An introduction to quantum measurement theory

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "An introduction to quantum measurement theory"

Transcription

1 Chapter 1 An introduction to quantum measurement theory In this introductory chapter we present those aspects of quantum measurement theory that we use in this thesis to discuss the quantum Zeno effect, both theoretically and to make experimental proposals for its testing. 1.1 Measurement in quantum mechanics That the Schrödinger equation [23] governs the dynamics of all closed physical systems is one of the fundamental postulates of quantum mechanics. In the Schrödinger representation this equation is i h ψ = Ĥ ψ, t (1.1) where Ĥ is the (presumed) time independent Hamiltonian of the system of interest described by the state vector ψ. (We discuss our operational definition of these terms below.) Under this equation the evolution of the system is fully unitary and time reversible. The state at time t is related to the the state at time t = 0 by the evolution operator U such that ψ(t) = U ψ(0) = e ī h Ĥt ψ(0). (1.2) This evolution is linear, and therefore the state of the system can always be described by a linear combination of the members of any particular eigenbasis of interest. The adoption of the Schrödinger equation as a postulate necessarily entails the acceptance of the existence of linear superpositions of eigenstates for arbitrary closed systems. This is of considerable interest as the postulated Schrödinger equation contains no parameters concerning the size or complexity of the system of interest, and thereby 1

2 2 CHAPTER 1. AN INTRODUCTION TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY claims applicability to all closed systems. In the Chap. (9) we intimate that the Schrödinger equation could be applied to the Universe as a whole, with the conclusion that the Universe exists in a coherent superposition of states. This prediction is difficult to reconcile with observations of our classical Universe. There are two major classes of systems which are generally observed not to be found in linear combinations of eigenstates. The first of these are macroscopic systems such as physicists or dust motes and other inconsequential objects. Such macroscopic systems consist of many microscopic systems interacting in such a way as to smear out their mutual quantum coherences and thus to render unobservable the superposition of their eigenstates. The extreme complexity of these interactions makes using quantum mechanics prohibitively difficult. Because of this, physicists make further postulates regarding the nature of macroscopic objects, and these postulates constitute classical mechanics. (Of course, this description reverses the usual order of postulation.) The reconciling of these two paradigms is itself a difficult and active area of research. Classical mechanics forbids the existence of macroscopic superposition states, and in effect sets all quantum coherences to be identically zero. On the other hand, quantum mechanics (based on the Schrödinger equation) ensures that the quantum coherences are faithfully maintained even though smeared out and thus predicts that systems of arbitrary size will display behaviour typical of quantum systems (such as recurrences for example). A fruitful approach to resolving this contradiction between these two fields consists in treating the interaction between a microscopic system, governed by quantum mechanics, and a macroscopic system referred to as the environment described semi-classically. Studying such a combination of micro- and macro-systems assists us in understanding how classical mechanics arises in a quantum universe. (See for example [28, 10].) Investigations such as these will be further considered in this thesis. The second area in which the Schrödinger equation is observed to be inapplicable is a subset of the system-environment interaction considered above. In this case, we specify the dynamics of the environment in such a way that part of it constitutes a semi-classical meter, or detector. We further carefully design the system-meter interaction so as to provide a channel along which information can flow and be amplified from the microscopic system so as to be reflected in the state of the macroscopic meter. After the (as yet unspecified) interaction and amplification has been completed we say that a measurement has been performed. Such a measurement interaction is observed to be non-unitary, and thus cannot be described by the Schrödinger equation. An accurate measurement results in a reduction of the linear superposition of eigenstates in an arbitrary eigenbasis to a single eigenstate in a pointer basis [28] specified by the measurement interaction. The modelling of this measurement interaction constitutes a large part of this thesis.

3 1.1. MEASUREMENT IN QUANTUM MECHANICS The Heisenberg cut and related measurement issues We note that while we do model various measurement interactions in this thesis, we emphatically do not address the question of what constitutes a measurement, or when a particular interaction can be considered to be a measurement. This question fully encapsulates the issues raised above about the placement of the divide between quantum and classical mechanics. This divide is referred to as the Heisenberg cut. The Heisenberg cut [8] is used to divide the realms of the microscopic world in which quantum mechanics applies and the realm in which classical mechanics is presumed to apply. As intimated above, the location and modelling of this divide is an active area of research. A consideration of the act of performing a measurement on a quantum system brings the issues into sharp focus. An experimenter seeking to perform such a measurement has no direct access to the quantum system, but only to the measuring device being used. (This applies even when we attempt to observe photons directly for instance. In this case the observing device is the macroscopic lens and retina of our eye.) The observer builds a careful channel along which information can flow from the quantum system, through various amplification stages until it impinges upon the observer s awareness. The observer is aware that every stage of the channel can be modelled quantum mechanically, including the observer. And thus, according to Schr dinger s equation, at no stage is a nonunitary interaction that might constitute a measurement ever effected. Every stage in the measurement chain must then be described by a superposition of eigenstates. However, most observers would agree that they themselves do not exist in a quantum superposition of states. This is established by introspection, or by an observation of oneself. For all practical purposes, we generally treat most of the stages of the measurement chain as being well described by classical mechanics, and thus, not existing in some superposition of states. This then faces us squarely with the conundrums neatly summed up in the Schrödinger s cat [22] and Wigner s friend paradoxes. (Attempts to resolve these paradoxes using metaphysics are, we believe, flawed and based on an alleged poor present understanding of the tools of quantum mechanics. We discuss this assertion in the epilogue and conclude that more attention must be given to developing better tools of quantum mechanics and a better understanding for these tools before any attempt at building a quantum metaphysics will be successful.) For the purposes of this thesis, we are content to assert operational definitions as required. In view of this we make the empirical observation that we are best described classically, and thus place the Heisenberg cut below us in the measurement chain. Where it is placed is relatively arbitrary. If it is placed at the level of the system itself, then we effectively model a measurement interaction as an instantaneous collapse of the system state. This instantaneous nonunitary collapse of the system state significantly disturbs the evolution of the system of interest and can t be described by the Schrödinger equation. In effect, we have two mechanisms by which a quantum state can evolve - the first described by the Schrödinger equation, and the second described by this nonunitary measurement interaction. (This

4 4 CHAPTER 1. AN INTRODUCTION TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY disturbance, or measurement back action, when applied directly to the system of interest generates the elementary quantum Zeno effect as detailed below.) However, we generally find it more useful to model the quantum system as weakly interacting with another, larger system, the detector, and treat this larger system as being the first part of the measurement chain. This detector can be modelled pseudo-classically, and by this we mean that it possesses certain classical attributes. We choose to apply the cut to the detector, whose semi-classical attributes [discussed further in Chap. (3)] are chosen to minimise (but not ignore) the measurement backaction onto the system. In what follows we develop an operational definition of measurement, and along the way, define terms like state of a system, ensemble, measurement device, and so on. This operational definition is sufficient for us to build an intuitive understanding of the theory and enable us to meaningfully compare our predictions with experiment. To a large part we follow the approach referred to as the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, though without delving (in this thesis) to deeply into the meaning of the terms employed in quantum theory. (Further discussion of some aspects of quantum metaphysics takes place in the epilogue.) 1.2 A guide to quantum measurement theory We introduce quantum measurement theory by means of the states, effects and operations approach. For this treatment we follow the treatment of Kraus [11], but make use of the reformulation by Milburn [51, 17] of this work using Dirac notation. This methodology is useful for later generalization, and serves to introduce many of the techniques of quantum measurement theory. We note that the techniques presented in this section are used to model measurement outcomes. This measurement approach does not make any pretence at modelling the interaction between a system and a detector, and effectively, only models the outcomes of measurements performed on a quantum system. We turn to formulating models of a measurement interaction in Chap. (3) Instantaneous, accurate measurements - elementary measurement theory In this section we introduce the elementary quantum measurement theory of instantaneous, arbitrarily accurate measurements. We consider an ensemble of many quantum systems (possibly infinitely many) that have been subject to a well determined state preparation procedure specified by the construction of some macroscopic physical device. We then ascribe a state to the members of the ensemble. We further assume that this state can be described by density operators in a Hilbert space in the usual manner. Kraus then introduces the empirical fact that macroscopic measuring instruments exist and are designed so that they internally register an effect after an interaction with an individual quantum system. It is empirically

5 1.2. A GUIDE TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY 5 observed that, after such an interaction the effect apparatuses are triggered with reproducible relative frequencies [11] by the microsystems prepared in the above ensemble. We further assume that we can model these effects through the use of projection operators on the Hilbert space possessed by the system, and that the above relative frequencies of empirical observation can be determined by tracing the projection operator with the ensemble density operator over the Hilbert space. The above assumptions are best clarified by using a specific example. Consider the arbitrarily accurate measurement of a physical quantity represented by the operator  with eigenstates a on an ensemble of systems described by the density operator ˆρ, ˆρ = a,a a ˆρ a a a. (1.3) We do not detail the measurement interaction, and only specify the effect to be, for example, a projection a a. After the completion of the undescribed measurement interaction, we postulate the measured value of the physical quantity  to be a (one of the eigenvalues) with probability P (a) = tr(ˆρ a a ). (1.4) The application of the projection postulate is here assumed to be instantaneous. The interaction with the measurement device does not leave the state of the system unaffected. There is always a measurement backaction onto the state of the system. Consider the ensemble of systems introduced above after the interaction with the effect device. We are perfectly justified in treating this additional interaction with the effect device as just another stage in the state preparation of the system, and, in view of the definition introduced above, we expect the system to be described by a new ensemble after the measurement interaction. We are naturally interested in the form of this new ensemble, but to describe it we must distinguish two experimental situations. Consider the case where the experimenter has perfect information about the outcome of the measurement interaction, then a selective operation is said to have occurred. This selective operation is also defined operationally in the following manner. After the measurement interaction, the experimenter selects those members of the ensemble that gave a particular result, and discards the rest. In this case, the outcome is a new ensemble whose members have all been through a special state selection procedure depending on the outcome of the previous measurement. In this case, we say the ensemble of systems has been partitioned according to the results of the measurement. The new ensemble corresponding to the result a is related to the old ensemble by the selective operation ˆρ (s) = φ I a ˆρ ( ) tr φi a ˆρ = a a ˆρ a a tr( ˆρ a a ) = a a, (1.5)

6 6 CHAPTER 1. AN INTRODUCTION TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY where we introduce the operation φ I a depending on the result a. The operation φ I a is referred to as a super-operator or sometimes as a Liouville-type operator. Here we make explicit use of the first representation theorem of Kraus [11] which relates the operation to the effect. This theorem also specifies the conditions that must be satisfied by each of these constructions, and shows that any operation on a density operator can be written in terms of ordinary operators on Hilbert space. The partitioning of the ensemble is commonly referred to as the collapse of the wavefunction and simply constitutes a replacement of one wavefunction by another as a result of the additional information we have about the measurement outcome. The above measurement model based on the projection postulate [20] forms the simplest model for measurement outcomes. Upon the completion of the above measurement interaction where full account is taken of the readout value, any subsequent measurement performed immediately after the first will, if accurate, obtain the same eigenvalue (a), as a result. In this case, the measurement interaction is said to be a Type I measurement [19] as it does not destroy the state of the system just measured. In such a case we see that the post-measurement state is left in the eigenstate a even for perfect projective measurements. This is not always the case. For instance, photon detection destroys photons upon detection. A measurement interaction that destroys the state of the system is referred to as a Type II measurement interaction. We will have need to distinguish between these measurement interactions in this thesis. A Type II measurement might destroy an arbitrary state a to leave the state a, and so, in this example, is described by the post-measurement ensemble ˆρ (s) = φ II a ˆρ tr ( φii a ˆρ ) = a a ˆρ a a tr( ˆρ a a ) = a a, where again we employ the first representation theorem. In Type II interactions, subsequent measurements of the observable  will not reproduce the previous read out. However, a collapse of the wavefunction is still said to have occurred. The above description is of a selective operation where the information about the microscopic system is channelled to the macroscopic realm. The experimenter has information about the measurement outcome -(a). If on the other hand we take no account of the experimental result, and discard all information about the outcome of the experiment then we must describe a measurement interaction performing a non-selective operation. A channel still exists by which this information might be obtained, but we do not avail ourselves of this opportunity. Instead we choose to dissipate the information into the environment. Depending on the environment and the experimental set up being considered, this dissipation of the information might, or might not be irreversible. For example, we might dissipate photons into the environment, and thus perform a measurement interaction describing a nonselective operation, but there is nothing (in principle) preventing us from deploying a photo-detector several light (1.6)

7 1.2. A GUIDE TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY 7 years away to finally complete a delayed measurement interaction and thus complete a selective operation. In the case of an interaction describing a nonselective operation, the ensemble is not partitioned, and the new state of the ensemble contains all the members of the old ensemble. Under the new expanded state preparation procedure the state of the ensemble is given by (for Type I measurements) ˆρ (NS) = Φ (NS)ˆρ = a = a = a φ I aˆρ a a ˆρ a a P (a) a a, (1.7) where setting Φ (NS)ˆρ = φ a I aˆρ employs the second representation theorem due to Kraus [11]. The corresponding result for Type II measurements is ˆρ (NS) = a a (1.8) reflecting the fact that while we have no information about the outcome of the measurement, we do know that, for the example considered above, the measurement interaction destroyed the initial state and left the system in state a. The above postulates involve the use of projection operators to model effects (here for example a a ) and the corresponding collapse of the wavefunction, and are sufficient to model the outcomes of single, instantaneous, accurate measurement interactions. Predictions based on these postulates are very well confirmed by experiment. However, there are some immediately apparent drawbacks with the use of these postulates to describe measurements in quantum mechanics. The first of the drawbacks to the above approach is that it does not model the actual measurement interaction between the system and detector. We address the issue of modelling specific system-detector interactions in Chap. (3). A worse drawback is that this approach gives no criteria for distinguishing whether a particular interaction between two arbitrary systems constitutes a measurement interaction or not. When does an interaction between a system and an apparatus constitute a measurement, and when does it simply result in unitary evolution. We answer this question operationally and apply what is referred to as the Heisenberg cut in order to resolve the issue of just when our measurement device does enact a measurement and just when it interacts unitarily with the system of interest. The application of this procedure has been discussed in the preceding section Inaccurate measurement interactions A further drawback in the above approach is that the simple projection postulate a a cannot well describe either inaccurate measurement interactions or continuous measurement interactions. For example, consider position measurements of a free particle. The use of the projector x x to model accurate

8 8 CHAPTER 1. AN INTRODUCTION TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY position measurement outcomes gives the correct distribution for ˆx but predicts that the particle has acquired infinite energy from the instantaneous interaction with the measurement device. This is a result of the uncertainty relations between the observables ˆx and ˆp which establish that a zero uncertainty in position must reflect an infinite uncertainty in momentum. To describe such continuous measurements we must also have mechanisms for describing inaccurate measurement interactions. We now consider such mechanisms. Here we briefly generalize the simple projective measurement approach considered above to treat measurements of finite accuracy. (Again we follow the treatment of Refs. [11, 51, 17] in using the terminology of effects and operations.) To achieve our aims Eq. (1.4) must be generalized, and the approach we take is to explicitly recognise that typical measurement devices make inaccurate measurements. To model this, we parameterize the accuracy of the measurement effect device by some parameter σ. The outcome of the measurement is still taken to be some result a. The probability of obtaining the measurement result a is ( ) P σ (a) = tr ˆρˆF σ (a) = tr ( Υ σ (a)ˆρυ σ(a) ). (1.9) Here, ˆFσ (a) =Υ σ(a)υ σ (a) is a positive, bounded, self-adjoint operator on Hilbert space and is referred to as an effect. This is not the most general formulation of a measurement that could be made. This can be seen by noting that we have specified the effect ˆF σ (a) giving the outcome a. In reality, there might be many different operators Υ σ (a) that generate the same effect ˆF σ (a) and give the outcome a. We later discuss the generalizations required to take our ignorance of the specific operators used in the measurement interaction into account. The effect defined above can easily model both non-destructive [Type I] measurements and destructive [Type II] measurements. As an example of this we consider photon detection. This example will arise later in the thesis. To model a quantum nondemolition or non-destructive counting of photons (a Type I measurement) we choose [( ) ] 1/2 k ˆΓ σ (m) = σ m (1 σ) k m k b k. (1.10) m k=m In this equation it is evident that for σ 1, ˆΓ m m which gives the usual non-destructive projection operator. This equation has an obvious interpretation when we interpret σ, the accuracy of the measurement, as the probability of detecting a photon, and conversely, (1 σ) is the probability of not detecting a photon. For the case of destructive photon counting (a Type II measurement) we have [( ) ] 1/2 k ˆΓ σ (m) = σ m (1 σ) k m k m b k. (1.11) m k=m

9 1.2. A GUIDE TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY 9 Again for σ 1, we see that ˆΓ 0 m, the expected projection operator. In both cases the related effect is ˆF σ (m) = ˆΓ σ(m)ˆγ σ (m) ( ) k = σ m (1 σ) k m k b k. (1.12) m k=m Here, it is evident that the effect ˆF σ (m) does not depend whether the photon number measurement was destructive or not. If we were ignorant of which measurement interaction was being employed we would need to generalise our approach. This is discussed below. We further note in the above the general result I = a Υ σ(a)υ σ (a). (1.13) The First Representation theorem of Kraus [11] also shows that it is not only projection operators that can describe effects. As defined in the previous section, an effect can always be related to a super-operator φ σ (a) (referred to as an operation) which operates on the system density matrix to generate the post-measurement state - ˆρ (S) σ = φ σ (a)ˆρ tr( φ σ (a)ˆρ), where (1.14) φ σ (a)ˆρ =Υ σ (a)ˆρυ σ(a) (1.15) Here the ensemble has been partitioned on the results of the measurement - that is the operation φ σ (a) represents a measurement interaction treated selectively. We further note that the effect ˆF σ (a) does not uniquely determine the operation φ σ (a), and this reflects the fact that different effect apparatuses... need not perform the same operation [11]. The operation and the effect are related to each other and the probability P σ (a) of achieving the result a as ) ( ) P σ (a) =tr( φσ (a)ˆρ =tr ˆρˆF σ (a), (1.16) as can be seen from Eqs. (1.9) and (1.15). As noted, this relation is not one to one as there may be many operations for a given effect. What this means in real terms is that differing measurement devices may yield the same measurement statistics for a. This is further discussed below. Should a non-selective inaccurate operation have been performed, the post-measurement state generalizing Eq. (1.7) is ˆρ (NS) = a φ σ (a)ˆρ = φ σˆρ, (1.17) where φ σ = a φ σ (a) is the nonselective operation for the measurement.

10 10 CHAPTER 1. AN INTRODUCTION TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY We have previously noted that the effect ˆF σ (a) does not uniquely determine the operation φ σ (a), and have given examples of this above. If we are ignorant of the specific operation used in a measurement interaction, we must generalize our approach to consider a two parameter operation [7] φ σ (a, α)ˆρ =Υ σ (a, α)ˆρυ σ(a, α), (1.18) where α labels the various operations that can be used to generate an outcome a. In this case the effect is given by ˆF σ (a) = α Υ σ(a, α)υ σ (a, α). (1.19) The probability of getting the outcome a given ignorance of the specific measurement interaction is then as given above. The above is adequate to get us started on the measurement problem and we introduce further details as needed. 1.3 Quantum trajectories It has been recently asserted [132] that one of the interpretational failings of the Copenhagen interpretation is in the application of quantum mechanics to individual systems. In this thesis we will be modelling the evolution of individual systems a number of times, both when such systems are evolving freely, and when subject to either measurement or damping interactions. We briefly introduce the techniques for doing this now. We use the technique of quantum trajectories [29, 30, 31, 40, 36, 35] as another way of viewing nonunitary quantum dynamics which lies closer to our intuitive understanding of the experimental context. The operational definition of state vectors and density matrices introduced above, employed the concept of a state preparation procedure. This procedure created an ensemble of systems each possessing a certain state. This assumption could always be tested through the use of effect apparatuses to evaluate reproducible measurement outcomes. Recently developed techniques in quantum mechanics make it routine to perform measurements on well defined single quantum systems. The question then arises as to how we apply the above formulation to follow the evolution of a single system subject to some evolution process. This process could be either the usual unitary evolution, a measurement interaction, or a general nonunitary evolution. The method employed is similar to that introduced above. We take a single quantum system that has been through some state preparation step. The state of the system can then be interpreted as above as representing a collection of systems, all of which have been through the same procedure. We then wish to follow the evolution of the system, and note that this evolution might be any, or all, of the three types described above. However, each is treated in an equivalent way, and is represented by a further state preparation step. This evolution step takes one

11 1.3. QUANTUM TRAJECTORIES 11 density matrix to another, and as defined above, is represented by an operation. In other words, to evolve the system forward in time we apply an operation representing any of the three possibilities introduced above as desired. By this means we can evolve the quantum system forward in time under any sort of desired evolution. The new feature of the quantum trajectories approach is to allow the path of the evolution of the system to be determined at each infinitesimal time step, by the properties of the system at that time step. It is this feature that permits us deep insight into the evolution of quantum systems. It is routine to evolve a system forward in time through the use of an operation, and this has been done ever since the evolution operator was introduced as part of the solution to the Schrödinger equation (1.2). However, if we put in these operations by hand, then we constrain the evolution of the system to fit with our conceptions, rather than allowing the evolution of the system to frame our conceptions. A better way is to define the initial state of the system, and as many operations as are required to specify all the possible evolutions that the system might undergo. We also need a scheme to evaluate at any time what the system is likely to do. We combine these elements, in forming a quantum trajectory for the evolution of the system. The trajectory is broken into (generally) infinitesimal time steps, and the probability of each of the operations being performed is evaluated based on the state of the system at that time. We can then employ a random number generator to evaluate which of the relevant operations is to be enacted at any particular time. This decision can be determined solely by the state of the system (if so desired). We apply the chosen operation, and repeat the procedure. This is the essence of the quantum trajectories approach. The form of the trajectories can be counterintuitive to physicists trained from birth in using nonselective master equation methods, but it is precisely this feature that makes this method so valuable in generating insight. Indeed, H.Carmichael has intimated that he foresees a time when quantum mechanics is initially taught using the quantum trajectories approach, and is only later generalized to consider the usual master equations. The above has been a brief summary of the philosophy underlying the technique of quantum trajectories. In what follows we go into detail sufficient for the needs of this thesis. We follow the formalism developed by Srinivas and Davies [32, 33, 34, 38] who (I believe) developed the formal solution of the master equation shown below. Our main motivation comes from contact with Carmichael who freely made available his lecture notes on this topic [30, 29] and who focussed on the quantum dynamics of the system, as opposed to the view emphasised by Srinivas and Davies which treated the interaction between the radiation field and a photo-detector (for instance). A useful guide to the use of these techniques to model photon detection is given in Milburn and Walls [91]. A similar approach is also nicely covered in later work by Ueda [39]. The literature in this field is extensive due to wide applicability of the insights offered. Recent work includes Refs. [31, 40, 36, 35]. We will develop this approach in various forms in this thesis as required, and introduce further references in later sections. Following Carmichael s emphasis on unravelling master equations, we consider a generic master

12 12 CHAPTER 1. AN INTRODUCTION TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY equation of the form ˆρ(t) =(L+J)ˆρ(t), (1.20) where L and J are super-operators equivalent to the operations introduced above. These operators can be chosen to represent any one of either free system evolution, the evolution of a damped system (in the Markoff approximation), or of measurement effected system dynamics. As we are interested in the dynamics of the system, we do not explicitly model the detector, or the environment under the Markoff approximation. An example that will come up in this thesis is the detection of photons emitted from a cavity mode of the electromagnetic field. In this case we would treat the environment as being configured as a detector, and every photon emitted from the system is collected and measured (counted) by the photodetector. (As usual the experimenter has the choice of either discarding the results of the readout or not.) To model such photon detection we would set Lˆρ(t) = ī h [Ĥ, ˆρ] R 2 ˆρ ˆρR 2 R = γa a J ˆρ(t) = γaˆρa, (1.21) where γ is a damping rate of the cavity into the field. In this equation the value of R is chosen to satisfy tr(rˆρ) = tr(j ˆρ). (1.22) It is straight forward to show by substitution that these assignments generate a master equation of the usual form for a damped cavity, namely ˆρ = ī h [Ĥ, ˆρ]+γ ( 2aˆρa a aˆρ ˆρa a ). (1.23) 2 As is usual in this approach, the operation J models the detection of a photon coming from the cavity. If we detect a photon then we can use the techniques of the previous section to calculate the new state of the cavity field. The detection of a photon represents a new state preparation step acting on the state of the cavity, and this preparation step is described by the operation J. This is seen through the effect of J on the number state [91] J n n = nγ n 1 n 1. (1.24) To interpret the operation L it is useful to consider the new operation e Lt ˆρ = e it h Rt it Rt Ĥ 2 ˆρe h Ĥ 2. (1.25) It is then possible to show that this operation does not change the state of the system, and is proportional to the probability of not detecting any photons in a time t. This can be seen through the application of this state to a number state [91] giving e Lt n n = e γnt n n. (1.26)

13 1.3. QUANTUM TRAJECTORIES 13 We are now equipped to write the formal solution to the master equation (1.20) as ˆρ(t) = e (L+J )tˆρ(0) t tm = dt m m=0 0 0 t2 dt m 1 dt m1 e L(t tm) J Je L(t2 t1) Je Lt1ˆρ 0. (1.27) 0 We note that with the above interpretations of these operations we can interpret this expansion as a sum over many possible histories of photon emission events from the cavity. Eq. (1.27) is the general solution to the non-selective master equation and thus describes the case where the experimenter has discarded all information deriving from the detector. This discarding of information can be seen in this equation as the sum over m, all possible detection events, and the multiple integrals over all possible detection times t m. An experimenter is always able to keep this information, if so desired, and if this information is retained for a particular system, then we can specify the selective state of the system at time t, given the emission of m photons at times t 1 t 2 t m t,as ˆρ(m, t, t 1,,t m ) = P 1 (m, t, t 1,,t m ) e L(t tm) J Je L(t2 t1) Je Lt1ˆρ 0 P(m, t, t 1,,t m ) = tr [e L(t tm) Je L(tm tm 1) J Je L(t2 t1) Je Lt1ˆρ ] 0. (1.28) This expansion can be understood in terms of the state preparation procedures introduced in the previous sections. We are observing a single system, and have perfect information about all detection events originating in that system. This history allows us to apply the required state preparing operations to exactly model the state of the system at any time. By doing this we describe the evolution of a single system, the state of which is conditioned on the entire history of measurement results. If all the information lost from the system is recorded it is possible to represent this path as a stochastic evolution of pure states and this has significant calculational advantages as discussed below. We can then model the behaviour of an ensemble of systems from the sum of T independently generated trajectories. The sum over trajectories is equivalent to discarding all information about the history of measurement results. We illustrate this later in this thesis when we compare such a sum over trajectories to the non-selective evolution calculated from the usual master equation. The algorithms for doing this have been sketched in broad strokes above, and involve a calculation at each infinitesimal time step of the likely next event in the evolution of the system. We allow the state of the system at any time to specify the probabilities that a photon will be emitted, and employ a random number generator to decide this issue. This process calculates a stochastic conditioned trajectory for the individual system. Each history is itself a random event and we can then talk about stochastic paths of states. This equation describes the trajectory of the system at any time given the observations of m, t 1,,t m. In generating a particular quantum trajectory we do the reverse. We generate the m, t 1,,t m trajectory with probability P (m, t, t 1,,t m ). We take the minimum resolution time of the photon detection apparatus to be τ. In this time, the apparatus can distinguish between the detection

14 14 CHAPTER 1. AN INTRODUCTION TO QUANTUM MEASUREMENT THEORY of m = 0 photons or m>0photons, but can t distinguish between m = 1 and m = 2 photons, for example. The probability for detection of m = 0orm > 0 photons is P (m =0,τ) = P(0,τ) P(m>0,τ) = 1 P(0,τ), (1.29) where P (0,τ) is calculated from Eq. (1.28). After any resolution time τ, we decide whether the system has emitted a photon or not, with the probabilities given above. There are a number of advantages to this approach. We gain special insight into quantum systems when we follow the selective evolution of a single system as opposed to the averaged, non-selective evolution of an ensemble. There can be a computational advantage for systems with large numbers of levels [29]. In our case, the action of both L and J on ˆρ is to take pure states to pure states so we can model the state of the system as a vector, rather than having to use the density matrix. The computation of a trajectory is simplified further by noting that often, the detection of a photon collapses the system to a known initial state, and every time this happens, the subsequent evolution away from the initial state follows an identical path. Every trajectory can be easily generated from the trajectory that has no emission of photons. [We give an explicit example of this in Chap. (5)] Also we can recover the non-selective evolution trajectory by summing over a large number of trajectories. Finally we note that the non-selective evolution can be obtained directly by treating the non-selective density matrix as a special case of a mixed state and iterating its trajectory as a mixed state density matrix. To generate the non-selective evolution we simply discard all information about the emission or non-emission of photons at every step. This requires the addition of the no-emission density matrix and the one-photon-emission density matrix with corresponding probabilities at every step.

Stochastic Histories. Chapter Introduction

Stochastic Histories. Chapter Introduction Chapter 8 Stochastic Histories 8.1 Introduction Despite the fact that classical mechanics employs deterministic dynamical laws, random dynamical processes often arise in classical physics, as well as in

More information

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) 1. The Copenhagen Interpretation Bohr interpreted quantum theory as showing that there is a fundamental partition in nature, between the microphysical

More information

Delayed Choice Paradox

Delayed Choice Paradox Chapter 20 Delayed Choice Paradox 20.1 Statement of the Paradox Consider the Mach-Zehnder interferometer shown in Fig. 20.1. The second beam splitter can either be at its regular position B in where the

More information

Lecture 13B: Supplementary Notes on Advanced Topics. 1 Inner Products and Outer Products for Single Particle States

Lecture 13B: Supplementary Notes on Advanced Topics. 1 Inner Products and Outer Products for Single Particle States Lecture 13B: Supplementary Notes on Advanced Topics Outer Products, Operators, Density Matrices In order to explore the complexity of many particle systems a different way to represent multiparticle states

More information

CONTROLLABILITY OF QUANTUM SYSTEMS. Sonia G. Schirmer

CONTROLLABILITY OF QUANTUM SYSTEMS. Sonia G. Schirmer CONTROLLABILITY OF QUANTUM SYSTEMS Sonia G. Schirmer Dept of Applied Mathematics + Theoretical Physics and Dept of Engineering, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, CB2 1PZ, United Kingdom Ivan C. H. Pullen

More information

Quantum Measurements: some technical background

Quantum Measurements: some technical background Quantum Measurements: some technical background [From the projection postulate to density matrices & (introduction to) von Neumann measurements] (AKA: the boring lecture) First: One more example I wanted

More information

A Simple Model of Quantum Trajectories. Todd A. Brun University of Southern California

A Simple Model of Quantum Trajectories. Todd A. Brun University of Southern California A Simple Model of Quantum Trajectories Todd A. Brun University of Southern California Outline 1. Review projective and generalized measurements. 2. A simple model of indirect measurement. 3. Weak measurements--jump-like

More information

1 Mathematical preliminaries

1 Mathematical preliminaries 1 Mathematical preliminaries The mathematical language of quantum mechanics is that of vector spaces and linear algebra. In this preliminary section, we will collect the various definitions and mathematical

More information

09a. Collapse. Recall: There are two ways a quantum state can change: 1. In absence of measurement, states change via Schrödinger dynamics:

09a. Collapse. Recall: There are two ways a quantum state can change: 1. In absence of measurement, states change via Schrödinger dynamics: 09a. Collapse Recall: There are two ways a quantum state can change:. In absence of measurement, states change via Schrödinger dynamics: ψ(t )!!! ψ(t 2 ) Schrödinger evolution 2. In presence of measurement,

More information

Decoherence and the Classical Limit

Decoherence and the Classical Limit Chapter 26 Decoherence and the Classical Limit 26.1 Introduction Classical mechanics deals with objects which have a precise location and move in a deterministic way as a function of time. By contrast,

More information

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds 236 My God, He Plays Dice! Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds Many Worlds 237 Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds Hugh Everett III was one of John Wheeler s most famous graduate students. Others included Richard

More information

Introduction to Quantum Mechanics

Introduction to Quantum Mechanics Introduction to Quantum Mechanics R. J. Renka Department of Computer Science & Engineering University of North Texas 03/19/2018 Postulates of Quantum Mechanics The postulates (axioms) of quantum mechanics

More information

Quantum mechanics in one hour

Quantum mechanics in one hour Chapter 2 Quantum mechanics in one hour 2.1 Introduction The purpose of this chapter is to refresh your knowledge of quantum mechanics and to establish notation. Depending on your background you might

More information

Dynamical Collapse in Quantum Theory

Dynamical Collapse in Quantum Theory Dynamical Collapse in Quantum Theory Lajos Diósi HAS Wigner Research Center for Physics Budapest August 2, 2012 Dynamical Collapse in Quantum Theory August 2, 2012 1 / 28 Outline 1 Statistical Interpretation:

More information

Quantum decoherence. Éric Oliver Paquette (U. Montréal) -Traces Worshop [Ottawa]- April 29 th, Quantum decoherence p. 1/2

Quantum decoherence. Éric Oliver Paquette (U. Montréal) -Traces Worshop [Ottawa]- April 29 th, Quantum decoherence p. 1/2 Quantum decoherence p. 1/2 Quantum decoherence Éric Oliver Paquette (U. Montréal) -Traces Worshop [Ottawa]- April 29 th, 2007 Quantum decoherence p. 2/2 Outline Quantum decoherence: 1. Basics of quantum

More information

Continuous quantum states, Particle on a line and Uncertainty relations

Continuous quantum states, Particle on a line and Uncertainty relations Continuous quantum states, Particle on a line and Uncertainty relations So far we have considered k-level (discrete) quantum systems. Now we turn our attention to continuous quantum systems, such as a

More information

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history Some remarks on the measurement problem in quantum theory (Davide Romano) 1. An introduction to the quantum formalism

More information

ECE 487 Lecture 6 : Time-Dependent Quantum Mechanics I Class Outline:

ECE 487 Lecture 6 : Time-Dependent Quantum Mechanics I Class Outline: ECE 487 Lecture 6 : Time-Dependent Quantum Mechanics I Class Outline: Time-Dependent Schrödinger Equation Solutions to thetime-dependent Schrödinger Equation Expansion of Energy Eigenstates Things you

More information

The Born Rule. Chapter Classical Random Walk

The Born Rule. Chapter Classical Random Walk Chapter 9 The Born Rule 9.1 Classical Random Walk The previous chapter showed how to construct sample spaces of histories for both classical and quantum systems. Now we shall see how to use dynamical laws

More information

Coins and Counterfactuals

Coins and Counterfactuals Chapter 19 Coins and Counterfactuals 19.1 Quantum Paradoxes The next few chapters are devoted to resolving a number of quantum paradoxes in the sense of giving a reasonable explanation of a seemingly paradoxical

More information

Page 684. Lecture 40: Coordinate Transformations: Time Transformations Date Revised: 2009/02/02 Date Given: 2009/02/02

Page 684. Lecture 40: Coordinate Transformations: Time Transformations Date Revised: 2009/02/02 Date Given: 2009/02/02 Page 684 Lecture 40: Coordinate Transformations: Time Transformations Date Revised: 2009/02/02 Date Given: 2009/02/02 Time Transformations Section 12.5 Symmetries: Time Transformations Page 685 Time Translation

More information

Quantum control of dissipative systems. 1 Density operators and mixed quantum states

Quantum control of dissipative systems. 1 Density operators and mixed quantum states Quantum control of dissipative systems S. G. Schirmer and A. I. Solomon Quantum Processes Group, The Open University Milton Keynes, MK7 6AA, United Kingdom S.G.Schirmer@open.ac.uk, A.I.Solomon@open.ac.uk

More information

The hybrid-epistemic model of quantum mechanics and the solution to the measurement problem

The hybrid-epistemic model of quantum mechanics and the solution to the measurement problem The hybrid-epistemic model of quantum mechanics and the solution to the measurement problem Jiří Souček Charles University in Prague, Faculty of Arts U Kříže 8, Prague 5, 158 00, Czech Republic jiri.soucek@ff.cuni.cz

More information

The Measurement Problem

The Measurement Problem The Measurement Problem Johannes Kofler Quantum Foundations Seminar Max Planck Institute of Quantum Optics Munich, December 12 th 2011 The measurement problem Different aspects: How does the wavefunction

More information

Lectures 1 and 2: Axioms for Quantum Theory

Lectures 1 and 2: Axioms for Quantum Theory Lectures 1 and 2: Axioms for Quantum Theory Joseph Emerson Course: AMATH 900/AMATH 495/PHYS 490 Foundations and Interpretations of Quantum Theory Course Instructors: Joseph Emerson and Ray Laflamme Hosted

More information

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION: QUANTUM PHILOSOPHY PCES 4.41 Perhaps the most difficult things to understand about QM are (i) how to reconcile our common sense ideas about physical reality with phenomena such as entanglement, & (ii)

More information

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Incompatibility Paradoxes Chapter 22 Incompatibility Paradoxes 22.1 Simultaneous Values There is never any difficulty in supposing that a classical mechanical system possesses, at a particular instant of time, precise values of

More information

arxiv: v2 [hep-th] 7 Apr 2015

arxiv: v2 [hep-th] 7 Apr 2015 Statistical Mechanics Derived From Quantum Mechanics arxiv:1501.05402v2 [hep-th] 7 Apr 2015 Yu-Lei Feng 1 and Yi-Xin Chen 1 1 Zhejiang Institute of Modern Physics, Zhejiang University, Hangzhou 310027,

More information

Review of the Formalism of Quantum Mechanics

Review of the Formalism of Quantum Mechanics Review of the Formalism of Quantum Mechanics The postulates of quantum mechanics are often stated in textbooks. There are two main properties of physics upon which these postulates are based: 1)the probability

More information

2 The Density Operator

2 The Density Operator In this chapter we introduce the density operator, which provides an alternative way to describe the state of a quantum mechanical system. So far we have only dealt with situations where the state of a

More information

Lecture 2: Open quantum systems

Lecture 2: Open quantum systems Phys 769 Selected Topics in Condensed Matter Physics Summer 21 Lecture 2: Open quantum systems Lecturer: Anthony J. Leggett TA: Bill Coish 1. No (micro- or macro-) system is ever truly isolated U = S +

More information

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy Significant content from: Quantum Mechanics and Experience by David Z. Albert, Harvard University Press (1992). Main Concepts: -- complementarity -- the

More information

From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity. Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL

From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity. Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL The Measurement Problem in Quantum Mechanics (1) The wave-function of a system is complete,

More information

Singlet State Correlations

Singlet State Correlations Chapter 23 Singlet State Correlations 23.1 Introduction This and the following chapter can be thought of as a single unit devoted to discussing various issues raised by a famous paper published by Einstein,

More information

De-coherence and transition from Quantum to Classical

De-coherence and transition from Quantum to Classical De-coherence and transition from Quantum to Classical Ravi Mohan Indian Institute of Technology Roorkee March 22, 2013 Outline 1 Introduction 2 Correlations and Measurements 3 Missing Information and Decoherence

More information

PHY305: Notes on Entanglement and the Density Matrix

PHY305: Notes on Entanglement and the Density Matrix PHY305: Notes on Entanglement and the Density Matrix Here follows a short summary of the definitions of qubits, EPR states, entanglement, the density matrix, pure states, mixed states, measurement, and

More information

Consistent Histories. Chapter Chain Operators and Weights

Consistent Histories. Chapter Chain Operators and Weights Chapter 10 Consistent Histories 10.1 Chain Operators and Weights The previous chapter showed how the Born rule can be used to assign probabilities to a sample space of histories based upon an initial state

More information

Coherent states, beam splitters and photons

Coherent states, beam splitters and photons Coherent states, beam splitters and photons S.J. van Enk 1. Each mode of the electromagnetic (radiation) field with frequency ω is described mathematically by a 1D harmonic oscillator with frequency ω.

More information

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics Steve Hsu Benasque, September 2010 Outline 1. No Collapse quantum mechanics 2. Does the Born rule (probabilities) emerge? 3. Possible resolutions R. Buniy,

More information

1 Traces, Traces Everywhere (5 points)

1 Traces, Traces Everywhere (5 points) Ph15c Spring 017 Prof. Sean Carroll seancarroll@gmail.com Homework - Solutions Assigned TA: Ashmeet Singh ashmeet@caltech.edu 1 Traces, Traces Everywhere (5 points) (a.) Okay, so the time evolved state

More information

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM Michele Caponigro ISHTAR, Bergamo University Abstract From conceptual point of view, we argue about the nature of reality inferred from EPR

More information

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction Chapter 25 Hardy s Paradox 25.1 Introduction Hardy s paradox resembles the Bohm version of the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox, discussed in Chs. 23 and 24, in that it involves two correlated particles,

More information

C/CS/Phys C191 Particle-in-a-box, Spin 10/02/08 Fall 2008 Lecture 11

C/CS/Phys C191 Particle-in-a-box, Spin 10/02/08 Fall 2008 Lecture 11 C/CS/Phys C191 Particle-in-a-box, Spin 10/0/08 Fall 008 Lecture 11 Last time we saw that the time dependent Schr. eqn. can be decomposed into two equations, one in time (t) and one in space (x): space

More information

Quantum measurement theory

Quantum measurement theory 1 Quantum measurement theory 1.1 Classical measurement theory 1.1.1 Basic concepts Although this chapter, and indeed this book, is concerned with quantum measurements, we begin with a discussion of some

More information

Introduction to Quantum Computing

Introduction to Quantum Computing Introduction to Quantum Computing Petros Wallden Lecture 3: Basic Quantum Mechanics 26th September 2016 School of Informatics, University of Edinburgh Resources 1. Quantum Computation and Quantum Information

More information

arxiv: v4 [quant-ph] 26 Oct 2017

arxiv: v4 [quant-ph] 26 Oct 2017 Hidden Variable Theory of a Single World from Many-Worlds Quantum Mechanics Don Weingarten donweingarten@hotmail.com We propose a method for finding an initial state vector which by ordinary Hamiltonian

More information

Density Matrices. Chapter Introduction

Density Matrices. Chapter Introduction Chapter 15 Density Matrices 15.1 Introduction Density matrices are employed in quantum mechanics to give a partial description of a quantum system, one from which certain details have been omitted. For

More information

The quantum state as a vector

The quantum state as a vector The quantum state as a vector February 6, 27 Wave mechanics In our review of the development of wave mechanics, we have established several basic properties of the quantum description of nature:. A particle

More information

Statistical Mechanics

Statistical Mechanics 42 My God, He Plays Dice! Statistical Mechanics Statistical Mechanics 43 Statistical Mechanics Statistical mechanics and thermodynamics are nineteenthcentury classical physics, but they contain the seeds

More information

Ensembles and incomplete information

Ensembles and incomplete information p. 1/32 Ensembles and incomplete information So far in this course, we have described quantum systems by states that are normalized vectors in a complex Hilbert space. This works so long as (a) the system

More information

PLEASE LET ME KNOW IF YOU FIND TYPOS (send to

PLEASE LET ME KNOW IF YOU FIND TYPOS (send  to Teoretisk Fysik KTH Advanced QM (SI2380), Lecture 2 (Summary of concepts) 1 PLEASE LET ME KNOW IF YOU FIND TYPOS (send email to langmann@kth.se) The laws of QM 1. I now discuss the laws of QM and their

More information

Vector Spaces in Quantum Mechanics

Vector Spaces in Quantum Mechanics Chapter 8 Vector Spaces in Quantum Mechanics We have seen in the previous Chapter that there is a sense in which the state of a quantum system can be thought of as being made up of other possible states.

More information

The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being

The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Beings Department of Mathematics 21 February 2011 Supported by NSF Quantum mechanics is very successful in computing quantities than can

More information

The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics

The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics p. 1/23 The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics We have reviewed the mathematics (complex linear algebra) necessary to understand quantum mechanics. We will now see how the physics of quantum mechanics fits

More information

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem PHYS419 Lecture 0 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem 1 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem As first shown by Bell (1964), the force of the arguments

More information

Einselection of Pointer Observables: The New H-Theorem?

Einselection of Pointer Observables: The New H-Theorem? Einselection of Pointer Observables: The New H-Theorem? Ruth E. Kastner 16 June 2014 to appear in Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics ABSTRACT. In attempting to derive irreversible macroscopic

More information

Why quantum field theory?

Why quantum field theory? Why quantum field theory? It is often said that quantum field theory is the natural marriage of Einstein s special theory of relativity and the quantum theory. The point of this section will be to motivate

More information

228 My God - He Plays Dice! Schrödinger s Cat. Chapter 28. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/scrodingerscat

228 My God - He Plays Dice! Schrödinger s Cat. Chapter 28. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/scrodingerscat 228 My God - He Plays Dice! Schrödinger s Cat This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/scrodingerscat Schrödinger s Cat Schrödinger s Cat Erwin Schrödinger s goal for his infamous cat-killing

More information

Bohmian Quantum Mechanics and the Finite Square Potential Barrier

Bohmian Quantum Mechanics and the Finite Square Potential Barrier Bohmian Quantum Mechanics and the Finite Square Potential Barrier Matthew Gorski Physics Department, The College of Wooster, Wooster, Ohio 44691, USA (Dated: May 6, 2008) This project studies Bohmian quantum

More information

PHY413 Quantum Mechanics B Duration: 2 hours 30 minutes

PHY413 Quantum Mechanics B Duration: 2 hours 30 minutes BSc/MSci Examination by Course Unit Thursday nd May 4 : - :3 PHY43 Quantum Mechanics B Duration: hours 3 minutes YOU ARE NOT PERMITTED TO READ THE CONTENTS OF THIS QUESTION PAPER UNTIL INSTRUCTED TO DO

More information

PHYS 508 (2015-1) Final Exam January 27, Wednesday.

PHYS 508 (2015-1) Final Exam January 27, Wednesday. PHYS 508 (2015-1) Final Exam January 27, Wednesday. Q1. Scattering with identical particles The quantum statistics have some interesting consequences for the scattering of identical particles. This is

More information

Lecture 4: Postulates of quantum mechanics

Lecture 4: Postulates of quantum mechanics Lecture 4: Postulates of quantum mechanics Rajat Mittal IIT Kanpur The postulates of quantum mechanics provide us the mathematical formalism over which the physical theory is developed. For people studying

More information

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem PHYS419 Lecture 0 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem 1 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem As first shown by Bell (1964), the force of the arguments

More information

Many Body Quantum Mechanics

Many Body Quantum Mechanics Many Body Quantum Mechanics In this section, we set up the many body formalism for quantum systems. This is useful in any problem involving identical particles. For example, it automatically takes care

More information

Does Quantum Measurement Violate the Conservation of Angular Momentum? A Paradox Resolved Rick Bradford, 6/12/16

Does Quantum Measurement Violate the Conservation of Angular Momentum? A Paradox Resolved Rick Bradford, 6/12/16 Does Quantum Measurement Violate the Conservation of Angular Momentum? A Parado Resolved Rick Bradford, 6//6 Presented here is a parado which took some considerable effort to resolve - and I don't think

More information

84 My God, He Plays Dice! Chapter 12. Irreversibility. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/reversibility

84 My God, He Plays Dice! Chapter 12. Irreversibility. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/reversibility 84 My God, He Plays Dice! This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/reversibility Microscopic In the 1870 s, Ludwig Boltzmann developed his transport equation and his dynamical H-theorem

More information

The quantum measurement paradox: The orthodox solution

The quantum measurement paradox: The orthodox solution PHYS419 Lecture 21 The quantum measurement paradox: Orthodox solution 1 The quantum measurement paradox: The orthodox solution In 1974, the physicist-philosopher Bernard d Espagnat introduced a discussion

More information

Decoherence and The Collapse of Quantum Mechanics. A Modern View

Decoherence and The Collapse of Quantum Mechanics. A Modern View Decoherence and The Collapse of Quantum Mechanics A Modern View It s time to make decoherence mainstream QM is ~90 years old But it is still taught like the 1930s Modern textbooks still ignore measurement

More information

3. Quantum Mechanics in 3D

3. Quantum Mechanics in 3D 3. Quantum Mechanics in 3D 3.1 Introduction Last time, we derived the time dependent Schrödinger equation, starting from three basic postulates: 1) The time evolution of a state can be expressed as a unitary

More information

Checking Consistency. Chapter Introduction Support of a Consistent Family

Checking Consistency. Chapter Introduction Support of a Consistent Family Chapter 11 Checking Consistency 11.1 Introduction The conditions which define a consistent family of histories were stated in Ch. 10. The sample space must consist of a collection of mutually orthogonal

More information

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities Chapter 24 EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities 24.1 Bohm Version of the EPR Paradox Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen (EPR) were concerned with the following issue. Given two spatially separated quantum systems

More information

Electron in a Box. A wave packet in a square well (an electron in a box) changing with time.

Electron in a Box. A wave packet in a square well (an electron in a box) changing with time. Electron in a Box A wave packet in a square well (an electron in a box) changing with time. Last Time: Light Wave model: Interference pattern is in terms of wave intensity Photon model: Interference in

More information

Quantum Mechanics I Physics 5701

Quantum Mechanics I Physics 5701 Quantum Mechanics I Physics 5701 Z. E. Meziani 02/23//2017 Physics 5701 Lecture Outline 1 General Formulation of Quantum Mechanics 2 Measurement of physical quantities and observables 3 Representations

More information

Lecture 4. QUANTUM MECHANICS FOR MULTIPLE QUBIT SYSTEMS

Lecture 4. QUANTUM MECHANICS FOR MULTIPLE QUBIT SYSTEMS Lecture 4. QUANTUM MECHANICS FOR MULTIPLE QUBIT SYSTEMS 4.1 Multiple Qubits Next we consider a system of two qubits. If these were two classical bits, then there would be four possible states,, 1, 1, and

More information

Theoretical Biophysics. Quantum Theory and Molecular Dynamics. Pawel Romanczuk WS 2017/18

Theoretical Biophysics. Quantum Theory and Molecular Dynamics. Pawel Romanczuk WS 2017/18 Theoretical Biophysics Quantum Theory and Molecular Dynamics Pawel Romanczuk WS 2017/18 http://lab.romanczuk.de/teaching/ 1 Introduction Two pillars of classical theoretical physics at the begin of 20th

More information

1 Fundamental physical postulates. C/CS/Phys C191 Quantum Mechanics in a Nutshell I 10/04/07 Fall 2007 Lecture 12

1 Fundamental physical postulates. C/CS/Phys C191 Quantum Mechanics in a Nutshell I 10/04/07 Fall 2007 Lecture 12 C/CS/Phys C191 Quantum Mechanics in a Nutshell I 10/04/07 Fall 2007 Lecture 12 In this and the next lecture we summarize the essential physical and mathematical aspects of quantum mechanics relevant to

More information

OPERATORS AND MEASUREMENT

OPERATORS AND MEASUREMENT Chapter OPERATORS AND MEASUREMENT In Chapter we used the results of experiments to deduce a mathematical description of the spin-/ system. The Stern-Gerlach experiments demonstrated that spin component

More information

Lecture notes 1. Standard physics vs. new physics. 1.1 The final state boundary condition

Lecture notes 1. Standard physics vs. new physics. 1.1 The final state boundary condition Lecture notes 1 Standard physics vs. new physics The black hole information paradox has challenged our fundamental beliefs about spacetime and quantum theory. Which belief will have to change to resolve

More information

Lecture 12. The harmonic oscillator

Lecture 12. The harmonic oscillator Lecture 12 The harmonic oscillator 107 108 LECTURE 12. THE HARMONIC OSCILLATOR 12.1 Introduction In this chapter, we are going to find explicitly the eigenfunctions and eigenvalues for the time-independent

More information

arxiv:quant-ph/ v3 25 Jan 2002

arxiv:quant-ph/ v3 25 Jan 2002 Relational Reality in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics Rodolfo Gambini 1 Rafael A. Porto 1 1. Instituto de Física, Facultad de Ciencias, Iguá 4225, esq. Mataojo, Montevideo, Uruguay. (May 20th 2001) Up to

More information

MAKING BOHMIAN MECHANICS COMPATIBLE WITH RELATIVITY AND QUANTUM FIELD THEORY. Hrvoje Nikolić Rudjer Bošković Institute, Zagreb, Croatia

MAKING BOHMIAN MECHANICS COMPATIBLE WITH RELATIVITY AND QUANTUM FIELD THEORY. Hrvoje Nikolić Rudjer Bošković Institute, Zagreb, Croatia MAKING BOHMIAN MECHANICS COMPATIBLE WITH RELATIVITY AND QUANTUM FIELD THEORY Hrvoje Nikolić Rudjer Bošković Institute, Zagreb, Croatia Vallico Sotto, Italy, 28th August - 4th September 2010 1 Outline:

More information

Recitation 1 (Sep. 15, 2017)

Recitation 1 (Sep. 15, 2017) Lecture 1 8.321 Quantum Theory I, Fall 2017 1 Recitation 1 (Sep. 15, 2017) 1.1 Simultaneous Diagonalization In the last lecture, we discussed the situations in which two operators can be simultaneously

More information

MP463 QUANTUM MECHANICS

MP463 QUANTUM MECHANICS MP463 QUANTUM MECHANICS Introduction Quantum theory of angular momentum Quantum theory of a particle in a central potential - Hydrogen atom - Three-dimensional isotropic harmonic oscillator (a model of

More information

Quantum Mechanics- I Prof. Dr. S. Lakshmi Bala Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Quantum Mechanics- I Prof. Dr. S. Lakshmi Bala Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Quantum Mechanics- I Prof. Dr. S. Lakshmi Bala Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Lecture - 6 Postulates of Quantum Mechanics II (Refer Slide Time: 00:07) In my last lecture,

More information

The 3 dimensional Schrödinger Equation

The 3 dimensional Schrödinger Equation Chapter 6 The 3 dimensional Schrödinger Equation 6.1 Angular Momentum To study how angular momentum is represented in quantum mechanics we start by reviewing the classical vector of orbital angular momentum

More information

Stochastic Processes

Stochastic Processes qmc082.tex. Version of 30 September 2010. Lecture Notes on Quantum Mechanics No. 8 R. B. Griffiths References: Stochastic Processes CQT = R. B. Griffiths, Consistent Quantum Theory (Cambridge, 2002) DeGroot

More information

Quantum Mechanics- I Prof. Dr. S. Lakshmi Bala Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Quantum Mechanics- I Prof. Dr. S. Lakshmi Bala Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Quantum Mechanics- I Prof. Dr. S. Lakshmi Bala Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Lecture - 4 Postulates of Quantum Mechanics I In today s lecture I will essentially be talking

More information

Macroscopic Quantum Mechanics and the SoSE Design Approach

Macroscopic Quantum Mechanics and the SoSE Design Approach Indo-US Workshop on System of Systems Engineering -2009 Oct 26-28, 2009 IIT-Kanpur Macroscopic Quantum Mechanics and the SoSE Design Approach Ravi V. Gomatam Institute for Semantic Information Sciences

More information

NANOSCALE SCIENCE & TECHNOLOGY

NANOSCALE SCIENCE & TECHNOLOGY . NANOSCALE SCIENCE & TECHNOLOGY V Two-Level Quantum Systems (Qubits) Lecture notes 5 5. Qubit description Quantum bit (qubit) is an elementary unit of a quantum computer. Similar to classical computers,

More information

Can Everettian Interpretation Survive Continuous Spectrum?

Can Everettian Interpretation Survive Continuous Spectrum? Can Everettian Interpretation Survive Continuous Spectrum? Bryce M. Kim 2016/02/21 Abstract This paper raises a simple continuous spectrum issue in many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics, or Everettian

More information

PHYS-454 The position and momentum representations

PHYS-454 The position and momentum representations PHYS-454 The position and momentum representations 1 Τhe continuous spectrum-a n So far we have seen problems where the involved operators have a discrete spectrum of eigenfunctions and eigenvalues.! n

More information

Quantum Mechanics I Physics 5701

Quantum Mechanics I Physics 5701 Quantum Mechanics I Physics 5701 Z. E. Meziani 02/24//2017 Physics 5701 Lecture Commutation of Observables and First Consequences of the Postulates Outline 1 Commutation Relations 2 Uncertainty Relations

More information

Time evolution of states in quantum mechanics 1

Time evolution of states in quantum mechanics 1 Time evolution of states in quantum mechanics 1 The time evolution from time t 0 to t of a quantum mechanical state is described by a linear operator Û(t, t 0. Thus a ket at time t that started out at

More information

Decoherence and the quantum-to-classical transition

Decoherence and the quantum-to-classical transition Decoherence and the quantum-to-classical transition A project report submitted in partial fulfillment for the award of the degree of Master of Science in Physics by Mohammad Asif Azad under the guidance

More information

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014 Evidence and Theory in Physics Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014 Two Features of Physics Physics displays two interesting features: 1) Programmatically, it aspires to be completely

More information

2. As we shall see, we choose to write in terms of σ x because ( X ) 2 = σ 2 x.

2. As we shall see, we choose to write in terms of σ x because ( X ) 2 = σ 2 x. Section 5.1 Simple One-Dimensional Problems: The Free Particle Page 9 The Free Particle Gaussian Wave Packets The Gaussian wave packet initial state is one of the few states for which both the { x } and

More information

Relativistic Energy-Momentum & Relativistic Quantum Mechanics

Relativistic Energy-Momentum & Relativistic Quantum Mechanics July 2010 Vol. 1 Issue 5 pp. 347-351 Relativistic Energy-Momentum & Relativistic Quantum Mechanics 347 Article Alexandru C. V. Ceapa * ABSTRACT The relativistic energy-momentum relationship is far more

More information

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality James Cross 2018-08-18 1 Introduction The field of quantum mechanics is practically synonymous with modern physics. The basics of quantum theory are taught in every introductory

More information

Basics on quantum information

Basics on quantum information Basics on quantum information Mika Hirvensalo Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Turku mikhirve@utu.fi Thessaloniki, May 2016 Mika Hirvensalo Basics on quantum information 1 of 52 Brief

More information

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 15 Oct 2012

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 15 Oct 2012 Nonperturbative theory of weak pre- and post-selected measurements Abraham G. Kofman, Sahel Ashhab, Franco Nori Advance Science Institute, RIKEN, Wako-shi, Saitama 351-0198, Japan Physics Department, The

More information