Relative Di erence Contest Success Function

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Relative Di erence Contest Success Function"

Transcription

1 Relative Di erence Contest Success Function Carmen Beviá Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona and Barcelona GSE Luis C. Corchón Universidad Carlos III de Madrid First version January 20 th, This version August 29 th, Abstract In this paper we present a Contest Sucess Function (CSF) which is homogeneous of degree zero and where the probabilities of winning the prize depend on the relative di erence of e orts. With two agents, we present a necessary and su cient condition for the existence of a Nash Equilibrium in pure strategies. This equilibrium is unique and interior. This condition does not depend on the size of the valuations as in absolute di erence CSF. We prove that several properties of Nash equilibrium and Leader-Follower equilibrium with the Tullock CSF still hold in our framework. Finally, we consider the case of n players, generalize the previous condition and show that it is su cient for the existence of a unique Nash equilibrium in pure strategies. This paper is dedicated to Gordon Tullock whose insightful work has being inspirational for both authors. We thank to Matthias Dahm, Joerg Franke, Magnus Ho mann, Guillaume Roger, Santiago Sanchez-Pages, Marco Serena, Anil Yildizparlak and the participants in a seminar in the SAET 2012 congress, Brisbane, for comments that improved substantially the quality of the paper. The rst author acknowledges nancial support from ECO and FEDER, SGR and Barcelona GSE research network. The second author acknowledges nancial support from ECO Both authors acknowledge the hospitality of the Australian School of Business during the revision of the paper. Electronic copy available at:

2 1. Introduction The concept of a Contest Success Function (CSF) plays a crucial role in the analysis of contests. This function encapsulates how the contest is played and what the consequences of the contest are. Thus the outcome of a contest is highly sensitive to the form of the CSF. There are two main families of CSF. The CSF proposed by Tullock (1980) (axiomatized by Skaperdas (1996)) in which the probabilities of winning the prize depend on relative e orts, and the di erence form proposed by Hirshleifer (1989) (also axiomatized by Skaperdas (1996), see, in addition, Baik (1998) and Che and Gale (2000)) in which the probabilities of winning the prize depend on the di erence between e orts. Both formulations have properties that one would like to have in an ideal CSF. The Tullock form is homogeneous of degree zero, so the units in which e orts are measured do not count. The Hirshleifer form captures "the tremendous advantage of being even just a little stronger than one s opponent" (Hirshleifer, 1991, p. 131). However this advantage cannot be independent of the size of the con ict. One more battalion is a great advantage in a battle of two battalions against one but of less help when two hundred battalions ght one hundred and ninety nine. Thus di erences must be scaled up to the size of the con ict. In this paper we present the Relative Di erence CSF (RDCSF) in which the probability of getting the prize depends on the di erence between e orts and is also homogeneous of degree zero. When there are two players, the RDCSF is a linear function of the di erence between a player e ort and the e ort of the other player weighted by a positive number, divided by the sum of e orts. When the weight of the e ort of the other player is zero we have the Tullock CSF, so the RDCSF generalizes the latter. The RDCSF is presented in Section 2 for the case of two players. In Section 3 we tackle the two players case. We present a necessary and su cient condition for the existence of a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies. This equilibrium is unique and all players make a positive e ort. This condition is satis ed when the sum of the intercept and the slope of the linear function de ning the RDCSF add up to less than one. We show that in equilibrium the player having a higher valuation of the prize regards e orts as strategic complements, whereas the player having a lower valuation regards e orts as strategic substitutes. This was shown by Dixit (1987) assuming either a di erence form or a logit form (a generalization of the Tullock CSF). Finally we consider the case in which players may move sequentially. Firstly, we compare the equilibrium 2 Electronic copy available at:

3 values of e orts and probabilities in the sequential model with those when moves are simultaneous. This allows us to see the impact of the change in the structure of moves on equilibrium. Secondly, we consider an endogenous order of moves, as in Baik and Shogren (1992) and Leininger (1993) again for logit or absolute di erence CSF. We show that the RDCSF replicates earlier ndings in these two issues, in particular the player with the smaller valuation has incentives to move rst. In Section 4 we consider the case of n players. The extension of the functional form presented in Section 2 to more than two players is not straightforward. First one has to choose a functional form that generalizes the one chosen before. But the main problem is to guarantee that this chosen functional form represents probabilities, i.e. yields non negative values and adds up to one. We solve this problem by introducing a rationing rule which gives priority to the players making the largest expenses. Probabilities are assigned until they add up to one. In some cases a player might be given zero probability of winning the contest despite the fact she is making a positive e ort but of course this cannot happen in equilibrium. With this procedure in hand we show that a Nash equilibrium exists and that this equilibrium is unique and all players make a positive e ort. Our results obtained in Sections 3 and 4 on the existence of a Nash equilibrium contrast with those obtained for Hirshleifer type CSF, where at most one contestant makes a positive e ort in any Nash equilibrium in pure strategies and a pure strategy Nash equilibrium does not exists when the value of the prize is su ciently large (see Hirshleifer (1989), Baik (1998) and Che and Gale (2000)). These two properties restrict severely the range of application of this kind of CSF. Finally Section 5 o ers some comments about possible extensions of our work. We are only aware of a CSF which depend on di erences and it is homogeneous of degree zero, the Serial Contest proposed by Alcalde and Dahm (2007). But this CSF does not generalize Tullock s CSF. A recent paper by Hwang (2012) present a CSF which depends on di erences and such that in the limit when a parameter tends to one, becomes the Tullock CSF. But this CSF is not of a di erence form and homogeneous of degree zero at the same time. 3

4 2. The Relative Di erence Contest Success Function We start with the case of two players to gain intuition on the relative contest success function. In Section 4 we present the generalization for the n players case. We motivate our CSF by means of the following properties. Our CSF should be based on a function, denoted by f i (), which depend on the di erence between weighted e orts G 1 and sg 2 where s is a positive number. If s = 1 the function depends on the di erence G 1 is to write f i ((G 1 G 2. We also want our CSF to be homogeneous of degree zero. A possibility sg 2 )=G j ) as in Alcalde and Dahm (2007) where j could be 1 or 2 but in this case we have to rede ne the function each time G j is zero. Instead, we divide the di erence by the aggregate e ort G 1 + G 2 so we have to rede ne our CSF only when both e orts are zero. Thus, f i () is written as f i ((G 1 sg 2 )=(G 1 + G 2 )). Next we take f i () to be the simplest possible form, namely linear. Last, we assume symmetry, so the intercept and the slopes of f 1 () and f 2 () are identical. A function with all these properties must have the following form: f i (G i ; G j ) = + G i sg j P 2 k=1 G ; if k 2X G k 6= 0; i; j 2 f1; 2g; i 6= j; (2.1) k=1 f i (G i ; G j ) = 1 2X 2 if G k = 0; i; j 2 f1; 2g; i 6= j: (2.2) k=1 with > 0 to guarantee that f i is increasing in G i and 2 [0; 1] to have f i (sg j ; G j ) 2 [0; 1]: When = s = 0 and = 1 we get the Tullock CSF. 1 The part (2.2) takes care of the case in which all e orts are zero and it is the usual expedient when de ning the Tullock CSF. In the sequel we will call the function de ned in (2.1) and (2.2) the notional CSF. For f 1 () and f 2 () to be a real CSF the two properties below must hold. a) f i (G) 2 [0; 1] for i 2 f1; 2g; and b) P 2 i=1 f i(g) = 1: where G = (G 1 ; G 2 ). Conditions a) and b) are satis ed in some special cases, i.e. when = s = 0 and = 1, i.e. when the notional CSF is the Tullock CSF. But in general, we need extra conditions to convert (2.1)-(2.2) into a CSF. To take care of part a) we de ne our CSF as min(max(f i (G); 0); 1): This minmax operator is used by Che and Gale (2000) with the same purpose we do, namely, to (5.1). 1 Actually it generalizes the Tullock CSF in ratio form but the generalization to general Tullock CSF is simple, see 4

5 guarantee that winning probabilities are between zero and one. To guarantee part b) above, we add up (2.1) over all players and nd that 2 + (1 s) = 1: (2.3) Condition (2.3) also guarantees that G 1 = G 2 implies that p 1 = p 2, i.e. that our notional CSF is symmetric. Note that this condition plus 2 [0; 1] implies 1 (1 s) 1. Now we are ready to o er our main de nition De nitio. The Relative Di erence CSF (RDCSF) for two players is de ned as follows: p i = min(max(f i (G i ; G j ); 0); 1); i; j 2 f1; 2g; i 6= j: (2.4) where 2 + (1 s) = 1. We note two things: 1. A more exact description of this CSF would be "Relative Weighted Di erence" but we chose the shorter name in the hope that this does not yield to any confusion. 2. When s = 0 (when the RDCSF becomes the Tullock CSF) the CSF in De nitio is no longer a "Relative Di erence" CSF. But we may assume that s > 0 and in this case the Tullock CSF is the limit case of the RDCSF when s! 0. We decided to retain the case s = 0 by simplicity. With the RDCSF, a player making zero e ort might win the contest (as it happens in the absolute di erence CSF of Che and Gale (2001)). A historical example of this is when the Mongol navy was wiped out by the divine wind (kamikaze) i281 without any intervention of the Japanese eet. 2 When it is reasonable to impose that a player making zero e ort has zero probability of winning, then by (2.1), + = 1 (which given condition (2.3), is equivalent to s = 0). As we will see later this equality implies the existence of a Nash equilibrium. In Figure 1 we represent the winning probability for player 1 as a function of the relative di erences for the case s = 1: In this case condition (2.3) does not impose any restriction on : When = 0; the outcome of the contest does not depend on relative di erences. When tends to in nity the contest coincides with the all pay auction. 2 Actually, before the typhoon destroyed the mongolian ships, an inconclusive battle took place between two small forces of japanese and mongol warriors. outcome of the war. But it could be argued that this encounter did not play any role in the 5

6 Winning Probaility for 1 1 1/(2β) 1/(2β) Relative Differences Winning Probability for Player 1 as a function of the Relative Differences when α=1/2 and s=1. Figure 1 A microfoundation to the RDCSF is given using the framework in Corchón and Dahm (2010). There, CSF is derived as the choice of a utility maximizing planner whose type is unknown to the contestants. Let be the type of the planner, assumed to be a random variable uniformly distributed in [0; 1]. Let U i (; G i ) be the planner s utility if i wins the contest. U 1 (; G 1 ) (resp. U 2 (; G 2 )) is increasing (decreasing) in ; so is her degree of favoritism towards contestant 2. U i (; ) is increasing in G i since expenses are correlated with the quality of the project which in turn is positively correlated with the planner s utility. Assume that the U i () 0 s are separable in and G i so U i (; G i ) = V (F i1 (); F i2 (G i )). V () is a symmetric Cobb-Douglas function so, U i (; G i ) = F i1 ()F i2 (G i ). Take F 0 s to be the simplest possible form, namely linear and assume that the comparison between the contestants is independent of the units in which expenses are measured so it only depends on the ratio G i =G j. Assume also symmetry such as F 12 () = F 22 () and df 11 () d = df 21() d (recall that F i1 () describes how the planner is partial to contestant 2 and thus F 11 () and F 21 () cannot be identical). Thus U 1 (; G 1 ) = (a 1 b)dg 1 and U 2 (; G 2 ) = (a 2 b)dg 2. Without lost of generality take d = 1. Write U 1 (; G 1 ) = (1 + )G 1 and U 2 (; G 2 ) = (s + )G 2: (2.5) Let (G) be such that U 1 (; G 1 ) = U 2 (; G 2 ). If U 1 (; G 1 ) > U 2 (; G 2 ) (resp <) for all take (G) = 1 (= 0). Assuming that when G1 = G 2, (G) = 1=2, we obtain (2.3). Since U 1 (; G 1 ) (resp. U 2 (; G 2 )) is decreasing (increasing) in, the probability that 1 wins the contest is (G) and this yields the RDCSF. Note that when! 1, U 1 (; G 1 ) > U 2 (; G 2 ) i G 1 > sg 2 which is the 6

7 (biased when s 6= 1 and unbiased when s = 1) all pay auction. To end this section, note that the RDCSF, denoted by p 1 (G); p 2 (G), yields payo functions i (G) = p i (G)V i G i, i = 1; 2 where V i is i s valuation of the prize. A Nash equilibrium is a pair G = (G 1 ; G 2 ) such that i(g ) i (G i ; G j ) j 6= i for all G i, i = 1; Equilibrium with Two Players. In this section we study the existence and uniqueness of Nash equilibrium and the properties of equilibrium strategies and payo s in the case of two players. Later, we consider the case in which players may act in di erent moments of time and we will endogenize the order of moves. We see that the results obtained with the Tullock CSF still hold with the RDCSF Existence and Uniqueness of a Nash Equilibrium Let us de ne V i P 2 k=1 1 V k ; i 2 f1; 2g: Note that for all players > 1 and that for the player with the smallest valuation, say j, Y j 2. If valuations of the two players are identical, = 2. To prove the existence of a Nash equilibrium we need the following assumption: ( + ) (1 + s)(2 1 ), i = 1; 2: (3.1) If players are identical and given (2.3) (2 + (1 s) = 1) condition (3.1) is 2 (1 + s) or + 3=2. If = 1 and s = = 0 (the Tullock CSF), condition (3.1) is + 1= 2 which always holds. In the Appendix we show that Assumption (3.1) is implied by + 1. All these conditions say that the probability of getting the prize cannot be very sensitive to relative di erences in e orts. This is because, as we saw before, when is large, the RDCSF approaches the all pay auction in which a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies does not exist (Hillman and Riley, 1989, Baye, Kovenock and de Vries, 1996). Note that, the ratio of valuations is limited by (3.1) but this assumption says nothing about the absolute value of valuations like in the Hirshleifer type CSF studied in Baik (1998) and Che and Gale (2000). Next proposition shows the existence of a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies. Propositio. Under (3.1) there is a unique Nash equilibrium in pure strategies in which both players are active. 7

8 Proof. Let us see rst that (0; 0) cannot be an equilibrium. In (0; 0) the payo for each player is V i =2: Let " > 0 su ciently close to zero. Consider that, say, player 1 deviates and increases his e ort to ": Let G = ("; 0): In this case, f 1 (G) = + ; and f 2 (G) = s: If + 1, given that 2 + (1 s) = 1; then s 0: Thus, p 1 = 1. So, player 1 will win the contest for sure and his payo will be V 1 " which is greater than V 1 =2: If f 1 (G) = + < 1; p 1 = + : Since 1 = 2 + (1 ( + )V i " > V i =2: s) 2 + < 2 + 2; then + > 1=2; for " su ciently close to zero, To prove that there is an equilibrium with positive e ort, consider an auxiliary game with payo s FOC in an interior equilibrium are ^ i = ( + G i sg j P 2 k=1 G )V i G i ; for all i 2 f1; 2g: (3.2) k (1 + s)g j ( P 2 k=1 G k) 2 V i 1 = 0, i 2 f1; 2g. (3.3) Adding up over players all equations in (3.3) and setting X P 2 k=1 G k we obtain that Plugging (3.4) in (3.3) we nd that X = (1 + s) P 2 k=1 1 V k : (3.4) G i = (1 + s)v i (1 1 ); i 2 f1; 2g. (3.5) Since > 1; G i > 0: From the de nition of probabilities we have that f i (G 1; G 2) = + (1 1 + s ); i 2 f1; 2g. (3.6) Note that f i (G 1 ; G 2 ) 0 if and only if ( + ) (1 + s); i 2 f1; 2g. (3.7) Under Assumption (3.1) condition (3.7) always holds. Furthermore, since P 2 k=1 f k(g 1 ; G 2 ) = 1; f i (G 1 ; G 2 ) 1 for all i 2 f1; 2g. Pro ts in equilibrium amount to i = V i [( + ) (1 + s)(2 1 )]; i 2 f1; 2g: (3.8) Assumption (3.1) implies that pro ts are non negative so (G 1 ; G 2 ) is an equilibrium of the auxiliary game. Next, we see that G = (G 1 ; G 2 ) is also an equilibrium of the original game. Clearly, no 8

9 player has a pro table deviation G i such that 0 f i (G i ; G i ) 1 because G is an equilibrium of the auxiliary game. In particular, Gi ~ such that f i ( G ~ i ; G i ) = 1 is not a pro table deviation. Thus, a pro table deviation G 0 i can only occur when f i(g 0 i ; G i ) > 1; or f i(g 0 i ; G i ) < 0: In the rst case, since f i is increasing in G i ; G 0 i > G ~ i ; and p i = 1: Payo at (G 0 i ; G i ) are less than payo s at ( ~ G i ; G i ): Therefore, G0 i can not be a pro table deviation. If f i(g 0 i ; G i ) < 0; p i = 0 and payo for player i in this deviation is not larger than zero. Thus, this is not a pro table deviation. Finally we will show that there cannot be an equilibrium with (G i ; 0), G i case, i = ( + )V i G i so G i > 0 cannot maximize the payo s of i. > 0. If this were the Note that, contrarily to the case in which the CSF is based on absolute di erences, the RDCSF yields a Nash Equilibrium in pure strategies in which all contestants make a positive e ort, even if they value the prize highly. Furthermore, condition (3.1) is not only su cient for the existence of equilibrium but also necessary. 3 Proposition 2. If Assumption (3.1) does not hold, there is no Nash equilibrium in pure strategies. Proof. We can not have an equilibrium with both players doing positive e ort because in this case, and given that condition (3.1) does not hold, payo s would be negative. A player by doing no e ort will be better o. Thus, if an equilibrium exists, it has to be with some player making zero e ort. Suppose G = (G i ; 0): Since condition (3.1) does not hold, it should be the case that + > 1 (otherwise condition (3.1) will hold as we prove in the Appendix). Therefore, f i (G) > 1; which implies that f j (G) < 0 for player j: Thus, p i (G i ; 0) = 1: But for any G i > 0; player i by decreasing an " his e ort will be better o. Thus, a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies does not exist. To build intuition on Propositions 1 and 2, we study the best reply functions in the case of a common valuation V. From (3.3) we obtain that G i (G j ) = q (1 + s)g j V G j : (3.9) Equation (3.9) is the best reply for player i whenever i gets non negative pro ts and f(g i (G j ); G j ) 1: If pro ts are positive at (G i (G j ); G j ); but f(g i (G j ); G j ) > 1; then the best reply for player i is to chose G i such that f(g i ; G j ) = 1: If pro ts are negative at (G i (G j ); G j ) then the best reply for 3 See Malueg and Yates (2005, 2006) for su cient conditions for the existence of a Nash equilibrium when the CSF is homogeneous of degree zero. 9

10 player i is G i = 0: We draw the best reply of each player for two cases. First when a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies exists and second when it does not. To simplify calculations we take V = 1; = 1=2; and s = 1. Given the condition (3.1), under these parameters a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies exists i 1: In the rst case we take = 1 and in the second case we take = 1:5: In Figures 2 and 3, the solid line represents the best reply for player 1 and the dash line the best reply for player 2. The curvilinear line in both gures corresponds to the part of the best reply characterized by the rst order condition as in (3.9). The straight lines with positive and nite slope correspond to the case where the best reply is determined by the probability of winning being equal to 1: And nally, the dashed and the solid lines on the axes corresponds to the case where pro ts are negative at (G i (G j ); G j ) with G i (G j ) determined by (3.9) and therefore the best reply is zero e ort. Note that the best reply are neither convex value nor continuous, even though they are upper-hemi-continuous. G Figure 2. Beta equals 1 G1 10

11 G G1 Figure 3. Beta equals 1.5 To close this section we analyze some properties of the Nash equilibrium. First, from (3.5) we obtain that the player with the highest valuation exerts the highest e ort: G i > G j, V i > V j, i; j = 1; 2: (3.10) Second, the player having a higher valuation of the prize regards e orts as strategic complements, whereas the player having a lower valuation regards e orts as strategic substitutes. Dixit (1987) proved an identical result assuming either a di erence form or a logit form (a generalization of the Tullock CSF). This point is easy to show by computing the slope of best reply. Totally di erentiating the rst order condition (3.3) we obtain 2 i 2 dg i i (G i ) dg j = 0: (3.11) j From (3.11) it follows that the sign of the slope of the best reply is the sign 2 i (G)=@G j. From (3.3) we obtain 2 i (G) = (1 + s)(g i G j j (G i + G j ) 3 which evaluated in equilibrium yields the desired 2 i (G j > 0, G i > G j, i; j = 1; 2: (3.12) Finally, the player with the highest valuation gets the highest winning probability. From (3.6) p i > p j, V i > V j, i; j = 1; 2: (3.13) By considering (3.10), (3.12) and (3.13) we obtain the following result: 11

12 Proposition 3. In equilibrium, G i > G j i (G j > 0 i p i > p j i V i > V j, i; j = 1; 2: 3.2. Leader-Follower Games We assume now that e orts are done sequentially. Firstly, we compare the equilibrium values of e orts and probabilities with those obtained in the case of simultaneous moves (Nash equilibrium) to see the impact of the change in the structure of moves on equilibrium. This was done by Dixit (1987) assuming a logit or a absolute di erence CSF. Secondly, we will consider an endogenous order of moves, as in Baik and Shogren (1992), Leininger (1993). They show that in the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium where in the rst stage players decide if they spend e ort "early" or "late" and in the second stage they exert e ort according to the order decided in the previous stage, the player with the lower valuation plays "early". We will see that the RDCSF replicates the earlier ndings in these two issues. A leader-follower equilibrium is a pair of e orts such that given the e ort of the leader, the e ort of the follower maximizes her payo s and the e ort of the leader maximizes her payo s taking into account the best reply of the follower. In a sequential game in which the leader moves in the rst stage, a leader-follower equilibrium is a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium. We denote by j the leader and by i the follower. To prove the existence of a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium we need the following assumptions: 3=2; (or equivalently, 2V i > V j ); (3.14) ( + )( 1) (1 + s)(1 1 ); (3.15) 4( 1) (1 + s) ( + ) 1: (3.16) 4( 1) If both players have the same valuation, condition (3.14) always holds because = 2: Given that 2+(1 s) = 1; condition (3.16) also holds and nally condition (3.15) is equivalent in this case to 2 (1 + s); which it coincides with condition (3.1) of existence of equilibrium in the simultaneous game of the previous section. Proposition 4. Under conditions (3.14), (3.15), and (3.16) a leader-follower equilibrium in pure strategies exists in which both players make a positive e ort. 12

13 Proof. Let us rst nd the best reply function of i, the follower. From FOC of payo maximization we obtain that G i = q (1 + s)v i G j G j. (3.17) Plugging this function into the payo s of the leader we obtain that j = ( + G j(1 + s) s p (1 + s)v i G j p )V j (1 + s)vi G j G j : (3.18) This expression can be simpli ed as follows FOC of payo maximization are j = ( s)v j + s G j (1 + s) V i V j G j : (3.19) s 1 (1 + s) V j 2 G j V i 1 = 0: (3.20) Clearly, SOC of payo maximization hold. Thus, in a leader-follower equilibrium G S j = (1 + s)v 2 j 4V i = (1 + s)v j 4( 1) : (3.21) Plugging the value of G S j into the best reply function of i we obtain the equilibrium value of G i, namely G S i = (1 + s)v j (2V i V j ) = (1 + s)v j (2 4V i 4 1 ): (3.22) ( 1) The follower s e ort is positive from 3=2. Total e ort in equilibrium, denoted by X S is The probability that in equilibrium j and i win is X S = (1 + s)v j : (3.23) 2 p S j = + 2V i (V j (1 + s) 2sV i ) = (3.24) = ( s) + (1 + s) 2( 1) : (3.25) p S i = + (2V i V j (1 + s)) = (3.26) 2V i (1 + s) = + 2( 1) : (3.27) Condition (3.16) guarantees that p S j 0; which implies that ps i that p S i 0 which implies that p S j 1: 1; and condition (3.15) guarantees 13

14 Finally, equilibrium payo s are: (1 + s) j = V j (( s) + ): (3.28) 4( 1) (1 + s) i = ( + 2( 1) )V (1 + s)v j 1 i (2 4 ( 1) ) = (3.29) (1 + s) = V j ( + 2( 1) )(Y (1 + s) 1 i 1) (2 4 ( 1) ) = (3.30) 1 = V j ( + )( 1) (1 + s)(1 4( 1) ) : (3.31) Condition (3.16) guarantees that j 0; and condition (3.15) guarantees that i 0: Remark 1. Note that if both players have the same valuation, the leader-follower equilibrium coincides with the Nash equilibrium of the simultaneous game. Aggregate e ort is smaller in the leader follower game than in the simultaneous game if and only if the leader is the player with the smallest valuation. Next we consider endogenous moves. The game is as follows. In the rst period players decide if they spend e ort early or late. In the second period they exert e ort. If both choose the same period the e orts correspond to the (simultaneous) Nash equilibrium. If, say, player 1 chooses early and player 2 chooses late the e orts are those corresponding to leader-follower equilibrium with 1 as a leader, etc. We will say that the player with the smaller (resp. larger) prize value will be called "the underdog" (resp. "the favorite"). We have the following: Proposition 5. In equilibrium, the favorite moves after the underdog. than it is in the Nash Equilibrium of the simultaneous-move game. Aggregate e ort is less Proof. Virtually identical to Baik and Shogren (1992). First note that, after lengthy calculations it can be shown that G S j > G j, V j > V i so as in Dixit (1987) the favorite "has incentive to overcommit e ort" (p. 891). Next, the expected payo of any player is decreasing when we move along her best reply e orts with respect to the e ort of the other player. From these two results we see that to play early for the underdog is a dominant strategy. Given this the favorite plays late. Finally from (3.23) and (3.4) we have that X S > X, V j > V i 14

15 as desired. 4. The Case of n Players. In this section we tackle the case of n players. First we generalize the CSF de ned in Section 2. The construction of a CSF for more than two players based on the idea of relative di erences requires some extra work with respect to the two person case because the minmax operator introduced there (see (2.4)) does not guarantee that the sum of the intended probabilities add up to one. 4 We introduce an extra device which guarantees that and show, that under a condition which is a generalization of assumption (3.1), a Nash equilibrium exists and is unique The Relative Di erence CSF in the case of n Players. Let G = (G 1 ; :::; G n ): The notional CSF (2.1) can be generalized in several ways. In order to keep as close as possible to the case of n = 2 we propose the following function: P f i (G) = + G j6=i i s G j P n j=1 G ; i 2 f1; ::; ng if j nx G j 6= 0; (4.1) f i (G) = 1 nx n if G j = 0; i 2 f1; ::; ng: (4.2) j=1 We require that for all G; P n i=1 f i(g) = 1: Adding up (4.1) over players the following condition must hold j=1 n + (1 s) = 1: (4.3) This condition is a generalization to n players of (2.3). The Tullock CSF arises when = 0, = 1 and s = 0. Note that the notional CSF is anonymous, whenever G i = G j ; f i (G) = f j (G): Based on (4.1), we de ne a contest success function using the following auxiliary function: i(g) = min(max(f i (G); 0); 1): (4.4) Unfortunately, when n > 2, the minmax operator does not guarantee that P i(g) = 1 so an extra construction is needed. In particular let the players with the largest expenses be given the probabilities corresponding to (4.4). Once probabilities add up to one the remaining players are 4 We note that the di culties of extending CSF for more than two players are shared by other CSF like the di erence of Baik (1998) and Che and Gale (2000) or the serial contest of Alcalde and Dahm (2007). 15

16 given zero probability. In order to formally introduce the CSF we need some extra notation. Given G; a type i player is a player that exercise e ort G i : Let k i be the number of players of type i; and let l i be the last player of type i: De nition 2. The Relative Di erence CSF for any number of players is de ned as follows: Given G, order the type of players by decreasing order of G i. Let m be the type of player such that P lm j=1 j(g) 1 and P l m+1 j=1 j(g) > 1: Then, p j (G) = j(g); for all j 2 f1; ::; l m g; (4.5) p m+1 (G) = (1 where n + (1 s) = 1. l m X j=1 j(g))=(k m+1 ); for all players of type m + 1; and (4.6) p h (G) = 0 for all h 2 fl m+1 + 1; ::; ng: (4.7) We may regard conditions (4.5), (4.6) and (4.7) as a rationing rule: players are rationed depending on their expenditures. Agents with the largest expenses are given priority and their probabilities of winning the contest are given by (4.4). Agent with less expenses might be given zero probability of winning despite the fact that (4.4) would recommend a positive probability. This rationing rule re ects the competitive aspect of the contest by rewarding players who make more e ort. Note that if G 6= (0; ::; 0) and 0 f i (G) 1 for all i 2 f1; ::; ng; then p i = f i (G); and if G = (0; ::; 0); p i = 1=n for all i 2 f1; ::; ng: For the case of n = 2; the CSF (4.5) can be written as: p i = i(g); and p j = 1 i(g); (4.8) because whenever f i (G) 0; then f j (G) 1 (given that condition (4.3) is satis ed). So in this case the extra conditions (4.5), (4.6) and (4.7) are not needed Nash Equilibrium with n Heterogeneous Players As in Section 3, let V i P n j=1 1 V j : To prove the existence of a Nash equilibrium we need the following assumption which is a generalization of (3.1): ( + ) (n 1 + s)(2 ), i 2 f1; ::; ng: (4.9) When all players have identical valuations, condition (4.9) collapses in n (n 1 + s) which when either n is su ciently large or s = 1, is just 1. In the Appendix we show that condition (4.9) is 16

17 implied by + 1. The latter implies that when all players but i make zero e ort, the notional CSF yields a number for player i less or equal than one. In order to simplify the presentation, we focus on Nash equilibria where all players exert a positive e ort. In order to guarantee this we make the following assumption: > (); i 2 f1; ::; ng (4.10) which, of course, holds in the symmetric case where = n for all i and when n = 2. An identical assumption guarantees that when the CSF is of the Tullock type, all players are active in equilibrium, see Franke et al. (2012), Theorem 2.2. Now we have the following. Proposition 6. Under Assumption (4.9) and Assumption (4.10) there is a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies with all players active. Proof. Note rst that (0; 0; ::; 0) can not be an equilibrium. In (0; :::; 0) the payo for each player is V i =n: Let " > 0 su ciently close to zero. And consider that player i deviates and increases his e ort, G i = ": Let G = (0; ::; "; ::; 0): In this case, f i (G) = + : If + 1, given that n + (1 s) = 1; then (s)=() 0: Thus, p i = 1. So, player i wins the contest for sure and her payo will be V i " which is greater than V i =n: If f i (G) = + < 1; p i = + : Since 1 = n + (1 ( + )V i " > V i =n: s) n + < n + n; then + > 1=n; for " su ciently close to zero, Consider now the auxiliary game where the payo s of each player are de ned by FOC in an interior equilibrium are P j6=i G j ^ i = ( + G i s P n j=1 G j )V i G i ; i 2 f1; ::; ng, (4.11) Pj6=i G j(1 + s ) ( P n j=1 G j) 2 V i 1 = 0: (4.12) We readily see that the second order conditions hold so payo s of i are concave in G i. Write (4.12) as follows: Adding up (4.13) over all players and simplifying we obtain that P j6=i G j ( P n j=1 G j) 2 = 1 V i (1 + s (4.13) ): nx G j = j=1 ()(1 + s ) P n j=1 1 V j : (4.14) 17

18 Now realize that (4.13) can be written as P n j=1 G j G i ( P n j=1 G j) 2 = and taking into account (4.14) we obtain that 1 V i (1 + s (4.15) ); G i = s ()(1 + )V i (1 ): (4.16) Since Assumption (4.10) requires > ; for all i 2 f1; ::; ng; G i 0: From the de nition of the notional CSF f i we have that in the Nash equilibrium P n f i (G ) = + G i (1 + s ) s j=1 G j P n j=1 G j = (4.17) = + Taking into account (4.15) we have that G P i n j=1 G j (1 + s ) s : (4.18) G i P n j=1 G j = 1 () ; (4.19) and we obtain f i (G ) = + (1 + (1 () )(1 + s ) s = (4.20) ()(1 + s ) ): (4.21) Note that f i (G ) 0 if and only if (+) ()(1+ s ). But, given assumptions (4.9) and (4.10), this condition always hold. Furthermore, since P n i=1 f i(g) = 1, we have that f i (G ) 1. Finally, pro ts in equilibrium amount to i = ( + (1 which can be rewritten as: ()(1 + s ) ()(1 + s ))V )V i i (1 ); (4.22) i = ( + )V i ()(1 + s n 1 )V i ()(1 + s )V i (1 ); (4.23) i = V i (( + ) ()(1 + s s ) ()(1 + )(1 ); (4.24) i = V i (( + ) ()(1 + s )(2 )): (4.25) 18

19 Assumption (4.9) implies that pro ts are non negative so G = (G 1 ; ::; G n) is an equilibrium of the auxiliary game. Let us nally see that G is also an equilibrium of the original game. Clearly, no player have a pro table deviation G i such that 0 f i (G i ; G i ) 1 because G is an equilibrium of the auxiliary game. In particular, Gi ~ such that f i ( G ~ i ; G i ) = 1 is not a pro table deviation. Thus, a pro table deviation G 0 i can only occur when f i(g 0 i ; G i ) > 1; or f i(g 0 i ; G i ) < 0: In the rst case, since f i is increasing in G i ; G 0 i > G i : Furthermore since player i has incresed hihs e ort, the f j of the other players is reduced, thus f j (G 0 i ; G i ) f j(g ) 1: Therefore, by the rationing rule p i = 1: Thus, payo at (G 0 i ; G i ) are less than payo s at ( G ~ i ; G i ): Therefore, G0 i can not be a pro table deviation. If f i (G 0 i ; G i ) < 0; p i = 0 and then payo for player i in this deviation can not be greater than zero. Thus, this is not a pro table deviation. Note that when all players have identical valuations, V; aggregate equilibrium e orts are ( + s)v n : (4.26) Assumption (4.9) implies that aggregate e ort is less or equal than V. Thus, unless n = (n 1+s) (which happens if s = = 1) rents are not fully dissipated, as it happened in the two person case. Again, aggregate e ort is minimized when s = 0 which includes the Tullock CSF (where in addition = 0) in which total e ort is V=2. Comparing Proposition 6 with the results obtained in the two person case, we note that assumption (4.9) is only a su cient condition for the existence of equilibrium. Nash equilibrium is unique. Next we show that Proposition 7. If + > 1 there is at most a Nash equilibrium which is interior. Proof. Suppose that there is a Nash equilibrium with G i = 0 some i. Then, p i = s = + 1 < 0: (4.27) Since probabilities add up to one, this implies that some active agent, say j, is rationed. Assume that G j 6= G r for any r. But then j can decrease in nitesimally G j, obtain the prize with the same probability and increase payo s. Assume that there are r and j with G r = G j. But player j by increasing in nitesimally G j takes all the probability allocated to r so we have a contradiction. 19

20 We now tackle the case + 1. A coalition C is a subset of the set of players. Let c be the number of agents in coalition C. Consider the following condition: For any coalition C and player i =2 C, V i X j2c 1 V j > c 1: (4.28) Lemma 1 shows that condition (4.28) is always satis ed whenever assumption (4.10) holds. Lemma 1. If Assumption (4.10) holds for any coalition C and player i =2 C, V i Pj2C 1 V j > c 1: Proof. Suppose that condition (4.28) does not hold. Then, there is a coalition C and a player i =2 C such that V i Pj2C 1 V j c 1: In particular, for any player k =2 C such that V k V i ; V k Pj2C 1 V j c 1: Let k min =2 C be such that V kmin V k for all k =2 C: Let us see that Y kmin in contradiction with the assumption of the Proposition. Given that Y kmin = V kmin P n j=1 1 V j ; we can rewrite Y kmin as: Y kmin = V kmin X j2c 1 X 1 + V kmin : (4.29) V j V k Given that V kmin P j2c 1 V j c 1; and V kmin P k =2C 1 V k n c; Y kmin : We are now ready to prove the counterpart of Proposition 7 for the case + 1: k =2C Proposition 8. If Assumption (4.10) holds and + 1 there is at most a Nash equilibrium which is interior. Proof. Suppose we have a Nash equilibrium in which only agents 1; 2; :::; k are active. First we show that player i = k + 1; ::::n is not rationed. Indeed p i = s = 1 0: (4.30) Thus player i maximizes, at least in a neighborhood of the Nash equilibrium, over the notional CSF. The FOC of payo maximization for i is Now computing the expenses made by active players we see that i = (1 + P k i j=1 G V i 1: (4.31) j kx s (k 1)(1 + G j = P ) k (4.32) j=1 1 V j j=1 20

21 and thus and applying condition (4.28) we obtain i = V P k i j=1 1 V i k 1 1 i > k i k 1 1 = 0 (4.34) which contradicts that the best reply of i is zero. 5. Conclusions In this paper we have presented a new CSF, the Relative Di erence CSF (RDCSF), which combines properties of the Tullock and the Hirshleifer CSF s. The RDCSF is analytically tractable yielding closed form solutions that generalize those of the Tullock CSF. When the valuations of both players are not very di erent and the impact of relative di erences on the winning probability is not large, all contestants make a positive e ort in a Nash equilibrium. Recall that in the Hirshleifer CSF this only happen when the value of the prize times the impact of absolute di erences on the winning probability is less than one. The RDCSF looks like a mild extension of the Tullock CSF. However new issues surface. 1. To convert the notional RDCSF into a RDCSF. In the case of two players this is accomplished with the minmax operator like in Gale and Che (2000). But with more than two players the minmax operator is not enough and we have to introduce a full- edged rationing rule that distributes the available probabilities among players. 2. Nash equilibrium not always exists. In the case of two players we present a necessary and su cient condition for the existence of equilibrium. In the case of more than two players we present a su cient condition for the existence of equilibrium. We show that equilibrium is always unique. A drawback of the RDCSF is that it is not continuous when aggregate e ort tends to zero, but this is a general property of all homogeneous of degree zero CSF (see Corchón (2000)). We hope that the RDCSF can be useful in the analysis of con icts in which there is an advantage of being stronger but this advantage must be weighted by a measure of how large the con ict is. 21

22 Since many papers in this area used the Tullock CSF, the use of the RDCSF would provide a generalization of this work. Moreover, from the point of view of revenue maximization, the RDCSF provides a simple CSF for which, for some parameters, full rent dissipation occurs for any number of players. The RDCSF is amenable to certain extensions. A simple one would be based on the following form: f i (G) = + G i sg j P 2 j=1 G j ; i = 1; 2, 2 [0; 1]: (5.1) It is easy to show that the methods used in this paper su ce to show the existence of a Nash equilibrium when the CSF is of the (5.1) form. An alternative to the RDCSF with n players presented in this paper would be the following form: f i (G) = + G i s max j6=i G P j n j=1 G ; i 2 f1; ::; ng. (5.2) j in which we substract from G i not the weighted average of the actions of all other competitors but only that of the best competitor. When players are homogeneous both formulations yield identical results but not when players are heterogeneous. References [1] Alcalde J. and M. Dahm (2007) Tullock and Hirshleifer: a meeting of the minds. Rev. Econ. Design (2007) 11, 2, [2] Baik KH (1998) Di erence-form contest success functions and e ort level in contests. Eur J Polit Eco4, [3] Baik, Kyung Hwan and Jason F. Shogren, Strategic Behavior in Contests: Comment," American Economic Review, 1992, 82 (1), [4] Baye, M., D. Kovenock and C. G. de Vries (1996). "The all-pay auction with complete information". Economic Theory, 8, [5] Corchón L. (2000) On the allocative e ects of rent-seeking. J Public Econ Theory 2, 4, [6] Corchón, L. and M. Dahm (2010). "Foundations for contest success functions," Economic Theory, 43, 1, 81-98, 22

23 [7] CheY-K and I. Gale (2000) Di erence-form contests and the robustness of all-pay auctions. Games Econ Behav 30, [8] Dixit, Avinash, Strategic Behaviour in Contests, American Economic Review, 1987, 77 (5), [9] Hillman, A. L. and Riley, J. G. (1989). Politically contestable rents and transfers. Economics and Politics 1, [10] Hirshleifer J (1989) Con ict and rent-seeking success functions: ratio vs. di erence models of relative success. Public Choice 63, [11] Hirshleifer J (1991) The Technology of Con ict as an Economic Activity. The American Economic Review, 81, 2, Papers and Proceedings, [12] Hwang, S.-H. (2012). "Technology of military con ict, military spending, and war". Journal of Public Economics, 96, [13] J. Franke, C. Kanzow, W. Leininger and A. Schwartz (2012). "E ort Maximization in Asymmetric Contests Games with Heterogeneous Contestants" Economic Theory, forthcoming. [14] Leininger, Wolfgang, More E cient Rent-Seeking - A Munchhausen Solution, Public Choice, 1993, 75, [15] Malueg D and A Yates (2005). "Equilibria and comparative statics in two-player contests" European Journal of Political Economy, 21, 3, [16] Malueg D and A Yates (2006). "Equilibria in rent-seeking contests with homogeneous success functions". Econ Theory, 27, [17] Nitzan, Shmuel, More on E cient Rent Seeking and Strategic Behavior in Contests: Comment, Public Choice, 1994, 79, [18] Skaperdas S (1996) Contest success functions. Econ Theory 7: [19] Tullock G (1980). "E cient rent-seeking". In: Buchanan JM, Tollison RD, Tullock G (eds) Towards a theory of a rent-seeking society. Texas A&M University Press, College Station, pp

24 6. Appendix We show that the su cient condition for the existence of a Nash equilibrium (and necessary in case of two players) is implied by the inequality + 1. Recall that the su cient condition is ( + ) (n 1 + s)(2 ), i 2 f1; ::; ng: (6.1) The minimum of the left hand side of (6.1) is achieved when = ( + s) + and the corresponding value of the left hand side of (6.1) is 2 ( + s) (( + s)() Thus the the left hand side of (6.1) is always positive if (n (4.3) (i.e. n + (1 s) = 1) is ) s which taking into account 24

SIRE DISCUSSION PAPER

SIRE DISCUSSION PAPER scottish institute for research in economics SIRE DISCUSSION PAPER SIRE-DP-00-83 Affirmative Action Policy and Effort Levels. Sequential-Move Contest Game Argument Andrzej Kwiatkowski University of Dundee

More information

On Overdissipation of Rents in Contests with Endogenous Intrinsic Motivation. Volker Schlepütz

On Overdissipation of Rents in Contests with Endogenous Intrinsic Motivation. Volker Schlepütz On Overdissipation of Rents in Contests with Endogenous Intrinsic Motivation Volker Schlepütz Diskussionsbeitrag Nr. 421 Februar 2008 Diskussionsbeiträge der Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaft der FernUniversität

More information

Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information

Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information E. Einy y, O. Haimanko y, D. Moreno z, A. Sela y, and B. Shitovitz x September 203 Abstract We show that under standard assumptions a Tullock contest with asymmetric

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key EconS 50 - Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam # - Answer Key 1. Revenue comparison in two auction formats. Consider a sealed-bid auction with bidders. Every bidder i privately observes his valuation

More information

Linking Individual and Collective Contests through Noise Level and Sharing Rules

Linking Individual and Collective Contests through Noise Level and Sharing Rules Linking Individual and Collective Contests through Noise Level and Sharing Rules Pau Balart Subhasish M. Chowdhury Orestis Troumpounis November 6, 2015 Abstract We provide a theoretical link between the

More information

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Calle Madrid, 126

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Calle Madrid, 126 UC3M Working papers Departamento de Economía Economics Universidad Carlos III de Madrid 13-14 Calle Madrid, 126 July, 2013 28903 Getafe (Spain) Fax (34) 916249875 TULLOCK CONTESTS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION

More information

Common-Value All-Pay Auctions with Asymmetric Information

Common-Value All-Pay Auctions with Asymmetric Information Common-Value All-Pay Auctions with Asymmetric Information Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach, Aner Sela July 14, 014 Abstract We study two-player common-value all-pay auctions in which the players have

More information

Volume 35, Issue 4. Group contests and technologies. Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University

Volume 35, Issue 4. Group contests and technologies. Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University Volume 35, Issue 4 Group contests and technologies Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University Abstract We study the role of returns of scale of the technology on the characterization of

More information

COMMON-VALUE ALL-PAY AUCTIONS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION AND BID CAPS. Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No.

COMMON-VALUE ALL-PAY AUCTIONS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION AND BID CAPS. Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No. COMMON-VALUE ALL-PAY AUCTIONS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION AND BID CAPS Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach and Aner Sela Discussion Paper No. 4-0 September 04 Monaster Center for Economic Research Ben-Gurion

More information

Solving Extensive Form Games

Solving Extensive Form Games Chapter 8 Solving Extensive Form Games 8.1 The Extensive Form of a Game The extensive form of a game contains the following information: (1) the set of players (2) the order of moves (that is, who moves

More information

Welfare Maximizing Contest Success Functions when the Planner Cannot Commit

Welfare Maximizing Contest Success Functions when the Planner Cannot Commit MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Welfare Maximizing Contest Success Functions when the Planner Cannot Commit Luis Corchon Carlos III 2. November 2009 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/876/ MPRA

More information

On the Existence of a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information y

On the Existence of a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information y On the Existence of a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information y E. Einy z, O. Haimanko z, D. Moreno x, A. Sela z, and B. Shitovitz { December 2014 Abstract We show that

More information

Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information

Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information E. Einy y, O. Haimanko y, D. Moreno z, A. Sela y, and B. Shitovitz x December 2014 Abstract We show that under general assumptions

More information

Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information y

Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information y Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information y E. Einy z, O. Haimanko z, D. Moreno x, A. Sela z, and B. Shitovitz { July 2014 Abstract We show that under standard assumptions every member of a broad class

More information

Mixed equilibria in Tullock contests

Mixed equilibria in Tullock contests University of Zurich Department of Economics Working Paper Series ISSN 1664-7041 (print) ISSN 1664-705X (online) Working Paper No. 143 Mixed equilibria in Tullock contests Christian Ewerhart March 2014

More information

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation joint work with Stephen Morris August 2009 Barcelona Introduction mechanism design and implementation literatures are theoretical successes mechanisms

More information

Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd

Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd March 25, 2008 Abstract We consider imperfectly discriminating, common-value,

More information

Information Advantage in Tullock Contests

Information Advantage in Tullock Contests Information Advantage in Tullock Contests A. Aiche, E. Einy y, O. Haimanko y, D. Moreno z, A. Sela y, and B. Shitovitz March 2017 Abstract We study the impact of an information advantage on the equilibrium

More information

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests Subhasish Chowdhury and Roman Sheremeta 20 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/5204/ MPRA Paper No. 5204, posted 0. December

More information

FOUNDATIONS FOR CONTEST SUCCESS FUNCTIONS

FOUNDATIONS FOR CONTEST SUCCESS FUNCTIONS Working Paper 07-04 Departamento de Economía Economic Series 01 Universidad Carlos III de Madrid January 2007 Calle Madrid, 126 28903 Getafe (Spain) Fax (34-91) 6249875 FOUNDATIONS FOR CONTEST SUCCESS

More information

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter Forthcoming in Public Choice A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter J. Atsu Amegashie Department of Economics University of Guelph Guelph, Ontario Canada NG W E-mail: jamegash@uoguelph.ca

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen 1 Bayesian Games So far we have assumed that all players had perfect information regarding the elements of a game. These are called games with complete information.

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE)

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE) EconS 3 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE). Based on MWG 9.B.3 Consider the three-player nite game of perfect information depicted in gure. L R Player 3 l r a b

More information

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter Public Choice (2006) 126: 135 144 DOI: 10.1007/s11127-006-2461-z C Springer 2006 A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter J. ATSU AMEGASHIE Department of Economics, University of Guelph,

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen Strategic Form Games In this part we will analyze games in which the players choose their actions simultaneously (or without the knowledge of other players

More information

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions Walter Trockel University of California, Los Angeles and Bielefeld University Mai 1999 Abstract The paper presents a method of supporting

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design 1. Public Good Provision Imagine that you and your colleagues want to buy a co ee machine for your o ce. Suppose that some of you may

More information

Working Paper Series. Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes. Jun Xiao. June Research Paper Number 1151

Working Paper Series. Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes. Jun Xiao. June Research Paper Number 1151 Department of Economics Working Paper Series Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes Jun iao June 212 Research Paper Number 1151 ISSN: 819 2642 ISBN: 978 734 451 Department of Economics The

More information

Unique Equilibrium in Contests with Incomplete Information

Unique Equilibrium in Contests with Incomplete Information 1 2 Unique Equilibrium in Contests with Incomplete Information 3 4 Christian Ewerhart y Federico Quartieri z 5 July 2013 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 Abstract. For a large class of contests with incomplete

More information

Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes

Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes Jun iao y May 212 Abstract This paper studies complete-information, all-pay contests with asymmetric players competing for multiple heterogeneous prizes.

More information

Hybrid All-Pay and Winner-Pay Contests

Hybrid All-Pay and Winner-Pay Contests Hybrid All-Pay and Winner-Pay Contests Seminar at DICE in Düsseldorf, June 5, 208 Johan N. M. Lagerlöf Dept. of Economics, U. of Copenhagen Email: johan.lagerlof@econ.ku.dk Website: www.johanlagerlof.com

More information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Pei-yu Lo 1 Introduction Recap: BoS. Look for all Nash equilibria. show how to nd pure strategy Nash equilibria. Show how to nd mixed strategy Nash equilibria.

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key EconS 503 - Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key 1. WEAs with market power. Consider an exchange economy with two consumers, A and B, whose utility functions are u A (x A 1 ; x A 2 ) = x A

More information

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours.

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours. University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring 2012 EC941: Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Final Exam Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours. 1. Consider

More information

DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES IN ECONOMICS AND MANAGEMENT Strategic Incentives for Managers in Contests Matthias Kräkel Discussion Paper No. 01-08 GERMAN ECONOMIC ASSOCIATION OF BUSINESS ADMINISTRATION - GEABA

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics WEAK LINKS, GOOD SHOTS AND OTHER PUBLIC GOOD GAMES: BUILDING ON BBV

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics WEAK LINKS, GOOD SHOTS AND OTHER PUBLIC GOOD GAMES: BUILDING ON BBV UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 06/09 WEAK LINKS, GOOD SHOTS AND OTHER PUBLIC GOOD GAMES: BUILDING ON BBV by Richard Cornes & Roger Hartley August 12 th 2006

More information

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) Game Theory Bargaining Theory J International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) (International Game Theory: Doctorate Bargainingin Theory Economic Analysis (IDEA)

More information

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form)

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form) Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form) A Game in Normal (strategic) Form consists of three components. A set of players. For each player, a set of strategies (called actions in textbook). The interpretation

More information

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 1 Modelling incomplete information So far, we have studied games in which information was complete,

More information

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search Labor Economics, 14.661. Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search Daron Acemoglu MIT December 6, 2011. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Sequential Search December 6, 2011. 1 / 43 Introduction Introduction

More information

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics ECON2285: Mathematical Economics Yulei Luo Economics, HKU September 17, 2018 Luo, Y. (Economics, HKU) ME September 17, 2018 1 / 46 Static Optimization and Extreme Values In this topic, we will study goal

More information

Carrot and stick games

Carrot and stick games Bond University epublications@bond Bond Business School Publications Bond Business School 6-14-2001 Carrot and stick games Jeffrey J. Kline Bond University, jeffrey_kline@bond.edu.au Follow this and additional

More information

Lottery versus All-Pay Auction Contests

Lottery versus All-Pay Auction Contests RUHR ECONOMIC PAPERS Jörg Franke Christian Kanzow Wolfgang Leininger Alexandra Schwartz Lottery versus All-Pay Auction Contests A Revenue Dominance Theorem #35 Imprint Ruhr Economic Papers Published by

More information

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Lecture Notes on Bargaining Lecture Notes on Bargaining Levent Koçkesen 1 Axiomatic Bargaining and Nash Solution 1.1 Preliminaries The axiomatic theory of bargaining originated in a fundamental paper by Nash (1950, Econometrica).

More information

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information:

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: Signalling Games In general, a dynamic game of incomplete information is any extensive form game in which at least one player is uninformed about some

More information

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis Natalia Lazzati y November 09, 2013 Abstract We study collective choice models from a revealed preference approach given limited

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Repeated Games

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Repeated Games EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Repeated Games. MWG 9.B.9 Consider the game in which the following simultaneous-move game as depicted in gure is played twice: Player Player 2 b b 2 b

More information

Rent-seeking with Non-Identical Sharing Rules: An Equilibrium Rescued

Rent-seeking with Non-Identical Sharing Rules: An Equilibrium Rescued Rent-seeking with Non-Identical Sharing Rules: An Equilibrium Rescued by Douglas D. Davis and Robert J. Reilly * September 1997 Abstract Nitzan s (1991) analysis of differential sharing rules in a collective

More information

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4 1 Hotelling s model 1.1 Two vendors Game Theory Solutions to Problem Set 4 Consider a strategy pro le (s 1 s ) with s 1 6= s Suppose s 1 < s In this case, it is pro table to for player 1 to deviate and

More information

Academic Editor: Ulrich Berger Received: 12 August 2016 ; Accepted: 5 September 2016 ; Published: 9 September 2016

Academic Editor: Ulrich Berger Received: 12 August 2016 ; Accepted: 5 September 2016 ; Published: 9 September 2016 games Article Payoff Shares in Two-Player Contests Samuel Häfner and Georg Nöldeke * Faculty of Business and Economics, University of Basel, Peter Merian-Weg 6, Basel 400, Switzerland; samuel.haefner@unibas.ch

More information

OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM IN GAMES

OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM IN GAMES OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM IN GAMES Jürgen Eichberger Department of Economics, Universität Heidelberg, Germany David Kelsey Department of Economics University of Exeter, England University of Exeter October

More information

game. Daniel Cardona Universitat de les Illes Balears and CREB Antoni Rubí-Barceló Universitat de les Illes Balears June 1, 2012 Abstract

game. Daniel Cardona Universitat de les Illes Balears and CREB Antoni Rubí-Barceló Universitat de les Illes Balears June 1, 2012 Abstract On the optimality of bargaining outcomes in the Collective-Particularistic multilateral bargaining game. Daniel Cardona Universitat de les Illes Balears and CREB Antoni Rubí-Barceló Universitat de les

More information

A Note on Multi-winner Contest Mechanisms

A Note on Multi-winner Contest Mechanisms A Note on Multi-winner Contest Mechanisms Subhasish M. Chowdhury and Sang-Hyun Kim February 11, 2014 Abstract In this note we consider a realistic multi-winner nested elimination contest in which losers

More information

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Nonlinear Programming (NLP) Natalia Lazzati Mathematics for Economics (Part I) Note 6: Nonlinear Programming - Unconstrained Optimization Note 6 is based on de la Fuente (2000, Ch. 7), Madden (1986, Ch. 3 and 5) and Simon and Blume

More information

Experimentation, Patents, and Innovation

Experimentation, Patents, and Innovation Experimentation, Patents, and Innovation Daron Acemoglu y Kostas Bimpikis z Asuman Ozdaglar x October 2008. Abstract This paper studies a simple model of experimentation and innovation. Our analysis suggests

More information

Contests with Bilateral Delegation: Unobservable Contracts

Contests with Bilateral Delegation: Unobservable Contracts Contests with Bilateral Delegation: Unobservable Contracts by Kyung Hwan Baik and Jihyun Kim Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, September 014, 170(3): 387-405. DOI: 10.168/09345614X13946975834836

More information

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. Caps on Political Lobbying: Reply. Yeon-Koo Che Ian Gale

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. Caps on Political Lobbying: Reply. Yeon-Koo Che Ian Gale Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series Caps on Political Lobbying: Reply Yeon-Koo Che Ian Gale Discussion Paper No.: 0506-15 Department of Economics Columbia University New

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

Negative Advertisement Strategies. Changrong Deng

Negative Advertisement Strategies. Changrong Deng Negative Advertisement Strategies Changrong Deng Saša Pekeµc The Fuqua School of Business, Duke University Preliminary Draft, July PLEASE DO NOT CIRCULATE Abstract We develop a multi-period model of dynamically

More information

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

Limit pricing models and PBE 1 EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Limit pricing models and PBE 1 1 Model Consider an entry game with an incumbent monopolist (Firm 1) and an entrant (Firm ) who analyzes whether or not to join the

More information

SIGNALING IN CONTESTS. Tomer Ifergane and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No November 2017

SIGNALING IN CONTESTS. Tomer Ifergane and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No November 2017 SIGNALING IN CONTESTS Tomer Ifergane and Aner Sela Discussion Paer No. 17-08 November 017 Monaster Center for Economic Research Ben-Gurion University of the Negev P.O. Box 653 Beer Sheva, Israel Fax: 97-8-647941

More information

Endogenous network formation in patent contests and its role as a barrier to entry

Endogenous network formation in patent contests and its role as a barrier to entry Endogenous network formation in patent contests and its role as a barrier to entry Marco Marinucci y Wouter Vergote z October 23, 2009 Abstract In a setting of R&D co-opetition we study, by using an all-pay

More information

Endogenous timing in a mixed duopoly

Endogenous timing in a mixed duopoly Endogenous timing in a mixed duopoly Rabah Amir Department of Economics, University of Arizona Giuseppe De Feo y CORE, Université Catholique de Louvain February 2007 Abstract This paper addresses the issue

More information

Information Sharing in Private Value Lottery Contest

Information Sharing in Private Value Lottery Contest Information Sharing in Private Value Lottery Contest Zenan Wu Jie Zheng May 4, 207 Abstract We investigate players incentives to disclose information on their private valuations of the prize ahead of a

More information

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018 EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 018 Show all your work clearly and make sure you justify all your answers. NAME 1. Consider the market for smart pencil in which only one firm (Superapiz) enjoys a

More information

Spatial Competition and Collaboration Networks

Spatial Competition and Collaboration Networks Spatial Competition and Collaboration Networks Yasunori Okumura y Kanagawa University May, 009 Abstract In this paper, we discuss the formation of collaboration networks among rms that are located in a

More information

8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS

8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS 8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS We have studied competitive markets where there are a large number of rms and each rm takes market prices as given. When a market contain only a few relevant rms, rms may

More information

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

Some Notes on Adverse Selection Some Notes on Adverse Selection John Morgan Haas School of Business and Department of Economics University of California, Berkeley Overview This set of lecture notes covers a general model of adverse selection

More information

The Geometry of Aggregative Games

The Geometry of Aggregative Games The Geometry of Aggregative Games Richard Cornes School of Economics University of Nottingham Nottingham NG2 7RD UK Roger Hartley Economic Studies School of Social Sciences University of Manchester Oxford

More information

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016 Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam # - Answer key Fall 06. [Checking properties of preference relations]. Consider the following preference relation de ned in the positive

More information

THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE

THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE M. J. ALBIZURI*, J. C. SANTOS Abstract. In this paper we introduce a new cost sharing rule-the minimal overlap cost sharing rule-which is associated with the minimal

More information

Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs

Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs Guofu Tan and Okan Yilankaya January 2005 Abstract We investigate equilibria of sealed-bid second price auctions with bidder participation costs

More information

Static Information Design

Static Information Design Static nformation Design Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris European Summer Symposium in Economic Theory, Gerzensee, July 2016 Mechanism Design and nformation Design Mechanism Design: Fix an economic environment

More information

Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective

Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective Alex Possajennikov University of Nottingham January 2012 Abstract Suppose that in aggregative games, in which a player s payoff

More information

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich Volume 30, Issue 3 Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich Abstract The Milgrom-Shannon single crossing property is essential for monotone

More information

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action Moral Hazard: Hidden Action Part of these Notes were taken (almost literally) from Rasmusen, 2007 UIB Course 2013-14 (UIB) MH-Hidden Actions Course 2013-14 1 / 29 A Principal-agent Model. The Production

More information

Learning and Risk Aversion

Learning and Risk Aversion Learning and Risk Aversion Carlos Oyarzun Texas A&M University Rajiv Sarin Texas A&M University January 2007 Abstract Learning describes how behavior changes in response to experience. We consider how

More information

Auctions with Rent Seeking

Auctions with Rent Seeking Auctions with Rent Seeking Marco Haan and Lambert Schoonbeek Department of Economics University of Groningen The Netherlands Abstract We present a model which combines elements of an auction and a rent-seeking

More information

Crowdsourcing contests

Crowdsourcing contests December 8, 2012 Table of contents 1 Introduction 2 Related Work 3 Model: Basics 4 Model: Participants 5 Homogeneous Effort 6 Extensions Table of Contents 1 Introduction 2 Related Work 3 Model: Basics

More information

Information Advantage in Cournot Ol Title Separable Information, or Nondiffer.

Information Advantage in Cournot Ol Title Separable Information, or Nondiffer. Information Advantage in Cournot Ol Title Separable Information, or Nondiffer Author(s) Haimanko, Ori Citation Issue 2009-09 Date Type Technical Report Text Version publisher URL http://hdl.handle.net/10086/17650

More information

Addendum to: International Trade, Technology, and the Skill Premium

Addendum to: International Trade, Technology, and the Skill Premium Addendum to: International Trade, Technology, and the Skill remium Ariel Burstein UCLA and NBER Jonathan Vogel Columbia and NBER April 22 Abstract In this Addendum we set up a perfectly competitive version

More information

Best-shot Versus Weakest-link in Political Lobbying: An Application of Group All-pay Auction *

Best-shot Versus Weakest-link in Political Lobbying: An Application of Group All-pay Auction * Best-shot Versus Weakest-link in Political Lobbying: An Application of Group All-pay Auction * Subhasish M. Chowdhury a and Iryna Topolyan b a School of Economics, Centre for Behavioural and Experimental

More information

Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply

Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply Matthias Kräkel y Anja Schöttner z Abstract It is well-known that, in static models, minimum wages generate positive worker rents and, consequently, ine ciently

More information

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions Some Lecture Notes on Auctions John Morgan Haas School of Business and Department of Economics Uniersity of California, Berkeley Preliminaries Perhaps the most fruitful area for the application of optimal

More information

The Strategic Equivalence of Rent-Seeking, Innovation, and Patent-Race Games

The Strategic Equivalence of Rent-Seeking, Innovation, and Patent-Race Games The Strategic Equivalence of Rent-Seeking, Innovation, and Patent-Race Games MichaelR.Baye Indiana University Heidrun C. Hoppe Universität Hamburg October 21 Abstract Conditions are identified which guarantee

More information

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Egregious Errata Positive Political Theory II (University of Michigan Press, 2005) regrettably contains a variety of obscurities and errors,

More information

Third down with a yard to go : the Dixit-Skeath conundrum on equilibria in competitive games.

Third down with a yard to go : the Dixit-Skeath conundrum on equilibria in competitive games. June 28, 1999 Third down with a yard to go : the Dixit-Skeath conundrum on equilibria in competitive games. Abstract In strictly competitive games, equilibrium mixed strategies are invariant to changes

More information

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods Soc Choice Welfare (1999) 16: 557±567 Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods Lars-Gunnar Svensson Department of Economics, Lund University, P.O. Box 7082, SE-220 07 of Lund, Sweden (e-mail: lars-gunnar.svensson@nek.lu.se)

More information

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection Geethanjali Selvaretnam Abstract This model takes into consideration the fact that depositors

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory COMP323 Introduction to Computational Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Paul G. Spirakis Department of Computer Science University of Liverpool Paul G. Spirakis (U. Liverpool) Introduction to Game

More information

Notes on the Thomas and Worrall paper Econ 8801

Notes on the Thomas and Worrall paper Econ 8801 Notes on the Thomas and Worrall paper Econ 880 Larry E. Jones Introduction The basic reference for these notes is: Thomas, J. and T. Worrall (990): Income Fluctuation and Asymmetric Information: An Example

More information

Econ Review Set 2 - Answers

Econ Review Set 2 - Answers Econ 4808 Review Set 2 - Answers EQUILIBRIUM ANALYSIS 1. De ne the concept of equilibrium within the con nes of an economic model. Provide an example of an economic equilibrium. Economic models contain

More information

Low-Quality Leadership in a Vertically Differentiated Duopoly with Cournot Competition

Low-Quality Leadership in a Vertically Differentiated Duopoly with Cournot Competition Low-Quality Leadership in a Vertically Differentiated Duopoly with Cournot Competition Luca Lambertini Alessandro Tampieri Quaderni - Working Paper DSE N 750 Low-Quality Leadership in a Vertically Di erentiated

More information

Asymmetric Information and Bank Runs

Asymmetric Information and Bank Runs Asymmetric Information and Bank uns Chao Gu Cornell University Draft, March, 2006 Abstract This paper extends Peck and Shell s (2003) bank run model to the environment in which the sunspot coordination

More information

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version)

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) July 4, 2017 1. Person A lexicographically prefers good x to good y, i.e., when comparing two bundles of x and y, she strictly prefers

More information

Contest Functions: Theoretical Foundations and Issues in Estimation

Contest Functions: Theoretical Foundations and Issues in Estimation Contest Functions: Theoretical Foundations and Issues in Estimation Hao Jia, Stergios Skaperdas, and Samarth Vaidya May 14, 2011 Abstract Contest functions (alternatively, contest success functions) determine

More information

On the Complete Information First Price Auction and its Intuitive Solution

On the Complete Information First Price Auction and its Intuitive Solution MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive On the Complete Information First Price Auction and its Intuitive Solution Jose Alcalde and Matthias Dahm University of Alicante, Universitat Rovira i Virgili 14. March

More information

On the level of public good provision in games of redistributive politics

On the level of public good provision in games of redistributive politics On the level of public good provision in games of redistributive politics Benoit S Y Crutzen and Nicolas Sahuguet y September 20 Abstract This paper studies an electoral competition game between two candidates,

More information

1 Extensive Form Games

1 Extensive Form Games 1 Extensive Form Games De nition 1 A nite extensive form game is am object K = fn; (T ) ; P; A; H; u; g where: N = f0; 1; :::; ng is the set of agents (player 0 is nature ) (T ) is the game tree P is the

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information