Sequential product on effect logics

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Sequential product on effect logics"

Transcription

1 Sequential product on effect logics Bas Westerbaan Thesis for the Master s Examination Mathematics at the Radboud University Nijmegen, supervised by prof. dr. B.P.F. Jacobs with second reader drs. J. Mandemaker, written by Bastiaan E. Westerbaan, student number , on August 15th Second corrected version, September 26th 2013.

2 Abstract In categorical logic predicates on an object X are traditionally represented as subobjects. Jacobs proposes [9] an alternative in which the predicates on X are maps p: X X + X with [id, id] p = id. If the coproduct of the category is well-behaved, the predicates form an effect algebra. So this approach is called effect logic. In the three prime examples of effect logics, a sequential effect algebra arises naturally. These structures are studied by Greechie and others in quantum logic. In this thesis we study several variations on effect logics, and prove that in these variations sequential effect algebras do not arise. 2

3 1 Introduction 1.1 Starting point Given a category C with coproducts and an object X of C. Following [9], define the (internal) predicates on X as ipred(x) = {p: X X + X; [id, id] p = id}. In Set, the category of sets, the predicates on X correspond to subsets: ipred Set (X) = { { x x U p U ; p U (x) = κ 2 x x / U ; U X}. In Kl(D), the Kleisli category of the distribution monad, the predicates on X correspond to maps X [0, 1]: ipred Kl(D) (X) = { p ψ ; p ψ (x) = ψ(x) x + (1 ψ(x))κ 2 x; ψ : X [0, 1] }. In Hilb, the category of Hilbert spaces with (bounded linear) operators, the predicates on X correspond to operators on X: ipred Hilb (X) = { p A ; p A (x) = (Ax, x Ax); A: X X }. If the category C is well-behaved, then ipred(x) carries an algebraic structure: it is an effect module. We will cover effect modules and related structures in Section 2. An effect module has (among other structure) a partially defined binary operation, a unary operation ( ) and a selected element 1. In the previous examples: C p q defined whenever p 1 Set U V U V = X U X Kl(D) ψ + χ ψ + χ 1 1 ψ 1 The predicates ipred(x) on a Hilbert space X do not form an effect module. However, the predicates that correspond to operators 0 A I, called positive predicates ppred(x), do form an effect module. C p q defined whenever p 1 Hilb A + B A + B I I A I In Set and Kl(D), there is an obvious way to extend the map X ipred(x) to a functor ipred: C EMod op. We write (f) for ipred(f). In the case of Hilbert spaces, the map X ppred(x) can be extended to a functor on the wide subcategory of Hilbert spaces with isometries: ppred: Hilb isom EMod op. We have three functors: Set Kl(D) Hilb isom ipred ipred ppred EMod op EMod op EMod op Assume we have any functor Pred: C EMod op. Any effect module is also a partially ordered set for each : X X + Y we have an order preserving 3

4 map ( ) : Pred(X +Y ) Pred(X). In our three examples, the map ( ) has a left and right order adjoint: ( ). Also, for each p Pred(X) there is an evident map char p : X X + X such that (char p ) 1 = p. On any Pred(X), we define p? (q), pronounced p andthen q, by In our examples, we have: p? (q) = (char p ) q. C Set Kl(D) Hilb isom p? (q) U V ψ χ AB A These three operations are examples of Sequential Products as defined by Gudder and Greechie [7] to study Quantum Logic. In fact, these are their prime examples as well. This leads to the following question, which is the starting point of this thesis: are there categorical axioms, which our examples obey, such that andthen is a sequential product as defined in [7]? 1.2 Overview First, we will cover in Section 2 the basic theory of several algebraic structures related to effect modules. Also a few specialized results will be proven, for instance on the existence of certain effect monoids, which will be used in the study of effect logics later on. Then, in Subsection 2.4, we introduce the sequential product as defined by Gudder and Greechie in [7]. We conclude the preliminaries by recalling some basic topics, such as galois connections, monads and the Kleisli category. We will assume the reader is familiar with Hilbert spaces and C -algebras. For an introductory text see [2]. To a lesser extend, we will assume familiarity with Category Theory. For an introductory text, see [1]. Before we will investigate effect logics in the line of [9], we will investigate, in Section 3, a weaker notion of effect logic, called weak effect logic. In a weak effect logic we start with a functor Pred: C EMod op of which we do not require that that Pred(X) = ipred(x). First we look at several examples of weak effect logics. Then, we prove a representation theorem to characterize the possible andthen that occur in a weak effect logic. In Section 4, we study effect logics. First we study internal predicates. Then we introduce the axioms of an effect logic and consider some examples. After that, we prove three representation theorems to partially characterize the andthen that occur in an effect logic. Finally, in Section 5, we summarize our results and state the open problems. We introduce some notions and prove some theorems that are not directly required for the results of this thesis. These are marked by a. We include these for one of two reasons. Either it is a negative result to justify our approach. For instance, the non-commutative effect monoid we construct in Subsection is rather complicated. One might expect that there is a finite example. That is 4

5 why we include Proposition 40, that states every finite effect monoid is commutative. Or: the result is a worthwhile deviation. For instance, to show there is a non-commutative effect monoid (Corollary 51) we only require one direction of the equivalence between OAU-algebras and convex effect monoids. However, the full result is worth proving. 5

6 Contents 1 Introduction Starting point Overview Preliminaries Effect algebras Some results on infima and suprema Isotropic index Interval effect algebras Convex effect algebras Lattice effect algebras Finite effect algebras Effect monoids Convex effect monoids and OAU-algebras Effect monoids on finite dimensional lexicographically ordered vector spaces Effect modules Sequential effect modules Examples Counterexamples Galois connections Kleisli category The distribution monad for an effect monoid Coproducts and split monos Weak effect logics Examples Basic theory Representation of weak sequential effect modules Effect logics Internal predicates Axioms Examples Set Kl(D M ) Hilb Representation theorems Conclusions Summary Further investigation Acknowledgments

7 2 Preliminaries Before we can fully state the axioms of (weak) effect logics, we need to introduce some algebraic structures of which the effect algebra, effect module and effect monoid are the most important. Also, we will use the notion of a Galois connection (or order adjunction). One class of effect logics is based on the Kleisli category of a distribution monad generalized to an arbitrary effect monoid. This class of effect logics is used to prove Theorem 116. Due to this theorem, we will study examples of non-commutative effect monoids. 2.1 Effect algebras In an effect logic, the set of predicates on an object will have (among others) the following algebraic structure. Definition 1 ([3]). Given a structure E,, 0, 1 where : E E E is a partial binary operation: we write a b whenever a b is defined and 0, 1 E are selected elements: 0 is called the zero and 1 the unit. This structure is called an effect algebra (EA) if the following holds. (E1) (partial commutativity) If a b then b a and a b = b a. (E2) (partial associativity) If a b and a b c, then b c, a b c and a (b c) = (a b) c. (E3) (unique orthocomplement) For every a E there exists a unique a such that a a = 1. (E4) If a 1, then a = 0. Given two effect algebras E and F a map f : E F is an effect algebra homomorphism if 1. f is additive, that is: when a b for a, b E, then also f(a) f(b) and furthermore: f(a) f(b) = f(a b) and 2. f preserves the unit, that is: f(1) = 1. The effect algebras along with their homomorphisms form a category called EA. Example 2. The following are effect algebras. 1. [0, 1], +, 0, 1 where [0, 1] R is the unit interval and + is the normal addition. x y whenever x + y 1 and x = 1 x. 2. P(X),,, X where P(X) is the set of subsets of X and is the disjoint union: A B whenever A B =. The orthocomplement is the normal complement: A = X A. 3. Eff(H ), +, 0, I where Eff(H ) are the positive operators on a Hilbert space below or equal to I; I is the unit operator and + is addition of operators. A B whenever A + B I and A = I A. 7

8 There is more structure on an effect algebra: there is a partial order and a difference. Before we define these, we need to derive some basic properties. Proposition 3. In any effect algebra, we have 1. (involution) a = a; 2. 1 = 0 and 0 = 1; 3. (zero) a 0 and a 0 = a; 4. (positivity) if a b = 0 then a = 0 and b = 0 and 5. (cancellation) if a b = a c then b = c. Proof. One at a time. 1. By (E3), we have a a = 1. Then by (E1), we have a a = 1. And thus by (E3) again, we must have a = a. 2. By (E3), we have 1 1 = 1. Then by (E4), we have 1 = 0. By the previous 1 = 1 = By (E3) and (E1), we have a a = 1. By the previous (a a) 0 = 1 0 = 1. Thus by (E2) we know a (a 0) = 1. Hence by (E3) we have a 0 = a. 4. By (E3) and the previous, we have (a b) 1 = 0 1 = 1. Then by (E2) we have b 1. Hence by (E4) we know b = 0. And similarly, using (E1), we see a = Since (a b) (a c) = (a b) (a b) = (((a b) a) b = 1, we know by uniqueness of the orthocomplement that b = ((a b) a) = c. Thus: effect algebras are partial commutative monoids with the extra axioms (E3) and (E4). Definition 4. We write a b if there exists a c such that a c = b. Proposition 5. For any effect algebra E. 1. E, is a poset; 2. a b if and only if b a ; 3. 0 is the minimum and 1 is the maximum element; 4. if a b and b c, then a c and a c b c and 5. a b if and only if a b. Proof. One by one. 1. First, reflexivity: a 0 = a thus a a. Then, anti-symmetry: suppose a b and b a. That is: there are c, d E such that a c = b and b d = a. Then a 0 = a = b d = (a c) d = a (c d). Hence by cancellation c d = 0. Thus by positivity c = d = 0. Consequently a = b d = b 0 = b. Finally, transitivity: suppose a b and b c. Then there are d, e E such that a d = b and b e = c. Hence c = b e = (a d) e = a (d e). Thus a c. 8

9 2. Suppose a b. Then a c = b for some c. Note that (b c) a = b b = 1. Thus b c = a. Hence b a. Conversely, suppose b a. Then by the previous a = a b = b, as desired a = a hence 0 a. Thus 0 is the minimum. In particular 0 a. Then by the previous: a = a 0 = 1. Thus 1 is the maximum. 4. Suppose a b and b c. There is a d such that a d = b. Hence a c d = a d c = b c. Thus a c b c. 5. Suppose a b. Then (a b) a b = 1. Hence by uniqueness of orthocomplement: (a b) a = b. And thus a b. Conversely, suppose a c = b. Then b b = a c and thus by (E3) and (E2) in particular a b. Note that if a c = b = a c, then by cancellation c = c. Definition 6. Suppose a b, let b a be the unique element such that we have a (b a) = b. Proposition 7. For any effect algebra E. (D1) x y is defined if and only if y x; (D2) x y x; (D3) x (x y) = y and (D4) if x y z, then z y z x and (z x) (z y) = y x. Proof. One by one. (D1) By definition. (D2) x (x y) = x hence x y x. (D3) (x (x y)) (x y) = x = (x y) y and thus, by cancellation, we derive x (x y) = y. (D4) x (y x) (z y) = y (z y) = z and hence by uniqueness of the difference we have (y x) (z y) = z x and thus z y z x. ((z x) (z y)) z x = ((z x) (z y)) (z y) y x = (z x) y x = z y and thus by cancellation ((z x) (z y)) x = y and finally by uniqueness of the difference: y x = (z x) (z y). Remark 8. Any X,,, 1 in which (D1) (D4) hold and has 1 as largest element is called a D-poset. Thus any effect algebra is a D-poset. Conversely: on any D-poset we can define a b = c c b = a and a = 1 a. This will form an effect algebra. Thus: D-posets are another way to look at effect algebras. 9

10 Proposition 9. For any effect algebra E, we have 1. a = 1 a; 2. if b a then (a b) = a b; 3. if b, c a and a b = a c, then b = c; 4. if a b, c and b a = c a, then b = c; 5. if a b, then (a b) b = a and 6. a (b c) = (a b) c whenever they are both defined. Proof. One at a time. 1. (1 a) a = 1 and thus the unique orthocomplement a = 1 a. 2. Certainly (a b) b = a. Thus (a b) b a = 1. Hence by uniqueness of the orthocomplement we know (a b) = a b. 3. Suppose a b = a c. Then by the previous: a b = (a b) = (a c) = a c and thus by cancellation b = c. 4. Suppose b a = c a. Then b = (b a) a = (c a) a = c. 5. Certainly b a b and ((a b) b) b = a b. Cancelling: (a b) b = a. 6. Certainly a b b. Thus a b b. Hence (a b) c b c = (b c). Thus (a b) c b c. Consequently (a b) c (b c) = (a b) b = a. By uniqueness of the difference (a b) c = a (b c). Definition 10. Given a b, define a b = (a b ). Proposition 11. For any effect algebra E. 1. (a b) = a b ; 2. (a b) = a b ; 3. a b = a b and 4. E = E,, 1, 0 is as an effect algebra isomorphic to E. Proof. One by one. 1. (a b) = (a b ) = a b 2. (a b) = (a b ) = a b 3. By the previous: a b = (a b) = a b = a b. 4. The map x x is its own inverse and thus a bijection. By the previous, 0 = 1 and 1 = 0 the effect algebra it induces is precisely E. Hence x x is an isomorphism between E and E. By definition, we only require an effect algebra homomorphism to preserve and 1. This is enough for it to preserve the other structure as well 10

11 Proposition 12. For any additive f : E F, we have the following. 1. (order preserving) If x y, then f(x) f(y). 2. Whenever y x is defined, we have: f(y x) = f(y) f(x). 3. (preservers zero) f(0) = 0 If additionally, f preserves the unit (and thus f is an effect algebra homomorphism), then also the following holds. 4. (preserves orthocomplement) f(x ) = f(x) 5. If x y, then f(x y) = f(x) f(y). Proof. One at a time. 1. Suppose x y. Then there is a c such that x c = y. Thus f(x) f(c) = f(x c) = f(y). Hence f(x) f(y), as desired. 2. Suppose y x is defined. By definition y = (y x) x. Thus f(y) = f((y x) x) = f(y x) f(x). By uniqueness of the difference: f(y) f(x) = f(y x). 3. Certainly 0 = 0 0 and thus 0 f(0) = f(0) = f(0 0) = f(0) f(0). Hence by cancelling: 0 = f(0), as desired. 4. By definition 1 = x x. Thus 1 = f(1) = f(x x ) = f(x) f(x ). By uniqueness of the orthocomplement, we know f(x ) = f(x). 5. By definition x y = (x y ). Thus by the previous f(x y) = f((x y ) ) = (f(x) f(y) ) = f(x) f(y) Some results on infima and suprema We will look at the order structure of an effect algebra in more detail. The results we prove, will be useful when we consider effect algebras that are lattice ordered in Subsection If we consider the partial binary relations, and with one argument fixed and restricted to its domain, we see they are either order isomorphisms or order antiisomorphisms. Proposition 13. Given an effect algebra E. 1. b a b is an order isomorphism from a to a. Its inverse is the map b b a, an order isomorphism from a to a. 2. b a b is an order isomorphism from a to a. Its inverse is the map b b a, an order isomorphism from a to a. 3. b a b is an order antiisomorphism from a to a, which is its own inverse. Proof. We already saw that the maps are appropriately order preserving or order reversing. Also we saw that the cancellation law holds for all these operations, hence all maps are injective. It is left to show that each map is defined on the given domain; maps into the given codomain and is surjective. 11

12 1. a b is defined whenever b a. Thus a is indeed the domain. Furthermore a b a. Given any a c. Then a (a c) = a. Hence the map is surjective. This also show that b a b is its inverse. 2. Note that b a = (b a ) = b a. Thus the previous pair of maps with a for a are exactly the current maps. Hence these are also order isomorphisms. 3. a b is defined whenever b a. Thus a is indeed its domain. Furthermore a b a. By (D3) the map is its own inverse. Thus in particular, it is surjective. A very useful corollary of the previous is that the operations, with some restriction due to their partial definition, either preserve or invert suprema and infima. Corollary 14. Given an effect algebra E and a subset U E. Write a U = {a u; u U}. And similarly for the other operations. Write a U whenever a u for each u U. 1. Suppose U a, then a U exists if and only if a U exists and we have a U = a U. Also a U exists if and only if a U exists and we have a U = a U. 2. Suppose U a, then a U exists if and only if a U exists and we have a U = a U. Also a U exists if and only if a U exists and we have a U = a U. Proof. Note that if U a, then also U, U a, whenever they exist. Thus the suprema and infima in the order restricted to a, are the same as in the whole of E. Similarly for a. The first part is now an easy consequence of the fact that a ( ) is an order isomorphism, from a to a, which preserves suprema and infima. The second part is similar. One of the applications is the following proposition. Proposition 15. Given an effect algebra E and a, b E. If a b and a b exists, then a b = (a b) (a b). Proof. Certainly a, b a b. And thus by the previous corollary, we have (a b) (a b) = ((a b) a) ((a b) b) = a b. Corollary 16. The previous proposition has some useful consequences. 1. If a b = 0 and a b, then a b = a b. 2. Whenever it is all defined: (a b) (a b) = a b Isotropic index In this section we introduce terminology that we will use when we study finite effect algebras in Subsection and lexicographically ordered vector spaces in Subsection Definition 17. Given an effect algebra E. 12

13 1. An element e is called isotropic if e e. 2. Given n N and an e E. We can define 0e = 0 and (n + 1)e = ne e whenever ne e. That is: ne is e summed n times with itself. 3. If ne is defined, but (n + 1)e is not, then n is the isotropic index of e; in symbols: ord(e) = n. 4. If ne is defined for all n N, then e is called infinitesimal and we write ord(e) =. 5. If a is infinitesimal and for all n N we have na b, then a is infinitely smaller than b and we write a b. 6. If 0 is the only infinitesimal, then we call E Archimedean Interval effect algebras The effect algebras [0, 1] and Eff(H ) we saw before are examples of a more general class of effect algebras: those that are derived from partially ordered abelian groups. Definition 18. A structure G, +,,, 0 is called a (partially) ordered abelian group provided 1. G, +,, 0 is an abelian group; 2. G, is a partial order and 3. if a b then a + c b + c for any a, b, c G. An element a G of a partially ordered group is called positive if 0 a. We write G + = {g; 0 g} for the positive elements. Given two elements a b in an ordered group G, we define the (order) interval with endpoints a and b as [a, b] = {c; c G; a c b}. Example 19. The following are examples of ordered abelian groups. 1. R, +,,, 0, the real line with addition. 2. B(H ) R, +,,, 0, the Hermitean operators on a Hilbert H space where the order is defined as follows. A B if Ax, x Bx, x for all x H. Proposition 20. Given any ordered group G and strictly positive element 0 < u, the structure [0, u], +, 0, u is an effect algebra with a = u a. Such an effect interval is called an interval effect algebra. Proof. Assume 0 a, b, c u. (E1) If a + b u, then a + b = b + a u, as desired. (E2) If (a + b) + c u, then (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) u, as desired. 13

14 (E3) 0 a thus u u + a hence u a u + a a = u. thus 0 = a a u a. Thus u a is in [0, u]. Also a u Clearly a + (u a) = u, thus u a is an orthocomplement of a. Given any other b [0, u] such that a + b = u. Then b = u a. Thus the orthocomplement is unique. (E4) Suppose a + u u. Then 0 a 0. Thus a = Convex effect algebras When we consider interval effect algebras derived from ordered vector spaces, the effect algebra inherits a scalar multiplication from the vector space. For a few proofs it is useful to introduce the notion of a scalar multiplication on any effect algebra. This definition will turn out to be equivalent to that of a [0, 1]-effect module. Definition 21. An effect algebra E is called convex if for every λ [0, 1] and a E there exists a λ a such that (C1) α (β a) = (αβ) a; (C2) if α + β 1, then αa βa and (α + β) a = α a β a; (C3) if λ [0, 1] and a b then λ a λ b and λ a λ b = λ (a b) and (C4) 1a = a. However, we did not discover anything new: any convex effect algebra is an interval effect algebra of some ordered vector space. Definition 22. Given an ordered vector space V over R and a vector u > 0. We say [0, u] generates V if for every v V there are r 1, r 2 R and v 1, v 2 [0, u] such that v = r 1 v 1 r 2 v 2. Theorem 23 (S. Gudder and S. Pulmannová [5]). For any convex effect algebra E, there exists a unique ordered vector space V and an u > 0 such that [0, u] = E and [0, u] generates V Lattice effect algebras Another class of effect algebras are those derived from orthomodular lattices. Definition 24. A lattice is a partial order for which each finite supremum and infimum exists. A bounded lattice is a lattice with a maximum element 1 and a minimum 0. An orthocomplemented lattice is a bounded lattice together with a unary operation ( ) such that 1. (complement) a a = 1 and a a = 0; 2. (involution) a = a and 3. (order-reversing) if a b then b a. An orthomodular lattice L is a orthocomplemented lattice such that for any a, b L, we have: if a b then a (a b) = b. 14

15 Example 25. The following are orthomodular lattices. 1. Any Boolean algebra is an orthomodular lattice with as orthocomplement the normal complement. In particular P(X),,,, X, X ( ). 2. Given a Hilbert space, the partial order of its closed linear subspaces by inclusion is an orthomodular lattice. We can extend any orthomodular lattice to an effect algebra. prove this, we need a lemma. Before we Lemma 26. In any orthocomplemented lattice, the laws of de Morgan are valid. That is: we have (a b) = a b and (a b) = a b. Proof. a b b thus (a b) b. Also (a b) a. By the definition of infimum (a b) a b. For the other inequality, we first note that clearly a b a. Thus a (a b ). Also b (a b ). Hence a b (a b ). That is (a b) a b. We proved (a b) = a b. The proof of the other equality is dual. Proposition 27. Given any orthomodular lattice L,,, 0, 1, ( ). Define a b if a b and then a b = a b. The structure L,, 0, 1 is an effect algebra. Furthermore, the order of the effect algebra is the same as the order on L. Proof. To prove that L,, 0, 1 is an effect algebra. (E1) Suppose a b. Then a b hence b a, since ( ) is order reversing. Thus b a and a b = a b = b a = b a. (E2) Suppose a b and a b c. Then a b and a b = a b c. Certainly b a b c. Thus b c. Also c (a b) = a b. Thus c b (a b ) c = a, by the orthomodularity since b a. Hence a b c. Thus we are justified to write: (a b) c = a b c = a (b c). (E3) a a = a thus a a hence a a = a a = 1. Indeed: a is an orthocomplement. Suppose a b = 1 for some b. Then b a and a b = 1. Thus by orthomodularity a = b (b a ) = b (a b) = b 1 = b 0 = b the orthocomplement is unique. (E4) Suppose a 1. Then a 1 = 0. Thus a = 0, as desired. Now we prove that the order of the effect algebra on L is the same as the order of the lattice. Suppose that there is a c such that a c = b. By definition, we have b = a c = a c a. Conversely, suppose a b. Then by orthomodularity we have a (a b) = b. Certainly a a b, thus a a b. Hence a (a b) = b. We saw that every orthomodular lattice can be extended to an effect algebra. This extension is, in fact, unique. Definition 28. If the order of an effect algebra is a lattice; that is: finite infima and suprema exist; then it is called a lattice effect algebra. If the order of an effect algebra is an orthomodular lattice, then it is called an orthomodular effect algebra. 15

16 Proposition 29. If E is an orthomodular effect algebra, then a b = a b. Proof. Given a b. Then a b. Certainly b 1. Thus by modularity b b = b (b 1) = 1. Hence 0 = 1 = (b b ) = b b. Consequently a b b b = 0. By Corollary 16, we see a b = (a b) (a b) = (a b) 0 = a b Finite effect algebras Another obvious class to investigate are the finite effect algebras. Definition 30. An effect algebra E is called finite if it has a finite number of elements. Definition 31. Given an effect algebra E. An element a E is called an atom if 0 < a and for every b < a we know b = 0. Proposition 32. Given a finite effect algebra E such that 0 1 and a 1,..., a n are its atoms. Then for each e E there exist e 1,..., e n N such that e = e 1 a 1 e n a n. Proof. First we prove that for every e > 0, there exists an atom a such that 0 < a e. If e itself is an atom, we are done. If not, there must exist an e 1 such that 0 < e 1 < e. Now we consider e 1. If it is atom, we are done. If not, there must exist an e 2 such that 0 < e 2 < e 1. And so forth. Since E is finite, there cannot exist an infinite strictly decreasing sequence 0 <... < e 3 < e 2 < e 1 < e. Thus there must be an atom a < e. Now we prove e is a sum of atoms. If e is an atom or equal 0, we are done. If not, there exists an atom a 1 such that 0 < a 1 < e. Then 0 < e a 1 < e. If e a 1 is an atom, we are done. If not: there exists an atom a 2 such that 0 < a 2 < e a 1. Then 0 < e a 1 a 2 < e a 1 < e. If e a 1 a 2 is an atom, we are done. If not: then we repeat with e a 1 a 2. This procedure must end, for otherwise we would find an infinite strictly decreasing sequence. Definition 33. Given a finite effect algebra E with atoms a 1,..., a n. A tuple (t 1,..., t n ) N n is called a multiplicity vector if t 1 a 1 t n a n = 1. Let T (E) denote the set of multiplicity vectors. The multiplicity vectors determine a finite effect algebra. Definition 34. Define T = {a; a N n ; t T (E). a i t i for all i}. For a, b T, define a + b pointwise. That is: (a + b) i = a i + b i for all i. We say a b if a + b T. Then we define a b = a + b. We define an equivalence relation on T as follows: a b if there is a c N n such that both a + c, b + c T (E). Theorem 35 ([4]). Given a finite effect algebra E such that 0 1. Then: E is isomorphic to T /,, [(0,..., 0)], T. Proof. We would like to prove T /,, [(0,..., 0)], T is an effect algebra and then prove it is isomorphic to E. However, for arbitrary T, it is not an effect algebra. That is why we first prove that there is an operation preserving bijection ϕ and then conclude the latter is an effect algebra and hence ϕ an isomorphism. 16

17 Given b E. Suppose c and c are tuples of natural numbers such that b = c 1 a 1 c n a n = c 1a 1 c na n. Let d be such that Then: b = d 1 a 1 d n a n. 1 = b b = (c 1 + d 1 )a 1 (c n + d n )a n = (c 1 + d 1 )a 1 (c n + d n )a n. Hence: c + d, c + d T. Thus: c c. Define ϕ: E T / by ϕ(b) = [c]. Given c T. Then c t for some t T. b = c 1 a 1 c n a n is defined, since c t and t is a multiplicity vector. By definition: ϕ(b) c. Thus ϕ is surjective. Given b, b E with ϕ(b) = ϕ(b ). Thus: there are tuples c, c and d such that b = c 1 a 1 c n a n ; b = c 1a 1 c na n and b + d, b + d T. Note d t for some t T. Hence d = d 1 a 1 d n a n is defined. Furthermore: d b = d b = 1. By canceling: b = b. Thus ϕ is injective. Given tuples c, c and d such that c c and c d. Then c + d T and: (c 1 + d 1 )a 1 (c n + d n )a n = (c 1 + d 1 )a 1 (c n + d n )a n 1. Hence c d and c + d c + d. Thus and can be extended to T /. Suppose b, b E with b b. Let c and c be such that: b = c 1 a 1 c n a n b = c 1a 1 c na n. Then: b b = (c 1 + c 1)a 1 (c n + c n)a n. Hence c + c ϕ(b b ). Thus c + c T. That is: c c. Also ϕ(b) ϕ(b ) = ϕ(b b ). Conversely, suppose ϕ(b) ϕ(b ). Again, find c and c such that: b = c 1 a 1 c n a n b = c 1a 1 c na n. Then c c. Thus (c 1 + c 1)a 1 (c n + c n)a n is defined. Thus b b. Finally, clearly ϕ(1) = T. The operations on T / are preserved by the surjective ϕ. Hence it is an effect algebra. Furthermore: since ϕ is injective, we have T / = E. 17

18 2.2 Effect monoids Various examples of effect algebras also carry a multiplication. We will consider effect monoids, which are effect algebras with an associative and distributive multiplication. They play an important rôle in one class of effect logics, see Subsection Definition 36. A structure E,,, 0, 1 is called an effect monoid if E,, 0, 1 is an effect algebra and the (total) binary operation satisfies the following. (M1) (unit) a 1 = 1 a = a. (M2) (left distributivity) if a b, then c a c b and (c a) (c b) = c (a b). (M3) (right distributivity) if a b, then a c b c and (a c) (b c) = (a b) c. (M4) (associativity) a (b c) = (a b) c. Example 37. We can extend the first two effect algebras of Example 2 to effect monoids as follows. 1. [0, 1], +,, 0, 1 where is the standard multiplication on R. 2. P(X),,,, X where is the intersection. Proposition 38. Given an effect monoid E, we have 1. a b a and a b b for any a, b E; 2. if a b then c a c b and a c b c; 3. if a b then c a c b and a c b c; 4. a b = a (a b) and a b = b (a b) and 5. whenever c b, we have a (b c) = (a b) (a c). Proof. One by one. 1. Certainly b b. Thus a b a b and (a b) (a b ) = a (b b ) = a 1 = a. Hence a b a. The argument for the other statement is similar. 2. Suppose a b. Then a d = b for some d. Hence (c a) (c d) = c (a d) = c b. Consequently c a c b. The argument for the other statement is similar. 3. For every n N we have na b. Hence by the previous n(c a) = c na c b. Thus c a c b. The proof of the other statement is similar. 4. Consider that b b and thus (a b ) (a b) = a (b b ) = a. By uniqueness of the difference, we know a b = a (a b). The other proof is similar. 18

19 5. If c b, then b c is defined and b c c. Hence (a (b c)) (a c) = a ((b c) c) = a b and thus by uniqueness of the difference we have a (b c) = (a b) (a c). Definition 39. An effect monoid E is called commutative if for every a, b E we have a b = b a. The previous two examples are both commutative. We will not find a finite effect monoid that is non-commutative. Proposition 40 ( ). If E is a finite effect monoid, then there exists a finite set X such that E = P(X),,,, X. Proof. Let a 1,..., a n be the atoms of E. If i j, then a i a j a i, a j hence a i a j = 0. Also note that a i a i = 0 or a i a i = a i. Given a multiplicity vector t 1,..., t n, that is t 1 a 1 t n a n = 1, then a j = 1 a j = (t 1 a i t n a n ) a j = t j (a j a j ) a j. Thus a j a j = a j and consequently t j = 1 for any j. Hence: the only multiplicity vector of E is (1,..., 1). Furthermore, given any b E, we know b = b 1 a 1 b n a n with b i {0, 1}. Thus b b = b b. Pick any X with X = n. Then P(X),,,, X also has n atoms and exactly one multiplicity vector: (1,..., 1). Thus by Theorem 35, it is, as an effect algebra, isomorphic to E. Also a b = a b. Thus it is, as an effect monoid, isomorphic to E. The effect monoid structure on [0, 1] is unique. Proposition 41. If makes [0, 1] R an effect monoid, then is the standard multiplication on R. Proof. First note that n 1 n = 1 and thus x 1 n = x n. Hence x m n = m n x. Given any x, y R. Let q 1, q 2,... Q such that y... q 2 q 1 1 and q i y. Then x y... xq 2 xq 1. And thus x y xy. Approximating y from the other side, we get x y xy. Consequently x y = xy. The crux of the previous proof was to show that has to respect the scalar multiplication on the underlying effect algebra. Because we will encounter such effect monoids again, we define: Definition 42. An effect monoid E is called convex if the underlying effect algebra is convex and λ (a b) = (λ a) b = a (λ b) Convex effect monoids and OAU-algebras We will prove a representation result for convex effect monoids, which we will use to simplify the study of a certain class of effect monoids. Recall that given any ordered vector space V and vector u > 0, we know that the order interval [0, u] is a convex effect algebra (Proposition 20). Conversely, any convex effect algebra is an interval effect algebra of some ordered vector space (Theorem 23). Given any convex effect monoid E. Then in particular it is a convex effect algebra. And thus it is an interval effect algebra of some ordered vector space V. 19

20 We will show that we can extend the multiplication of the effect algebra to the whole vector space, which will form an ordered, associative and unitary algebra. Conversely, given any ordered, associative and unitary algebra with unit 1, we can restrict the algebra multiplication to the order interval [0, 1], which will form an effect monoid. Definition 43. A structure V, +,,,, 0, 1 is called an ordered associative unitary algebra (OAU-algebra) if V, +,,, 0 is a vector space and is a binary operation that satisfies 1. (associativity) a (b c) = (a b) c; 2. (distributivity) (b + c) a = b a + c a and a (b + c) = a b + a c; 3. (unit) 1 a = a 1 = a; 4. ( preserves order) if c 0 and a b, then c a c b and a c b c and 5. (homogeneity) r (a b) = (r a) b = a (r b). Proposition 44. Given an OAU-algebra V. For a, b [0, 1] with a + b 1, define a b = a + b. Then E = [0, 1],,, 0, 1 is a convex effect monoid. Proof. Given a, b [0, 1]. Then 0 a and thus 0 = 0 (0 b) = 0 b a b. Also a 1 and thus a b 1 b = b 1. Thus a b is a total binary operation on [0, 1]. By Proposition 20, E is a convex effect algebra. Now, we check the convex effect monoid axioms. (M1), (M4) and convexity are immediate from the OAU-algebra axioms. To prove (M2), assume a, b [0, 1] with a + b 1. Then c a + c b = c (a + b) c 1 = c 1, as desired. The proof of (M3) similar. Before we prove that any convex interval effect monoid can be extended to an OAU-algebra, we need a small result on ordered vector spaces. Lemma 45 ( ). Given an ordered vectorspace V and an element u > 0. The following are equivalent. 1. [0, u] generates V, see Definition Given v V, we have v = r(v 1 v 2 ) for some v 1, v 2 [0, u] and r [1, ). 3. u is a strong unit, that is: for every v V, there is a n N such that v nu. Proof. 1. First we prove (i) implies (ii). Thus suppose [0, u] generates V. Given v = r 1 v 1 r 2 v 2. Suppose r 1, r 2 < 0. Then v = r 2 v 2 r 1 v 1. Thus we may assume not both: r 1, r 2 < 0. Suppose only r 1 < 0. Note 1 2 (v 1 + v 2 ) [0, u]. Thus 2(r 2 r 1 ) 1 2 (v 1 + v 2 ) 0 0 = r 1 v 1 r 2 v 2. Note r 2 r 1 0. Thus we may assume r 1 0. Similarly, we may assume r 2 0. Suppose both r 1, r 2 [0, 1]. Then r 1 v 1, r 2 v 2 [0, u] and hence v = 1(r 1 v 1 r 2 v 2 ), which is of the right form. Suppose r 1 [0, 1] and r 2 (1, ). Then r1 r 2 v 1 [0, u] and v = r 2 ( r1 r 2 v 1 v 2 ), thus we are done. We are also done if r 1 (1, ) and r 2 [0, 1]. Finally, suppose r 1, r 2 (1, ). Then 1 r 2 v 1, 1 r 1 v 2 [0, u] and v = r 1 r 2 ( 1 r 2 v 1 1 r 1 v 2 ), which is of the desired form. 20

21 2. Now we prove (ii) implies (iii). Thus suppose (ii). Given v V. Then v = r(v 1 v 2 ) for some r [1, ) and 0 v 1, v 2 u. Note v 1 v 2 u. Hence v = r(v 1 v 2 ) ru r u as desired. 3. Finally, we prove (iii) implies (i). Thus suppose u is a strong unit. In particular, for some n 1, we have nu v nu. Thus: ( u + v n ) u and ( v ) u u. n Now define v 1 = 1 2 (u + v n ); and v 2 = 1 2 (u v n ). We have v = nv 1 nv 2 as desired. Theorem 46 ( ). Given an ordered vector space V and a vector u > 0 such that [0, u] generates V. Suppose [0, u],,,, 0, u is a convex effect monoid. Then there is a unique extension of to V such that V, +,,,, 0, u is an OAU-algebra. Proof. Suppose is an extension of to V such that V, +,,,, 0, u is an OAU-algebra. Write U = [0, u]. Given a, a V. Then a = r(v w) and a = r (v w ) for some r, r (1, ) and v, v, w, w U. Hence a a = r(v w) r (v w ) = rr (v v + w w w v v w ) = rr (v v + w w w v v w ). (1) Thus the extension, if it exists, is unique. It also suggests a definition for a a. However, we need to show that the choice of r, r, v, v, w and w does not effect the value of (1). We do this in two steps. First we define on U V. Then extend it to V V. Given r, r [1, ) and x, v, v, w, w U. Without loss of generality, we may assume r r. Suppose r(v w) = r (v w ). We want to show that r(x v x w) = r (x v x w ). From the assumption and thus by dividing by 2r gives Note that r r [0, 1] and thus r r w, r rv + r w = r v + rw 1 2 v + r 2r w = r 2r v w. also 1 2 u u U. Thus 1 2 v + r 2r w = r 2r v r 2 (x v) + 2r (x w ) = x ( 1 2 v + r 2r w ) = x ( r 2r v w) r v U. Furthermore, if u, u U, then w U. And consequently = r 2r (x v ) (x w). Rearranging and multiplying by 2r, yields the desired r(x v x w) = r (x v x w ). 21

22 And thus we can define x a = r(x v x w) if a = r(v w) for r [1, ) and x, v, w U. We want to repeat this argument to define x y for x, y V, by x y = r(v y w y). If we review the argument, we see we need to check whether (a + b) y = a y + b y and s(a y) = (sa) y for s [0, 1] and a, b, a + b U. We check the latter first. Suppose s [0, 1], a U and y V with y = r(u v) for some r [0, 1] and u, v U. Then s(a y) = sr(a v a w) = r(a (sv) a (sw)) = a (sy). Now, for the partial distributivity, additionally assume a, b, a + b U. Then (a + b) y = r((a + b) v (a + b) w) = r(a v + b v (a w + b w)) = r(a v a w) + r(b v b w) = a y + b y. Thus we can indeed repeat to previous argument and define x y = r(v y w y), which is the same as (1). Finally, we need to check whether obeys the axioms of an OAU-algebra. We do this in a convenient order. Suppose a, b, c V ; a = r a (v a w a ); b = r b (v b w b ) and c = r c (v c w c ). 1. (distributivity) Assume, without loss of generality that r b r c. Then r b r c ( [0, 1] and we have a + b = 2r c ( r b 2r c v b v c) ( r b 2r c w b w c) ). Hence ( a (b + c) = 2r a r c va ( r b 2r c v b v c) + w a ( r b 2r c w b w c) v a ( r b 2r c w b w c) w a ( r b 2r c v b v c) ) ( = 2r a r rb c 2r c (v a v b ) (v a v c ) + r b 2r c (w a w b ) (w a w c ) r b 2r c (v a w b ) 1 2 (v a w c ) r b 2r c (w a v b ) 1 2 (w a v c ) ) = r a r b (v a v b + w a w b v a w b w a v b ) + r a r c (v a v c + w a w c v a w c w a v c ) = a b + a c. The argument for right distributivity is similar. 2. (homogeneity) Suppose r R. We distinguish cases. If r [1, ), then ra = rr a (v a w a ) with rr a [1, ) and thus (ra) b = rr a r b (v a v b + w a w b v a w b w a v b ) = r(a b). Suppose r [0, 1]. Then ra = r a (rv a rw a ) with rv a, rw a U and thus (ra) b) = r a r b ((rv a ) v b + (rw a ) w b (rv a ) w b (rw a ) v b ) = r a r b r(v a v b + w a w b v a w b w a v b ) = r(a b). 22

23 Suppose r = 1. Then a = r a (v a w a ) = r a (w a v a ). And thus ( a) b = r a r b (w a v b + v a w b v a v b w a w b ) = r a r b (v a v b + w a w b v a w b w a v b ) = (a b) = r(a b). For the remaining case, suppose r < 0. We can reduce it to the previous cases: (ra) b = ( r ( a)) b = (( ra) b) = ( r)(a b) = r(a b). The argument for r(a b) = a (rb) is similar. 3. (associativity) Using the homogeneity and distributivity we just demonstrated, we can reduce the associativity of to that of, as follows. a (b c) = a (r b r c (v b v c + w b w c v b w c w b v c )) = r b r c ( a (vb v c ) + a (w b w c ) a (v b w c ) a (w b v c ) ) = r b r c ( (ra (v a w a )) (v b v c ) + (r a (v a w a )) (w b w c ) (r a (v a w a )) (v b w c ) (r a (v a w a )) (w b v c ) ) = r a r b r c ( va (v b v c ) + v a (w b w c ) + w a (v b w c ) + w a (w b v c ) v a (v b w c ) + v a (w b v c ) w a (v b v c ) + w a (w b w c ) ) = r a r b r c ( (va v b ) v c + (v a w b ) w c + (w a v b ) w c + (w a w b ) v c (v a v b ) w c + (v a w b ) v c (w a v b ) v c + (w a w b ) w c ) = r a r b ( (va v b ) c + (w a w b ) c (v a w b ) c (w a v b ) c ) = r a r b (v a v b + w a w b v a w b w a v b ) c = (a b) c 4. (unit) u a = r a (u v a u w a ) = r a (v a w a ) = a. Similarly a u = a. 5. ( preserves order) First note that if a 0, then r a (v a w a ) 0 and thus v a w a 0. Also v a w a u, thus v a w a U. Thus a = rv for some v U viz v = v a w a. Next, suppose c, a 0. With the previous we may assume c = r c v c and a = r a v a. Thus c a = (r c v c ) (r a v a ) = r c r a (v c v a ) = r c r a (v c v a ). We know v c v a U. In particular v c v a 0. Also r c r a 0. Thus c a 0. Finally, suppose c 0 and a b. Then b a 0. Hence 0 c (b a) = c b c a. Thus c a c b, as desired. The other case is similar Effect monoids on finite dimensional lexicographically ordered vector spaces We want to study effect monoids that are not commutative. Suppose we find a non-commutative OAU-algebra. By Proposition 44, its unit interval is an effect monoid. It is not hard to see it must be non-commutative too. 23

24 In this section we will study the class of effect monoids derived from OAUalgebras on lexicographically ordered vector spaces. This will give us examples of non-commutative effect monoids. For this section, assume n N and n 1. We write e 1,..., e n for the standard basis of the real vector space R n. Given a vector v R n, we assume v 1,..., v n R are the components; that is: i v ie i = v. We can totally order R n as if it were words in a dictionary. Definition 47. Given n N. Given v, w R n, we say v < w if there is an i such that v i < w i and for all j < i we have v j = w j. R n with this order is an ordered vector space, which is called lexicographically ordered. Since the order is total, we can familiarly define { v v 0 v = v v 0. We write v w if for all n N we have n v w. Note that 0 e n e n 1 e 2 e 1. The order interval [0, e 1 ] generates R n and thus [0, e 1 ] is a convex effect monoid. See Section Call it Elex n. We are interested in the effect monoids on En lex. First, we will prove that any effect monoid on Elex n is convex. Then by Theorem 46 we know that an effect monoid on Elex n extends uniquely to an OAUalgebra on R n. We will show that an OAU-algebra on R n is fixed by e i e j. Then we will give necessary and sufficient conditions to extend a multiplication defined on the standard basis to an OAU-algebra. Lemma 48. Any effect monoid on Elex n (the unit interval effect algebra of the n- dimensional lexicographically ordered vector space) is convex. Proof. Given n N and a, b Elex n. Certainly n(a 1 n b) = a n( 1 n b) = a b and thus a ( 1 n b) = 1 n (a b). Then also for any 0 m n, we have m n (a b) = a ( m n ) b. Similarly m n (a b) = ( m n a) b. For any r [0, 1] we can find q i, q i Q [0, 1] such that r is the uniquely defined by q i r q i for all i. Suppose a b = 0. Then certainly a (r b) a b = 0 = r(a b). Suppose a b 0. Then a b > 0 and if q i (a b) r (a b), then q i r. Thus r (a b) is uniquely defined by q i (a b) r (a b) q i (a b) for all i. Now note that q i (a b) = a q i b a (r b) a q i b = q i (a b). Thus a (r b) = r (a b). Similarly (r a) b = r (a b). Given any OAU-algebra on the lexicographically ordered R n. Note that by the homogeneity and distributivity of, that is: its bilinearity, we have v w = ( ) ( ) v i e i v j e j = v i v j (e i e j ). i j Write e ij = e i e j. We see is fixed by the vectors e ij. Conversely, given vectors e ij, we can define a multiplication by i,j v w = i,j v i v j e ij. 24

25 However, this does not necessarily form an OAU-algebra. necessary and sufficient conditions. The following are Proposition 49. Given vectors e ij. Write v w = i,j v iw j e ij. The following are equivalent. R n, +,,,, 0, e 1 is an OAU-algebra. The following four conditions hold. e 1j = e j and e i1 = e i e i (e j e k ) = (e i e j ) e k e ij 0 If i < j, then e ik e jk and e ki e kj. Proof. The necessity is clear. To prove sufficiency of the four conditions, we check the axioms of an OAU-algebra in a convenient order. 1. (distributivity) Given a, b, c R n. Then a (b + c) = i,j a i (b j + c j )e ij = i,j a i b j e ij + i,j a i c j e ij = a b + a c. Right distributivity is proven similarly. 2. (homogeneity) Given a, b R n and r R. Then r(a b) = r i,j a ib j e ij = i,j (ra i)b j e ij = (ra) b. The other case is proven in the same way. 3. (associativity) Given a, b, c R n. By the second condition and the distributivity and homogeneity just proven, we have a (b c) = a j,k b j c k e jk = j,k b j c k (a e jk ) = j,k ( ) b j c k a i e i (ej e k ) i = i,j,k a i b j c k (e i (e j e k )) = i,j,k a i b j c k ((e i e j ) e k ) = (a b) c. 4. (unit) From the first condition and the definition of we get e 1 a = j a je 1j = j a je j = a and similarly a e 1 = i a ie i1 = i a ie i = a. 25

26 5. ( preserves order) If we can prove that a b 0, whenever a, b 0, then we are done. For suppose c 0 and a b. Then b a 0. Thus 0 c (b a) = c b c a. And thus c a c b, as desired. The other case is similar. Thus, suppose a, b 0. If a = 0 or b = 0, then a b = 0 0. Thus, we may assume a, b > 0. Then there are α and β such that a α, b β > 0 and a i = 0 for all i < α and b i = 0 for all i < β. Consider a α b β e αβ. By the third condition and the current assumptions, we know a α b β e αβ 0. Given i and j with (i, j) (α, β). We will show a α b β e αβ a i b j e ij, by distinguishing cases. Suppose i < α. Then a i = 0 and thus a i b j e ij = 0 a α b β e αβ. The same argument covers the case j < β. Suppose i > α and j β. By the fourth condition, we know e αβ e iβ e ij. And since a α b β > 0, we also have a α b β e αβ a i b j e ij. The case i α and j > β is similar. Note that if 0 v then for any w v we have 0 v + w. And thus a b = a i b j e ij = a α b β e αβ + a i b j e ij 0. i,j (i,j) (α,β) Corollary 50 ( ). The unique effect monoid on E 2 lex is: e 1 e 2 e 1 e 1 e 2 e 2 e 2 0 Corollary 51. There is a non-commutative effect monoid on Elex 5, fixed by: e 1 e 2 e 3 e 4 e 5 e 1 e 1 e 2 e 3 e 4 e 5 e 2 e 2 e 4 e e 3 e e 4 e e 5 e

27 2.3 Effect modules Recall that a convex effect algebra is an effect algebra equipped with a scalar multiplication with [0, 1]. See Definition Effect modules are a generalization of convex effect algebras, where the scalars can come from any effect monoid. Definition 52. Given an effect monoid M. An M-effect module is an effect algebra E together with an operation ( ) ( ): M E E such that (V1) α (β a) = (α β) a; (V2) if α β then αa βa and (α β) a = α a β a; (V3) if a b then λ a λ b and λ a λ b = λ (a b) and (V4) 1 a = a. Example Every convex effect algebra is a [0, 1]-effect module. 2. Every effect algebra is a 2-effect module with 0 a = 0 and 1 a = a. 3. Given any effect monoid M and n N, the set M n is a M-effect module with pointwise operations. 4. A bit more general: given any effect monoid M and set X, the set M X of functions from X to M is an M-effect module with pointwise operations. Definition 54. Given a map between M-effect modules f : E 1 E 2. f is an effect module homomorphism if f is an effect algebra homomorphism and furthermore f(λ a) = λ f(a) for all λ M and a E. We write EMod M for the category of M-effect modules with effect module homomorphisms. 27

28 2.4 Sequential effect modules Recall that the starting point of this thesis, was the observation that in the examples of effect logics initially studied by Jacobs, a sequential effect algebra arises. We did not define this notion, yet. See Subsection 1.1. Definition 55 ([7]). A sequential effect algebra is an effect algebra E together with a binary multiplication such that (S1) a (b c) = (a b) (a c) (S2) 1 a = a (S3) If a b = 0, then a b = b a. (S4) If a b = b a, then a b = b a and a (b c) = (a b) c. (S5) If c a = a c and c b = b c. Then: c (a b) = (a b) c and c (a b) = (a b) c. Definition 56. A sequential effect module is a sequential effect algebra, where the underlying effect algebra is an effect module and (SM) λ(a b) = (λa) b = a (λb) for any scalar λ. Definition 57. A sequential effect algebra E is called commutative if for any a, b E, we have a b = b a Examples We have seen commutative sequential effect algebras already, in disguise. Proposition 58. Every commutative effect monoid is a commutative sequential effect algebra. And, conversely, every commutative sequential effect algebra is a commutative effect monoid. Furthermore, the commutative effect monoid is convex if and only if the commutative sequential effect algebra is a [0, 1]-effect module. Proof. 1. Given a commutative effect monoid E. The axioms (S1) and (S2) are satisfied directly by definition. The axioms (S3), (S4) and (S5) are implications of which the conclusions are directly satisfied by definition. If the effect monoid is convex, then (SM) follows by definition. 2. Conversely, given a commutative sequential effect algebra. (M3) is the same as (S1). Since everything commutes, (M3) implies (M2) and (S4) implies the associativity of ; that is: (M4). We are left to prove (M1). By (S1), we have (a 0) (a 1) = a 1. By cancellation: a 0 = 0. Thus by (S3), we have 0 a = a 0 = 0 and by (S4) and (S2) also 1 a = a 1 = a. That is: we have shown (M1). If the sequential effect algebra is a sequential [0, 1]-effect monoid, then the underlying effect algebra is convex and the multiplication is bi-homogeneous, hence (SM). Now, the prime example of a sequential effect module: 28

Coreflections in Algebraic Quantum Logic

Coreflections in Algebraic Quantum Logic Coreflections in Algebraic Quantum Logic Bart Jacobs Jorik Mandemaker Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands Abstract Various generalizations of Boolean algebras are being studied in algebraic quantum

More information

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXV, 2(1996), pp. 247 279 247 GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS J. HEDLÍKOVÁ and S. PULMANNOVÁ Abstract. A difference on a poset (P, ) is a partial binary

More information

Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras

Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras Gejza Jenča Department of Mathematics Faculty of Electrical Engineering and Information Technology Slovak Technical University Ilkovičova 3 812 19

More information

Categories and Quantum Informatics: Hilbert spaces

Categories and Quantum Informatics: Hilbert spaces Categories and Quantum Informatics: Hilbert spaces Chris Heunen Spring 2018 We introduce our main example category Hilb by recalling in some detail the mathematical formalism that underlies quantum theory:

More information

Boolean Inner-Product Spaces and Boolean Matrices

Boolean Inner-Product Spaces and Boolean Matrices Boolean Inner-Product Spaces and Boolean Matrices Stan Gudder Department of Mathematics, University of Denver, Denver CO 80208 Frédéric Latrémolière Department of Mathematics, University of Denver, Denver

More information

CONTINUITY. 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits. Suppose that F : J C and R: C D are functors. Consider the limit diagrams.

CONTINUITY. 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits. Suppose that F : J C and R: C D are functors. Consider the limit diagrams. CONTINUITY Abstract. Continuity, tensor products, complete lattices, the Tarski Fixed Point Theorem, existence of adjoints, Freyd s Adjoint Functor Theorem 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits.

More information

Quantum Logic in Dagger Kernel Categories

Quantum Logic in Dagger Kernel Categories Quantum Logic in Dagger Kernel Categories Chris Heunen Bart Jacobs December 4, 2009 Abstract This paper investigates quantum logic from the perspective of categorical logic, and starts from minimal assumptions,

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

Universal Algebra for Logics

Universal Algebra for Logics Universal Algebra for Logics Joanna GRYGIEL University of Czestochowa Poland j.grygiel@ajd.czest.pl 2005 These notes form Lecture Notes of a short course which I will give at 1st School on Universal Logic

More information

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA These are notes for our first unit on the algebraic side of homological algebra. While this is the last topic (Chap XX) in the book, it makes sense to

More information

1 Categorical Background

1 Categorical Background 1 Categorical Background 1.1 Categories and Functors Definition 1.1.1 A category C is given by a class of objects, often denoted by ob C, and for any two objects A, B of C a proper set of morphisms C(A,

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras 3. ABSTRACT BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 123 3. Abstract Boolean Algebras 3.1. Abstract Boolean Algebra. Definition 3.1.1. An abstract Boolean algebra is defined as a set B containing two distinct elements 0 and 1,

More information

Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition

Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition Abstract This document contains supplementary material, such as definitions, explanations, examples, etc., to complement that of the text, How to Think

More information

Injective objects and lax idempotent monads

Injective objects and lax idempotent monads Master Project Injective objects and lax idempotent monads Author: Eiichi Piguet Supervised by: Dr. Gavin Jay Seal Autumn 2013 eiichi.piguet@epfl.ch i Acknowledgement I would like to express my deepest

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato September 10, 2015 ABSTRACT. This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a

More information

Notes about Filters. Samuel Mimram. December 6, 2012

Notes about Filters. Samuel Mimram. December 6, 2012 Notes about Filters Samuel Mimram December 6, 2012 1 Filters and ultrafilters Definition 1. A filter F on a poset (L, ) is a subset of L which is upwardclosed and downward-directed (= is a filter-base):

More information

Rings and Fields Theorems

Rings and Fields Theorems Rings and Fields Theorems Rajesh Kumar PMATH 334 Intro to Rings and Fields Fall 2009 October 25, 2009 12 Rings and Fields 12.1 Definition Groups and Abelian Groups Let R be a non-empty set. Let + and (multiplication)

More information

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Hongtaek Jung December 27, 2017 Abstract This is a part of a supplementary note for a Logic and Set Theory course. The main goal is to

More information

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra SET THEORY Basic concepts Notations Subset Algebra of sets The power set Ordered pairs and Cartesian product Relations on sets Types of relations and their properties Relational matrix and the graph of

More information

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths.

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths. CATEGORY THEORY PROFESSOR PETER JOHNSTONE Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths. Definition 1.1. A category C consists

More information

Atomic effect algebras with compression bases

Atomic effect algebras with compression bases JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICAL PHYSICS 52, 013512 (2011) Atomic effect algebras with compression bases Dan Caragheorgheopol 1, Josef Tkadlec 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Informatics, Technical University

More information

Foundations of Mathematics

Foundations of Mathematics Foundations of Mathematics Andrew Monnot 1 Construction of the Language Loop We must yield to a cyclic approach in the foundations of mathematics. In this respect we begin with some assumptions of language

More information

Linear Algebra March 16, 2019

Linear Algebra March 16, 2019 Linear Algebra March 16, 2019 2 Contents 0.1 Notation................................ 4 1 Systems of linear equations, and matrices 5 1.1 Systems of linear equations..................... 5 1.2 Augmented

More information

MTH 309 Supplemental Lecture Notes Based on Robert Messer, Linear Algebra Gateway to Mathematics

MTH 309 Supplemental Lecture Notes Based on Robert Messer, Linear Algebra Gateway to Mathematics MTH 309 Supplemental Lecture Notes Based on Robert Messer, Linear Algebra Gateway to Mathematics Ulrich Meierfrankenfeld Department of Mathematics Michigan State University East Lansing MI 48824 meier@math.msu.edu

More information

Algebras. Larry Moss Indiana University, Bloomington. TACL 13 Summer School, Vanderbilt University

Algebras. Larry Moss Indiana University, Bloomington. TACL 13 Summer School, Vanderbilt University 1/39 Algebras Larry Moss Indiana University, Bloomington TACL 13 Summer School, Vanderbilt University 2/39 Binary trees Let T be the set which starts out as,,,, 2/39 Let T be the set which starts out as,,,,

More information

0.2 Vector spaces. J.A.Beachy 1

0.2 Vector spaces. J.A.Beachy 1 J.A.Beachy 1 0.2 Vector spaces I m going to begin this section at a rather basic level, giving the definitions of a field and of a vector space in much that same detail as you would have met them in a

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

Fuzzy Sets. Mirko Navara navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 28, 2019

Fuzzy Sets. Mirko Navara   navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 28, 2019 The notion of fuzzy set. Minimum about classical) sets Fuzzy ets Mirko Navara http://cmp.felk.cvut.cz/ navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 8, 09 To aviod problems of the set theory, we restrict ourselves

More information

Foundations of non-commutative probability theory

Foundations of non-commutative probability theory Foundations of non-commutative probability theory Daniel Lehmann School of Engineering and Center for the Study of Rationality Hebrew University, Jerusalem 91904, Israel June 2009 Abstract Kolmogorov s

More information

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS AARON LANDESMAN CONTENTS 1. Introduction to finite fields 2 2. Definition and constructions of fields 3 2.1. The definition of a field 3 2.2. Constructing field extensions by adjoining

More information

EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS AND OPERATORS ON ORDERED ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES. UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DELL'INSUBRIA Via Ravasi 2, Varese, Italy

EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS AND OPERATORS ON ORDERED ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES. UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DELL'INSUBRIA Via Ravasi 2, Varese, Italy UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DELL'INSUBRIA Via Ravasi 2, 21100 Varese, Italy Dipartimento di Scienze Teoriche e Applicate Di.S.T.A. Dipartimento di Scienza e Alta Tecnologia Di.S.A.T. PH.D. DEGREE PROGRAM IN

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SERGIO A. CELANI AND MARÍA ESTEBAN Abstract. Distributive Hilbert Algebras with infimum, or DH -algebras, are algebras with implication

More information

Linear Algebra. Chapter 5

Linear Algebra. Chapter 5 Chapter 5 Linear Algebra The guiding theme in linear algebra is the interplay between algebraic manipulations and geometric interpretations. This dual representation is what makes linear algebra a fruitful

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato June 23, 2015 This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a more direct connection

More information

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15 CHAPTER 15 Boolean Algebra 15.1 INTRODUCTION Both sets and propositions satisfy similar laws, which are listed in Tables 1-1 and 4-1 (in Chapters 1 and 4, respectively). These laws are used to define an

More information

FUNCTORS AND ADJUNCTIONS. 1. Functors

FUNCTORS AND ADJUNCTIONS. 1. Functors FUNCTORS AND ADJUNCTIONS Abstract. Graphs, quivers, natural transformations, adjunctions, Galois connections, Galois theory. 1.1. Graph maps. 1. Functors 1.1.1. Quivers. Quivers generalize directed graphs,

More information

Silvio Valentini Dip. di Matematica - Università di Padova

Silvio Valentini Dip. di Matematica - Università di Padova REPRESENTATION THEOREMS FOR QUANTALES Silvio Valentini Dip. di Matematica - Università di Padova Abstract. In this paper we prove that any quantale Q is (isomorphic to) a quantale of suitable relations

More information

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Boolean Algebras Let X be an arbitrary set and let P(X) be the class of all subsets of X (the power set of X). Three natural set-theoretic operations on P(X) are the binary operations of union

More information

Linear Algebra. Min Yan

Linear Algebra. Min Yan Linear Algebra Min Yan January 2, 2018 2 Contents 1 Vector Space 7 1.1 Definition................................. 7 1.1.1 Axioms of Vector Space..................... 7 1.1.2 Consequence of Axiom......................

More information

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories PART I Abstract algebraic categories It should be observed first that the whole concept of category is essentially an auxiliary one; our basic concepts are those of a functor and a natural transformation.

More information

Involutive Categories and Monoids, with a GNS-correspondence

Involutive Categories and Monoids, with a GNS-correspondence nvolutive Categories and Monoids, with a GNS-correspondence Bart Jacobs Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands Abstract This paper develops the basics of the theory of involutive categories and

More information

NEW DIRECTIONS IN CATEGORICAL LOGIC, FOR CLASSICAL, PROBABILISTIC AND QUANTUM LOGIC

NEW DIRECTIONS IN CATEGORICAL LOGIC, FOR CLASSICAL, PROBABILISTIC AND QUANTUM LOGIC Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 11(3:24)2015, pp. 1 76 www.lmcs-online.org Submitted Dec. 10, 2014 Published Sep. 30, 2015 NEW DIRECTIONS IN CATEGORICAL LOGIC, FOR CLASSICAL, PROBABILISTIC AND

More information

Adjoints, naturality, exactness, small Yoneda lemma. 1. Hom(X, ) is left exact

Adjoints, naturality, exactness, small Yoneda lemma. 1. Hom(X, ) is left exact (April 8, 2010) Adjoints, naturality, exactness, small Yoneda lemma Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ The best way to understand or remember left-exactness or right-exactness

More information

0 Sets and Induction. Sets

0 Sets and Induction. Sets 0 Sets and Induction Sets A set is an unordered collection of objects, called elements or members of the set. A set is said to contain its elements. We write a A to denote that a is an element of the set

More information

Properties of Boolean Algebras

Properties of Boolean Algebras Phillip James Swansea University December 15, 2008 Plan For Today Boolean Algebras and Order..... Brief Re-cap Order A Boolean algebra is a set A together with the distinguished elements 0 and 1, the binary

More information

General Notation. Exercises and Problems

General Notation. Exercises and Problems Exercises and Problems The text contains both Exercises and Problems. The exercises are incorporated into the development of the theory in each section. Additional Problems appear at the end of most sections.

More information

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u.

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u. 5. Fields 5.1. Field extensions. Let F E be a subfield of the field E. We also describe this situation by saying that E is an extension field of F, and we write E/F to express this fact. If E/F is a field

More information

Introduction to Real Analysis

Introduction to Real Analysis Christopher Heil Introduction to Real Analysis Chapter 0 Online Expanded Chapter on Notation and Preliminaries Last Updated: January 9, 2018 c 2018 by Christopher Heil Chapter 0 Notation and Preliminaries:

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

ALGEBRA II: RINGS AND MODULES OVER LITTLE RINGS.

ALGEBRA II: RINGS AND MODULES OVER LITTLE RINGS. ALGEBRA II: RINGS AND MODULES OVER LITTLE RINGS. KEVIN MCGERTY. 1. RINGS The central characters of this course are algebraic objects known as rings. A ring is any mathematical structure where you can add

More information

Endomorphism Semialgebras in Categorical Quantum Mechanics

Endomorphism Semialgebras in Categorical Quantum Mechanics Endomorphism Semialgebras in Categorical Quantum Mechanics Kevin Dunne University of Strathclyde November 2016 Symmetric Monoidal Categories Definition A strict symmetric monoidal category (A,, I ) consists

More information

Foundations of mathematics. 5. Galois connections

Foundations of mathematics. 5. Galois connections Foundations of mathematics 5. Galois connections Sylvain Poirier http://settheory.net/ The notion of Galois connection was introduced in 2.11 (see http://settheory.net/set2.pdf) with its first properties.

More information

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions 24 Andreas Gathmann 3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions After having defined affine varieties, our next goal must be to say what kind of maps between them we want to consider as morphisms, i. e. as nice

More information

NOTES ON MODULES AND ALGEBRAS

NOTES ON MODULES AND ALGEBRAS NOTES ON MODULES AND ALGEBRAS WILLIAM SCHMITT 1. Some Remarks about Categories Throughout these notes, we will be using some of the basic terminology and notation from category theory. Roughly speaking,

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

GALOIS CATEGORIES MELISSA LYNN

GALOIS CATEGORIES MELISSA LYNN GALOIS CATEGORIES MELISSA LYNN Abstract. In abstract algebra, we considered finite Galois extensions of fields with their Galois groups. Here, we noticed a correspondence between the intermediate fields

More information

BERNARD RUSSO. University of California, Irvine

BERNARD RUSSO. University of California, Irvine A HOLOMORPHIC CHARACTERIZATION OF OPERATOR ALGEBRAS (JOINT WORK WITH MATT NEAL) BERNARD RUSSO University of California, Irvine UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE ANALYSIS SEMINAR OCTOBER 16, 2012 KEYWORDS

More information

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property Congruence Boolean Lifting Property George GEORGESCU and Claudia MUREŞAN University of Bucharest Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Academiei 14, RO 010014, Bucharest, Romania Emails: georgescu.capreni@yahoo.com;

More information

A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces

A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces Reinhold Heckmann AbsInt Angewandte Informatik GmbH, Stuhlsatzenhausweg 69, D-66123 Saarbrücken, Germany e-mail: heckmann@absint.com Abstract The category

More information

Cantor-Bendixson, socle, and atomicity H. Simmons

Cantor-Bendixson, socle, and atomicity H. Simmons Cantor-Bendixson, socle, and atomicity H. Simmons The University, Manchester, England Harold.Simmons @ manchester.ac.uk This document is the second in the series [1] [7], concerned with the use of lattices

More information

Algebraic Geometry

Algebraic Geometry MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 18.726 Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. 18.726: Algebraic Geometry

More information

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras Chapter 2 Equational Logic 2.1 Syntax 2.1.1 Terms and Term Algebras The natural logic of algebra is equational logic, whose propositions are universally quantified identities between terms built up from

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Review of Linear Algebra

Review of Linear Algebra Review of Linear Algebra Throughout these notes, F denotes a field (often called the scalars in this context). 1 Definition of a vector space Definition 1.1. A F -vector space or simply a vector space

More information

2MA105 Algebraic Structures I

2MA105 Algebraic Structures I 2MA105 Algebraic Structures I Per-Anders Svensson http://homepage.lnu.se/staff/psvmsi/2ma105.html Lecture 12 Partially Ordered Sets Lattices Bounded Lattices Distributive Lattices Complemented Lattices

More information

Direct Limits. Mathematics 683, Fall 2013

Direct Limits. Mathematics 683, Fall 2013 Direct Limits Mathematics 683, Fall 2013 In this note we define direct limits and prove their basic properties. This notion is important in various places in algebra. In particular, in algebraic geometry

More information

Abstract Vector Spaces and Concrete Examples

Abstract Vector Spaces and Concrete Examples LECTURE 18 Abstract Vector Spaces and Concrete Examples Our discussion of linear algebra so far has been devoted to discussing the relations between systems of linear equations, matrices, and vectors.

More information

ne varieties (continued)

ne varieties (continued) Chapter 2 A ne varieties (continued) 2.1 Products For some problems its not very natural to restrict to irreducible varieties. So we broaden the previous story. Given an a ne algebraic set X A n k, we

More information

CATEGORICAL GROTHENDIECK RINGS AND PICARD GROUPS. Contents. 1. The ring K(R) and the group Pic(R)

CATEGORICAL GROTHENDIECK RINGS AND PICARD GROUPS. Contents. 1. The ring K(R) and the group Pic(R) CATEGORICAL GROTHENDIECK RINGS AND PICARD GROUPS J. P. MAY Contents 1. The ring K(R) and the group Pic(R) 1 2. Symmetric monoidal categories, K(C), and Pic(C) 2 3. The unit endomorphism ring R(C ) 5 4.

More information

1 Fields and vector spaces

1 Fields and vector spaces 1 Fields and vector spaces In this section we revise some algebraic preliminaries and establish notation. 1.1 Division rings and fields A division ring, or skew field, is a structure F with two binary

More information

Lectures - XXIII and XXIV Coproducts and Pushouts

Lectures - XXIII and XXIV Coproducts and Pushouts Lectures - XXIII and XXIV Coproducts and Pushouts We now discuss further categorical constructions that are essential for the formulation of the Seifert Van Kampen theorem. We first discuss the notion

More information

Number Axioms. P. Danziger. A Group is a set S together with a binary operation (*) on S, denoted a b such that for all a, b. a b S.

Number Axioms. P. Danziger. A Group is a set S together with a binary operation (*) on S, denoted a b such that for all a, b. a b S. Appendix A Number Axioms P. Danziger 1 Number Axioms 1.1 Groups Definition 1 A Group is a set S together with a binary operation (*) on S, denoted a b such that for all a, b and c S 0. (Closure) 1. (Associativity)

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Ivan Avramidi New Mexico Institute of Mining and Technology Socorro, NM 87801 June 3, 2004 Author: Ivan Avramidi; File: absmath.tex; Date: June 11,

More information

Convex Optimization Notes

Convex Optimization Notes Convex Optimization Notes Jonathan Siegel January 2017 1 Convex Analysis This section is devoted to the study of convex functions f : B R {+ } and convex sets U B, for B a Banach space. The case of B =

More information

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: ADJOINTS IN HILBERT SPACES

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: ADJOINTS IN HILBERT SPACES FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: ADJOINTS IN HILBERT SPACES CHRISTOPHER HEIL 1. Adjoints in Hilbert Spaces Recall that the dot product on R n is given by x y = x T y, while the dot product on C n is

More information

Symbol Index Group GermAnal Ring AbMonoid

Symbol Index Group GermAnal Ring AbMonoid Symbol Index 409 Symbol Index Symbols of standard and uncontroversial usage are generally not included here. As in the word index, boldface page-numbers indicate pages where definitions are given. If a

More information

1. A Little Set Theory

1. A Little Set Theory . A Little Set Theory I see it, but I don t believe it. Cantor to Dedekind 29 June 877 Functions are the single most important idea pervading modern mathematics. We will assume the informal definition

More information

Math 762 Spring h Y (Z 1 ) (1) h X (Z 2 ) h X (Z 1 ) Φ Z 1. h Y (Z 2 )

Math 762 Spring h Y (Z 1 ) (1) h X (Z 2 ) h X (Z 1 ) Φ Z 1. h Y (Z 2 ) Math 762 Spring 2016 Homework 3 Drew Armstrong Problem 1. Yoneda s Lemma. We have seen that the bifunctor Hom C (, ) : C C Set is analogous to a bilinear form on a K-vector space, : V V K. Recall that

More information

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/monomorphism 1 of 3 24/11/2012 02:01 Monomorphism From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In the context of abstract algebra or

More information

Recall: a mapping f : A B C (where A, B, C are R-modules) is called R-bilinear if f is R-linear in each coordinate, i.e.,

Recall: a mapping f : A B C (where A, B, C are R-modules) is called R-bilinear if f is R-linear in each coordinate, i.e., 23 Hom and We will do homological algebra over a fixed commutative ring R. There are several good reasons to take a commutative ring: Left R-modules are the same as right R-modules. [In general a right

More information

THE LENGTH OF NOETHERIAN MODULES

THE LENGTH OF NOETHERIAN MODULES THE LENGTH OF NOETHERIAN MODULES GARY BROOKFIELD Abstract. We define an ordinal valued length for Noetherian modules which extends the usual definition of composition series length for finite length modules.

More information

Introduction to abstract algebra: definitions, examples, and exercises

Introduction to abstract algebra: definitions, examples, and exercises Introduction to abstract algebra: definitions, examples, and exercises Travis Schedler January 21, 2015 1 Definitions and some exercises Definition 1. A binary operation on a set X is a map X X X, (x,

More information

Exercises on chapter 0

Exercises on chapter 0 Exercises on chapter 0 1. A partially ordered set (poset) is a set X together with a relation such that (a) x x for all x X; (b) x y and y x implies that x = y for all x, y X; (c) x y and y z implies that

More information

Two-sided multiplications and phantom line bundles

Two-sided multiplications and phantom line bundles Two-sided multiplications and phantom line bundles Ilja Gogić Department of Mathematics University of Zagreb 19th Geometrical Seminar Zlatibor, Serbia August 28 September 4, 2016 joint work with Richard

More information

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Sergiu Rudeanu University of Bucharest Romania Closure operators are abundant in mathematics; here are a few examples. Given an algebraic structure, such

More information

Topological vectorspaces

Topological vectorspaces (July 25, 2011) Topological vectorspaces Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ Natural non-fréchet spaces Topological vector spaces Quotients and linear maps More topological

More information

Algebraic Geometry: Limits and Colimits

Algebraic Geometry: Limits and Colimits Algebraic Geometry: Limits and Coits Limits Definition.. Let I be a small category, C be any category, and F : I C be a functor. If for each object i I and morphism m ij Mor I (i, j) there is an associated

More information

Physical justification for using the tensor product to describe two quantum systems as one joint system

Physical justification for using the tensor product to describe two quantum systems as one joint system Physical justification for using the tensor product to describe two quantum systems as one joint system Diederik Aerts and Ingrid Daubechies Theoretical Physics Brussels Free University Pleinlaan 2, 1050

More information

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07)

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07) P. J. Šafárik University, Faculty of Science, Košice Project 2005/NP1-051 11230100466 Basic information Extent: 2 hrs lecture/1 hrs seminar per week. Assessment: Written tests during the semester, written

More information

Structure of rings. Chapter Algebras

Structure of rings. Chapter Algebras Chapter 5 Structure of rings 5.1 Algebras It is time to introduce the notion of an algebra over a commutative ring. So let R be a commutative ring. An R-algebra is a ring A (unital as always) together

More information

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued)

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued) 2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued) 2.1. New examples of commutative rings. Recall that in the first lecture we defined the notions of commutative rings and field and gave some examples of

More information

University of Oxford, Michaelis November 16, Categorical Semantics and Topos Theory Homotopy type theor

University of Oxford, Michaelis November 16, Categorical Semantics and Topos Theory Homotopy type theor Categorical Semantics and Topos Theory Homotopy type theory Seminar University of Oxford, Michaelis 2011 November 16, 2011 References Johnstone, P.T.: Sketches of an Elephant. A Topos-Theory Compendium.

More information

MATH 101: ALGEBRA I WORKSHEET, DAY #1. We review the prerequisites for the course in set theory and beginning a first pass on group. 1.

MATH 101: ALGEBRA I WORKSHEET, DAY #1. We review the prerequisites for the course in set theory and beginning a first pass on group. 1. MATH 101: ALGEBRA I WORKSHEET, DAY #1 We review the prerequisites for the course in set theory and beginning a first pass on group theory. Fill in the blanks as we go along. 1. Sets A set is a collection

More information

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ag] 3 Mar 2002

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ag] 3 Mar 2002 How to sum up triangles arxiv:math/0203022v1 [math.ag] 3 Mar 2002 Bakharev F. Kokhas K. Petrov F. June 2001 Abstract We prove configuration theorems that generalize the Desargues, Pascal, and Pappus theorems.

More information

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs MAT 1362 Fall 2018 Alistair Savage Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0

More information

Spectral Theory, with an Introduction to Operator Means. William L. Green

Spectral Theory, with an Introduction to Operator Means. William L. Green Spectral Theory, with an Introduction to Operator Means William L. Green January 30, 2008 Contents Introduction............................... 1 Hilbert Space.............................. 4 Linear Maps

More information

BERNARD RUSSO. University of California, Irvine

BERNARD RUSSO. University of California, Irvine A HOLOMORPHIC CHARACTERIZATION OF OPERATOR ALGEBRAS (JOINT WORK WITH MATT NEAL) BERNARD RUSSO University of California, Irvine UNIVERSITY OF HOUSTON GREAT PLAINS OPERATOR THEORY SYMPOSIUM MAY 30-JUNE 2,

More information