The Relativity of Simultaneity

Similar documents
Lecture 13 Notes: 07 / 20. Invariance of the speed of light

Accelerated Observers

Unit 1 Lesson 6: Seeing Structure in Expressions

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime

EPGY Special and General Relativity. Lecture 4B

Lecture: Lorentz Invariant Dynamics

04. Kinematical Effects 1. Time Dilation

Special Theory Of Relativity Prof. Shiva Prasad Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay

Chapter 11. Special Relativity

Introduction to Special Relativity

Lecture 5. The Lorentz Transformation

Physics 225 Relativity and Math Applications. Fall Unit 7 The 4-vectors of Dynamics

Observations versus Measurements

MINKOWSKIAN SPACE, GRAPHS, EVENTS, WORLD LINES and MEASURING TIME

For those of you who are taking Calculus AB concurrently with AP Physics, I have developed a

The Lorentz Transformation

Consequences of special relativity.

Mathematics Background

Kinematics of special relativity

Consequences of special relativity.

Galilean Spacetime (Neo-Newtonian Spacetime) P t = 2

Communicating with accelerated observers in Minkowski spacetime

CHAPTER 6 VECTOR CALCULUS. We ve spent a lot of time so far just looking at all the different ways you can graph

Lecture 13 Notes, Electromagnetic Theory II Dr. Christopher S. Baird, faculty.uml.edu/cbaird University of Massachusetts Lowell

THE GEOMETRY OF SPECIAL RELATIVITY

Introduction. Classical vs Modern Physics. Classical Physics: High speeds Small (or very large) distances

Special Relativity - Math Circle

Tech Notes 4 and 5. Let s prove that invariance of the spacetime interval the hard way. Suppose we begin with the equation

Minkowski spacetime. Pham A. Quang. Abstract: In this talk we review the Minkowski spacetime which is the spacetime of Special Relativity.

Math 90 Lecture Notes Chapter 1

EQ: How do I identify exponential growth? Bellwork:

Curved Spacetime... A brief introduction

Special Theory of Relativity Prof. Shiva Prasad Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay. Lecture - 15 Momentum Energy Four Vector

Welcome back to PHY 3305

Motion and Forces. Describing Motion

Scott Hughes 12 May Massachusetts Institute of Technology Department of Physics Spring 2005

MIT Course 8.033, Fall 2006, Relativistic Kinematics Max Tegmark Last revised October

has a lot of good notes on GR and links to other pages. General Relativity Philosophy of general relativity.

Special relativity, 3. How big is gamma? The Lorentz transformations depend on the factor γ =

Unit 01 Motion with constant velocity. What we asked about

Einstein Toolkit Workshop. Joshua Faber Apr

Week 1. 1 The relativistic point particle. 1.1 Classical dynamics. Reading material from the books. Zwiebach, Chapter 5 and chapter 11

More with Special Relativity

DISTANCE, VELOCITY AND ACCELERATION. dt.

I D a. :ntta1 I C a m I. Homework Problems 83. Figure R4.7. M is f v I = V GM/R, where G is the universal gravitational

Relativistic Mechanics

PHY152H1S Practical 10: Special Relativity

PHYSICS Kinematics in One Dimension

What is allowed? relativity: physics is the same for all observers so light travels at the same speed for everyone. so what? THE UNIVERSITY OF ALABAMA

Covariant Formulation of Electrodynamics

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006

Motion in 1 Dimension. By Prof. Massimiliano Galeazzi, University of Miami

Vectors and Coordinate Systems

Precalculus idea: A picture is worth 1,000 words

AST1100 Lecture Notes

Mechanics Physics 151

Physics 8 Monday, September 12, 2011

Spacetime Diagrams Lab Exercise

Number-Flux Vector and Stress-Energy Tensor

carroll/notes/ has a lot of good notes on GR and links to other pages. General Relativity Philosophy of general

Special Relativity: What Time is it?

DIFFERENTIATION AND INTEGRATION PART 1. Mr C s IB Standard Notes

Notes on the Geometry of Spacetime, and some associated Vector, Tensor and matrix Notation and Conventions

Lecture 4 - Lorentz contraction and the Lorentz transformations

1.1 The Language of Mathematics Expressions versus Sentences

Physics 200a Relativity notes Shankar (2006)

Worksheet 1: One-Dimensional Kinematics

Before we work on deriving the Lorentz transformations, let's first look at the classical Galilean transformation.

The Seven Messengers and the Buzzati sequence

Relativistic Kinematics

THE GEOMETRY OF SPECIAL RELATIVITY

Spacetime diagrams and Bondi s k-calculus

The result is; distances are contracted in the direction of motion.

Physics 325: General Relativity Spring Final Review Problem Set

16. Einstein and General Relativistic Spacetimes

2.1 The Ether and the Michelson-Morley Experiment

Experiment 4 Free Fall

2.2 Average vs. Instantaneous Description

The Nature of Space-Time

Math Boot Camp: Integration

Error Analysis in Experimental Physical Science Mini-Version

LECSS Physics 11 Introduction to Physics and Math Methods 1 Revised 8 September 2013 Don Bloomfield

Core 1 Basic Algebra. Section 1: Expressions and equations

The Lorentz Transformation from Light-Speed Invariance Alone

Chapter S3 Spacetime and Gravity Pearson Education, Inc.

3.1 Transformation of Velocities

Correlation. We don't consider one variable independent and the other dependent. Does x go up as y goes up? Does x go down as y goes up?

Special Relativity: Derivations

Spacetime Diagrams and Einstein s Theory For Dummies

Paradoxes in Special Relativity Paradoxes in Special Relativity. Dr. Naylor

Lecture 6. Velocity Through Spacetime

MAT1193 1f. Linear functions (most closely related to section 1.4) But for now, we introduce the most important equation in this class:

Physics 8.20 Special Relativity IAP 2008

Announcement. Einstein s Postulates of Relativity: PHYS-3301 Lecture 3. Chapter 2. Sep. 5, Special Relativity

Module M4.1 Introducing differentiation

Relativistic Boats: an explanation of special relativity. Brianna Thorpe, Dr. Michael Dugger

Special relativity. Announcements:

Ordinary Differential Equations Prof. A. K. Nandakumaran Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Science Bangalore

We begin our discussion of special relativity with a power point presentation, available on the website.

Section 1.1: Patterns in Division

Transcription:

Let me begin with a little homily. In non-technical presentations of the theories of relativity (even the best of them) the austere pictures of world-lines of clocks are sometimes humanized or anthropomorphized by adding a human observer to the world line to go along with the clock. As an eminent philosopher once remarked, this serves to add artistic verisimilitude to an otherwise bald and unconvincing narrative. The addition of observers should be harmless, but it may not be. Our friends Alice and Bob busily consult their clocks, note when light pulses leave or arrive, and then calculate various quantities, as shall we. But sometimes the verb see (or its cognates or closely related expressions) is used to describe their clock readings and the results of their calculations. Thus an author might say that Alice sees the light pulse arrives at time t = 12 and that Alice sees Bob s clock running slow. But the latter sort of statement needs to be treated cautiously. Alice may calculate that Bob s clock is, somehow, running more slowly than hers, but what

she sees is when light pulses from Bob s clock arrives at her clock. As an example of how matters can be mixed together, consider the sentence we find on page 107 of GRAB: By apparent we now mean apparent to that observer who happens to see the events as occurring simultaneously. To see events as occurring simultaneously is, we are told in the text, to make an inference from the equality of two temporal intervals, t1 and t2. We shall look at simultaneity in a bit more detail below. With this preliminary caution in mind, let us populate our clock world line with observers and note what they see or conclude in various situations. We might suppose, for instance, that our observers wish to think about space and time in terms of the concepts we used in Aristotelian spacetime. To what extent are they able to do so, using the interval? We imagine the familiar situation. We have a worldline (with a clock) and on this worldline we fix a point p. We send out a pulse of light at some point r. The pulse reflects from (or at) q and returns to the clock worldline at point s. Since the clock assigns times to all points on its worldline, it gives us the times that r, p, and s occurred, T(r), 2

T(p), and T(s), amongst many others. We call the elapsed time between p and s (that is, T(s) - T(p)) t1 and the elapsed time between r and p (T(p) - T(r)) t2. All this is familiar. 1 What could we say about when q occurs, in terms of the readings of our clock? We know the total time that the light pulse takes to travel to q and back--t1 + t2. Since the speed of light in space is fixed, the pulse must take as much time to reach q as it does traveling back from q. So the pulse must reach q exactly 1/2 (t1 + t2 ) seconds after leaving r. We know that p occurs exactly t2 seconds after r, according to our clock. So a reasonable way to think of the time difference between p and q is that it is 1/2 (t1 + t2) - t2. If we indicate the time difference in our usual way, as Δt, we can write: Δt = ½(t1 - t2). In this formula Δt measures the difference between the (estimated) time at which q occurs after r and the (measured) time at which p occurs after r. So if Δt > 0, then q would be held to occur 1 And let s use the same units as Geroch, seconds and light-seconds. 3

after p; if Δt < 0, q would be held to occur before p. This formula tells us, then, how much later than p the event q occurred. If Δt = 0--that is, if t1 = t2, then our observer would say that there is no difference in the time that p and q occurred--that is, that they occurred at the same time. This observer would not see that p and q were simultaneous but would, rather, conclude that they were, based on the clock s measurement of t1 and t2. Let s stay with this case for a moment. It should be clear that many points can be found that are simultaneous with p, since all that s required is that t1 - t2. The more time before p the pulse is sent out--that is, the larger t2 is--the further from p the other simultaneous point is. And the pulse can be sent out in any direction from the clock s worldline. So we can construct a little hyperplane of nearby events all simultaneous with p, a local counterpart in relativistic spacetime of the global hyperplanes of simultaneity in Aristotelian and Galilean spacetime. See figure 55 in GRAB. 4

Let s continue thinking about the situation we re describing, with p on a clock worldline and q simultaneous with p according to a clock that goes through p. Let us ask how far away from p the point q is? We have already convinced ourselves that it must take time 1/2 (t1 + t2) for our light pulse to reach q from the worldline containing p. Since light travels at speed c in space, the distance of q from p must be Δx = c/2 (t1 + t2). Then we use the formulas for Δx and Δt in a little algebraic manipulation. From the formula immediately above, we can derive that We know already that Δx/c = 1/2 (t1 + t2). Δt = 1/2 (t1 - t2). If we add these two formulas, we get Δx/c + Δt = t1. 5

And if we subtract the second from the first, we get Δx/c - Δt = t2. The last two formulas tell us that: t 1 t 2 = Δx c 2 Δt 2. Since we assume that the quantity on the left hand side, the interval, is an invariant quantity, then the expression on the right hand side must also be invariant. It is rather neat, and expressed in terms of distances and times (or coordinates, if you like to think of it that way). One sees this way of representing the interval in slightly different guises. One might take advantage of the fact that (in appropriate units) the speed of light, c, is equal to 1 and drop if from the formula. 2 In that case one might write (Δx) 2 - (Δt) 2 = (Δx ) 2 - (Δt ) 2. 2 If one follows this convenient course, one might find oneself from time to time puzzling over an equation in which the units on the two sides do not match. If the units matter, then one has to find and insert the missing c s. 6

The same relation can appear in its infinitesimal form (dx) 2 - (dt) 2 = (dx ) 2 - (dt ) 2. Of course the interval is really a four-dimensional invariant, so it may be written out explicitly as (ds) 2 = (dx) 2 + (dy) 2 + (dz) 2 - (dt) 2. Or, if one is focussing on temporal rather than spatial relations, one can multiply this expression by -1. The result is often written as (dτ) 2 = (dt) 2 - (dx) 2 - (dy) 2 - (dz) 2. The new symbol, τ, is the lower-case Greek letter tau. Let us return now to our consideration of local hyperplanes of simultaneity. We have seen how Alice might set up hers, for some event p on her world line. But let us suppose that Bob too encounters that event on his world line. If his world line differs from that of Alice, we shall see that he must disagree as to what events are simultaneous with p. This result is what is shown in the next figure, where I let observers have 7

straight or inertial world-lines to reduce the amount of graphic artistry involved. Results are often most firmly proved by analytic means, and spacetime pictures can be misleading. But this figure is not misleading and makes its point vividly. t 1 s s t 1 p q t 2 t 2 r r B A 8

What we see is, first of all, Alice (and her clock) sending out a light pulse at r and receiving it back from q at s. Since t1, the interval of time from p to s, is equal to t2, the interval of time from r to p, Alice knows that Δt = 0 and concludes that q occurs at the same time as p. An examination of the figure makes it clear that Bob must have a different view of the matter. He must send his light pulse out to q from point r, so that it can travel along with Alice s light pulse. He notes its return at s. As Bob measures time intervals his t2 is longer than Alice s, and his t1 is shorter. Since from Bob s perspective t1 t2, he cannot conclude that q occurs at the same time as p. Given that t2 > t1, Bob will find that Δt < 0 and so conclude that q occurs earlier than p. (Were Bob moving in the -x direction instead of the x-direction, he would find that Δt > 0 and hold that q occurs later than p.) 9