Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd

Similar documents
Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests

Volume 35, Issue 4. Group contests and technologies. Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University

DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Academic Editor: Ulrich Berger Received: 12 August 2016 ; Accepted: 5 September 2016 ; Published: 9 September 2016

Linking Individual and Collective Contests through Noise Level and Sharing Rules

Incentives versus Competitive Balance

A Note on Multi-winner Contest Mechanisms

A Simple Model of Competition Between Teams

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Calle Madrid, 126

Information Sharing in Private Value Lottery Contest

Common-Value All-Pay Auctions with Asymmetric Information

A Simple Model of Competition Between Teams

Contests with Bilateral Delegation: Unobservable Contracts

The incidence of overdissipation in rent-seeking contests

Contest Functions: Theoretical Foundations and Issues in Estimation

Information Advantage in Tullock Contests

Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information

Lottery versus All-Pay Auction Contests

Rent-seeking with Non-Identical Sharing Rules: An Equilibrium Rescued

Auctions with Rent Seeking

The Revenue Equivalence Theorem 1

Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information

The Strategic Equivalence of Rent-Seeking, Innovation, and Patent-Race Games

The Lottery Contest is a Best-Response Potential Game

COMMON-VALUE ALL-PAY AUCTIONS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION AND BID CAPS. Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No.

On the Existence of a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information y

A nested contest: Tullock meets the All-Pay Auction*

Hybrid All-Pay and Winner-Pay Contests

Game theory lecture 4. September 24, 2012

Asymmetric Rent-seeking Contests with Multiple Agents of Two Types

Players with Fixed Resources in Elimination Tournaments Alexander Matros Department of Economics University of Pittsburgh.

Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information y

Mixed equilibria in Tullock contests

Advanced Microeconomics II

Contest Functions: Theoretical Foundations and Issues in Estimation

Theory of Auctions. Carlos Hurtado. Jun 23th, Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Interdependent Value Auctions with an Insider Bidder 1

Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

THEORIES ON AUCTIONS WITH PARTICIPATION COSTS. A Dissertation XIAOYONG CAO

Lecture 6 Games with Incomplete Information. November 14, 2008

Welfare Maximizing Contest Success Functions when the Planner Cannot Commit

Contests between groups of unknown size

Second Price Auctions with Differentiated Participation Costs

Sealed-bid first-price auctions with an unknown number of bidders

All-Pay Contests. Ron Siegel Graduate School of Business Stanford University. May Abstract

Optimal Favoritism in All-Pay Auctions and Lottery Contests

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. Caps on Political Lobbying: Reply. Yeon-Koo Che Ian Gale

Relative Di erence Contest Success Function

Ability Grouping in All-Pay Contests

Contests between groups of unknown size

Contests with Endogenous and Stochastic Entry

Unique Equilibrium in Contests with Incomplete Information

SIGNALING IN CONTESTS. Tomer Ifergane and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No November 2017

Haruo Imai and Hannu Salonen Bargaining and Rent Seeking. Aboa Centre for Economics

Best-shot Versus Weakest-link in Political Lobbying: An Application of Group All-pay Auction *

Second-Price Auctions with Different Participation Costs

SIRE DISCUSSION PAPER

On Overdissipation of Rents in Contests with Endogenous Intrinsic Motivation. Volker Schlepütz

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

FOUNDATIONS FOR CONTEST SUCCESS FUNCTIONS

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

Characterization of equilibrium in pay-as-bid auctions for multiple units

A simple microfoundation for the utilization of fragmentation indexes to measure the performance of a team

Discussion Papers Department of Economics University of Copenhagen

Online Appendix for "Auctions in Markets: Common Outside Options and the Continuation Value Effect" Not intended for publication

Charity Auctions for the Happy Few

Winner-Take-All Crowdsourcing Contests with Stochastic Production

A Simple Example to Illustrate the Linkage Principle

Non-Existence of Equilibrium in Vickrey, Second-Price, and English Auctions

Working Paper EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN COMMON-VALUE SECOND-PRICE AUCTIONS. Heng Liu

Game Theory. Monika Köppl-Turyna. Winter 2017/2018. Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business

Symmetric Separating Equilibria in English Auctions 1

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

Working Paper EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN COMMON-VALUE SECOND-PRICE AUCTIONS. Heng Liu

Crowdsourcing contests

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions

Structural Analysis of Tullock Contests with an Application to U.S. House of Representatives Elections

Thus far, we ve made four key assumptions that have greatly simplified our analysis:

An Analysis of the War of Attrition and the All-Pay Auction

Game Theory. Professor Peter Cramton Economics 300

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2)

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012

Second Price Auctions with Valuations and Participation Costs Both Privately Informed

Games and Economic Behavior

Asymmetric Contests: A Resolution of the Tullock Paradox* John G. Riley** Revised January 12, Forthcoming in

THE MAX-MIN GROUP CONTEST: WEAKEST-LINK (GROUP) ALL-PAY AUCTION

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann

Michael R. Baye 1 Dan Kovenock 2 Casper G. de Vries 3

Robert Wilson (1977), A Bidding Model of Perfect Competition, Review of Economic

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions

Interdependent Value Auctions with Insider Bidders

All-pay auctions with interdependent valuations: The highly competitive case 1

Sequential Majoritarian Blotto Games

KRANNERT GRADUATE SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT

Introduction to Game Theory

Sharing contests with general preferences

Transcription:

Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd

Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd March 25, 2008 Abstract We consider imperfectly discriminating, common-value, all-pay auctions (or contests) in which some players know the value of the prize, others do not We show that if the prize is always of positive value, then all players are active in equilibrium If the prize is of value zero with positive probability, then there is some threshold number of informed players such that if there are less, all uninformed players are active, and otherwise all uninformed players are inactive Journal of Economic Literature Classification Numbers: C72, D44, D72, D82, K41 Keywords: contests, all-pay auctions, asymmetric information 1 Introduction In a contest the players expend effort, resources, or money in order to increase their probability of winning a prize Contest models therefore have important applications across the social sciences Warfare, litigation, rent-seeking, Department of Economics, Stockholm School of Economics, Box 6501, S 113 83 Stockholm, Sweden, and CESifo Email: KarlWarneryd@hhsse I thank Patsy Haccou and participants at the 2005 Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin conference on Advances in the Theory of Contests and Tournaments for helpful remarks 1

campaigning in elections, and sports competitions are just a few examples of activities that have been modeled as contests (See, eg, Hirshleifer [9, 10], Skaperdas [17], Bernardo, Talley, and Welch [3], Tullock [22], Baron [1], and Szymanski [20]) Studies of abstract contests include Dixit [4], Gradstein and Konrad [6], Myerson and Wärneryd [15], and Wärneryd [23] In this paper we study the effects of introducing asymmetric information in a multi-player contest A contest may also be seen as an auction, specifically an all-pay auction, ie, one where each participant must pay their bid Hillman and Riley [7] distinguish between perfectly and imperfectly discriminating all-pay auctions In a perfectly discriminating auction one bidder wins with certainty when all bids are different A well-known example of a perfectly discriminating all-pay auction is the war of attrition While the properties of perfectly discriminating allpay auctions have been studied extensively (see, eg, Baye, Kovenock, and de Vries [2] or Krishna and Morgan [11]), much less is known about imperfectly discriminating models, where the bid profile induces a nontrivial probability distribution over the winner From the standpoint of a seller offering a good in an auction a perfectly discriminating mechanism is optimal, but for applications such as those listed above imperfectly discriminating contests are frequently more realistic models We study common-value, imperfectly discriminating contests, ie, contests where ex post all players would agree on the value of the prize, and a player who makes positive expenditure has a positive probability of winning We further assume that some players may know the value of the prize with certainty at the point when they make their expenditure decision, others know only the prior distribution We shall show, in particular, that if the prize is of positive value with probability one, then in equilibrium all players, informed as well as uninformed, spend positive amounts, and hence all have a positive probability of winning This contrasts dramatically with equilibrium in a first-price auction in an otherwise similar setup If there is more than one informed player in a common-value first-price auction, an uninformed player will not bid in equilibrium and will hence have a zero probability of winning (See, eg, Milgrom 2

and Weber [13]) In Section 2 we introduce a class of common-value contests with asymmetric information, and show that if the prize is positive with probability one, then all players are active in equilibrium If there is a positive probability of the prize being of value zero, then there is some finite threshold number of informed players such that if it is met, uninformed players expend zero in equilibrium Section 3 provides an example from the subclass of lottery contests 2 Multi-Player Contests We consider n 2 risk-neutral players participating in a contest for a prize of value y The value y is distributed according to the cumulative distribution function F We assume F has support on [0, ) only Let ỹ be the expectation of y, which we assume is finite and positive A number n I of the players are privately informed about the value of the prize; the rest, numbering n U := n n I, know only its prior distribution Player i spends effort or resources x i on increasing his probability p i (x 1,x 2,,x n ) of winning the prize At a most general level, we would only require that the p i be non-negative, that they sum up to 1, and that a player s probability of winning be increasing in his own effort or expenditure and decreasing in everyone else s Since we are ultimately interested in studying the effects of varying the numbers of players of different types, however, hence in effect comparing different games, we need a class of contests that meaningfully allows us to scale the size of the game up or down We shall therefore study contests from a class axiomatized by Skaperdas [18] If player i spends x i, then player i s probability of winning the prize is g (xi )/ j p i (x 1,x 2,,x n ) = g (x j ) if g (x j j ) > 0 1/n otherwise, where g is such that g (0) = 0, g (x ) > 0 for all x, and g (x ) < 0 for all x 3

Consider now the optimal expenditure choice x I i (y ) of informed player i when he knows the value of the prize to be y Define G I (y ) := g (x I j j (y )) and G U := g (x U j j ) Assuming G U > 0, the informed player i s expected utility is then u I (y ) := g (x I i (y )) i G I (y ) +G y x I (y ), U i which is concave in x I i (y ) Consider the first partial derivative of this utility with respect to own expenditure It is u I i (y ) x I i (y ) = g (x I i (y ))(G I i (y ) +GU ) (G I (y ) +G U ) 2 y 1 This implies that all informed players expend the same amount in equilibrium For suppose informed player i optimally expends the positive amount x I i (y ), ie, that u I i (y )/ x I i (y ) = 0, and suppose there is some other informed player j who expends x I j (y ) x I i (y ) Without loss of generality, let x I j (y ) < x I i (y ) We would then have that and u I i (y ) x I i (y ) = g I (x i (y ))(g (x I j (y )) +G I i,j (y ) +GU ) y 1 = 0 (G I (y ) +G U ) 2 u I j (y ) x I j (y ) = g (x I j (y ))(g (x I i (y )) +G I i,j (y ) +GU ) (G I (y ) +G U ) 2 y 1 0, an impossibility since g is strictly concave Similarly, if it is optimal for one informed player to be inactive, ie, if u I i (y )/ x I i (y ) 0 at x I i (y ) = 0, then all other informed players are optimally inactive as well ie, if Hence all informed players expend zero if and only if we have that g (0) G U y 1 0, y G U g (0) =: y 0 In particular, this implies x I (y ) > 0 for all y > 0 if we have G U = 0 4

Let x I (y ) be the common equilibrium expenditure of informed players when the realized value of the prize is y To summarize, we have that g (x I (y ))((n I 1)g (x I (y )) +G U ) (n I g (x I (y )) +G U ) 2 y 1 = 0 if y > y 0 (1) and x I (y ) = 0 if y y 0 Next consider uninformed player i, whose expected utility is u U i := 0 g (x U i ) G I (y ) +G U y df (y ) x U i, which is concave in x U i Note that since G I (y ) is continuous and increasing in y, the integral is well-defined We have that u U i x U i = 0 g (x U i )(G I (y ) +G U i ) (G I (y ) +G U ) 2 y df (y ) 1 For reasons analogous to those in the case of the informed players, this implies that all uninformed players behave the same way when behaving optimally Letting x U be the common equilibrium expenditure of the uninformed players, this means that we have that when x U > 0, and when x U = 0 0 g (x U )(G I (y ) + (n U 1)g (x U )) (G I (y ) + n U g (x U )) 2 y df (y ) 1 = 0 g (0) 1 y df (y ) 1 0 (2) G I (y ) y >y 0 There cannot be an equilibrium such that the informed players are inactive, ie, never expend anything For suppose x I (y ) = 0 for all y We would then have that y 0 = g (x U ) g (0) n U 1 ỹ < ỹ n U 5

by the concavity of g Hence there would be values of y occurring with positive probability such that informed players would in fact want to make positive expenditure Consider now an equilibrium such that the uninformed players expend zero We then have y 0 = 0, so the informed players make positive expenditure whenever y is positive From (1) we have that Substituting in (2), we have that y >0 G I (y ) = g (x I (y )) n I 1 n I y n I g (0) df (y ) 1 0 (3) g (x I (y )) n I 1 Since we have g (0)/g (x I (y )) > 1 by concavity of g, a necessary condition for this to hold is that F (0) > 0 We furthermore note that because of the concavity of the payoff functions, the arguments of Szidarovszky and Okuguchi [19] carry over straightforwardly, and an equilibrium exists and is unique Hence we have the following Proposition 1 There is a unique equilibrium If y only takes positive values, then in equilibrium all players are active Next note that if the uninformed players are inactive, from (1) we have that Differentiating, we see that g (x I (y )) g (x I (y )) = n I 1 y for all y > 0 (4) n 2 I x I (y ) (n I 2)g (x I (y ))g (x I (y )) = n I n I (n I 1)(g (x I (y ))g (x I (y )) (g (x I (y ))) 2 ) < 0 for n I > 2 Hence x I (y ) is strictly decreasing in n I for all y if we have n I > 2 Furthermore, x I (y ) must in fact converge to zero as n I approaches infinity, since the right-hand side of (4) approaches zero Hence for any y, both terms inside the 6

integral in (3) approach 1 as n I approaches infinity If we have F (0) > 0, there must therefore be some finite n I such that (3) holds for n I n I Furthermore, we have that n I (1 F (0)) n 1 1 < I y >0 g (0) g (x I (y )) which implies that n I 1/F (0) We have therefore proved the following n I n I 1dF (y ) 1 0, Proposition 2 Suppose we have F (0) > 0 Then there is some finite n I such that if n I < n I, then all players are active in equilibrium, but if n I n I, then only informed players are active in equilibrium Furthermore, we have n I 1/F (0) Hence if we have n < 1/F (0), all players are active in equilibrium The next section provides a simple example illustrating this result 3 An Example 31 Lottery contests In this section we consider an example with g (x ) = x This type of contest is sometimes known as a lottery contest It was popularized by Tullock [21, 22] for the study of legal battles and rent seeking For further discussion, see, eg, Hirshleifer [8] For an axiomatization, see Skaperdas [18] Fullerton and McAfee [5], Müller and Wärneryd [14], and Nitzan [16] is a small sample of the large body of literature on applications of this class of contests Wärneryd [23] exhaustively treats the two-player case with asymmetric information We now assume the prize is of value zero with probability 1 p, and of value ȳ > 0 with probability p, with p (0,1) While this example is in some ways trivial, it has the great advantage of allowing for explicit analytical solutions It also clearly shows the role of the number of informed players 7

n I This also allows us to conclude that if all players are informed, or all are 32 Case I: All players are active In an equilibrium in which all players are active the first-order conditions imply that it must hold that n I x I (ȳ ) + (n U 1)x U (n I x I (ȳ ) + n U x U ) 2 pȳ = 1 and (n I 1)x I (ȳ ) + n U x U ȳ = 1 (n I x I (ȳ ) + n U x U ) 2 Solving this simultaneous equation system, in such an equilibrium we therefore have that and x I (0) = 0, x I (ȳ ) = (n 1)(p + (1 p)n U) (n U + pn I ) 2 pȳ, x U = (n 1)(1 (1 p)n I ) (n U + pn I ) 2 pȳ Uninformed players are therefore active if and only if we have n I < 1/(1 p) = uninformed, ex ante expected aggregate equilibrium expenditure is equal to (n 1)p ȳ /n More generally, aggregate expenditure is n U x U + pn I x I (ȳ ) 33 Case II: Only informed players are active In an equilibrum where only informed players are active, which happens if and only if we have n I 1/(1 p), we must have that and x I (0) = 0 x I (ȳ ) = n I 1 ȳ n 2 I Expected aggregate equilibrium expenditure in such an equilibrium is therefore pȳ (n I 1)/n I 8

34 Expected aggregate equilibrium expenditure From an efficiency point of view we might be interested in how expected aggregate equilibrium expenditure X := n U x U + pn I x I varies as a function of the relative shares of informed and uninformed players Consider, therefore, X as a function of the number of informed players, keeping the total number of players, n, constant (Throughout, we shall ignore that n, n I, and n U are necessarily integers) Since the uninformed players will be inactive whenever we have n I 1/(1 p) = n I, and defining D = n n I (1 p), we have that X = ((n 1)(n I p 2 (n n I )(n I (1 p) 2 1))pȳ )/D 2 pȳ (n I 1)/n I if n I < n I otherwise Note that X is continuous in n I at n I In case we have p > (n 1)/n, all players will be active in equilibrium, regardless of the relative numbers of informed and uninformed players, and in this case X is a strictly convex function of n I, with a minimum at n I = n/(1+p) Figure 1 illustrates this case Next consider the case where we have p (n 1)/n Two subcases are of interest It could be the case that we have n I n/(1 + p), ie, that p (n 1)/(n +1), in which case n I = n/(1+p) is still the number of informed players that minimizes expected aggregate equilibrium expenditure Figure 2 illustrates this case Note that the scales used in the figures are not commensurate the values of the minimized expenditure in two figures may, of course, be different Finally, it may be the case that p < (n 1)/(n + 1), in which case the minimum expenditure is reached at n I This case is illustrated in Figure 3 In particular, we note that in each case that equilibrium expenditure is minimized with a population of players that includes both informed and uninformed players Equilibrium expenditure is maximized when there are only players of one type 9

X H X (n I ) X L 0 n 1+p n n I Figure 1: Aggregate expenditure with p > (n 1)/n X H X (n I ) X L 0 n 1+p 1 1 p n n I Figure 2: Aggregate expenditure with (n 1)/(n + 1) p (n 1)/n 10

X H X (n I ) X L 0 1 1 p n n I 4 Remarks Figure 3: Aggregate expenditure with p < (n 1)/(n + 1) We have seen that in common-value contests with players who can be either perfectly informed of the value of the prize, or perfectly uninformed, both types of player will expend positively in equilibrium as long as the prize is always of positive value In the case of lottery contests we showed that there is a unique mix of informed and uninformed players that minimizes expected equilibrium expenditure The latter result suggests in particular, if it can be generalized that from the perspective of a contest designer who collects the expenditures of the contestants, having differentially informed contestants is never optimal A risk neutral contest designer who does not himself know the value of the prize would prefer to have the contestants be either all informed or all uninformed Since it seems reasonable to assume that the contest designer does typically know the value of the prize, however, the optimal composition of the population of contestants is then for all of them to be uninformed as they will, of course, 11

typically spend more than would informed contestants when the value of the prize happens to be low From the point of view of rent-seeking applications, in which the focus is often on the social waste of contest expenditure, we see that analyses that do not take asymmetric information into account may overestimate equilibrium rent dissipation As in many applications it seems reasonable to assume that contestant are in fact asymmetrically informed, our results provide yet another clue to why empirical estimates of rent-seeking expenditures typically show them to be considerably lower than predicted by symmetric information models (see, eg, Laband and Sophocleus [12]) References [1] David P Baron Service-induced campaign contributions and the electoral equilibrium Quarterly Journal of Economics, 104:45 72, 1989 [2] Michael R Baye, Dan Kovenock, and Casper G de Vries Rigging the lobbying process: An application of the all-pay auction American Economic Review, 83:289 294, 1993 [3] Antonio E Bernardo, Eric Talley, and Ivo Welch A theory of legal presumptions Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 16:1 49, 2000 [4] Avinash Dixit Strategic behavior in contests American Economic Review, 77:891 898, 1987 [5] Richard L Fullerton and R Preston McAfee Auctioning entry into tournaments Journal of Political Economy, 107:573 605, 1999 [6] Mark Gradstein and Kai A Konrad Orchestrating rent seeking contests Economic Journal, 109:536 545, 1999 [7] Arye L Hillman and John G Riley Politically contestable rents and transfers Economics & Politics, 1:17 39, 1989 12

[8] Jack Hirshleifer Conflict and rent-seeking success functions: Ratio vs difference models of relative success Public Choice, 63:101 112, 1989 [9] Jack Hirshleifer The technology of conflict as an economic activity American Economic Review, 81:130 134, 1991 [10] Jack Hirshleifer Anarchy and its breakdown Journal of Political Economy, 103:26 52, 1995 [11] Vijay Krishna and John Morgan An analysis of the war of attrition and the all-pay auction Journal of Economic Theory, 72:343 362, 1997 [12] David N Laband and John P Sophocleus An estimate of resource expenditures on transfer activity in the United States Quarterly Journal of Economics, CVII:959 983, 1992 [13] Paul R Milgrom and Robert J Weber The value of information in a sealed bid auction Journal of Mathematical Economics, 10:105 114, 1982 [14] Holger M Müller and Karl Wärneryd Inside vs outside ownership: A political theory of the firm RAND Journal of Economics, 32:527 541, 2001 [15] Roger B Myerson and Karl Wärneryd Population uncertainty in contests Economic Theory, 27:469 474, 2006 [16] Shmuel Nitzan Collective rent dissipation Economic Journal, 101:1522 1534, 1991 [17] Stergios Skaperdas Cooperation, conflict, and power in the absence of property rights American Economic Review, 82:720 739, 1992 [18] Stergios Skaperdas Contest success functions Economic Theory, 7:283 290, 1996 [19] Ferenc Szidarovszky and Koji Okuguchi On the existence and uniqueness of pure Nash equilibrium in rent-seeking games Games and Economic Behavior, 18:135 140, 1997 13

[20] Stefan Szymanski The economic design of sporting contests Journal of Economic Literature, XLI:1137 1187, 2004 [21] Gordon Tullock On the efficient organization of trials Kyklos, 28:745 762, 1975 [22] Gordon Tullock Efficient rent seeking In James M Buchanan, Robert D Tollison, and Gordon Tullock, editors, Toward a Theory of the Rent-Seeking Society, pages 269 282 Texas A&M University Press, College Station, Texas, 1980 [23] Karl Wärneryd Information in conflicts Journal of Economic Theory, 110:121 136, 2003 14