Teoria das organizações e contratos Chapter 6: Adverse Selection with two types Mestrado Profissional em Economia 3 o trimestre 2015 EESP (FGV) Teoria das organizações e contratos 3 o trimestre 2015 1

More information

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

Some Notes on Adverse Selection Some Notes on Adverse Selection John Morgan Haas School of Business and Department of Economics University of California, Berkeley Overview This set of lecture notes covers a general model of adverse selection

More information

Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply

Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply Matthias Kräkel y Anja Schöttner z Abstract It is well-known that, in static models, minimum wages generate positive worker rents and, consequently, ine ciently

More information

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form)

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form) Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form) A Game in Normal (strategic) Form consists of three components. A set of players. For each player, a set of strategies (called actions in textbook). The interpretation

More information

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection Geethanjali Selvaretnam Abstract This model takes into consideration the fact that depositors

More information

Answers to Spring 2014 Microeconomics Prelim

Answers to Spring 2014 Microeconomics Prelim Answers to Spring 204 Microeconomics Prelim. To model the problem of deciding whether or not to attend college, suppose an individual, Ann, consumes in each of two periods. She is endowed with income w

More information

Final Exam (Solution) Economics 501b Microeconomic Theory

Final Exam (Solution) Economics 501b Microeconomic Theory Dirk Bergemann and Johannes Hoerner Department of Economics Yale Uniersity Final Exam (Solution) Economics 5b Microeconomic Theory May This is a closed-book exam. The exam lasts for 8 minutes. Please write

More information

Economics 3012 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 20, 2006

Economics 3012 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 20, 2006 Economics 301 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 0, 006 Lecture 11 Topics Problem Set 9 Extensive Games of Imperfect Information An Example General Description Strategies and Nash Equilibrium Beliefs

More information

Low-Quality Leadership in a Vertically Differentiated Duopoly with Cournot Competition

Low-Quality Leadership in a Vertically Differentiated Duopoly with Cournot Competition Low-Quality Leadership in a Vertically Differentiated Duopoly with Cournot Competition Luca Lambertini Alessandro Tampieri Quaderni - Working Paper DSE N 750 Low-Quality Leadership in a Vertically Di erentiated

More information

Game theory lecture 4. September 24, 2012

Game theory lecture 4. September 24, 2012 September 24, 2012 Finding Nash equilibrium Best-response or best-reply functions. We introduced Nash-equilibrium as a profile of actions (an action for each player) such that no player has an incentive

More information

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search Labor Economics, 14.661. Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search Daron Acemoglu MIT December 6, 2011. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Sequential Search December 6, 2011. 1 / 43 Introduction Introduction

More information

U b (x b ) = xb 1x b 2 x a 1. means the consumption of good i by an h-type person.

U b (x b ) = xb 1x b 2 x a 1. means the consumption of good i by an h-type person. Chapter 9 Welfare Exercise 9. In a two-commodity exchange economy there are two large equalsized groups of traders. Each trader in group a has an endowment of 300 units of commodity ; each person in group

More information

A : a b c d a : B C A E B : d b c a b : C A B D E C : d c a c : E D B C D : a d b d : A D E B C E : a b d. A : a b c d a : B C A D E

A : a b c d a : B C A E B : d b c a b : C A B D E C : d c a c : E D B C D : a d b d : A D E B C E : a b d. A : a b c d a : B C A D E Microeconomics II( ECO 50) Questions on the comprehensive exam will be chosen from the list below( with possible minor variations) CALCULATORS ARE ALLOWED Matching. Consider the Gale-Shapley marriage problem

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen 1 Bayesian Games So far we have assumed that all players had perfect information regarding the elements of a game. These are called games with complete information.

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Leonardo Felli EC441: Room D.106, Z.332, D.109 Lecture 8 bis: 24 November 2004 Monopoly Consider now the pricing behavior of a profit maximizing monopolist: a firm that is the only

More information

Industrial Organization Lecture 7: Product Differentiation

Industrial Organization Lecture 7: Product Differentiation Industrial Organization Lecture 7: Product Differentiation Nicolas Schutz Nicolas Schutz Product Differentiation 1 / 57 Introduction We now finally drop the assumption that firms offer homogeneous products.

More information

Bayesian Games and Mechanism Design Definition of Bayes Equilibrium

Bayesian Games and Mechanism Design Definition of Bayes Equilibrium Bayesian Games and Mechanism Design Definition of Bayes Equilibrium Harsanyi [1967] What happens when players do not know one another s payoffs? Games of incomplete information versus games of imperfect

More information

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action Moral Hazard: Hidden Action Part of these Notes were taken (almost literally) from Rasmusen, 2007 UIB Course 2013-14 (UIB) MH-Hidden Actions Course 2013-14 1 / 29 A Principal-agent Model. The Production

More information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Pei-yu Lo 1 Introduction Recap: BoS. Look for all Nash equilibria. show how to nd pure strategy Nash equilibria. Show how to nd mixed strategy Nash equilibria.

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012 The time limit for this exam is 4 hours. It has four sections. Each section includes two questions. You are

More information

Mechanism Design: Bayesian Incentive Compatibility

Mechanism Design: Bayesian Incentive Compatibility May 30, 2013 Setup X : finite set of public alternatives X = {x 1,..., x K } Θ i : the set of possible types for player i, F i is the marginal distribution of θ i. We assume types are independently distributed.

More information

Economics 2450A: Public Economics Section 8: Optimal Minimum Wage and Introduction to Capital Taxation

Economics 2450A: Public Economics Section 8: Optimal Minimum Wage and Introduction to Capital Taxation Economics 2450A: Public Economics Section 8: Optimal Minimum Wage and Introduction to Capital Taxation Matteo Paradisi November 1, 2016 In this Section we develop a theoretical analysis of optimal minimum

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 More on strategic games and extensive games with perfect information Block 2 Jun 12, 2016 Food for thought LUPI Many players

More information

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann Dirk Bergemann Department of Economics Yale University Microeconomic Theory (50b) Problem Set 0. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann 4/5/4 This problem set is due on Tuesday, 4//4..

More information

Aggregate Supply. Econ 208. April 3, Lecture 16. Econ 208 (Lecture 16) Aggregate Supply April 3, / 12

Aggregate Supply. Econ 208. April 3, Lecture 16. Econ 208 (Lecture 16) Aggregate Supply April 3, / 12 Aggregate Supply Econ 208 Lecture 16 April 3, 2007 Econ 208 (Lecture 16) Aggregate Supply April 3, 2007 1 / 12 Introduction rices might be xed for a brief period, but we need to look beyond this The di

More information

Econ 101A Problem Set 6 Solutions Due on Monday Dec. 9. No late Problem Sets accepted, sorry!

Econ 101A Problem Set 6 Solutions Due on Monday Dec. 9. No late Problem Sets accepted, sorry! Econ 0A Problem Set 6 Solutions Due on Monday Dec. 9. No late Problem Sets accepted, sry! This Problem set tests the knowledge that you accumulated mainly in lectures 2 to 26. The problem set is focused

More information

Game Theory. Monika Köppl-Turyna. Winter 2017/2018. Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business

Game Theory. Monika Köppl-Turyna. Winter 2017/2018. Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business Monika Köppl-Turyna Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business Winter 2017/2018 Static Games of Incomplete Information Introduction So far we assumed that payoff functions

More information

Lecture 4. 1 Examples of Mechanism Design Problems

Lecture 4. 1 Examples of Mechanism Design Problems CSCI699: Topics in Learning and Game Theory Lecture 4 Lecturer: Shaddin Dughmi Scribes: Haifeng Xu,Reem Alfayez 1 Examples of Mechanism Design Problems Example 1: Single Item Auctions. There is a single

More information

Solving Extensive Form Games

Solving Extensive Form Games Chapter 8 Solving Extensive Form Games 8.1 The Extensive Form of a Game The extensive form of a game contains the following information: (1) the set of players (2) the order of moves (that is, who moves

More information

1 Oligopoly: Bertrand Model

1 Oligopoly: Bertrand Model 1 Oligopoly: Bertrand Model Bertrand model: There are two rms and no entry is possible. Homogeneity of product. Single period. Consumers always purchase from the cheapest seller. If the two selllers charge

More information

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009 Department of Agricultural Economics PhD Qualifier Examination May 009 Instructions: The exam consists of six questions. You must answer all questions. If you need an assumption to complete a question,

More information

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation joint work with Stephen Morris August 2009 Barcelona Introduction mechanism design and implementation literatures are theoretical successes mechanisms

More information

Bertrand Model of Price Competition. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 1

Bertrand Model of Price Competition. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 1 Bertrand Model of Price Competition Advanced Microeconomic Theory 1 ҧ Bertrand Model of Price Competition Consider: An industry with two firms, 1 and 2, selling a homogeneous product Firms face market

More information

EconS Sequential Competition

EconS Sequential Competition EconS 425 - Sequential Competition Eric Dunaway Washington State University eric.dunaway@wsu.edu Industrial Organization Eric Dunaway (WSU) EconS 425 Industrial Organization 1 / 47 A Warmup 1 x i x j (x

More information

CPS 173 Mechanism design. Vincent Conitzer

CPS 173 Mechanism design. Vincent Conitzer CPS 173 Mechanism design Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu edu Mechanism design: setting The center has a set of outcomes O that she can choose from Allocations of tasks/resources, joint plans, Each

More information

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Tymofiy Mylovanov Thomas Tröger University of Bonn June 21, 2008 1/28 Motivation 2/28 Motivation In most applications of mechanism design, the proposer

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Summer 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the four areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory A, (III) game theory B, and (IV) psychology & economics). Be sure

More information

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions Some Lecture Notes on Auctions John Morgan February 25 1 Introduction These notes sketch a 1 hour and 5 minute lecture on auctions. The main points are: 1. Set up the basic auction problem. 2. Derie the

More information

5. Externalities and Public Goods. Externalities. Public Goods types. Public Goods

5. Externalities and Public Goods. Externalities. Public Goods types. Public Goods 5. Externalities and Public Goods 5. Externalities and Public Goods Externalities Welfare properties of Walrasian Equilibria rely on the hidden assumption of private goods: the consumption of the good

More information

General Equilibrium and Welfare

General Equilibrium and Welfare and Welfare Lectures 2 and 3, ECON 4240 Spring 2017 University of Oslo 24.01.2017 and 31.01.2017 1/37 Outline General equilibrium: look at many markets at the same time. Here all prices determined in the

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Incentives and Machine Learning

Incentives and Machine Learning Incentives and Machine Learning John Hegeman December 12, 2008 In 2007, US paid search ad spend was $8.9 billion - most of which used a pay per click (PPC) billing model. In PPC, advertisers only pay the

More information

EconS Nash Equilibrium in Games with Continuous Action Spaces.

EconS Nash Equilibrium in Games with Continuous Action Spaces. EconS 424 - Nash Equilibrium in Games with Continuous Action Spaces. Félix Muñoz-García Washington State University fmunoz@wsu.edu February 7, 2014 Félix Muñoz-García (WSU) EconS 424 - Recitation 3 February

More information

5. Externalities and Public Goods

5. Externalities and Public Goods 5. Externalities and Public Goods Welfare properties of Walrasian Equilibria rely on the hidden assumption of private goods: the consumption of the good by one person has no effect on other people s utility,

More information

Department of Economics, University of California, Davis Ecn 200C Micro Theory Professor Giacomo Bonanno ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS 18

Department of Economics, University of California, Davis Ecn 200C Micro Theory Professor Giacomo Bonanno ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS 18 Department of Economics, University of California, Davis Ecn 00C Micro Theory Professor Giacomo Bonanno ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBEMS 8. If price is Number of cars offered for sale Average quality of cars

More information

Module 8: Multi-Agent Models of Moral Hazard

Module 8: Multi-Agent Models of Moral Hazard Module 8: Multi-Agent Models of Moral Hazard Information Economics (Ec 515) George Georgiadis Types of models: 1. No relation among agents. an many agents make contracting easier? 2. Agents shocks are

More information

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts Advanced Microeconomic Theory: Economics 521b Spring 2011 Juuso Välimäki Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts The setup is similar to that of a Bayesian game. The ingredients are: 1. Set of players, i {1,

More information

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP Prof. Olivier Bochet Room A.34 Phone 3 63 476 E-mail olivier.bochet@vwi.unibe.ch Webpage http//sta.vwi.unibe.ch/bochet Advanced Microeconomics Fall 2 Lecture Note Choice-Based Approach Price e ects, Wealth

More information

Backwards Induction. Extensive-Form Representation. Backwards Induction (cont ) The player 2 s optimization problem in the second stage

Backwards Induction. Extensive-Form Representation. Backwards Induction (cont ) The player 2 s optimization problem in the second stage Lecture Notes II- Dynamic Games of Complete Information Extensive Form Representation (Game tree Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium Repeated Games Trigger Strategy Dynamic Games of Complete Information Dynamic

More information

1 Objective. 2 Constrained optimization. 2.1 Utility maximization. Dieter Balkenborg Department of Economics

1 Objective. 2 Constrained optimization. 2.1 Utility maximization. Dieter Balkenborg Department of Economics BEE020 { Basic Mathematical Economics Week 2, Lecture Thursday 2.0.0 Constrained optimization Dieter Balkenborg Department of Economics University of Exeter Objective We give the \ rst order conditions"

More information

A Centralized or a Decentralized Labor Market?

A Centralized or a Decentralized Labor Market? ömmföäflsäafaäsflassflassflas ffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffff Discussion Papers A Centralized or a Decentralized Labor Market? Juha Virrankoski Aalto University and HECER Discussion Paper No. 42 November

More information

8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS

8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS 8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS We have studied competitive markets where there are a large number of rms and each rm takes market prices as given. When a market contain only a few relevant rms, rms may

More information

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions Some Lecture Notes on Auctions John Morgan Haas School of Business and Department of Economics Uniersity of California, Berkeley Preliminaries Perhaps the most fruitful area for the application of optimal

More information

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Piero Gottardi EUI Sept. 26, 2016 Piero Gottardi (EUI) Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Sept. 26, 2016 1 / 53 Choice Theory Set of alternatives: X, with generic elements x,

More information

Lecture Notes - Dynamic Moral Hazard

Lecture Notes - Dynamic Moral Hazard Lecture Notes - Dynamic Moral Hazard Simon Board and Moritz Meyer-ter-Vehn October 27, 2011 1 Marginal Cost of Providing Utility is Martingale (Rogerson 85) 1.1 Setup Two periods, no discounting Actions

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design Makis Arsenis National Technical University of Athens April 216 Makis Arsenis (NTUA) AGT April 216 1 / 41 Outline 1 Social Choice Social Choice

More information

Research and Development

Research and Development Chapter 9. March 7, 2011 Firms spend substantial amounts on. For instance ( expenditure to output sales): aerospace (23%), o ce machines and computers (18%), electronics (10%) and drugs (9%). is classi

More information

Market Power. Economics II: Microeconomics. December Aslanyan (VŠE) Oligopoly 12/09 1 / 39

Market Power. Economics II: Microeconomics. December Aslanyan (VŠE) Oligopoly 12/09 1 / 39 Market Power Economics II: Microeconomics VŠE Praha December 2009 Aslanyan (VŠE) Oligopoly 12/09 1 / 39 Microeconomics Consumers: Firms: People. Households. Monopoly. Oligopoly Now Perfect Competition.

More information

Lecture 10: Mechanism Design

Lecture 10: Mechanism Design Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2009/10 Lecture 10: Mechanism Design Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Vera Vsevolozhsky, Nadav Wexler 10.1 Mechanisms with money 10.1.1 Introduction As we have

More information

Moral Hazard: Part 1. April 9, 2018

Moral Hazard: Part 1. April 9, 2018 Moral Hazard: Part 1 April 9, 2018 Introduction In a standard moral hazard problem, the agent A is characterized by only one type. As with adverse selection, the principal P wants to engage in an economic

More information

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics ECON2285: Mathematical Economics Yulei Luo Economics, HKU September 17, 2018 Luo, Y. (Economics, HKU) ME September 17, 2018 1 / 46 Static Optimization and Extreme Values In this topic, we will study goal

More information

Lecture 5: Labour Economics and Wage-Setting Theory

Lecture 5: Labour Economics and Wage-Setting Theory Lecture 5: Labour Economics and Wage-Setting Theory Spring 2017 Lars Calmfors Literature: Chapter 7 Cahuc-Carcillo-Zylberberg: 435-445 1 Topics Weakly efficient bargaining Strongly efficient bargaining

More information

A Solution to the Problem of Externalities When Agents Are Well-Informed

A Solution to the Problem of Externalities When Agents Are Well-Informed A Solution to the Problem of Externalities When Agents Are Well-Informed Hal R. Varian. The American Economic Review, Vol. 84, No. 5 (Dec., 1994), pp. 1278-1293 Introduction There is a unilateral externality

More information

Lecture Note II-3 Static Games of Incomplete Information. Games of incomplete information. Cournot Competition under Asymmetric Information (cont )

Lecture Note II-3 Static Games of Incomplete Information. Games of incomplete information. Cournot Competition under Asymmetric Information (cont ) Lecture Note II- Static Games of Incomplete Information Static Bayesian Game Bayesian Nash Equilibrium Applications: Auctions The Revelation Principle Games of incomplete information Also called Bayesian

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen Strategic Form Games In this part we will analyze games in which the players choose their actions simultaneously (or without the knowledge of other players

More information

Vickrey Auction. Mechanism Design. Algorithmic Game Theory. Alexander Skopalik Algorithmic Game Theory 2013 Mechanism Design

Vickrey Auction. Mechanism Design. Algorithmic Game Theory. Alexander Skopalik Algorithmic Game Theory 2013 Mechanism Design Algorithmic Game Theory Vickrey Auction Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanisms Mechanisms with Money Player preferences are quantifiable. Common currency enables utility transfer between players. Preference

More information

Adding Production to the Theory

Adding Production to the Theory Adding Production to the Theory We begin by considering the simplest situation that includes production: two goods, both of which have consumption value, but one of which can be transformed into the other.

More information

Simplifying this, we obtain the following set of PE allocations: (x E ; x W ) 2

Simplifying this, we obtain the following set of PE allocations: (x E ; x W ) 2 Answers Answer for Q (a) ( pts:.5 pts. for the de nition and.5 pts. for its characterization) The de nition of PE is standard. There may be many ways to characterize the set of PE allocations. But whichever

More information

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications Lecture 18: Auctions and Mechanism Design II: a little social choice theory, the VCG Mechanism, and Market Equilibria Kousha Etessami Reminder: Food for Thought:

More information

Externalities and PG. MWG- Chapter 11

Externalities and PG. MWG- Chapter 11 Externalities and PG MWG- Chapter 11 Simple Bilateral Externality When external e ects are present, CE are not PO. Assume: 1 Two consumers i = 1, 2 2 The actions of these consumers do not a ect prices

More information

Competitive Equilibrium and the Welfare Theorems

Competitive Equilibrium and the Welfare Theorems Competitive Equilibrium and the Welfare Theorems Craig Burnside Duke University September 2010 Craig Burnside (Duke University) Competitive Equilibrium September 2010 1 / 32 Competitive Equilibrium and

More information

4- Current Method of Explaining Business Cycles: DSGE Models. Basic Economic Models

4- Current Method of Explaining Business Cycles: DSGE Models. Basic Economic Models 4- Current Method of Explaining Business Cycles: DSGE Models Basic Economic Models In Economics, we use theoretical models to explain the economic processes in the real world. These models de ne a relation

More information

Oligopoly Theory. This might be revision in parts, but (if so) it is good stu to be reminded of...

Oligopoly Theory. This might be revision in parts, but (if so) it is good stu to be reminded of... This might be revision in parts, but (if so) it is good stu to be reminded of... John Asker Econ 170 Industrial Organization January 23, 2017 1 / 1 We will cover the following topics: with Sequential Moves

More information

Mechanism Design. Terence Johnson. December 7, University of Notre Dame. Terence Johnson (ND) Mechanism Design December 7, / 44

Mechanism Design. Terence Johnson. December 7, University of Notre Dame. Terence Johnson (ND) Mechanism Design December 7, / 44 Mechanism Design Terence Johnson University of Notre Dame December 7, 2017 Terence Johnson (ND) Mechanism Design December 7, 2017 1 / 44 Market Design vs Mechanism Design In Market Design, we have a very

More information

Mechanism Design: Bargaining

Mechanism Design: Bargaining Mechanism Design: Bargaining Dilip Mookherjee Boston University Ec 703b Lecture 5 (text: FT Ch 7, pp 275-279) DM (BU) Mech Design 703b.5 2019 1 / 13 The Bargaining Problem Two agents: S, seller and B,

More information

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid May Microeconomics Grade

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid May Microeconomics Grade Universidad Carlos III de Madrid May 017 Microeconomics Name: Group: 1 3 5 Grade You have hours and 5 minutes to answer all the questions. 1. Multiple Choice Questions. (Mark your choice with an x. You

More information

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion:

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: Interpretation and Step-by-Step Examples Ana Espínola-Arredondo School of Economic Sciences Washington State University Pullman, WA 99164 Félix Muñoz-García y School

More information

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4 1 Hotelling s model 1.1 Two vendors Game Theory Solutions to Problem Set 4 Consider a strategy pro le (s 1 s ) with s 1 6= s Suppose s 1 < s In this case, it is pro table to for player 1 to deviate and

More information

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics Ph. D. Comprehensive Examination: Macroeconomics Fall, 202 Answer Key to Section 2 Questions Section. (Suggested Time: 45 Minutes) For 3 of

More information

Bayesian Nash equilibrium

Bayesian Nash equilibrium Bayesian Nash equilibrium Felix Munoz-Garcia EconS 503 - Washington State University So far we assumed that all players knew all the relevant details in a game. Hence, we analyzed complete-information

More information

General idea. Firms can use competition between agents for. We mainly focus on incentives. 1 incentive and. 2 selection purposes 3 / 101

General idea. Firms can use competition between agents for. We mainly focus on incentives. 1 incentive and. 2 selection purposes 3 / 101 3 Tournaments 3.1 Motivation General idea Firms can use competition between agents for 1 incentive and 2 selection purposes We mainly focus on incentives 3 / 101 Main characteristics Agents fulll similar

More information

1. The General Linear-Quadratic Framework

1. The General Linear-Quadratic Framework ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Slides to accompany 21. Incentives for Effort - Multi-Dimensional Cases 1. The General Linear-Quadratic Framework Notation: x = (x j ), n-vector of agent

More information

Screening. Diego Moreno Universidad Carlos III de Madrid. Diego Moreno () Screening 1 / 1

Screening. Diego Moreno Universidad Carlos III de Madrid. Diego Moreno () Screening 1 / 1 Screening Diego Moreno Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Diego Moreno () Screening 1 / 1 The Agency Problem with Adverse Selection A risk neutral principal wants to o er a menu of contracts to be o ered

More information

In the Ramsey model we maximized the utility U = u[c(t)]e nt e t dt. Now

In the Ramsey model we maximized the utility U = u[c(t)]e nt e t dt. Now PERMANENT INCOME AND OPTIMAL CONSUMPTION On the previous notes we saw how permanent income hypothesis can solve the Consumption Puzzle. Now we use this hypothesis, together with assumption of rational

More information