Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices"

Transcription

1 Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Sergiu Rudeanu University of Bucharest Romania Closure operators are abundant in mathematics; here are a few examples. Given an algebraic structure, such as group, ring, field, lattice, vector space, etc., taking the substructure generated by a set, i.e., the least substructure which includes that set, is a closure operator. Given a binary relation, taking the relation with certain properties, such as reflexive, transitive, equivalence, etc., generated by the given relation, i.e., the least relation with the desired properties which includes the original relation, is a closure operator. The consequence operators in mathematical logic are closure operators. Topological spaces can be defined by Kuratowski closure operators. In this survey paper we have selected those facts about closure operators that we consider to be the most important ones. We present them in the Ockham razor spirit, i.e., under no more hypotheses than necessary. We have thus detected three levels of generality: A) closure operators on posets, B) closure operators on complete lattices, and C) closure operators on fields of sets P(A), which we tackle in this order. Level A, due to Bourbaki, is less known. However the fundamental property used in the applications of closure operators to various fields of mathematics is valid for arbitrary posets: the existence of the closure x of each element x of the underlying set, that is, the least closed element which includes x. Besides, closure operators are in bijection with the associated sets of closed elements, known as closure systems or Moore families. In the case of complete lattices, every (finite or not) meet of closed elements is closed, so that every Moore family is itself a complete lattice, but not a sublattice of the original one. Level C is the framework of algebraic closures, whose associated closure systems describe an algebraic structure, or equivalently, a deductive structure. We have incorporated this equivalence and two intrinsic characterizations of algebraic closures, in a theorem which is emblematic for the unifying power of closure operators. The last part of the paper is devoted to compactly generated complete lattices, known as algebraic lattices. They are related to level C by a representation theorem. For properties of closure operators not included in this paper see e.g. [2, 4.4, 4.5]. * * * 1

2 In the sequel we will use the abbreviation poset for a partially ordered set (P, ) and we will read x y as x is included in y, or y includes x. Definition 1 If P is a poset, a map : P P is called a closure operator or simply a closure, if for every x, y P the following properties hold: x x (extensivity), x = x (idempotence), x y = x ȳ (isotony). The elements x P satisfying x = x are said to be closed. We denote by C the set of closed elements: C = {x P x = x}. We have mentioned above several examples of closures. Besides, note that the identity map x x is a closure operator. Proposition 1 If is a closure on the poset P, then for each x P, x is the least closed element which includes x. Proof: x is closed by idempotence, x x by extensivity, and if y is a closed element such that x y then x ȳ = y, so that x y. Notation For every poset P, every subset S P and every x P, we set S(x] = {y S x y}. Instead of P (x] we use the simplified notation (x] = {y P x y}. Definition 2 If P is a poset, by a closure system or Moore family we mean any non-empty subset C P such that for each x P, the set C(x] has least element. With this definition, Proposition 1 can be reformulated: Proposition 1 The set of closed elements of a closure operator is a closure system. The converse is also true : Proposition 2 Let P be a poset and C a closure system of P. The assignment is a closure on P. x x = least element of C(x] Proof: It is well known that the bottom element of a poset, whenever it exists, is unique. Therefore the above assigment is indeed a map. We have x C(x], hence the extensivity x x holds and x C. The latter membership together with x x show that x C( x], hence the least element x satisfies x x. But extensivity implies x x, therefore the idempotence x = x holds. If x y then C(y] C(x], therefore the (least) element x of C(x] is included in particular in all the elements of C(y] and since ȳ C(y] it follows that x ȳ, proving isotony. 2

3 Theorem 1 The maps constructed in Propositions 1 and 2 establish a bijection between the closure operators and the closure systems of P. Proof: We shall prove that by composing the two maps in the two possible orders one obtains the identity maps, i.e., Prop1 C Prop2 C Prop2? =, Prop1 C? = C. First composition: x is the least element of C(x]. On the other hand x = x, hence x C, and moreover, x C(x] because x x. Besides, if y C(x] then y C and x y, hence x ȳ = y. Therefore x is also the first element of C(x], hence x= x. Second composition: x C x = x x is the least element of C(x] = x C = x C(x] = x is bottom of C(x] x C. In the case of complete lattices, Moore families have a simpler characterization. Proposition 3 A subset C of a complete lattice L is a closure system if and only if every meet of elements from C belongs to C. Comment: The above statement includes the case of the empty meet, which is the greatest element 1. If you don t like this convention, replace the above by 1 C and the meet of every non-empty subset.... Anyway the proof must distinguish the two cases. Proof: Suppose C is a closure system and let be the associated closure operator. Then 1 C because 1 1 and 1 1 as greatest element. Now suppose X C and set a = infx. Then for every x X we have a x hence ā x = x, proving that a is a lower bound of all x X, therefore ā a and since a ā, it follows that a = ā C. Conversely, suppose C satisfies the above condition. Then 1 C, as remarked in Comment, so C. For every x L set a = infc(x]; to prove that a is least element, it remains to check that a C(x]. Since C(x] C, it follows that a C. Besides, since x is a lower bound of C(x], it follows that x a, therefore a C(x]. Proposition 3 can be extended to an important property. Theorem 2 Every closure system C of a complete lattice (L, inf, sup, 0, 1) is a complete lattice (C, inf,, 0, 1) under the same meet operation as L, while X = supx for every X C. Proof: The property established in Proposition 3 implies that C is a complete lattice under the same meet operation as L because, according to a well-known remark, the join of an arbitrary subset X C is obtained as the meet of the set of all upper bounds of X. Clearly 0 is the least element of C and it was shown in the proof of Proposition 3 that 1 C. 3

4 The other construction of expresses the fact that supx is the least upper bound in C of all the elements of the subset X C In the sequel we take an arbitrary but fixed non-empty set A and we concentrate on the closure operators of the set P(A) of all subsets of A. Since (P(A),,,, A) is a complete lattice, the previous results apply to this case, but there are also many specific results of greatest interest. Recall that an algebra A with underlying set A is a structure A = (A, (f i ) i I ) where each f i is an operation f i : A ni A of arity n i on A. The subalgebras of A (properly speaking, of A) are defined in a natural way and every intersection of subalgebras is a subalgebra, therefore the set SubA of all subalgebras of A is a Moore family. Definition 3 A closure system C on P(A) is called algebraic if there exists an algebra A such that C = SubA. Recall also that an ideal of a join semilattice (L, ) is a non-empty subset I L such that x y I = x I and x, y I = x y I. Proposition 4 The ideals of a join semilattice with least element (L,, 0) form an algebraic closure system. Proof: Let (L,, 0) be a join semilattice with zero. For each a L define { a, if a x, ϕ a (x) = x, if a x. The subalgebras of the algebra A = (L,, 0, (ϕ a ) a L ) form a Moore family SubA. To prove that the ideals of L form an algebraic closure system, we will prove that the ideals coincide with the subalgebras of A. If S is a subalgebra then 0 S. If x, y S then x y S. If x S and y x then y = ϕ y (x) S. If I is an ideal then 0 I and if x, y I then x y I. For every x I and every a L, if a x then ϕ a (x) = a I, while if a x then ϕ a (x) = x I again. The following structures are more general than algebras. Definition 4 A deductive structure or a formal proof system is a tuple D = (A, (R i ) i I ) where R i A n(i) A, n(i) 0, for each i I. The R i s are called deduction rules if n(i) > 0 and axiom schemes if n(i) = 0, in which case R i A. If X A and y A, by a formal proof of y from X is meant a sequence (y 1,..., y m = y) of elements from A such that for each k = 1,..., m, either y k X or there is i I and a sequence of indices k 1,..., k n(i) < k such that (y k1,..., y kn(i), y k ) R i. If this happens we say that y is deducible from X and we denote this fact by X D y or simply X y. We set X = {y A X y}. In particular the elements of are called theses. A subset S A is said to be deductively closed if S = S. We say that the map X X is the consequence operator of D. 4

5 Proposition 5 The consequence operator of a deductive structure D is a closure operator on the set P(A) of subsets of the underlying set A of D. Proof: If x X then the singleton sequence (x) is a formal proof of x from X, therefore X X. For idempotence we will prove that X X. Indeed, if y X then there is a formal proof y 1,..., y m = y of y from X. If in the sequence y 1,..., y m we replace each y k by a formal proof of y k from X, we obtain a formal proof of y from X and therefore y X. Finally suppose X Y and take z X. Then there is a formal proof of z from X, say z 1,..., z m = z. For each k = 1,..., m for which z k X, we have z k Y ; this shows that z Y. Therefore X Y = X Y. Definition 5 A closure operator on (P(A), ) is said to be deductive if it is the consequence operator of a deductive structure defined on A. A closure system C is said to be deductive if the closure operator associated with C is deductive. Definition 6 A poset is said to be directed if every two elements of it have a common upper bound. A family (A t ) t T of subsets of A is said to be directed if the index set T is a directed poset and for every s, t T, s t = A s A t. Theorem 3 The following conditions are equivalent for a closure system C on (P(A), ) : (i) C is algebraic; (ii) C is deductive: (iii) if (A t ) t T C is a directed family then t T A t C; (iv) the closure operator associated with C satisfies (*) X = {Y Y X, Y finite} X P(A). Comment: The equivalence (i) (iv) is known as the Birkhoff-Frink theorem. Proof: (i)= (ii): Let C = SubA, where A = (A, (f i ) i I ), and let be the closure operator associated with C. We can identify each operation f i : A ni A with its graph f i A ni A, so that A becomes a deductive structure as well. Moreover, as shown in universal algebra, for every X A, each element y X has finitely many generators from X and the construction of y is the same in the algebra (see e.g. [3], Proposition 6.5.5) and in the deductive structure, that is, y X X y. This shows that C is also the closure system associated with the deductive structure A. (ii)= (iii): Let (A t ) t T C be a directed family and B = t T A t. If B y then there is a formal proof x 1,..., x m = x of x from B. Let {k 1,..., k r } {1,..., m} be the set of those indices k m for which x k B. For each of these indices k j there is t j T such that x kj A tj. Let s T be an upper bound of t 1,..., t r ; it follows that x k1,..., x kr A s. For the other indices k {1,..., m}, the elements x k are obtained by applying deduction rules. This 5

6 shows that A s x and since A s is deductively closed, it follows that x A s B. Thus B x = x B, showing that B C. (iii)= (iv): Let X A and denote by X # the right side of (*). We shall prove that X # = X. We have # = {Y Y } = {Y Y = } =. Now we suppose X and we shall prove that X # is the least set from C which includes X. In view of (iii), in order to prove that X # C, it suffices to prove that X = {Y Y X, Y finite} is a directed family if it is directed by X itself. Indeed, take Y 1, Y 2 X, where Y 1 and Y 2 are finite subsets of X. Then Y 1 Y 2 is a finite subset of X, hence Y 1, Y 2 Y 1 Y 2 X. If x X then x {x} {x} X #. Therefore X X #. Now suppose X Z C. For every Y X # where Y is a finite subset of X we have Y X Z = Z, hence Y Z. It follows that X # Z. (iv)= (i): For every finite subset Z A and every a Z, define f Za : A n A, where n = cardz, as follows: { a, if {x1,..., x f ZA (x 1,..., x n ) = n } = Z, x 1, if {x 1,..., x n } Z; in particular if a then f a = a. Let < X > denote the subalgebra of A = (A, (f Za ) Za ) generated by a subset X A. We shall prove that < X >= X, which will show that C = SubA. It is known from universal algebra that < X >= p 0 X p where X 0 = X and X p+1 = X p Y p where Y p is the set of all the elements f Za (x 1,..., x n ) with arguments x 1,..., x n X p (see e.g. [3], Proposition 6.5.5). In order to show that < X > X we will prove by induction that X p X for all p. We have X 0 = X X. Now we suppose X p X and must prove that X p+1 X; it suffices to show that Y p X. Indeed, take f Za (x 1,..., x n ) Y p ; then x 1,..., x n X p X. If {x 1,..., x n } Z then f Za (x 1,..., x n ) = x 1 X. If {x 1,..., x n } = Z then f Za (x 1,..., x n ) = a Z = {x 1,..., x n } X = X. Thus we have proved that < X > X and it remains to prove that X < X >, which we will do in three steps. For X = there are two posibilities. If = then < >. If then for every a we have a = f a < > because the constant operations belong to any subalgebra, therefore again < >. If X = {x 1,..., x n } then for every A X we have a = f Xa (x 1,..., x n ) < X >, therefore X < X >. We have thus proved that Y < Y > for every finite set Y, therefore in formula (*) we have Y < Y > < X >, so that X < X > for any subset X A. In the sequel we discuss algebraic lattices. The inclusion of this topic within closure operators on sets is justified by the fact that the closure system (C, ) from Theorem 3 is an algebraic lattice, as shown in Theorem 4 below. Moreover, any algebraic lattice can be represented as an algebra of sets, namely the ideal lattice of a join semilattice with 0, as shown in Theorem 5. 6

7 Definition 7 Let S be a complete join semilattice, i.e., a poset S such that supx exists for every non-empty subset X S. An element c S is called compact if for every non-empty subset X S, (**) c sup X = c sup X 0 for some finite subset X 0 X. A complete join semilattice with bottom element 0 is a complete lattice because 0 = sup, so that all joins exist, hence all meets exist, too. Note that 0 is a trivial example of a compact element. Definition 8 A complete lattice is said to be algebraic if every element is a supremum of compact elements. Remark 1 A complete lattice is algebraic iff every element x satisfies x = sup K(x] = sup {c K c x}, where K stands for the set of compact elements. Recall that we denote by C and a closure system and the associated closure operator. Theorem 4 Every algebraic closure (C, ) on (P(A), ) is an algebraic lattice in which the compact elements are the closures X of finite sets X. Proof: We already know that C is a complete lattice by Theorem 2 applied to (P(A),,,, A). Having in view Theorem 3, it remains to prove that the compact elements coincide with the closures of finite sets. The set is the bottom element of the lattice C, hence it is compact, as was noted above. Now take X = {x 1,..., x n }; to prove that X is compact, suppose X sup {F t t T }, where F t C for all t T. Then, using Theorem 3, we get X X sup {F t t T } = F t = {Y Y F t, Y finite}, t T hence for each i {1,..., n} there is Y i t T F t, Y i finite, such that x i Y i. Set Y = n i=1 Y i. Then Y is a finite set, Y t T F t, and since all Y i Y, it follows that Y i Y (i = 1,..., n), hence X n i=1 Y i Y. If Y = then X F t for each t T. If Y = {y 1,..., y p } then for each k {1,..., p} there is t k T such that y k F tk, hence Y p k=1 F t k, therefore X Y t T p F tk = sup {F t1,..., F tp }. k=1 Conversely, let F be a compact element of C. Then F = F = {Y Y F, Y finite} sup {Y Y F, Y finite}, because X X = supx by Theorem 2 applied with := sup and sup :=. Therefore there exists a finite subset Y {Y Y F, Y finite} such that 7

8 F supy. If Y = then supy is the least element of C, so that F and in fact F =, where is a finite set. Otherwise Y = {Y 1,..., Y p }, where Y 1,..., Y p are finite subsets of F. Then Y = p k=1 Y k is a finite subset of F and Y F. On the other hand, Y k Y implies Y k Y (k = 1,..., p), hence F sup {Y 1,..., Y p } Y. Therefore F = Y, where Y is a finite set. Theorems 3 and 4 enable us to strengthen Proposition 4, with a quite different proof. Proposition 6 The set IdS of ideals of a join semilattice with zero (S,, 0) is an algebraic lattice, in which the compact elements are the principal ideals. Proof: Clearly every non-empty intersection of ideals is an ideal, while S is the improper ideal, therefore IdS is a Moore family. It is also clear that IdS satisfies condition (iii) from Theorem 3, therefore IdS is an algebraic closure. It follows by Theorem 4 that IdS is an algebraic lattice and the compact elements are the ideals generated by finite sets. The ideal generated by is the bottom ideal {0} = (0] and the ideal generated by a set {x 1,..., x n } is the principal ideal (x 1... x n ]. Exercise 1 In the lattice IdS the following hold: the ideal generated by a non-empty subset X is X = {y S y x 1... x n ; x 1,..., x n X, n 1} and in particular, if I 1,..., I n IdS then I 1... I n = {y S y x 1... x n ; x k I k (k = 1,..., n)}, while every ideal I satisfies I = x I (x] = x I (x]. Exercise 2 The set K(L) of compact elements of an algebraic lattice (L,,, 0, 1) is a join semilattice with zero (K(L),, 0). Our last aim in this paper is an isomorphism theorem. We need a preparation about poset isomorphisms. Let Pos denote the category whose objects are all the posets, while the morphisms are the functions f which satisfy x y = f(x) f(y), known as isotone functions. Lemma 1 A function f : P Q between two posets P,Q is an isomorphism in Pos if and only if it satisfies the conditions (α) f is surjective, (β) x 1, x 2 P : x 1 x 2 f(x 1 ) f(x 2 ). Proof: The conditions are obviously necessary. Conversely, suppose f satisfies (α) and (β). If f(x 1 ) = f(x 2 ) then f(x 1 ) f(x 2 ) and f(x 2 ) f(x 1 ), hence x 1 x 2 and x 2 x 1, therefore x 1 = x 2, showing that f is an injection, therefore f is a bijection. The implication = in (β) shows that f is isotone, and since f is a bijection, the implication = in (β) shows that f 1 is isotone. 8

9 Lemma 2 An isomorphism f : P Q in Pos preserves all existing infima and suprema. Proof: Let us prove that f(supx) = supf(x) provided there exists a = supx. If X = then a = 0 x for every x P, hence f(a) f(x) where f(x) is an arbitrary element of Q because f is surjective, so that f(a) = 0 (bottom of Q), while f( ) = Q, therefore supf( ) = 0 as well. If X then for every x X we have x a, hence f(x) f(a). This proves that f(a) is an upper bound of f(x); to prove it is the least one, take an arbitrary upper bound z of f(x) in Q. Then z = f(b) for some b P and f(x) z = f(b) for all x X, therefore by applying (β) from Lemma 1 it follows that x b for all x X, hence a b by the definition of a, and finally f(a) f(b) = z. This proves that f(a) is indeed the l.u.b. of f(x), that is, f(a) = supf(x). It is commonplace that lattices have two equivalent definitions, as algebras and as posets with a special property. This is not exactly so if we refer to morphisms. Indeed, a lattice homomorphism is naturally defined as a map which preserves and, that is, f(x y) = f(x) f(y) and f(x y) = f(x) f(y). It is well known that a lattice morphism is isotone but the converse fails. Lemma 2 shows that the equivalence is recaptured at the level of isomorphisms. To state this fact properly, we must extend the isomorphisms of Pos beyond Pos, in the sense of the following definition. Definition 9 Consider a map f : P Q where P and Q are sets endowed with structures that include a partial order. We say that f is an order isomorphism if f is a bijection and both f and f 1 are isotone. Noting that 0 and 1 are sup s (or that they are inf s), from Lemma 2 we obtain the following Corollary 1 In each of the following categories: meet semilattices, join semilattices, lattices, with or without 0, with or without 1, isomorphisms coincide with order isomorphisms. It is clear that this corollary can be extended to other similar categories. At first glance complete lattices don t fall exactly within the similar categories mentioned above. A complete lattice may be regarded either as a poset in which every subset has inf and sup, or as a lattice which has this supplementary property, as we have understood in this paper. In either variant the category of complete lattices is defined by taking as morphisms the maps that preserve all meets and joins. Corollary 2 In the category of complete lattices isomorphisms coincide with order isomorphisms. It is natural to define the category of algebraic lattices as the full subcategory of the category of complete lattices determined by algebraic lattices. 9

10 In the last theorem we use the semilattice (K(L),, 0) of compact elements of an algebraic lattice L and the algebraic lattice IdS of ideals of a semilattice S, which appear in Exercise 2 and Proposition 6, respectively. Theorem 5 Every algebraic lattice L is isomorphic to the algebraic lattice IdK(L) of ideals of the join semilattice K(L). Proof: For every x L, the set k(x) = {c K(L) c x} = K(L)(x] is the principal ideal defined by x in the semilattice K(L), therefore we have defined a map k : L IdK(L). In view of Corollary 2, it suffices to prove that k is an order isomorphism. We will do this by using Lemma 1. To prove (α), that is surjectivity, take I IdK(L). Then I K(L) L and let a = sup I. For every x I we have x K(L) and x a, hence x k(a). This proves that I k(a). Conversely, take x k(a). Then x K(L) and x a = sup I, hence there is a finite subset I 0 I such that x sup I 0. If I 0 = then x 0, therefore x = 0 I. If I 0 = {i 1,..., i n } then x i 1... i n I, hence x I again. This proves that k(a) I, therefore I = k(a). To prove (β), take x 1, x 2 L. If x 1 x 2 then clearly k(x 1 ) k(x 2 ). Conversely, suppose k(x 1 ) k(x 2 ). Then, using Remark 1, we get x 1 = sup k(x 1 ) sup k(x 2 ) = x 2. Exercise 3 Every isomorphism f : L L of algebraic lattices preserves compact elements, i.e., f(k(l)) K(L ). Exercise 4 Every sub-complete-lattice of an algebraic lattice is an algebraic lattice. References [1] N. Bourbaki, Eléments de Mathématiques. Théorie des Ensembles. Chap.3. Hermann, Paris [2] S. Rudeanu, Sets and Ordered Structures. Bentham ebooks, Bentham Sci, Publ., 2012 (online). [3] S. Rudeanu, Chapters VI, VII in C.P. Popovici, S. Rudeanu, H. Georgescu, Bazele informaticii, vol. II. Univ. Bucureşti, Facultatea de Matematică, Bucureşti [4] W. Wechler, Universal Algebra for Computer Scientists. Springer-Verlag, Berlin/Heidelberg/New York,

Universal Algebra for Logics

Universal Algebra for Logics Universal Algebra for Logics Joanna GRYGIEL University of Czestochowa Poland j.grygiel@ajd.czest.pl 2005 These notes form Lecture Notes of a short course which I will give at 1st School on Universal Logic

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013)

Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013) Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013) Navid Alaei September 17, 2013 1 Lattice Basics There are, in general, two equivalent approaches to defining a lattice; one is rather

More information

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras Chapter 2 Equational Logic 2.1 Syntax 2.1.1 Terms and Term Algebras The natural logic of algebra is equational logic, whose propositions are universally quantified identities between terms built up from

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property Congruence Boolean Lifting Property George GEORGESCU and Claudia MUREŞAN University of Bucharest Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Academiei 14, RO 010014, Bucharest, Romania Emails: georgescu.capreni@yahoo.com;

More information

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra SET THEORY Basic concepts Notations Subset Algebra of sets The power set Ordered pairs and Cartesian product Relations on sets Types of relations and their properties Relational matrix and the graph of

More information

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees Francesc Rosselló 1, Gabriel Valiente 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Research Institute

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

Lecture 1: Lattice(I)

Lecture 1: Lattice(I) Discrete Mathematics (II) Spring 207 Lecture : Lattice(I) Lecturer: Yi Li Lattice is a special algebra structure. It is also a part of theoretic foundation of model theory, which formalizes the semantics

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato September 10, 2015 ABSTRACT. This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a

More information

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12 MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 2 CİHAN BAHRAN 3.2.. Let Y be a Noetherian scheme. Show that any Y -scheme X of finite type is Noetherian. Moreover, if Y is of finite dimension, then so is X. Write f

More information

A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces

A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces Reinhold Heckmann AbsInt Angewandte Informatik GmbH, Stuhlsatzenhausweg 69, D-66123 Saarbrücken, Germany e-mail: heckmann@absint.com Abstract The category

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

Cantor-Bendixson, socle, and atomicity H. Simmons

Cantor-Bendixson, socle, and atomicity H. Simmons Cantor-Bendixson, socle, and atomicity H. Simmons The University, Manchester, England Harold.Simmons @ manchester.ac.uk This document is the second in the series [1] [7], concerned with the use of lattices

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato June 23, 2015 This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a more direct connection

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps

1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps 1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps Last updated: April 14, 2011. 1.1 Examples and definitions Roughly, manifolds are sets where one can introduce coordinates. An n-dimensional manifold is a set

More information

Extending Algebraic Operations to D-Completions

Extending Algebraic Operations to D-Completions Replace this file with prentcsmacro.sty for your meeting, or with entcsmacro.sty for your meeting. Both can be found at the ENTCS Macro Home Page. Extending Algebraic Operations to D-Completions Klaus

More information

ON POSITIVE, LINEAR AND QUADRATIC BOOLEAN FUNCTIONS

ON POSITIVE, LINEAR AND QUADRATIC BOOLEAN FUNCTIONS Kragujevac Journal of Mathematics Volume 36 Number 2 (2012), Pages 177 187. ON POSITIVE, LINEAR AND QUADRATIC BOOLEAN FUNCTIONS SERGIU RUDEANU Abstract. In [1], [2] it was proved that a function f : {0,

More information

CW complexes. Soren Hansen. This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes.

CW complexes. Soren Hansen. This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes. CW complexes Soren Hansen This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes. 1. Notation and conventions In the following a space is a topological space and a map f : X Y between topological

More information

On the Structure of Rough Approximations

On the Structure of Rough Approximations On the Structure of Rough Approximations (Extended Abstract) Jouni Järvinen Turku Centre for Computer Science (TUCS) Lemminkäisenkatu 14 A, FIN-20520 Turku, Finland jjarvine@cs.utu.fi Abstract. We study

More information

Properties of Boolean Algebras

Properties of Boolean Algebras Phillip James Swansea University December 15, 2008 Plan For Today Boolean Algebras and Order..... Brief Re-cap Order A Boolean algebra is a set A together with the distinguished elements 0 and 1, the binary

More information

COMPACT ORTHOALGEBRAS

COMPACT ORTHOALGEBRAS COMPACT ORTHOALGEBRAS ALEXANDER WILCE Abstract. We initiate a study of topological orthoalgebras (TOAs), concentrating on the compact case. Examples of TOAs include topological orthomodular lattices, and

More information

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals MATH 02 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS Properties of Real Numbers Some Fundamentals The whole course will be based entirely on the study of sequence of numbers and functions defined on the real

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 30 Aug 2018

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 30 Aug 2018 arxiv:1808.10324v1 [math.lo] 30 Aug 2018 Real coextensions as a tool for constructing triangular norms Thomas Vetterlein Department of Knowledge-Based Mathematical Systems Johannes Kepler University Linz

More information

2MA105 Algebraic Structures I

2MA105 Algebraic Structures I 2MA105 Algebraic Structures I Per-Anders Svensson http://homepage.lnu.se/staff/psvmsi/2ma105.html Lecture 12 Partially Ordered Sets Lattices Bounded Lattices Distributive Lattices Complemented Lattices

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

Exploring the Exotic Setting for Algebraic Geometry

Exploring the Exotic Setting for Algebraic Geometry Exploring the Exotic Setting for Algebraic Geometry Victor I. Piercey University of Arizona Integration Workshop Project August 6-10, 2010 1 Introduction In this project, we will describe the basic topology

More information

ANNIHILATOR IDEALS IN ALMOST SEMILATTICE

ANNIHILATOR IDEALS IN ALMOST SEMILATTICE BULLETIN OF THE INTERNATIONAL MATHEMATICAL VIRTUAL INSTITUTE ISSN (p) 2303-4874, ISSN (o) 2303-4955 www.imvibl.org /JOURNALS / BULLETIN Vol. 7(2017), 339-352 DOI: 10.7251/BIMVI1702339R Former BULLETIN

More information

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07)

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07) P. J. Šafárik University, Faculty of Science, Košice Project 2005/NP1-051 11230100466 Basic information Extent: 2 hrs lecture/1 hrs seminar per week. Assessment: Written tests during the semester, written

More information

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXV, 2(1996), pp. 247 279 247 GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS J. HEDLÍKOVÁ and S. PULMANNOVÁ Abstract. A difference on a poset (P, ) is a partial binary

More information

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections.

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections. 125 Chapter 5. Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections. 5.1. Semilattices and lattices. Many of the partially ordered sets P we have seen have a further valuable property: that for any two

More information

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Boolean Algebras Let X be an arbitrary set and let P(X) be the class of all subsets of X (the power set of X). Three natural set-theoretic operations on P(X) are the binary operations of union

More information

Algebraic General Topology. Volume 1. Victor Porton. address: URL:

Algebraic General Topology. Volume 1. Victor Porton.  address: URL: Algebraic General Topology. Volume 1 Victor Porton Email address: porton@narod.ru URL: http://www.mathematics21.org 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. 54J05, 54A05, 54D99, 54E05, 54E15, 54E17, 54E99

More information

Knowledge spaces from a topological point of view

Knowledge spaces from a topological point of view Knowledge spaces from a topological point of view V.I.Danilov Central Economics and Mathematics Institute of RAS Abstract In this paper we consider the operations of restriction, extension and gluing of

More information

11 Annihilators. Suppose that R, S, and T are rings, that R P S, S Q T, and R U T are bimodules, and finally, that

11 Annihilators. Suppose that R, S, and T are rings, that R P S, S Q T, and R U T are bimodules, and finally, that 11 Annihilators. In this Section we take a brief look at the important notion of annihilators. Although we shall use these in only very limited contexts, we will give a fairly general initial treatment,

More information

Filters on posets and generalizations

Filters on posets and generalizations Filters on posets and generalizations Victor Porton 78640, Shay Agnon 32-29, Ashkelon, Israel Abstract They are studied in details properties of filters on lattices, filters on posets, and certain generalizations

More information

cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska

cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska LECTURE 3 CHAPTER 1 SETS, RELATIONS, and LANGUAGES 6. Closures and Algorithms 7. Alphabets and Languages 8. Finite Representation

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017 Luca Carai and Silvio Ghilardi arxiv:1702.08352v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017 Università degli Studi di Milano, Milano, Italy luca.carai@studenti.unimi.it silvio.ghilardi@unimi.it July 26, 2017 Abstract The

More information

Foundations of mathematics. 5. Galois connections

Foundations of mathematics. 5. Galois connections Foundations of mathematics 5. Galois connections Sylvain Poirier http://settheory.net/ The notion of Galois connection was introduced in 2.11 (see http://settheory.net/set2.pdf) with its first properties.

More information

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS BRIAN OSSERMAN We discuss the inverse limit construction, and consider the special case of inverse limits of finite groups, which should best be considered as topological

More information

Topological properties

Topological properties CHAPTER 4 Topological properties 1. Connectedness Definitions and examples Basic properties Connected components Connected versus path connected, again 2. Compactness Definition and first examples Topological

More information

Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos. Martino Garonzi. Universidade de Brasília. Primeiro semestre 2018

Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos. Martino Garonzi. Universidade de Brasília. Primeiro semestre 2018 Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos Martino Garonzi Universidade de Brasília Primeiro semestre 2018 1 Le risposte uccidono le domande. 2 Contents 1 Topology 4 2 Profinite spaces 6 3 Topological groups 10 4

More information

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths.

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths. CATEGORY THEORY PROFESSOR PETER JOHNSTONE Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths. Definition 1.1. A category C consists

More information

A Natural Equivalence for the Category of Coherent Frames

A Natural Equivalence for the Category of Coherent Frames A Natural Equivalence for the Category of Coherent Frames Wolf Iberkleid and Warren Wm. McGovern Abstract. The functor on the category of bounded lattices induced by reversing their order, gives rise to

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SERGIO A. CELANI AND MARÍA ESTEBAN Abstract. Distributive Hilbert Algebras with infimum, or DH -algebras, are algebras with implication

More information

RINGS IN POST ALGEBRAS. 1. Introduction

RINGS IN POST ALGEBRAS. 1. Introduction Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXXVI, 2(2007), pp. 263 272 263 RINGS IN POST ALGEBRAS S. RUDEANU Abstract. Serfati [7] defined a ring structure on every Post algebra. In this paper we determine all the

More information

Comparing cartesian closed categories of (core) compactly generated spaces

Comparing cartesian closed categories of (core) compactly generated spaces 1 Comparing cartesian closed categories of (core) compactly generated spaces By MARTÍN ESCARDÓ School of Computer Science University of Birmingham, UK JIMMIE LAWSON Department of Mathematics Louisiana

More information

EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS AND OPERATORS ON ORDERED ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES. UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DELL'INSUBRIA Via Ravasi 2, Varese, Italy

EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS AND OPERATORS ON ORDERED ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES. UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DELL'INSUBRIA Via Ravasi 2, Varese, Italy UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DELL'INSUBRIA Via Ravasi 2, 21100 Varese, Italy Dipartimento di Scienze Teoriche e Applicate Di.S.T.A. Dipartimento di Scienza e Alta Tecnologia Di.S.A.T. PH.D. DEGREE PROGRAM IN

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) Contents. 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) Contents. 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) JAN ŠŤOVÍČEK Contents 1. Affine varieties 1 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30 1. Affine varieties The basic objects

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES DUSTIN HEDMARK Abstract. A study of the conditions under which a topological space is metrizable, concluding with a proof of the Nagata Smirnov

More information

Lattices and Orders in Isabelle/HOL

Lattices and Orders in Isabelle/HOL Lattices and Orders in Isabelle/HOL Markus Wenzel TU München October 8, 2017 Abstract We consider abstract structures of orders and lattices. Many fundamental concepts of lattice theory are developed,

More information

A Logician s Toolbox

A Logician s Toolbox A Logician s Toolbox 461: An Introduction to Mathematical Logic Spring 2009 We recast/introduce notions which arise everywhere in mathematics. All proofs are left as exercises. 0 Notations from set theory

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

SIMPLICIAL COMPLEXES WITH LATTICE STRUCTURES GEORGE M. BERGMAN

SIMPLICIAL COMPLEXES WITH LATTICE STRUCTURES GEORGE M. BERGMAN This is the final preprint version of a paper which appeared at Algebraic & Geometric Topology 17 (2017) 439-486. The published version is accessible to subscribers at http://dx.doi.org/10.2140/agt.2017.17.439

More information

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Hongtaek Jung December 27, 2017 Abstract This is a part of a supplementary note for a Logic and Set Theory course. The main goal is to

More information

Appendix A. Definitions for Ordered Sets. The appendices contain all the formal definitions, propositions and proofs for

Appendix A. Definitions for Ordered Sets. The appendices contain all the formal definitions, propositions and proofs for 161 Appendix A Definitions for Ordered Sets The appendices contain all the formal definitions, propositions and proofs for developing a model of the display process based on lattices. Here we list some

More information

Adjunctions! Everywhere!

Adjunctions! Everywhere! Adjunctions! Everywhere! Carnegie Mellon University Thursday 19 th September 2013 Clive Newstead Abstract What do free groups, existential quantifiers and Stone-Čech compactifications all have in common?

More information

Completeness of Star-Continuity

Completeness of Star-Continuity Introduction to Kleene Algebra Lecture 5 CS786 Spring 2004 February 9, 2004 Completeness of Star-Continuity We argued in the previous lecture that the equational theory of each of the following classes

More information

Silvio Valentini Dip. di Matematica - Università di Padova

Silvio Valentini Dip. di Matematica - Università di Padova REPRESENTATION THEOREMS FOR QUANTALES Silvio Valentini Dip. di Matematica - Università di Padova Abstract. In this paper we prove that any quantale Q is (isomorphic to) a quantale of suitable relations

More information

Lecture Notes: Selected Topics in Discrete Structures. Ulf Nilsson

Lecture Notes: Selected Topics in Discrete Structures. Ulf Nilsson Lecture Notes: Selected Topics in Discrete Structures Ulf Nilsson Dept of Computer and Information Science Linköping University 581 83 Linköping, Sweden ulfni@ida.liu.se 2004-03-09 Contents Chapter 1.

More information

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012 Logic via Algebra Sam Chong Tay A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012 Abstract The purpose of this paper is to gain insight to mathematical logic through an algebraic perspective.

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

Algebraic duality for partially ordered sets

Algebraic duality for partially ordered sets arxiv:math/0002025v1 [math.ct] 3 Feb 2000 Algebraic duality for partially ordered sets Roman R. Zapatrin Department of Mathematics, SPb UEF, Griboyedova 30/32, 191023, St-Petersburg, Russia and Division

More information

P.S. Gevorgyan and S.D. Iliadis. 1. Introduction

P.S. Gevorgyan and S.D. Iliadis. 1. Introduction MATEMATIČKI VESNIK MATEMATIQKI VESNIK 70, 2 (208), 0 9 June 208 research paper originalni nauqni rad GROUPS OF GENERALIZED ISOTOPIES AND GENERALIZED G-SPACES P.S. Gevorgyan and S.D. Iliadis Abstract. The

More information

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz Algebraic Structures and Their Applications Vol. 2 No. 2 ( 2015 ), pp 57-66. z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) R. MOHAMADIAN Communicated by B. Davvaz Abstract. In this article we introduce the concept

More information

An algebraic approach to Gelfand Duality

An algebraic approach to Gelfand Duality An algebraic approach to Gelfand Duality Guram Bezhanishvili New Mexico State University Joint work with Patrick J Morandi and Bruce Olberding Stone = zero-dimensional compact Hausdorff spaces and continuous

More information

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University February 7, 2007 2 Contents 1 Metric Spaces 1 1.1 Basic definitions...........................

More information

10. Smooth Varieties. 82 Andreas Gathmann

10. Smooth Varieties. 82 Andreas Gathmann 82 Andreas Gathmann 10. Smooth Varieties Let a be a point on a variety X. In the last chapter we have introduced the tangent cone C a X as a way to study X locally around a (see Construction 9.20). It

More information

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han Set, functions and Euclidean space Seungjin Han September, 2018 1 Some Basics LOGIC A is necessary for B : If B holds, then A holds. B A A B is the contraposition of B A. A is sufficient for B: If A holds,

More information

III A Functional Approach to General Topology

III A Functional Approach to General Topology III A Functional Approach to General Topology Maria Manuel Clementino, Eraldo Giuli and Walter Tholen In this chapter we wish to present a categorical approach to fundamental concepts of General Topology,

More information

On poset Boolean algebras

On poset Boolean algebras 1 On poset Boolean algebras Uri Abraham Department of Mathematics, Ben Gurion University, Beer-Sheva, Israel Robert Bonnet Laboratoire de Mathématiques, Université de Savoie, Le Bourget-du-Lac, France

More information

On the algebra of relevance logics

On the algebra of relevance logics On the algebra of relevance logics by Johann Joubert Wannenburg Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree Master of Science in the Faculty of Natural & Agricultural Sciences University

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.lo] 4 Sep 2018

arxiv: v1 [cs.lo] 4 Sep 2018 A characterization of the consistent Hoare powerdomains over dcpos Zhongxi Zhang a,, Qingguo Li b, Nan Zhang a a School of Computer and Control Engineering, Yantai University, Yantai, Shandong, 264005,

More information

An Introduction to the Theory of Lattice

An Introduction to the Theory of Lattice An Introduction to the Theory of Lattice Jinfang Wang Λy Graduate School of Science and Technology, Chiba University 1-33 Yayoi-cho, Inage-ku, Chiba 263-8522, Japan May 11, 2006 Λ Fax: 81-43-290-3663.

More information

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018 Lecture 2: Syntax January 24, 2018 We now review the basic definitions of first-order logic in more detail. Recall that a language consists of a collection of symbols {P i }, each of which has some specified

More information

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS. Disclaimer: There are millions of errors in these notes!

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS. Disclaimer: There are millions of errors in these notes! ALGEBRAIC GROUPS Disclaimer: There are millions of errors in these notes! 1. Some algebraic geometry The subject of algebraic groups depends on the interaction between algebraic geometry and group theory.

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

Sets, Structures, Numbers

Sets, Structures, Numbers Chapter 1 Sets, Structures, Numbers Abstract In this chapter we shall introduce most of the background needed to develop the foundations of mathematical analysis. We start with sets and algebraic structures.

More information

UNIVERSALITY OF THE LATTICE OF TRANSFORMATION MONOIDS

UNIVERSALITY OF THE LATTICE OF TRANSFORMATION MONOIDS UNIVERSALITY OF THE LATTICE OF TRANSFORMATION MONOIDS MICHAEL PINSKER AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. The set of all transformation monoids on a fixed set of infinite cardinality λ, equipped with the order

More information

Lecture 4. Algebra, continued Section 2: Lattices and Boolean algebras

Lecture 4. Algebra, continued Section 2: Lattices and Boolean algebras V. Borschev and B. Partee, September 21-26, 2006 p. 1 Lecture 4. Algebra, continued Section 2: Lattices and Boolean algebras CONTENTS 1. Lattices.... 1 1.0. Why lattices?... 1 1.1. Posets... 1 1.1.1. Upper

More information

NONSINGULAR CURVES BRIAN OSSERMAN

NONSINGULAR CURVES BRIAN OSSERMAN NONSINGULAR CURVES BRIAN OSSERMAN The primary goal of this note is to prove that every abstract nonsingular curve can be realized as an open subset of a (unique) nonsingular projective curve. Note that

More information

ON FUZZY IDEALS OF PSEUDO MV -ALGEBRAS

ON FUZZY IDEALS OF PSEUDO MV -ALGEBRAS Discussiones Mathematicae General Algebra and Applications 28 (2008 ) 63 75 ON FUZZY IDEALS OF PSEUDO MV -ALGEBRAS Grzegorz Dymek Institute of Mathematics and Physics University of Podlasie 3 Maja 54,

More information

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions 24 Andreas Gathmann 3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions After having defined affine varieties, our next goal must be to say what kind of maps between them we want to consider as morphisms, i. e. as nice

More information

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions vanrooijschikhof.tex April 25, 2018 van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions Notes from [vrs]. Introduction A monotone function is Riemann integrable. A continuous function is Riemann integrable.

More information

IDEMPOTENT n-permutable VARIETIES

IDEMPOTENT n-permutable VARIETIES IDEMPOTENT n-permutable VARIETIES M. VALERIOTE AND R. WILLARD Abstract. One of the important classes of varieties identified in tame congruence theory is the class of varieties which are n-permutable for

More information

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 Index Page 1 Topology 2 1.1 Definition of a topology 2 1.2 Basis (Base) of a topology 2 1.3 The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 1.4 Basic topology concepts: limit points, closed sets,

More information

Introduction to generalized topological spaces

Introduction to generalized topological spaces @ Applied General Topology c Universidad Politécnica de Valencia Volume 12, no. 1, 2011 pp. 49-66 Introduction to generalized topological spaces Irina Zvina Abstract We introduce the notion of generalized

More information

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Department of Mathematics Bachelor Thesis (7.5 ECTS) Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Author: Dionijs van Tuijl Supervisor: Dr. Jaap van Oosten June 15, 2016 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminaries

More information

BOOLEAN SUBALGEBRAS OF ORTHOALGEBRAS

BOOLEAN SUBALGEBRAS OF ORTHOALGEBRAS OOLEAN SUALGERAS OF ORTHOALGERAS JOHN HARDING, CHRIS HEUNEN, AND MIRKO NAVARA Abstract. Earlier work had shown that every nontrivial orthomodular lattice is characterized by its poset of oolean subalgebras

More information

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 Instructions: Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 If you signed up for Computability Theory, do two E and two C problems. If you signed up for Model Theory, do two E and two M problems. If you signed up

More information

4 Countability axioms

4 Countability axioms 4 COUNTABILITY AXIOMS 4 Countability axioms Definition 4.1. Let X be a topological space X is said to be first countable if for any x X, there is a countable basis for the neighborhoods of x. X is said

More information

1. Supremum and Infimum Remark: In this sections, all the subsets of R are assumed to be nonempty.

1. Supremum and Infimum Remark: In this sections, all the subsets of R are assumed to be nonempty. 1. Supremum and Infimum Remark: In this sections, all the subsets of R are assumed to be nonempty. Let E be a subset of R. We say that E is bounded above if there exists a real number U such that x U for

More information

ClC (X ) : X ω X } C. (11)

ClC (X ) : X ω X } C. (11) With each closed-set system we associate a closure operation. Definition 1.20. Let A, C be a closed-set system. Define Cl C : : P(A) P(A) as follows. For every X A, Cl C (X) = { C C : X C }. Cl C (X) is

More information