Funcoids and Reloids

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Funcoids and Reloids"

Transcription

1 Funcoids and Reloids by Victor Porton March 16, 2010 Abstract It is a part of my Algebraic General Topology research. In this article I introduce the concepts of funcoids which generalize proximity spaces and reloids which generalize uniform spaces. The concept of funcoid is generalized concept of proximity space, the concept of reloid is cleared from superfluous details (generalized) concept of uniform space. Also funcoids and reloids are generalizations of binary relations whose domains and ranges are filters (instead of sets). That funcoids and reloids are common generalizations of both (proximity, pretopology, uniform) spaces and of (multivalued) functions, makes this theory smart for analyzing properties (e.g. continuousness) of functions on spaces. Also funcoids and reloids can be considered as a generalization of (oriented) graphs, this provides us with a common generalization of analysis and discrete mathematics. Keywords: algebraic general topology, quasi-uniform spaces, generalizations of proximity spaces, generalizations of nearness spaces, generalizations of uniform spaces A.M.S. subject classification: 54J05, 54A05, 54D99, 54E05, 54E15, 54E17, 54E99 Table of contents 1 Common Draft status Used concepts, notation and statements Filters Earlier works Partially ordered dagger categories Partially ordered categories Dagger categories Monovalued and entirely defined morphisms Funcoids Informal introduction into funcoids Basic definitions Composition of funcoids Funcoid as continuation Lattice of funcoids More on composition of funcoids Domain and range of a funcoid Category of funcoids Specifying funcoids by functions or relations on atomic filter objects Direct product of filter objects Atomic funcoids Complete funcoids Completion of funcoids Monovalued funcoids T 1 - and T 2 -separable funcoids Filter objects closed regarding a funcoid This document has been written using the GNU TEX MAC S text editor (see 1

2 2 Section 1 4 Reloids Composition of reloids Direct product of filter objects Restricting reloid to a filter object. Domain and image Category of reloids Monovalued reloids Relationships of funcoids and reloids Funcoid induced by a reloid Reloids induced by funcoid Continuous morphisms Traditional definitions of continuity ? Pre-topology ? Proximity spaces ? Uniform spaces ? 6.2 Our three definitions of continuity ? 6.3 Continuousness of a restricted morphism ? 7 Postface ? 7.1 Misc ? 7.2 Pointfree funcoids and reloids ? Appendix A Some counter-examples ? Bibliography ? 1 Common 1.1 Draft status This article is a draft. This text refers to a preprint edition of [5]. Theorem number clashes may appear due editing both of these manuscripts. 1.2 Used concepts, notation and statements Set of functions from a set A to a set B is denoted as B A. I will often skip parentheses and write fx instead of f(x) to denote the result of a function f acting on the argument x. I will denote f X={fα α X}. For simplicity I will assume that all sets in consideration are subsets of universal set Filters In this work the word filter will refer to a filter on a set (in contrast to [5] where are considered filters on arbitrary posets). I will call the set of filters ordered reverse to set-theoretic inclusion of filters the set of filter objects F and its element filter objects (f.o. for short). I will denote upf the filter corresponding to a filter object F. So we have A B upa upb for every filter objects A and B. We also will equate filter objects corresponding to principal filters with corresponding sets. (Thus we have P F.) See [5] for formal definition of filter objects in the framework of ZF. Filters (and filter objects) are studied in the work [5]. Filter objects corresponding to ultrafilters are atoms of the lattice F and will be called atomic filter objects.

3 Partially ordered dagger categories 3 Also we will need to introduce the concept of generalized filter base. Definition 1. Generalized filter base is a set S PF\{ } such that A,B S C S:C A B. Proposition 2. Let S is a generalized filter base. If A 1,,A n S (n N), then C S:C A 1 A n. Can be easily proved by induction. Theorem 3. If S is a generalized filter base, then up F S= up S. Obviously up F S up S. Reversely, let K F S; then K = A 1 A n where A i upa i S, i=1,,n, n N; so exists C S such that C A 1 A n A 1 A n =K, K upc, K up S. Corollary 4. If S is a generalized filter base, then F S= S. F S= up F S up S X S: upx S. Definition 5. I will call a partially ordered (pre)category a (pre)category together with partial order on each of its Hom-sets. 1.3 Earlier works Some mathematician were researching generalizations of proximities and uniformities before me but they have failed to reach the right degree of generalization which is presented in this work allowing to represent properties of spaces with algebraic (or categorical) formulas. Some references to predecessors: In [1] and [2] are studied semi-uniformities and proximities. [3] and [4] contains recent progress in quasi-uniform spaces. 2 Partially ordered dagger categories 2.1 Partially ordered categories Definition 6. I will call a partially ordered (pre)category a (pre)category together with partial order on each of its Hom-sets with the additional requirement that f 1 f 2 g 1 g 2 g 1 f 1 g 2 f 2 for any morphisms f 1, g 1, f 2, g 2 such that Src f 1 = Src f 2 Dst f 1 = Dst f 2 = Src g 1 = Src g 2 Dstg 1 = Dstg Dagger categories Definition 7. I will call a dagger precategory a precategory together with an involutive contravariant identity-on-objects prefunctor x x. In other words, a dagger precategory is a precategory equipped with a function x x on its set of morphisms which reverses the source and the destination and is subject to the following identities for every morphisms f and g: 1. f =f;

4 4 Section 2 2. (g f) =f g. Definition 8. I will call a dagger category a category together with an involutive contravariant identity-on-objects functor x x. In other words, a dagger category is a category equipped with a function x x on its set of morphisms which reverses the source and the destination and is subject to the following identities for every morphisms f and g and object A: 1. f =f; 2. (g f) =f g ; 3. (1 A ) =1 A. Theorem 9. If a category is a dagger precategory then it is a dagger category. We need to prove only that (1 A ) =1 A. Really (1 A ) =(1 A ) 1 A =(1 A ) (1 A ) =((1 A ) 1 A ) =(1 A ) =1 A. For a partially ordered dagger (pre)category I will additionally require (for any morphisms f and g) f g f g. An example of dagger category is the category Rel whose objects are sets and whose morphisms are binary relations between these sets with usual composition of binary relations and with f = f 1. Definition 10. A morphism f of a dagger category is called unitary when it is an isomorphism and f =f 1. Definition 11. Symmetric (endo)morphism of a dagger precategory is such a morphism f that f =f. Definition 12. Transitive (endo)morphism of a precategory is such a morphism f that f = f f. Theorem 13. The following conditions are equivalent for a morphism f of a dagger precategory: 1. f is symmetric and transitive. 2. f =f f. (1) (2). If f is symmetric and transitive then f f =f f =f. (2) (1). f =(f f) = f f = f f = f, so f is symmetric. f = f f = f f, so f is transitive Monovalued and entirely defined morphisms Definition 14. For a partially ordered dagger category I will call monovalued morphism such a morphism f that f f 1 Dst f. Definition 15. For a partially ordered dagger category I will call entirely defined morphism such a morphism f that f f 1 Src f. Remark 16. Easy to show that this is a generalization of monovalued and entirely defined binary relations as morphisms of the category Rel.

5 Funcoids 5 Definition 17. For a given partially ordered dagger category C the category of monovalued (entirely defined) morphisms of C is the category with the same set of objects as of C and the set of morphisms being the set of monovalued (entirely defined) morphisms of C with the composition of morphisms the same as in C. We need to prove that these are really categories, that is that composition of monovalued (entirely defined) morphisms is monovalued (entirely defined) and that identity morphisms are monovalued and entirely defined. Monovalued. Let f and g are monovalued morphisms, Dstf = Src g. (g f) (g f) = g f f g g 1 Dst f g = g 1 Src g g = g g 1 Dst g =1 Dst(g f). So g f is monovalued. That identity morphisms are monovalued follows from the following: 1 A (1 A ) =1 A 1 A =1 A =1 Dst1A 1 Dst 1A. Entirely defined. Let f and g are entirely defined morphisms, Dstf = Src g. (g f) (g f)= f g g f f 1 Src g f = f 1 Dst f f = f f 1 Src f =1 Src(g f). So g f is entirely defined. That identity morphisms are entirely defined follows from the following: (1 A ) 1 A = 1 A 1 A =1 A =1 Src 1A 1 Src1A. 3 Funcoids 3.1 Informal introduction into funcoids Funcoids are a generalization of proximity spaces and a generalization of pretopological spaces. Also funcoids are a generalization of binary relations. That funcoids are a common generalization of spaces (proximity spaces, (pre)topological spaces) and binary relations (including monovalued functions) makes them smart for describing properties of functions in regard of spaces. For example the statement f is a continuous function from a space µ to a space ν can be described in terms of funcoids as the formula f µ ν f (see my yet unpublished article Generalized continuity for details). Most naturally funcoids appear as a generalization of proximity spaces. Let δ be a proximity that is certain binary relation so that AδB is defined for any sets A and B. We will extend it from sets to filter objects by the formula: Aδ B A upa,b upb:aδb. Then (as will be proved below) exist two functions α,β F F such that Aδ B B αa A βb. The pair (α;β) is called funcoid when B αa A βb. So funcoids are a generalization of proximity spaces. Funcoids consist of two components the first α and the second β. The first component of a funcoid f is denoted as f and the second component is denoted as f 1. (The similarity of this notation with the notation for the image of a set under a function is not a coincidence, we will see that in the case of discrete funcoids (see below) these coincide.) One of the most important properties of a funcoid is that it is uniquely determined by just one of its components. That is a funcoid f is uniquely determined by the function f. Moreover a funcoid f is uniquely determined by f P that is by values of function f on sets. Next we will consider some examples of funcoids determined by specified values of the first component on sets.

6 6 Section 3 Funcoids as a generalization of pretopological spaces: Let α be a pretopological space that is a map α F. Then we define α X= def F {αx x X} for any set X. We will prove that there exists a unique funcoid f such that α = f P. So funcoids are a generalization of pretopological spaces. Funcoids are also a generalization of preclosure operators: For every preclosure operator p exists unique funcoid such that f P =p; in this case f P P P. For any binary relation p exists unique funcoid f such that X P : f X = p X (where p is defined in the introduction), recall that a funcoid is uniquely determined by the values of its first component on sets. I will call such funcoids discrete. So funcoids are a generalization of binary relations. Composition of binary relations (i.e. of discrete funcoids) complies with the formulas: g f = g f and (g f) 1 = f 1 g 1. By the same formulas we can define composition of any two funcoids. Also funcoids can be reversed (like reversal of X and Y in a binary relation) by the formula (α; β) 1 =(β;α). In particular case if µ is a proximity we have µ 1 = µ because proximities are symmetric. Funcoids behave similarly to (multivalued) functions but acting on filter objects instead of acting on sets. Below will be defined domain and image of a funcoid (the domain and the image of a funcoid are filter objects). 3.2 Basic definitions Definition 18. Let s call a funcoid a pair (α;β) where α,β F F such that X,Y F:(Y F αx X F βy ). Definition 19. (α;β) = def α for a funcoid (α;β). Definition 20. (α;β) 1 =(β;α) for a funcoid (α;β). Proposition 21. If f is a funcoid then f 1 is also a funcoid. Follows from symmetry in the definition of funcoid. Obvious 22. (f 1 ) 1 =f for a funcoid f. Definition 23. The relation [f] PF 2 is defined by the formula (for any filter objects X, Y and funcoid f) X[f]Y= def Y F f X. Obvious 24. X[f]Y Y F f X X F f 1 Y for any filter objects X, Y and funcoid f. Obvious 25. [ f 1] =[f] 1 for a funcoid f. Theorem For given value of f exists no more than one funcoid f. 2. For given value of [f] exists no more than one funcoid f. Let f and g are funcoids. Obviously f = g [f]=[g] and f 1 = g 1 [f]=[g]. So enough to prove that [f]= [g] f = g. Provided that [f]=[g] we have Y F f X X[f]Y X[g]Y Y F g X and consequently f X = g X for any f.o. X and Y because the set of filter objects is separable [5], thus f = g.

7 Funcoids 7 Proposition 27. f (I F J)= f I F f J for any funcoid f and I,J F. [TODO: Point used theorems.] f (I F J) = { Y F Y F f (I F J) } = (by corollary 10 in [5]) { Y F (I F J) F f 1 Y } = { Y F (I F f 1 Y) F (J F f 1 Y) } = { Y F (Y F f I) F (Y F f J) } = { Y F Y F ( f I F f J) } = ( f I F f J). Thus f (I F J)= f I F f J because F is separable Composition of funcoids Definition 28. Composition of funcoids is defined by the formula (α 2 ;β 2 ) (α 1 ;β 1 )=(α 2 α 1 ;β 1 β 2 ). Proposition 29. If f, g are funcoids then g f is funcoid. Let f =(α 1 ;β 1 ), g=(α 2 ;β 2 ). Y F (α 2 α 1 )X Y F α 2 α 1 X α 1 X F β 2 Y X F β 1 β 2 Y X F (β 1 β 2 )Y. So (α 2 α 1 ;β 1 β 2 ) is a funcoid. Obvious 30. g f = g f for any funcoids f and g. Proposition 31. (h g) f =h (g f) for any funcoids f, g, h. (h g) f = h g f =( h g ) f = h ( g f )= h g f = h (g f). Theorem 32. (g f) 1 =f 1 g 1 for any funcoids f and g. (g f) 1 = f 1 g 1 = f 1 g Funcoid as continuation Theorem 33. For any funcoid f and filter objects X and Y 1. f X = F f upx ; 2. X[f]Y X upx,y upy:x[f]y. 2. X[f]Y Y F f X Y upy:y F f X Y upy:x[f]y. Analogously X[f]Y X upx:x[f]y. Combining these two equalities we get X[f]Y X upx,y upy:x[f]y. 1. Y F f X X upx:y F f X Let s denote W = { Y F f X X up X }. Let P, Q W. Then P = Y F f A, Q = Y F f B where A,B upx ; A B upx and R P F Q for R=Y F f (A B) W. So W is a generalized filter base. [TODO: Simplify the proof than it is a g.f.b.]

8 8 Section 3 W F W by the corollary 4 of the theorem 3. That is X upx:y F f X Y F F f upx. Comparing with the above, Y F f X Y F F f up X. So f X = F f upx. Theorem A function α F P conforming to the formulas (for any I,J P ) α =, α(i J)=αI αj can be continued to the function f for exactly one funcoid f; for any filter object X. f X = F α upx (1) 2. A relation δ P(P ) 2 conforming to the formulas (for any I,J,K P ) ( δi), I J δk IδK J δk, (Iδ ), KδI J KδI KδJ (2) can be continued to the relation [f] for exactly one funcoid f; for any filter objects X, Y. X[f]Y X upx,y upy:x δy (3) Existence of no more than one such funcoids and formulas (1) and (3) follow from the previous theorem. 2. Let define α F P by the formula (αx) ={Y P X δy } for any X P. Analogously can be defined β F P by the formula (βx) = {X P X δy }. Let s continue α and β to α F F and β F F by the formulas α X = F α upx and β X = F β upx. and δ to δ PF 2 by the formula X δ Y X upx,y upy:xδy. Y F α X Y F F α upx F Y F α upx. Let s prove that W = Y F α upx is a generalized filter base: [TODO: Simplify this proof.] If A, B W then exist X 1, X 2 up X such that A=Y F αx 1 and A=Y F αx 2. Then Y F α(x 1 X 2 ) W. So W is a generalized filter base. Accordingly the corollary 4 of the theorem 3, F Y F α upx is equivalent to X upx:y F αx, what is equivalent to X upx,y up Y:Y F αx X upx,y up Y:Y (αx) X upx,y upy:x δy. Combining the equivalencies we get Y F α X X δ Y. Analogously X F β Y X δ Y. So Y F α X X F β Y, that is (α ; β ) is a funcoid. From the formula Y F α X X δ Y follows that [(α ;β )] is a continuation of δ. 1. Let define the relation δ P(P ) 2 by the formula XδY Y F αx. Then the formulas (2) are true. Accordingly the above δ can be continued to the relation [f] for some funcoid f. X,Y P :X[f]Y Y F αx, consequently X P :αx = f X. So f is a continuation of α.

9 Funcoids 9 Note that by the last theorem to every proximity δ corresponds exactly one funcoid. So funcoids is a generalization of proximity structures. Definition 35. Any (multivalued) function f will be considered as a funcoid, where by definition f X = F f upx for any X F. Using the last theorem it is easy to show that this definition is monovalued and does not contradict to former stuff. So binary relations (= multivalued functions) may be called discrete funcoids. I will denote FCD the set of funcoids or the category of funcoids (see below) dependently on context. 3.4 Lattice of funcoids Definition 36. f g= def [f] [g] for f,g FCD. Thus FCD is a poset. Conjecture 37. The filtrator of funcoids is: 1. with separable core; 2. with co-separable core. Definition 38. I will call the filtrator of funcoids (see [5] for the definition of filtrators) the filtrator (FCD; P 2 ). Theorem 39. The set of funcoids is a complete lattice. For any R PFCD and X,Y P 1. X [ FCD R ] Y f R:X[f]Y ; 2. FCD R X= F { f X f R}. 2. h X= def F { f X f R}. h = ; h (I J) = F { f (I J) f R} = F { f (I F J) f R } = F { f I F f J f R } = F { f I f R} F F { f J f R} = h I F h J. So h can be continued to a funcoid. Obviously f R:h f. (4) And h is the least funcoid for which holds the condition (4). So h= FCD R. 1. X [ FCD R ] Y Y F FCD R X Y F F { f X f R} f R: Y F f X f R:X[f]Y. In the next theorem, compared to the previous one, the class of infinite unions is replaced with lesser class of finite unions and simultaneously class of sets is changed to more wide class of filter objects. Theorem 40. For any funcoids f and g and a filter object X 1. f FCD g X = f X F g X ; 2. [ f F g ] =[f] [g].

10 10 Section 3 1. Let h X = def f X F g X ; h 1 Y= def f 1 Y F g 1 Y for any X,Y F. Then Y F h X Y F f X Y F g X So h is a funcoid. Consequently f FCD g=h. X F f 1 Y X F g 1 Y X F h 1 Y. 2. X [ f FCD g ] Y Y F f FCD g X Y F ( f X F g X) Y F f X Y F g X X[f]Y X[g]Y for any X,Y F. 3.5 More on composition of funcoids Proposition 41. [g f]=[g] f = g 1 1 [f] for f,g FCD. X[g f]y Y F g f X Y F g f X f X[g]Y X([g] f )Y for any X,Y F. [g f]= [ (f 1 g 1 ) 1] = [ f 1 g 1] 1 =( [ f 1] g 1 ) 1 = g 1 1 [f]. The following theorem is the variant for funcoids of the statement (which defines compositions of relations) that x(g f)z y(xfy ygz) for any x and z and any binary relations f and g. Theorem 42. For any X,Z F and f,g FCD X[g f]z y atoms F :(X[f]y y[g]z). y atoms F :(X[f]y y[g]z) y atoms F :(Z F g y y F f X ) y atoms F :(Z F g y y f X) Z F g f X X[g f]z. Reversely, if X[g f]z then f X[g]Z, consequently exists y atoms F f X such that y[g]z; we have X[f]y. Theorem 43. If f, g, h are funcoids then 1. f (g FCD h)=f g FCD f h; 2. (g FCD h) f =g f FCD h f. I will prove only the first equality because the other is analogous. For any X,Z F X [ f (g FCD h) ] Z y atoms F :(X [ g FCD h ] y y[f]z) y atoms F :((X[g]y X[h]y) y[f]z) y atoms F :(X[g]y y[f]z X[h]y y[f]z) y atoms F :(X[g]y y[f]z) y atoms F :(X[h]y y[f]z) X[f g]z X[f h]z X [ f g FCD f h ] Z. 3.6 Domain and range of a funcoid Definition 44. Let A F. The identity funcoid I A will be defined by the formula I A X = def X F A.

11 Funcoids 11 Proposition 45. This definition is correct and X[I A ]Y A F X F Y for any X, Y F; (I A ) 1 =I A. Y F I A X Y F A F X X F I A Y. Definition 46. I will define restricting of a funcoid f to a filter object A by the formula f A = def f I A. Obviously the last definition does not contradict to the previous. Definition 47. Image of a funcoid f will be defined by the formula imf = f. Domain of a funcoid f is defined by the formula domf = imf 1. Proposition 48. f X = f (X F domf) for any f FCD, X F. For any filter object Y we have Y F f (X F dom f) X F dom f F f 1 Y X F imf 1 F f 1 Y X F f 1 Y Y F f X. Proposition 49. X F domf f X for any f FCD, X F. X F domf X F f 1 F f X f X. Corollary 50. domf = F { a a atoms F, f a }. This follows from that F is an atomistic lattice. 3.7 Category of funcoids I will define the category FCD of funcoids: The set of objects is F. The set of morphisms from a filter object A to a filter object B is the set of triples (f;a; B) where f is a funcoid such that domf A, imf B. Composition of morphisms is defined in the natural way. Identity morphism of a filter object A is (I A ;A;A). To prove that it is really a category is trivial. 3.8 Specifying funcoids by functions or relations on atomic filter objects Theorem 51. For any funcoid f and filter objects X and Y 1. f X = F f atoms F X ; 2. X[f]Y x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:x[f]y. 1. Y F f X X F f 1 Y x atoms F X:x F f 1 Y x atoms F X:Y F f x. f X = f atoms F X = f atoms F X. 2. If X[f]Y, then Y F f X, consequently exists y atoms F Y such that y F f X, X[f]y. Repeating this second time we get that there exist x atoms F X such that x[f]y. From this follows The reverse is obvious. x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:x[f]y.

12 12 Section 3 Theorem A function α F atomsf such that (for any a atoms F ) αa F F α atoms F up a (5) can be continued to the function f for exactly one funcoid f; for any filter object X. f X = F α atoms F X (6) 2. A relation δ P(atoms F ) 2 such that (for any a,b atoms F ) X upa,y upb x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:xδ y aδb (7) can be continued to the relation [f] for exactly one funcoid f; for any filter objects X, Y. X[f]Y x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:xδ y (8) Existence of no more than one such funcoids and formulas (6) and (8) follow from the previous theorem. 1. Consider the function α F defined by the formula (for any X P ) Obviously α =. For any I,J P α X= F α atoms F X. α (I J) = F α atoms F (I J) = F α (atoms F I atoms F J) = F ( α atoms F I α atoms F J ) = F α atoms F I F F α atoms F. = α I F α J. Let continue α till a funcoid f (by the theorem 25): f X = F α upx. Let s prove the reverse of (5): F F α atoms F upa = F F atoms F α upa F F α {{a}} = ) } F{( F α {a} = } F{ F α {a} = } F{ F {αa} = F {αa}=αa. Finally, αa= F F α atoms F upa= F α upa= f a, so f is a continuation of α. 2. Consider the relation δ P(P ) 2 defined by the formula (for any X,Y P ) Obviously (Xδ ) and ( δ Y). X δ Y x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:xδ y. (I J)δ Y x atoms F (I J),y atoms F Y:xδ y x atoms F I atoms F J,y atoms F Y:xδ y x atoms F I,y atoms F Y:xδ y x atoms F J,y atoms F Y:xδ y Iδ Y J δ Y;

13 Funcoids 13 analogously Xδ (I J) Xδ I Xδ J. Let s continue δ till a funcoid f (by the theorem 25): X[f]Y X upx,y upy:x δ Y The reverse of (7) implication is trivial, so X upa,y upb x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:xδ y aδb. X upa,y upb x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:xδ y X upa,y upb:xδ Y a[f]b. So aδb a[f]b, that is [f] is a continuation of δ. One of uses of the previous theorem is proof of the following theorem: Theorem 53. If R is a set of funcoids, x,y atoms F, then 1. FCD R x= F { f x f R}; 2. x [ FCD R ] y f R:x[f]y. 2. Let denote xδ y f R:x[f]y. X upa,y upb x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:xδ y f R,X upa,y upb x atoms F X,y atoms F Y:x[f]y f R,X upa,y upb:x[f]y f R:a[f]b aδb. So, by the theorem 52, δ can be continued till [p] for some funcoid p. For any funcoid q such that f R: q f we have x[q]y f R:x[f]y xδ y x[p]y, so q f. Consequently p= FCD R. From this x [ FCD R ] y f R:x[f]y. 1. From the former y F FCD R x f R: y F f x for any y atoms F. From this follows what we need to prove. 3.9 Direct product of filter objects A generalization of direct (Cartesian) product of two sets is direct product of two filter objects as defined in the theory of funcoids: Definition 54. Direct product of filter objects A and B is such a funcoid A FCD B that X [ A FCD B ] Y X F A Y F B. Proposition 55. A FCD B is really a funcoid and A FCD B { B ifx X = F A ; ifx F A=. Obvious. Obvious 56. A B=A FCD B for sets A and B. Proposition 57. f A FCD B domf A imf B for any f FCD and A,B F. If f A FCD B then dom f dom(a FCD B) A, im f im(a FCD B) B. If domf A imf B then consequently f A FCD B. X,Y F:(X[f]Y X F A Y F B );

14 14 Section 3 The following theorem gives a formula for calculating an important particular case of intersection on the lattice of funcoids: Theorem 58. f FCD A FCD B=I B f I A for any f FCD and A,B F. h= def I B f I A. For any X F h X = I B f I A X =B f (A X). From this, as easy to show, h f and h A B. If g f g A FCD B for a funcoid g then domg A, img B, g X =B F g (A F X) B F f (A F X)= I B f I A X = h X, g h. So h=f FCD A FCD B. Corollary 59. f A =f A FCD for any f FCD and A F. f FCD A FCD =I f I A =f I A =f A. Corollary 60. f FCD (A FCD B) A[f]B for any f FCD, A,B F. f FCD A FCD B f FCD A FCD B I B f I A I B f I A B FCD f (A F ) B F f A A[f]B. Corollary 61. The filtrator of funcoids is star-separable. The set of direct products of sets is a separation subset of the lattice of funcoids. Theorem 62. If S PF 2 then FCD { A FCD B (A;B) S } = F doms FCD F ims. If x atoms F then by the theorem 53 FCD { A FCD B (A;B) S } x= F { A FCD B x (A;B) S }. If x F F doms then if x F F doms= then (A;B) S:(x F A A FCD B x=b); { A FCD B x (A;B) S } = ims; (A;B) S:(x F A= A FCD B x= ); { A FCD B x (A;B) S }. So FCD { A FCD B (A;B) S } { F ims if x x= F F doms ; if x F F doms=. From this follows the statement of the theorem. Corollary 63. A 0 FCD B 0 FCD A 1 FCD B 1 =(A 0 FCD A 1 ) FCD (B 0 FCD B 1 ) for any A 0,A 1,B 0, B 1 F. A 0 FCD B 0 FCD A 1 FCD B 1 = { } F A 0 FCD B 0,A 1 FCD B 1 what is by the last theorem equal to (A 0 FCD A 1 ) FCD (B 0 FCD B 1 ). Theorem 64. If A FthenA FCD is a complete homomorphism of the lattice F to a complete sublattice of the lattice FCD, if also A then it is an isomorphism.

15 Funcoids 15 Let S PF, X P, x atoms F. FCD A FCD S X = F { A FCD B X B S } = = { F S ifx F A ifx F A= A FCD F S X; FCD A FCD S x = F { A FCD B x B S } = = { F S ifx F A ifx F A= A FCD F S x. If A then obviously the function A FCD is injective. The following proposition states that cutting a rectangle of atomic width from a funcoid always produces a rectangular (representable as a direct product of filter objects) funcoid (of atomic width). Proposition 65. If a is an atomic filter object, f FCD then f a =a FCD f a. Let X F. X F a f a X = f a, X F a= f a X = Atomic funcoids Theorem 66. A funcoid is an atom of the lattice of funcoids iff it is direct product of two atomic filter objects. Direct implication. Let f is an atomic funcoid. Let s get elements a atoms F dom f and b atoms F f a. Then for any X F X F a= a FCD b X = f X, X F a a FCD b X =b f X. So a FCD b f; because f is an atomic funcoid f =a FCD b. Reverse implication. Let a, b atoms F, f FCD. If b F f a = then (a[f]b), f F a FCD b= ; if b f a then X F:(X F a f X b), f a FCD b. Consequently f FCD a FCD b= f a FCD b; that is a FCD b is an atomic filter object. Theorem 67. The lattice of funcoids is atomic. Let f is a non-empty funcoid. Then dom f, thus by the theorem 46 in [5] exists a atoms domf. So f a thus exists b atoms f a. Finally the atomic funcoid a FCD b f. Theorem 68. The lattice of funcoids is atomically separable. Let f, g FCD, f g. Then exists a atoms F such that f a g a. So because the lattice F is atomically separable then exists b atoms F such that f a F b = and b g a. For any x atoms F f a F a FCD b a= f a F b=, x a f x F a FCD b x= f x F =

16 16 Section 3 Thus f x F a b x= and consequently f FCD a FCD b=. a FCD b a=b g a, x a a FCD b x= g a. Thus a FCD b x=b g x and consequently a FCD b g. So the lattice of funcoids is separable by the theorem 19 in [5]. Corollary 69. The lattice of funcoids is: 1. separable; 2. atomically separable; 3. conforming to Wallman s disjunction property. By the theorem 22 in [5]. Remark 70. For more ways to characterize (atomic) separability of the lattice of funcoids see [5], subsections Separation subsets and full stars and Atomically separable lattices. Corollary 71. The lattice of funcoids is an atomistic lattice. Let f is a funcoid. Suppose contrary to the statement to be proved that F atoms FCD f f. Then exists a atoms FCD f such that a F F atoms FCD f = what is impossible. Proposition 72. atoms FCD (f F g)=atoms FCD f atoms FCD g for any funcoids f and g. a FCD b FCD (f FCD g) a [ f FCD g ] b a[f]b a[g]b a FCD b FCD f a FCD b FCD g for any atomic filter objects a and b. Corollary 73. For any f,g,h FCD, R PFCD 1. f FCD (g FCD h)=(f FCD g) FCD (f FCD h); 2. f FCD FCD R= FCD f FCD R. We will take in account that the lattice of funcoids is an atomistic lattice. To be concise I will write atoms instead of atoms FCD and and instead of FCD and FCD. 1. atoms(f (g h))=atomsf atoms(g h)=atoms f (atoms g atomsh)=(atoms f atomsg) (atomsf atomsh)=atoms(f g) atoms(f h)=atoms((f g) (f h)). 2. atoms ( f FCD R ) = atoms f atoms FCD R = atoms f FCD atoms R = FCD (atomsf) atoms R= FCD atoms f R=atoms FCD f R. Note that distributivity of the lattice of funcoids is proved through using atoms of this lattice. I have never seen such method of proving distributivity. The next proposition is one more (among the theorem 42) generalization for funcoids of composition of relations. Corollary 74. The lattice of funcoids is co-brouwerian. Proposition 75. For any f,g FCD atoms FCD (g f)= { x FCD z x,z atoms F, y atoms F :(x FCD y atoms FCD f y FCD z atoms FCD g) }. x FCD z FCD g f x[g f]z y atoms F : (x[f]y y[g]z) y atoms F : (x FCD y FCD f y FCD z FCD g ) (were used the theorem 42).

17 Funcoids 17 Conjecture 76. The set of discrete funcoids is the center of the lattice of funcoids Complete funcoids Definition 77. I will call co-complete such a funcoid f that X P : f X P. Remark 78. I will call generalized closure such a function α P P that 1. α = ; 2. I,J P :α(i J)=αI F αj. Obvious 79. A funcoid f is co-complete iff f P is a generalized closure. Remark 80. Thus funcoids can be considered as a generalization of generalized closures. A topological space in Kuratowski sense is the same as reflexive and transitive generalized closure. So topological spaces can be considered as a special case of funcoids. Definition 81. I will call a complete funcoid a funcoid whose reverse is co-complete. Theorem 82. The following conditions are equivalent for every funcoid f: 1. funcoid f is complete. 2. S PF,J P :( F S[f]J I S:I[f]J); 3. S PP,J P :( S[f]J I S:I[f]J); 4. S PF: f F S= F f S; 5. S PP : f S= F f S; 6. A P : f A= F { f a a A}. (3) (1). For any S PP, J P S F f 1 J I S:I F f 1 J, (9) consequently by the theorem 52 in [5] we have f 1 J P. (1) (2). For any S PF, J P we have f 1 J P, consequently the formula (9) is true. From this follows (2). (6) (5). f S = F { f a a S} = F { F { f a a A} A S } = F { f A A S}= F f S. (2) (3), (4) (5), (5) (3), (2) (4), (5) (6). Obvious. The following proposition shows that complete funcoids are a direct generalization of pre-topological spaces. Proposition 83. To specify a complete funcoid f it is enough to specify f on one-element sets, values of f on one element sets can be specified arbitrarily. From the above theorem is clear that knowing f on one-element sets f can be found on any sets and then its value can be inferred for any filter objects. Choosing arbitrarily the values of f on one-element sets we can define a complete funcoid the following way: f X= def F { f {α} α X} for any X P. Obviously it is really a complete funcoid. Theorem 84. A funcoid is discrete iff it is both complete and co-complete.

18 18 Section 3 Direct implication. Obvious. Reverse implication. Let f is both a complete and co-complete funcoid. Consider the relation g defined by that g {α}= f {α} (g is correctly defined because f is a generalized closure). Because f is a complete funcoid f =g. Theorem 85. If R is a set of (co-)complete funcoids then FCD R is a (co-)complete funcoid. It is enough to prove only for co-complete funcoids. Let R is a set of co-complete funcoids. Then for any X P FCD R X = { f X f R} P (used the theorem 39). Corollary 86. If R is a set of binary relations then FCD R= R. From two last theorems. Theorem 87. The filtrator of funcoids is filtered. It s enough to prove that every funcoid is representable as (infinite) intersection (on the lattice of funcoids) of some set of discrete funcoids. Let f FCD, A P, B up f A, g(a;b)= def A B FCD A. For any X P g(a;b) X= A FCD B X A FCD X= ifx= B if X A ifx A so g(a;b) f. For any A P F { g(a;b) A B up f A}= F {B B up f A}= f A; f X; consequently FCD {g(a;b) A P,B up f A}=f. In certain cases the theorem 43 can be generalized for infinite unions. Theorem 88. Let f FCD. If R is a set of co-complete funcoids then f FCD R= FCD f R. If R is a set of co-complete funcoids then for X,Z P [ X f ] FCD R Z ( ] ) (by the theorem 42) y atoms F : X[ FCD R y y[f]z ( ) y atoms F : y F FCD R X y[f]z ( (by the theorem 39) y atoms F : y F ) { u X u R} y[f]z (by the theorem 52 in [5]) y atoms F :( u R:y F u X y[f]z) y atoms F :( u R:X[u]y y[f]z) y atoms F,u R:(X[u]y y[f]z) (by the theorem 42) u R:X[f u]z ] (by the theorem 39) X[ FCD f R Z.

19 Funcoids Completion of funcoids I will denote ComplFCD and CoComplFCD the sets of complete and co-complete funcoids correspondingly. Obvious 89. ComplFCD and CoComplFCD are closed regarding composition of funcoids. Proposition 90. ComplFCD and CoComplFCD (with induced order) are complete lattices. Follows from the corollary 85. Theorem 91. Corf = Cor f for an element f of the filtrator of funcoids. From the theorem 26 in [5] and the corollary 86 and theorem 87. Definition 92. Completion of a funcoid f is the complete funcoid Compl f defined by the formula Complf {α}= f {α} for α. Definition 93. Co-completion of a funcoid f is defined by the formula CoComplf =(Complf 1 ) 1. Proposition 94. The filtrator (FCD; ComplFCD) is filtered. Because the filtrator (FCD; P 2 ) is filtered. Theorem 95. Complf = Cor (FCD;ComplFCD) f = Cor (FCD;ComplFCD) f. Cor (FCD;ComplFCD) f = Cor (FCD;ComplFCD) f since (the theorem 26 in [5]) the filtrator (FCD; ComplFCD) is filtered (as a consequence of the theorem 87) and with join closed core (the theorem 85). Let g up (FCD;ComplFCD) f. Then g ComplFCD and g f. Thus g= Complg Complf. Thus g up (FCD;ComplFCD) f:g Complf. Let g up (FCD;ComplFCD) f:h g for some h ComplFCD. Then h FCD up (FCD;ComplFCD) f =f and consequently h=complh Complf. Thus Complf = ComplFCD up (FCD;ComplFCD) f = Cor (FCD;ComplFCD) f. Theorem 96. Atoms of the lattice ComplFCD are exactly direct products of the form {α} FCD b where α and b is an atomic f.o. First, easy to see that {α} FCD b are elements of ComplFCD. Also is an element of ComplFCD. {α} FCD b are atoms of ComplFCD because these are atoms of FCD. Remain to prove that if f is an atom of ComplFCD then f ={α} FCD b for some α and an atomic f.o. b. Suppose f is a non-empty complete fucnoid. Then exists α such that f α. Thus {α} FCD b f for some atomic f.o. b. If f is an atom then f ={α} FCD b. Theorem 97. CoComplf X = Cor f X for every funcoid f and set X. CoCompl f f thus CoCompl f X f X, but CoCompl f X P thus CoComplf X Cor f X. Let αx= Cor f X. Then h = and α(x Y)=Cor f (X Y)=Cor( f X f Y)=Cor f X Cor f Y =αx αy. (used the theorem 64 from [5]). Thus α can be continued till g for some funcoid g. This funcoid is co-complete. Evidently g is the greatest co-complete funcoid which is lower than f.

20 20 Section 3 Thus g= CoComplf and so Cor f X=αX = g X = CoComplf X. Theorem 98. Complf FCD Complg= Compl(f FCD g) for every funcoids f and g. CoCompl f FCD CoCompl g x = CoCompl f x F CoCompl g x = Cor f x F Cor g x = Cor f x Cor g x = Cor( f x F g x) = Cor f FCD g x = CoCompl(f FCD g) x for every atomic f.o. x (used the theorem 63 from [5]). Thus CoComplf FCD CoComplg= CoCompl(f FCD g). Corollary 99. If f, g are (co-)complete funcoids then f FCD g is a (co-)complete funcoid. Let f and g are complete funcoids. f FCD g= Complf FCD Complg= Compl(f FCD g) ComplFCD. Corollary 100. If f, g are discrete funcoids then f FCD g is a discrete funcoid. Let f, g are discrete funcoids. Then f FCD g is both complete and co-complete. Corollary 101. If f,gare discrete funcoids thenf FCD g=f g. Theorem 102. ComplFCD is an atomistic lattice. Let f ComplFCD. f X = F { f x x X} = { } F f {x} x x X, thus f = FCD { f {x} x X }. It is trivial that every f {x} is a union of atoms of ComplFCD. Theorem 103. A funcoid is complete iff it is a join (on the lattice FCD) of atomic complete funcoids. Follows from the theorem 85 and the previous theorem. [TODO: Research the filtrators related to completion: Is ComplFCD a distributive lattice? Is ComplFCD a co-brouwerian lattice? Is it a separable lattice? Is the filtrator (FCD; ComplFCD) with (finitely) meet/join closed core? Is it with sepable core? Is it star-separable?] [TODO: Complete reloids can be defined as join of {α} b atoms. Composition of complete reloids is complete. Complete reloids are convex. Relationships of complete reloids and complete funcoids.] Lemma 104. Co-completion of a complete funcoid is complete. Let f is a complete funcoid. CoCompl f X = Cor f X = Cor F {fx x X} = {Cor fx x X} = { CoComplf x x X}. Theorem 105. Compl CoComplf = CoCompl Complf = Corf for every funcoid f. Compl CoCompl f is co-complete since (used the lemma) CoCompl f is co-complete. Thus Compl CoCompl f is a discrete funcoid. Trivially [TODO: Detailed proof] it is the greatest discrete funcoid under f. Thus Compl CoCompl f = Cor f. Similarly CoCompl Compl f = Corf. Theorem 106. Corf FCD Corg= Cor(f FCD g). From the previous theorem and the theorem Monovalued funcoids Following the idea of definition of monovalued morphism let s call monovalued such a funcoid f that f f 1 I im f.

21 Funcoids 21 Obvious 107. A morphism (f;a;b) of the category of funcoids is monovalued iff the funcoid f is monovalued. Theorem 108. The following statements are equivalent for a funcoid f: 1. f is monovalued. 2. a atoms F A: f a atoms F { }. 3. I,J F: f 1 (I F J)= f 1 I F f 1 J. 4. I,J P : f 1 (I J)= f 1 I F f 1 J. (2) (3). Let a atoms F, f a=b. Then because b atoms F { } (I F J) F b I F b J F b ; a[f](i F J) a[f]i a[f]j; (I F J) [ f 1] a I [ f 1] a J [ f 1] a; a F f 1 (I F J) a F f 1 I a F f 1 J ; f 1 (I F J)= f 1 I F f 1 J. (4) (1). f 1 a F f 1 b= for any two distinct atomic filter objects a and b. This is equivalent to (b [ f 1] f 1 a); ( f 1 a[f]b); b F f f 1 a= ; b F f f 1 a= ; (a [ f f 1] b). So a [ f f 1] b a=b for any atomic filter objects a and b. This is possible only when f f 1 I Dst f. (3) (4). Obvious. (2) (1). Suppose f a atoms F B { } for some a atoms F A. Then there exist two atomic filter objects p q such that f a p f a q. Consequently p F f a ; a F f 1 p ; a f 1 p; f f 1 p= f f 1 p f a q; f f 1 p p. So it cannot be f f 1 I Dst f. Corollary 109. A function is a monovalued funcoid. Remark 110. This corollary can be reformulated as follows: For binary relations the classic concept of monovaluedness and monovaluedness in the above defined sense of monovaluedness of a funcoid are the same. Because I,J P : f 1 (I J)= f 1 I F f 1 J is true for any function f T 1 - and T 2 -separable funcoids For funcoids can be generalized T 0 -, T 1 - and T 2 - separability. Worthwhile note that T 0 and T 2 separability is defined through T 1 separability. Definition 111. Let call T 1 -separable such funcoid f that for any α,β is true α β ({α}[f]{β}) Definition 112. Let call T 0 -separable such funcoid f that f FCD f 1 is T 1 -separable. Definition 113. Let call T 2 -separable such funcoid f that the funcoid f 1 f is T 1 -separable. For symmetric transitive funcoids T 1 - and T 2 -separability are the same (see theorem 13) Filter objects closed regarding a funcoid Definition 114. Let s call closed regarding a funcoid f such filter object A that f A A.

22 22 Section 4 This is a generalization of closedness of a set regarding an unary operation. Proposition 115. If I and J are closed (regarding some funcoid), S is a set of closed filter objects, then 1. I F J is a closed filter object; 2. F S is a closed filter object. Let denote the given funcoid as f. f (I F J) = f I F f J I F J, f F S F f S F S. Consequently the filter objects I F J and F S are closed. Proposition 116. If S is a set of closed regarding a complete funcoid filter objects, then the filter object F S is also closed regarding our funcoid. f F S= F f S F S where f is the given funcoid. 4 Reloids Definition 117. I will call a reloid a filter object on the set of binary relations. Reloids are a generalization of uniform spaces. Also reloids are generalization of binary relations. Definition 118. The reverse reloid of a reloid f is defined by the formula upf 1 = { F 1 F upf 1}. Reverse reloid is a generalization of conjugate quasi-uniformity. 4.1 Composition of reloids Definition 119. Composition of reloids is defined by the formula g f = RLD {G F F upf,g upg}. Composition of reloids is a reloid. Lemma 120. (h g) f =h (g f) for any reloids f, g, h. For two nonempty collections A and B of sets I will denote A B ( K A L B:L K) ( K B L A:L K). It is easy to see that is a transitive relation. I will denote B A={L K K A,L B}. Let first prove that for any nonempty collections of relations A, B, C A B A C B C. Suppose A B and P A C that is K A and M C such that P =K M. K B:K K because A B. We have P =K M B C. Obviously P P. So for any P A C exist P B C such that P P ; vice verse is analogous. So A C B C. up((h g) f) up(h g) upf, up(h g) (uph) (upg). By proven above up((h g) f) (uph) (upg) (upf). Analogously up(h (g f)) (uph) (upg) (upf). So up((h g) f) up(h (g f)) what is possible only if up((h g) f)=up(h (g f)).

23 Reloids 23 Theorem f f = RLD {F F F upf}; 2. f 1 f = { RLD F 1 F F upf } ; 3. f f 1 = { RLD F F 1 F upf }. I will prove only (1) and (2) because (3) is analogous to (2). [FIXME: Proof here.] Conjecture 122. If f, g, h are reloids then 1. f (g RLD h)=f g RLD f h; 2. (g RLD h) f =g f RLD h f. 4.2 Direct product of filter objects In theory of reloids direct product of filter objects A and B is defined by the formula A RLD B= def F {A B A upa,b upb}. Theorem 123. A RLD B= F { a RLD b a atoms F A, b atoms F B } for any A,B F. Obviously A RLD B F { a RLD b a atoms F A, b atoms F B } Reversely, let K up { F a RLD b a atoms F A, b atoms F B }. Then K up(a RLD b) for every a atoms F A, b atoms F B; K X a RLD Y b for some X a up a, Y b upb; K { X a Y b a atoms F A, b atoms F B } = { X a a atoms F A } { Y b b atoms F A } = A B where A upa, B upb; K up(a RLD B). Theorem 124. A 0 RLD B 0 RLD A 1 RLD B 1 =(A 0 RLD A 1 ) RLD (B 0 RLD B 1 ) for any A 0,A 1, B 0,B 1 F. A 0 RLD B 0 RLD A 1 RLD B 1 = RLD { P Q P up(a 0 RLD B 0 ),Q up(a 1 RLD B 1 ) } = RLD {A 0 B 0 A 1 B 1 A 0 upa 0, B 0 upb 0, A 1 upa 1, B 1 upb 1 } = RLD {(A 0 A 1 ) (B 0 B 1 ) A 0 upa 0,B 0 upb 0,A 1 upa 1, B 1 upb 1 } = RLD {K L K up(a 0 A 1 ),L up(b 0 B 1 )} = (A 0 RLD A 1 ) RLD (B 0 RLD B 1 ). Theorem 125. If S PF 2 then RLD { A RLD B (A;B) S } = F doms RLD F ims. Let P = F doms, Q= F ims; l= RLD { A RLD B (A;B) S }. P RLD Q l is obvious. Let F up(p RLD Q). Then exist P upp and Q upq such that F P Q. P =P 1 P n where P i up doms and Q=Q 1 Q m where Q i up ims. P Q= i,j (P i Q i ). P i Q i A RLD B for some (A;B) S. P Q= i,j (P i Q i ) l. F upl.

24 24 Section 4 Conjecture 126. If A F then A RLD is a complete homomorphism of the lattice F to a complete sublattice of the lattice RLD, if also A then it is an isomorphism. Definition 127. I will call a reloid convex iff it is a union of direct products. I will call two filter objects isomorphic when the corresponding filters are isomorphic (in the sense defined in [5]). Theorem 128. The reloid {a} RLD F is isomorphic to the filter object F for every a. Consider B={a} and f ={(x;(a;x)) x }. Then f is a bijection from to B. If X upf then f X B and f X ={a} X up({a} RLD F). For every Y up({a} RLD F) PB we have Y ={a} X for some X upf and thus Y = f X. So f up F P = f up F is a bijection from upf P to up({a} RLD F) PB. We have upf P and up({a} RLD F) PB directly isomorphic and thus upf is isomorphic to up({a} RLD F). 4.3 Restricting reloid to a filter object. Domain and image Definition 129. I call restricting a reloid f to a filter object A as f A =f RLD A RLD. Definition 130. Domain and image of a reloid f are defined as follows: domf = F dom upf; imf = F im upf. Proposition 131. f A RLD B domf A imf B. Direct implication. Follows from dom(a RLD B) A im(a RLD B) B. Reverse implication. domf A A upa F upf: domf A. Analogously imf B B upb G upf: img B. Let dom f A im f B, A upa, B upb. Then exist F up f, G up f such that domf A img B. Consequently F G upf, dom(f G) A, im(f G) B that is F G A B. We have exists H up f such that H A B for any A upa, B upb. So f A RLD B. Definition 132. I call identity reloid for a filter object A the reloid I A = def (=) A. Theorem 133. I A = F {I A A upa} where I A is the identity relation on a set A. Let K up F {I A A upa}, then exists A upa such that K I A. Then (=) A = (=) RLD A (=) A = I A K; K up I A. Reversely let K up I A = up((=) RLD A RLD ), then exists A upa such that K up((=) A )=upi A upi A. Proposition 134. I A 1 =I A. Follows from the previous theorem. Theorem 135. f A =f I A for any reloid f and filter object A. We need to prove that f RLD A = f RLD {I A A upa}. f RLD {I A A upa}= RLD {F I A F up f,a upa}= RLD {F A F up f,a upa}= RLD {F A F upf,a upa}= RLD {F F upf} RLD {A A upa}=f RLD A RLD.

25 Relationships of funcoids and reloids 25 Theorem 136. (g f) A =g (f A ) for any reloids f and g and filter object A. (g f) A =(g f) I A =g (f I A )=g (f A ). Theorem 137. f RLD A RLD B=I B f I A for any reloid f and filter objects A and B. f RLD A RLD B=f RLD A RLD RLD RLD B=f A RLD B=f I A RLD B=((f I A ) 1 RLD ( RLD B) 1 ) 1 =(I A f 1 RLD B RLD ) 1 =(I A f 1 I B ) 1 =I B f I A. 4.4 Category of reloids I will define the category RLD of reloids: The set of objects is F. The set of morphisms from a filter object A to a filter object B is the set of triples (f;a; B) where f is a reloid such that domf A, imf B. Composition of morphisms is defined in the natural way. Identity morphism of a filter object A is (I A ;A;A). To prove that it is really a category is trivial Monovalued reloids Following the idea of definition of monovalued morphism let s call monovalued such a reloid f that f f 1 I im f. Obvious 138. A morphism (f;a;b) of the category of reloids is monovalued iff the reloid f is monovalued. Conjecture 139. If a reloid is monovalued then it is a monovalued function restricted to some filter object. Conjecture 140. A reloid f is monovalued iff g RLD:(g f A F:g=f A ). Conjecture 141. A monovalued reloid restricted to an atomic filter object is atomic or empty. A weaker conjecture: Conjecture 142. A (monovalued) function restricted to an atomic filter object is atomic or empty. 5 Relationships of funcoids and reloids 5.1 Funcoid induced by a reloid Every reloid f induces a funcoid (FCD)f by the following formulas: X[(FCD)f]Y F upf:x[f]y (FCD)f X = F { F X F upf}. We should prove that (FCD)f is really a funcoid. For this purpose we will additionally define (FCD)f 1 Y = F { F 1 Y F upf }. We need to prove that X[(FCD)f]Y Y F (FCD)f X X F (FCD)f 1 Y.

26 26 Section 5 The above formula is equivalent to: F upf:x[f]y Y F F { F X F upf} X F F { F 1 Y F upf }. We have Y F F { F X F upf}= { F Y F F X F upf }. Let s denote W = { Y F F X F upf }. We need to prove that F W F up f: Y F F X. (The rest follows from symmetry.) Let s prove that W is a generalized filter base. [TODO: Simplify this proof.] Let A, B W that is A=Y F P X, B=Y F Q X where P, Q up f. Then for C =Y F P Q X is true both C W and C A,B. So W is a generalized filter base. From this by the corollary 4 follows that F W W F upf:y F F X. Theorem 143. X[(FCD)f]Y X RLD Y f for any X,Y F and f RLD. X RLD Y RLD f P up(x RLD Y):P RLD f F upf,p up(x RLD Y):P F F upf, X upx,y upy:x RLD Y RLD F F upf,x upx,y upy:x[f]y F upf:x[f]y X[(FCD)f]Y. Theorem 144. (FCD)f = FCD upf for any reloid f. Let a is an atomic filter object. ((FCD)f)a= F { F a F upf} by the definition of (FCD). FCD upf a= F { F a F upf} by the theorem 53. So (FCD)f a= FCD upf a for any atomic filter object a. Lemma 145. g F S= F g S if g is a funcoid and S is a filter base. up F S= up S by the theorem 3. g F S= F g up F S by the theorem 33. F g up F S= F g up S. Easy to see that F g up S= F g S because S up S. Combining these equalities we produce g F S= F g S. Lemma 146. For two sets of binary relations S and T and a set A F S= F T F { F A F S}= F { G A G T} Let F S = F T. Suppose X up F { F A F S}. Then X { F A F S} where X X. That is X = F A for some F S. There exists G T such that G F. So Y = G A X X. Y { G A G T}; Y up F { G A G T}; X up F { G A G T}. The reverse is symmetric. Theorem 147. (FCD)(g f)=((fcd)g) ((FCD)f) for any reloids f and g. (FCD)(g f) X = F { H X H up(g f)} = { F H X H up } RLD {G F F upf,g upg}.

Funcoids and Reloids

Funcoids and Reloids Funcoids and Reloids by Victor Porton March 29, 2010 Abstract It is a part of my Algebraic General Topology research. In this article I introduce the concepts of funcoids which generalize proximity spaces

More information

Funcoids and Reloids a generalization of proximities and uniformities

Funcoids and Reloids a generalization of proximities and uniformities Funcoids and Reloids a generalization of proximities and uniformities by Victor Porton October 26, 2010 Abstract It is a part of my Algebraic General Topology research. In this article I introduce the

More information

I m not a professional mathematician, I work as a programmer.

I m not a professional mathematician, I work as a programmer. About myself I m not a professional mathematician, I work as a programmer. I have been studying in a university in Russia but have not finished my study. So, I know little beyond my specialization. Nevertheless

More information

Filters on posets and generalizations

Filters on posets and generalizations Filters on posets and generalizations Victor Porton 78640, Shay Agnon 32-29, Ashkelon, Israel Abstract They are studied in details properties of filters on lattices, filters on posets, and certain generalizations

More information

Open Problems in Algebraic General Topology

Open Problems in Algebraic General Topology Open Problems in Algebraic General Topology by Victor Porton September 10, 2016 Abstract This document lists in one place all conjectures and open problems in my Algebraic General Topology research which

More information

Algebraic General Topology. Volume 1. Victor Porton. address: URL:

Algebraic General Topology. Volume 1. Victor Porton.  address: URL: Algebraic General Topology. Volume 1 Victor Porton Email address: porton@narod.ru URL: http://www.mathematics21.org 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. 54J05, 54A05, 54D99, 54E05, 54E15, 54E17, 54E99

More information

Connectors and generalized connectedness

Connectors and generalized connectedness Connectors and generalized connectedness Victor Porton 77711, Metzada 107-39, Ashdod, Israel Abstract I define connectors and generalized connectedness which generalizes topological connectedness, path

More information

Algebraic General Topology. Volume 2 partial draft. Victor Porton. address: URL:

Algebraic General Topology. Volume 2 partial draft. Victor Porton.  address: URL: Algebraic General Topology. Volume 2 partial draft Victor Porton Email address: porton@narod.ru URL: http://www.mathematics21.org 2000 Mathematics Subject lassification. 54J05, 54A05, 54D99, 54E05, 54E15,

More information

CHAPTER 1. AFFINE ALGEBRAIC VARIETIES

CHAPTER 1. AFFINE ALGEBRAIC VARIETIES CHAPTER 1. AFFINE ALGEBRAIC VARIETIES During this first part of the course, we will establish a correspondence between various geometric notions and algebraic ones. Some references for this part of the

More information

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths.

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths. CATEGORY THEORY PROFESSOR PETER JOHNSTONE Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths. Definition 1.1. A category C consists

More information

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Sergiu Rudeanu University of Bucharest Romania Closure operators are abundant in mathematics; here are a few examples. Given an algebraic structure, such

More information

Binary Operations Applied to Functions

Binary Operations Applied to Functions FORMALIZED MATHEMATICS Vol.1, No.2, March April 1990 Université Catholique de Louvain Binary Operations Applied to Functions Andrzej Trybulec 1 Warsaw University Bia lystok Summary. In the article we introduce

More information

Partial, Total, and Lattice Orders in Group Theory

Partial, Total, and Lattice Orders in Group Theory Partial, Total, and Lattice Orders in Group Theory Hayden Harper Department of Mathematics and Computer Science University of Puget Sound April 23, 2016 Copyright c 2016 Hayden Harper. Permission is granted

More information

Appendix A. Definitions for Ordered Sets. The appendices contain all the formal definitions, propositions and proofs for

Appendix A. Definitions for Ordered Sets. The appendices contain all the formal definitions, propositions and proofs for 161 Appendix A Definitions for Ordered Sets The appendices contain all the formal definitions, propositions and proofs for developing a model of the display process based on lattices. Here we list some

More information

Definitions. Notations. Injective, Surjective and Bijective. Divides. Cartesian Product. Relations. Equivalence Relations

Definitions. Notations. Injective, Surjective and Bijective. Divides. Cartesian Product. Relations. Equivalence Relations Page 1 Definitions Tuesday, May 8, 2018 12:23 AM Notations " " means "equals, by definition" the set of all real numbers the set of integers Denote a function from a set to a set by Denote the image of

More information

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Hongtaek Jung December 27, 2017 Abstract This is a part of a supplementary note for a Logic and Set Theory course. The main goal is to

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos. Martino Garonzi. Universidade de Brasília. Primeiro semestre 2018

Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos. Martino Garonzi. Universidade de Brasília. Primeiro semestre 2018 Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos Martino Garonzi Universidade de Brasília Primeiro semestre 2018 1 Le risposte uccidono le domande. 2 Contents 1 Topology 4 2 Profinite spaces 6 3 Topological groups 10 4

More information

Rings and groups. Ya. Sysak

Rings and groups. Ya. Sysak Rings and groups. Ya. Sysak 1 Noetherian rings Let R be a ring. A (right) R -module M is called noetherian if it satisfies the maximum condition for its submodules. In other words, if M 1... M i M i+1...

More information

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a Solutions to Homework #6 1. Complete the proof of the backwards direction of Theorem 12.2 from class (which asserts the any interval in R is connected). Solution: Let X R be a closed interval. Case 1:

More information

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories PART I Abstract algebraic categories It should be observed first that the whole concept of category is essentially an auxiliary one; our basic concepts are those of a functor and a natural transformation.

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato September 10, 2015 ABSTRACT. This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a

More information

Multidimensional Funcoids

Multidimensional Funcoids Multidimensional Funcoids by Victor Porton 78640, Shay Agnon 32-29, Ashkelon, Israel Web: http://www.mathematics21.org Abstract First I define a product of two funcoids. Then I define multifuncoids and

More information

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees Francesc Rosselló 1, Gabriel Valiente 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Research Institute

More information

Chapter 0. Introduction: Prerequisites and Preliminaries

Chapter 0. Introduction: Prerequisites and Preliminaries Chapter 0. Sections 0.1 to 0.5 1 Chapter 0. Introduction: Prerequisites and Preliminaries Note. The content of Sections 0.1 through 0.6 should be very familiar to you. However, in order to keep these notes

More information

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) Contents. 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) Contents. 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) JAN ŠŤOVÍČEK Contents 1. Affine varieties 1 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30 1. Affine varieties The basic objects

More information

Zaslavsky s Theorem. As presented by Eric Samansky May 11, 2002

Zaslavsky s Theorem. As presented by Eric Samansky May 11, 2002 Zaslavsky s Theorem As presented by Eric Samansky May, 2002 Abstract This paper is a retelling of the proof of Zaslavsky s Theorem. For any arrangement of hyperplanes, there is a corresponding semi-lattice

More information

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi Real Analysis Math 3AH Rudin, Chapter # Dominique Abdi.. If r is rational (r 0) and x is irrational, prove that r + x and rx are irrational. Solution. Assume the contrary, that r+x and rx are rational.

More information

Introduction to Restriction Categories

Introduction to Restriction Categories Introduction to Restriction Categories Robin Cockett Department of Computer Science University of Calgary Alberta, Canada robin@cpsc.ucalgary.ca Estonia, March 2010 Defining restriction categories Examples

More information

Adjunctions! Everywhere!

Adjunctions! Everywhere! Adjunctions! Everywhere! Carnegie Mellon University Thursday 19 th September 2013 Clive Newstead Abstract What do free groups, existential quantifiers and Stone-Čech compactifications all have in common?

More information

A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces

A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces Reinhold Heckmann AbsInt Angewandte Informatik GmbH, Stuhlsatzenhausweg 69, D-66123 Saarbrücken, Germany e-mail: heckmann@absint.com Abstract The category

More information

Notes about Filters. Samuel Mimram. December 6, 2012

Notes about Filters. Samuel Mimram. December 6, 2012 Notes about Filters Samuel Mimram December 6, 2012 1 Filters and ultrafilters Definition 1. A filter F on a poset (L, ) is a subset of L which is upwardclosed and downward-directed (= is a filter-base):

More information

Algebras. Larry Moss Indiana University, Bloomington. TACL 13 Summer School, Vanderbilt University

Algebras. Larry Moss Indiana University, Bloomington. TACL 13 Summer School, Vanderbilt University 1/39 Algebras Larry Moss Indiana University, Bloomington TACL 13 Summer School, Vanderbilt University 2/39 Binary trees Let T be the set which starts out as,,,, 2/39 Let T be the set which starts out as,,,,

More information

ON SOME BASIC CONSTRUCTIONS IN CATEGORIES OF QUANTALE-VALUED SUP-LATTICES. 1. Introduction

ON SOME BASIC CONSTRUCTIONS IN CATEGORIES OF QUANTALE-VALUED SUP-LATTICES. 1. Introduction Math. Appl. 5 (2016, 39 53 DOI: 10.13164/ma.2016.04 ON SOME BASIC CONSTRUCTIONS IN CATEGORIES OF QUANTALE-VALUED SUP-LATTICES RADEK ŠLESINGER Abstract. If the standard concepts of partial-order relation

More information

PERVERSE SHEAVES ON A TRIANGULATED SPACE

PERVERSE SHEAVES ON A TRIANGULATED SPACE PERVERSE SHEAVES ON A TRIANGULATED SPACE A. POLISHCHUK The goal of this note is to prove that the category of perverse sheaves constructible with respect to a triangulation is Koszul (i.e. equivalent to

More information

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07)

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07) P. J. Šafárik University, Faculty of Science, Košice Project 2005/NP1-051 11230100466 Basic information Extent: 2 hrs lecture/1 hrs seminar per week. Assessment: Written tests during the semester, written

More information

Sequential product on effect logics

Sequential product on effect logics Sequential product on effect logics Bas Westerbaan bas@westerbaan.name Thesis for the Master s Examination Mathematics at the Radboud University Nijmegen, supervised by prof. dr. B.P.F. Jacobs with second

More information

FUNDAMENTAL GROUPS AND THE VAN KAMPEN S THEOREM. Contents

FUNDAMENTAL GROUPS AND THE VAN KAMPEN S THEOREM. Contents FUNDAMENTAL GROUPS AND THE VAN KAMPEN S THEOREM SAMUEL BLOOM Abstract. In this paper, we define the fundamental group of a topological space and explore its structure, and we proceed to prove Van-Kampen

More information

A general Stone representation theorem

A general Stone representation theorem arxiv:math/0608384v1 [math.lo] 15 Aug 2006 A general Stone representation theorem Mirna; after a paper by A. Jung and P. Sünderhauf and notes by G. Plebanek September 10, 2018 This note contains a Stone-style

More information

Lecture 2. x if x X B n f(x) = α(x) if x S n 1 D n

Lecture 2. x if x X B n f(x) = α(x) if x S n 1 D n Lecture 2 1.10 Cell attachments Let X be a topological space and α : S n 1 X be a map. Consider the space X D n with the disjoint union topology. Consider further the set X B n and a function f : X D n

More information

NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF SINGAPORE. Department of Mathematics. MA4247 Complex Analysis II. Lecture Notes Part IV

NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF SINGAPORE. Department of Mathematics. MA4247 Complex Analysis II. Lecture Notes Part IV NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF SINGAPORE Department of Mathematics MA4247 Complex Analysis II Lecture Notes Part IV Chapter 2. Further properties of analytic/holomorphic functions (continued) 2.4. The Open mapping

More information

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS. Disclaimer: There are millions of errors in these notes!

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS. Disclaimer: There are millions of errors in these notes! ALGEBRAIC GROUPS Disclaimer: There are millions of errors in these notes! 1. Some algebraic geometry The subject of algebraic groups depends on the interaction between algebraic geometry and group theory.

More information

Convex Optimization Notes

Convex Optimization Notes Convex Optimization Notes Jonathan Siegel January 2017 1 Convex Analysis This section is devoted to the study of convex functions f : B R {+ } and convex sets U B, for B a Banach space. The case of B =

More information

Topological properties

Topological properties CHAPTER 4 Topological properties 1. Connectedness Definitions and examples Basic properties Connected components Connected versus path connected, again 2. Compactness Definition and first examples Topological

More information

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, 2017 1 Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski Class of August 17: Course and syllabus overview. Topology

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato June 23, 2015 This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a more direct connection

More information

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal semigroup rings and formal power series rings We next want to explore the notion of a (formal) power series ring in finitely

More information

Algebraic Geometry: Limits and Colimits

Algebraic Geometry: Limits and Colimits Algebraic Geometry: Limits and Coits Limits Definition.. Let I be a small category, C be any category, and F : I C be a functor. If for each object i I and morphism m ij Mor I (i, j) there is an associated

More information

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012 Logic via Algebra Sam Chong Tay A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012 Abstract The purpose of this paper is to gain insight to mathematical logic through an algebraic perspective.

More information

Ultraproducts of Finite Groups

Ultraproducts of Finite Groups Ultraproducts of Finite Groups Ben Reid May 11, 010 1 Background 1.1 Ultrafilters Let S be any set, and let P (S) denote the power set of S. We then call ψ P (S) a filter over S if the following conditions

More information

DISCRETE MATH (A LITTLE) & BASIC GROUP THEORY - PART 3/3. Contents

DISCRETE MATH (A LITTLE) & BASIC GROUP THEORY - PART 3/3. Contents DISCRETE MATH (A LITTLE) & BASIC GROUP THEORY - PART 3/3 T.K.SUBRAHMONIAN MOOTHATHU Contents 1. Cayley s Theorem 1 2. The permutation group S n 2 3. Center of a group, and centralizers 4 4. Group actions

More information

Reid 5.2. Describe the irreducible components of V (J) for J = (y 2 x 4, x 2 2x 3 x 2 y + 2xy + y 2 y) in k[x, y, z]. Here k is algebraically closed.

Reid 5.2. Describe the irreducible components of V (J) for J = (y 2 x 4, x 2 2x 3 x 2 y + 2xy + y 2 y) in k[x, y, z]. Here k is algebraically closed. Reid 5.2. Describe the irreducible components of V (J) for J = (y 2 x 4, x 2 2x 3 x 2 y + 2xy + y 2 y) in k[x, y, z]. Here k is algebraically closed. Answer: Note that the first generator factors as (y

More information

Axiomatisation of Hybrid Logic

Axiomatisation of Hybrid Logic Imperial College London Department of Computing Axiomatisation of Hybrid Logic by Louis Paternault Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the MSc Degree in Advanced Computing of Imperial

More information

7. Homotopy and the Fundamental Group

7. Homotopy and the Fundamental Group 7. Homotopy and the Fundamental Group The group G will be called the fundamental group of the manifold V. J. Henri Poincaré, 895 The properties of a topological space that we have developed so far have

More information

Constructive version of Boolean algebra

Constructive version of Boolean algebra Constructive version of Boolean algebra Francesco Ciraulo, Maria Emilia Maietti, Paola Toto Abstract The notion of overlap algebra introduced by G. Sambin provides a constructive version of complete Boolean

More information

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property Congruence Boolean Lifting Property George GEORGESCU and Claudia MUREŞAN University of Bucharest Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Academiei 14, RO 010014, Bucharest, Romania Emails: georgescu.capreni@yahoo.com;

More information

Optimization and Optimal Control in Banach Spaces

Optimization and Optimal Control in Banach Spaces Optimization and Optimal Control in Banach Spaces Bernhard Schmitzer October 19, 2017 1 Convex non-smooth optimization with proximal operators Remark 1.1 (Motivation). Convex optimization: easier to solve,

More information

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA These are notes for our first unit on the algebraic side of homological algebra. While this is the last topic (Chap XX) in the book, it makes sense to

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

11 Annihilators. Suppose that R, S, and T are rings, that R P S, S Q T, and R U T are bimodules, and finally, that

11 Annihilators. Suppose that R, S, and T are rings, that R P S, S Q T, and R U T are bimodules, and finally, that 11 Annihilators. In this Section we take a brief look at the important notion of annihilators. Although we shall use these in only very limited contexts, we will give a fairly general initial treatment,

More information

Section Summary. Relations and Functions Properties of Relations. Combining Relations

Section Summary. Relations and Functions Properties of Relations. Combining Relations Chapter 9 Chapter Summary Relations and Their Properties n-ary Relations and Their Applications (not currently included in overheads) Representing Relations Closures of Relations (not currently included

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

Denotational Semantics

Denotational Semantics 5 Denotational Semantics In the operational approach, we were interested in how a program is executed. This is contrary to the denotational approach, where we are merely interested in the effect of executing

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017 Luca Carai and Silvio Ghilardi arxiv:1702.08352v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017 Università degli Studi di Milano, Milano, Italy luca.carai@studenti.unimi.it silvio.ghilardi@unimi.it July 26, 2017 Abstract The

More information

Constructive version of Boolean algebra

Constructive version of Boolean algebra Constructive version of Boolean algebra Francesco Ciraulo, Maria Emilia Maietti, Paola Toto Abstract The notion of overlap algebra introduced by G. Sambin provides a constructive version of complete Boolean

More information

Fuzzy Sets. Mirko Navara navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 28, 2019

Fuzzy Sets. Mirko Navara   navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 28, 2019 The notion of fuzzy set. Minimum about classical) sets Fuzzy ets Mirko Navara http://cmp.felk.cvut.cz/ navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 8, 09 To aviod problems of the set theory, we restrict ourselves

More information

Math 203A - Solution Set 4

Math 203A - Solution Set 4 Math 203A - Solution Set 4 Problem 1. Let X and Y be prevarieties with affine open covers {U i } and {V j }, respectively. (i) Construct the product prevariety X Y by glueing the affine varieties U i V

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY

A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY Tame congruence theory is not an easy subject and it takes a considerable amount of effort to understand it. When I started this project, I believed that this

More information

which is a group homomorphism, such that if W V U, then

which is a group homomorphism, such that if W V U, then 4. Sheaves Definition 4.1. Let X be a topological space. A presheaf of groups F on X is a a function which assigns to every open set U X a group F(U) and to every inclusion V U a restriction map, ρ UV

More information

Convex Functions and Optimization

Convex Functions and Optimization Chapter 5 Convex Functions and Optimization 5.1 Convex Functions Our next topic is that of convex functions. Again, we will concentrate on the context of a map f : R n R although the situation can be generalized

More information

1.1 Definition. A monoid is a set M together with a map. 1.3 Definition. A monoid is commutative if x y = y x for all x, y M.

1.1 Definition. A monoid is a set M together with a map. 1.3 Definition. A monoid is commutative if x y = y x for all x, y M. 1 Monoids and groups 1.1 Definition. A monoid is a set M together with a map M M M, (x, y) x y such that (i) (x y) z = x (y z) x, y, z M (associativity); (ii) e M such that x e = e x = x for all x M (e

More information

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15 CHAPTER 15 Boolean Algebra 15.1 INTRODUCTION Both sets and propositions satisfy similar laws, which are listed in Tables 1-1 and 4-1 (in Chapters 1 and 4, respectively). These laws are used to define an

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Universal Algebra for Logics

Universal Algebra for Logics Universal Algebra for Logics Joanna GRYGIEL University of Czestochowa Poland j.grygiel@ajd.czest.pl 2005 These notes form Lecture Notes of a short course which I will give at 1st School on Universal Logic

More information

Chapter 1. Logic and Proof

Chapter 1. Logic and Proof Chapter 1. Logic and Proof 1.1 Remark: A little over 100 years ago, it was found that some mathematical proofs contained paradoxes, and these paradoxes could be used to prove statements that were known

More information

Contents. Index... 15

Contents. Index... 15 Contents Filter Bases and Nets................................................................................ 5 Filter Bases and Ultrafilters: A Brief Overview.........................................................

More information

FUNCTORS AND ADJUNCTIONS. 1. Functors

FUNCTORS AND ADJUNCTIONS. 1. Functors FUNCTORS AND ADJUNCTIONS Abstract. Graphs, quivers, natural transformations, adjunctions, Galois connections, Galois theory. 1.1. Graph maps. 1. Functors 1.1.1. Quivers. Quivers generalize directed graphs,

More information

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions 1. Suppose k is a positive integer. Use induction to prove the following two statements. (a) For all n N 0, the inequality (k 2 + n)! k 2n holds.

More information

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS.

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS. FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS. Let A be a ring, for simplicity assumed commutative. A filtering, or filtration, of an A module M means a descending sequence of submodules M = M 0

More information

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University February 7, 2007 2 Contents 1 Metric Spaces 1 1.1 Basic definitions...........................

More information

AAA616: Program Analysis. Lecture 3 Denotational Semantics

AAA616: Program Analysis. Lecture 3 Denotational Semantics AAA616: Program Analysis Lecture 3 Denotational Semantics Hakjoo Oh 2018 Spring Hakjoo Oh AAA616 2018 Spring, Lecture 3 March 28, 2018 1 / 33 Denotational Semantics In denotational semantics, we are interested

More information

Homework 5. Solutions

Homework 5. Solutions Homework 5. Solutions 1. Let (X,T) be a topological space and let A,B be subsets of X. Show that the closure of their union is given by A B = A B. Since A B is a closed set that contains A B and A B is

More information

MATH 101A: ALGEBRA I PART C: TENSOR PRODUCT AND MULTILINEAR ALGEBRA. This is the title page for the notes on tensor products and multilinear algebra.

MATH 101A: ALGEBRA I PART C: TENSOR PRODUCT AND MULTILINEAR ALGEBRA. This is the title page for the notes on tensor products and multilinear algebra. MATH 101A: ALGEBRA I PART C: TENSOR PRODUCT AND MULTILINEAR ALGEBRA This is the title page for the notes on tensor products and multilinear algebra. Contents 1. Bilinear forms and quadratic forms 1 1.1.

More information

Foundations of Mathematics

Foundations of Mathematics Foundations of Mathematics Andrew Monnot 1 Construction of the Language Loop We must yield to a cyclic approach in the foundations of mathematics. In this respect we begin with some assumptions of language

More information

3.1 Basic properties of real numbers - continuation Inmum and supremum of a set of real numbers

3.1 Basic properties of real numbers - continuation Inmum and supremum of a set of real numbers Chapter 3 Real numbers The notion of real number was introduced in section 1.3 where the axiomatic denition of the set of all real numbers was done and some basic properties of the set of all real numbers

More information

3. Categories and Functors We recall the definition of a category: Definition 3.1. A category C is the data of two collections. The first collection

3. Categories and Functors We recall the definition of a category: Definition 3.1. A category C is the data of two collections. The first collection 3. Categories and Functors We recall the definition of a category: Definition 3.1. A category C is the data of two collections. The first collection is called the objects of C and is denoted Obj(C). Given

More information

Axioms of Kleene Algebra

Axioms of Kleene Algebra Introduction to Kleene Algebra Lecture 2 CS786 Spring 2004 January 28, 2004 Axioms of Kleene Algebra In this lecture we give the formal definition of a Kleene algebra and derive some basic consequences.

More information

A fresh perspective on canonical extensions for bounded lattices

A fresh perspective on canonical extensions for bounded lattices A fresh perspective on canonical extensions for bounded lattices Mathematical Institute, University of Oxford Department of Mathematics, Matej Bel University Second International Conference on Order, Algebra

More information

HOMOLOGY THEORIES INGRID STARKEY

HOMOLOGY THEORIES INGRID STARKEY HOMOLOGY THEORIES INGRID STARKEY Abstract. This paper will introduce the notion of homology for topological spaces and discuss its intuitive meaning. It will also describe a general method that is used

More information

cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska

cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska LECTURE 1 Course Web Page www3.cs.stonybrook.edu/ cse303 The webpage contains: lectures notes slides; very detailed solutions to

More information

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT)

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT) CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT) MATH 378, CSUSM. SPRING 2009. AITKEN This chapter reviews some of the background concepts needed for Math 378. This chapter is new to the course (added Spring

More information

ACLT: Algebra, Categories, Logic in Topology - Grothendieck's generalized topological spaces (toposes)

ACLT: Algebra, Categories, Logic in Topology - Grothendieck's generalized topological spaces (toposes) ACLT: Algebra, Categories, Logic in Topology - Grothendieck's generalized topological spaces (toposes) Steve Vickers CS Theory Group Birmingham 2. Theories and models Categorical approach to many-sorted

More information

On z -ideals in C(X) F. A z a r p a n a h, O. A. S. K a r a m z a d e h and A. R e z a i A l i a b a d (Ahvaz)

On z -ideals in C(X) F. A z a r p a n a h, O. A. S. K a r a m z a d e h and A. R e z a i A l i a b a d (Ahvaz) F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 160 (1999) On z -ideals in C(X) by F. A z a r p a n a h, O. A. S. K a r a m z a d e h and A. R e z a i A l i a b a d (Ahvaz) Abstract. An ideal I in a commutative ring

More information

Math 341: Convex Geometry. Xi Chen

Math 341: Convex Geometry. Xi Chen Math 341: Convex Geometry Xi Chen 479 Central Academic Building, University of Alberta, Edmonton, Alberta T6G 2G1, CANADA E-mail address: xichen@math.ualberta.ca CHAPTER 1 Basics 1. Euclidean Geometry

More information

(1) A frac = b : a, b A, b 0. We can define addition and multiplication of fractions as we normally would. a b + c d

(1) A frac = b : a, b A, b 0. We can define addition and multiplication of fractions as we normally would. a b + c d The Algebraic Method 0.1. Integral Domains. Emmy Noether and others quickly realized that the classical algebraic number theory of Dedekind could be abstracted completely. In particular, rings of integers

More information

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SERGIO A. CELANI AND MARÍA ESTEBAN Abstract. Distributive Hilbert Algebras with infimum, or DH -algebras, are algebras with implication

More information