BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I"

Transcription

1 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA Preliminary version Contents Introduction 1 1. Places and morphisms 8 2. Calculus of fractions Equivalences of categories Birational finite correspondences Triangulated category of irational motives Birational motivic complexes Main theorem Equivalence of categories Aelian schemes Birational motives and locally aelian schemes 49 References 54 Introduction In this article, we try to conciliate two important ideas in algeraic geometry: motives and irational geometry. There are many reasons to do this; the one which motivated us originally was to understand unramified cohomology from a motivic point of view. Although this is not yet achieved in this paper (ut see (2) at the end of this introduction), it led us to rather large developments and surprising structure theorems. For an application of an elementary part of our theory to function fields over finite fields, see [20]. In order to give the reader a rief resumé of our results, we assume familiarity with Voevodsky s construction of his triangulated categories of motives and recall the naturally commutative diagram of categories Date: Octoer 22,

2 2 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA [38, 40], where F is a perfect field Sm(F ) SmCor(F ) ff ff DMgm(F eff ) ff Sm proj (F ) SmCor proj (F ) Chow eff (F ) ff DM eff (F ) in which ff means fully faithful. Here Sm(F ) is the category of smooth connected F -varieties, Sm proj (F ) is its full sucategory consisting of smooth projective varieties, SmCor(F ) is the category of smooth varieties with morphisms finite correspondences, SmCor proj (F ) its full sucategory consisting of smooth projective varieties, Chow eff (F ) the category of effective Chow motives, DMgm(F eff ) the triangulated category of effective geometrical motives and DM eff (F ) the triangulated category of effective motivic complexes (for the Nisnevich topology). Then, for F of characteristic 0, we construct a diagram to which the former maps naturally S 1 S 1 r r Sm(F ) Sr 1 SmCor(F ) ff DMgm(F o ) ff Sm proj (F ) Sr 1 SmCor proj (F ) Chow o (F ) Al T 1 place(f ) op AS(F ) ff DM o (F ) Here means an equivalence of categories, denotes karouian envelope (or pseudo-aelian envelope, or idempotent completion), Sr 1 and T 1 denote localisation with respect to certain sets of morphisms S r and T, place(f ) is the category of function fields over F with morphisms given y F -places, Chow o (F ) is the category of irational Chow motives, DMgm(F o ) the triangulated category of irational geometrical motives, DM (F o ) the triangulated category of rationally invariant motivic complexes and AS(F ) the category of locally aelian schemes. As a very special case, this diagram shows that any function field has a irational Chow motive which is natural with respect to F -places. It also shows that the situation is strikingly simpler in the irational case than in the regular case. In particular, the equivalence etween a localisation of the category of finite correspondences on smooth projective varieties and that of irational Chow motives, although not one of the most difficult results of this paper, is crucial in our proof that the functor Chow o (F ) DMgm(F o ) is fully faithful.

3 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 3 Let us now give a few more details on the various categories introduced aove and some intuition of the situation. First, if one wants to make sense of a irational category, one is confronted at the outset with two different ideas: use the notion of place of Zariski-Samuel [41] or use the geometric idea of a irational map. It turns out that oth ideas work ut give rather different answers. The first idea gives the category place(f ), that we like to call the coarse irational category. For the second idea, one has to e a little careful: the naïve attempt at taking as ojects smooth varieties and as morphisms irational maps does not work ecause, as was pointed out to us y Hélène Esnault, one cannot compose irational maps in general. On the other hand, one can certainly start from the category Sm(F ) and localise it with respect to the multiplicative set S of irational isomorphisms. We like to call the resulting category S 1 Sm(F ) the fine irational category. By hindsight, the prolem mentioned just aove can e understood as a prolem of calculus of fractions in S 1 Sm(F ). These definitions raise the following issues. First, in place(f ), the Hom sets are very ig. Second, in Sm(F ), the set S does not admit calculus of left or right fractions in the sense of Gariel-Zisman [14]. And finally, there is no ovious comparison functor etween the coarse and the fine irational categories at this stage. In order to answer these issues at least to an extent, we introduce an incidence category SmP(F ), whose ojects are smooth connected F - varieties and morphisms from X to Y are given y pairs (f, v), where f is a morphism X Y, v is a place F (Y ) F (X) and f, v are compatile in an ovious sense (see Definition 1.4 elow). This category maps to oth place(f ) op and Sm(F ) y ovious forgetful functors. Denote y Sm proj P(F ) the full sucategory of SmP(F ) consisting of smooth projective varieties. Note that the set S lifts naturally to SmP(F ) and restricts to Sm proj (F ) and Sm proj P(F ) (same notation). Then: Theorem 1 (cf. Theorem 3.8). Assume F of characteristic 0. Then localisation with respect to S yields a naturally commutative diagram of categories, in which vertical functors are equivalences of categories

4 4 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA while horizontal functors are full and essentially surjective: S 1 Sm proj P(F ) S 1 SmP(F ) place(f ) op. S 1 Sm proj (F ) S 1 Sm(F ) In particular, we get a full and essentially surjective functor place(f ) op S 1 Sm(F ), justifying the terminology of coarse and fine irational categories. In the course of the proof, we get that, at least, the first axiom of calculus of right fractions ( Ore condition ) holds for S, which is y no means ovious a priori (see Proposition 3.2). Hence in S 1 Sm(F ) any morphism may e written as a single fraction fs 1, with f a regular map and s S. On the other hand, the second axiom definitely does not hold. If X, Y are two connected smooth projective varieties over F, we get in this way a surjective map from the set of F -places from F (Y ) to F (X) to the set of morphisms from X to Y in S 1 Sm proj (F ). This defines a natural equivalence relation on the first set, which is stale under composition of places. Unfortunately we don t know how to descrie this equivalence relation in concrete terms, and this appears to e a very challenging question. If we now define T to e the multiplicative set of (trivial) places in place(f ) given y purely transcendental extensions of function fields, and S r as the multiplicative set of rational morphisms in Sm(F ), i.e. dominant morphisms such that the corresponding extension of function fields is purely transcendental, then we may localise further the diagram of Theorem 1, getting part of the second diagram in this introduction (see Theorem 3.8). We call the corresponding categories the coarse and fine stale irational categories. Having the aove categories at hand is well and good ut, as for usual algeraic geometry, it is very difficult to compute with them. So we apply the classical idea to enlarge morphisms y adding algeraic correspondences and making the categories additive. In this programme, having Voevodsky s categories in mind, the first logical step (even if for us it came rather late in the development) is to extend part of Theorem 1 to finite correspondences, i.e. to study the functor S 1 SmCor proj (F ) S 1 SmCor(F )

5 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 5 where S denotes the image of S under the natural functor Sm(F ) SmCor(F ), i.e. the multiplicative set of graphs of irational morphisms. In Proposition 4.1, we prove that this functor is an equivalence of categories if F has characteristic zero. (The issue is faithfulness.) Although the idea of the proof is simple (interpret finite correspondences as maps to symmetric powers as in [34]), details are not really straightforward and the proof takes several pages. It uses the category SmP(F ) at a crucial step. Although, in view of the aove, the most natural definition of irational Chow motives would e to localise effective Chow motives with respect to S r, this is not the way we proceed and we go through a more convoluted way, even though in the end our definition coincides with the one just outlined (see Corollary 7.3). We define the category Chow o (F ) as the pseudo-aelian envelope of the quotient of Chow eff (F ) y the ideal I characterised as follows: for X, Y two smooth projective varieties, I(h(X), h(y )) is the sugroup of CH dim Y (X Y ) formed of those correspondences whose restriction to U Y is 0 for some dense open suset U of X. The fact that I is an ideal, i.e. is stale under left and right composition y any correspondence, is not ovious and amounts to a generalisation of the argument in [13, Ex ]. In fact, I is even a monoidal ideal, see Lemma 5.3, which means that the tensor structure of Chow eff (F ) passes to Chow o (F ). In characteristic 0, I can e descried more concretely as the set of those morphisms factoring through an oject of the form M L, where L is the Lefschetz motive; in characteristic p, this remains true at least if one tensors all morphisms with Q (Lemma 5.4). Hence, to otain irational Chow motives, we do something orthogonal to what is done haitually: instead of inverting the Lefschetz motive, we kill it! This rather surprising picture ecomes a little more natural if we consider the parallel one for Voeovdsky s triangulated motives. To get DMgm(F o ), we simply invert open immersions (or, equivalently, the image of S in DMgm(F eff )) and add projectors. The resulting category is a tensor triangulated category. It is easy to see, only assuming F perfect, that DMgm(F o ) = DMgm(F eff )/DMgm(F eff )(1) (Proposition 5.2 )); this is made intuitive y thinking of the Gysin exact triangles. Then one easily sees that the functor Chow eff (F ) DMgm(F eff ) of Voevodsky induces a functor Chow o (F ) DMgm(F o ). The main result of this paper is the computation of Hom( M(X), M(Y )[i]) for two smooth projective varieties X, Y and i Z, where M(X) and M(Y ) denote their motives in DMgm(F o ). It may e stated as follows:

6 6 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA Theorem 2 (cf. Cor. 7.9). a) The functor Chow o (F ) DMgm(F o ) is fully faithful. ) For X, Y, i as aove, we have { Hom( M(X), M(Y CH 0 (Y F (X) ) if i = 0 )[i]) = 0 if i 0. The proof of this theorem is rather intricate. We follow the method Voevodsky used to compute Hom groups in DMgm(F eff ): we introduce another category DM (F o ) of rationally invariant motivic complexes and construct a functor DMgm(F o ) DM (F o ) that we show to e fully faithful. In fact the definition of DM (F o ) is simple: it is the full sucategory of DM eff (F ) consisting of those ojects C such that H i Nis (X, C) H i Nis (U, C) for any dense open immersion of smooth schemes U X. So DM (F o ) is defined naturally as a sucategory of DM eff (F ), while DMgm(F o ) is defined as a quotient of DMgm(F eff ). This is not surprising, as DM eff (F ) is a sucategory of the category of functors from DMgm(F eff ) to aelian groups. However, we have to show that the emedding (1) i : DM o (F ) DM eff (F ) has a left adjoint ν 0. This is done fairly easily in Lemma 6.6. The fact that Voevodsky s full emedding DMgm(F eff ) DM eff (F ) descends to a full emedding DMgm(F o ) DM (F o ) is then formal (Theorem 6.7). At this point, it remains to compute the group Hom( M(X), M(Y )[i]) within DM (F o ). This turns out to e very delicate and we can only refer the reader to Section 7 for the proof. We end this paper y relating the previous constructions to more classical ojects. We define a tensor additive category AS(F ) of locally aelian schemes, whose ojects are those F -group schemes that are extensions of a lattice (i.e. locally isomorphic for the étale topology to a free finitely generated aelian group) y an aelian variety. We then show that the classical construction of the Alanese variety of a smooth projective variety extends to a tensor functor Al : Chow o (F ) AS(F ) which ecomes full and essentially surjective after tensoring morphisms y Q (Proposition 10.2). So, one could say that AS(F ) is the representale part of Chow o (F ). We also show that, after tensoring with Q, Al has a right adjoint-right inverse, which identifies AS(F ) Q

7 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 7 with the thick sucategory of Chow o (F ) Q generated y motives of varieties of dimension 1. This work is only the eginning of our investigations on irational motives. Let us just mention for the moment future lines of research: (1) Structure of DMgm(F o ). In the course of the proof of theorem 2, we realise Chow o (F ) as the sucategory of compact ojects in the aelian category HI o (F ) of rationally invariant Nisnevich sheaves with transfers (Propositions 7.2 and 7.4). In particular, this descries Chow o (F ) as an exact sucategory of an aelian category. What is the relationship etween DMgm(F o ) and the ounded derived category of Chow o (F )? (2) Where does unramified cohomology enter this picture? Expected answer: it should e a right adjoint to the functor i of (1). (3) We hope to use this formalism to study the unramified cohomology of BG, where G is a linear algeraic group. (4) Is it true that i(dmgm(f o )) DMgm(F eff ) and that i(chow o (F )) Chow eff (F )? This question was asked y Luca Barieri-Viale and is expected to e difficult to answer: it is closely related to a conjecture of Voevodsky [37, Conj ]. We expect this to e true after tensoring with Q. At the very least, the second statement ecomes true (and easy) if one replaces Chow motives y numerical motives, cf. [20, Prop. 1]. (5) The localisation of the Morel-Voevodsky A 1 -homotopy category of schemes H(F ) [23] with respect to S r should e studied, as well as that of Voevodsky s effective stale A 1 -homotopy category of schemes. For the latter, this is very likely any chunk of the slice filtration of [39]; this analogy was pointed out to us y Chuck Weiel. (6) The relationship etween these ideas and the proofs that the Bloch-Kato conjecture implies the Beilinson-Lichtenaum conjecture [35, 15, 16, 19] should definitely e investigated: a start is given in [19, Def and Lemma 2.15]. The est context for this seems to e in the previous item. (7) Equally the relationship with Déglise s category of generic motives [8, 9]: at this point it is not completely clear what this relationship is. (8) Finally, the exact relationship etween the category Chow o (F ) and Beilinson s correspondences at the generic point [3] should e investigated as well.

8 8 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA Acknowledgements. We would like to thank Shreeram Ayankhar, Luca Barieri-Viale, Jean-Louis Colliot-Thélène, Frédéric Déglise, Hélène Esnault, Eric Friedlander, Jens Hornostel, Annette Huer-Klawitter, Bernhard Keller, Georges Maltsiniotis, Faien Morel, Amnon Neeman, Michel Vaquié, Vladimir Voevodsky and Chuck Weiel for various discussions and exchanges while writing this paper. Notation. F is the ase field. All varieties are F -varieties and all morphisms are F -morphisms. If X is irreducile, η X denotes its generic point. 1. Places and morphisms 1.1. Definition. Let K/F and L/F e two extensions. An F -place from K to L is a pair v formed of a valuation ring O of K/F (i.e. F O K) and an F -homomorphism M L, where M is the residue field of O. We write O = O v and M = F (v). Composition of places defines the category place(f ) with ojects finitely generated extensions of F and morphisms F -places Remark. If v : K L is a morphism in place(f ), then its residue field F (v) is finitely generated over F, as a sufield of the finitely generated field L. On the other hand, given a finitely generated extension K/F, there exist valuation rings of K/F with infinitely generated residue fields as soon as trdeg(k/f ) > 1, cf. [41, Ch. VI, 15, Ex. 4] Lemma. Let f, g : X Y e two morphisms, with X integral and Y separated. Then f = g if and only if f(η X ) = g(η X ) =: y and f, g induce the same map F (y) F (X) on the residue fields. Proof. Let ϕ : X Y F Y e given y (f, g). Then the diagonal Y is closed, so Ker(f, g) = ϕ 1 ( Y ) is closed in X and contains η X (compare [EGA, Ch. I, Prop and Cor ]) Definition. Let X, Y e two integral varieties, with Y separated, f : X Y a morphism and v : F (Y ) F (X) a place. We say that f and v are compatile if v is finite on Y (i.e. has a centre in Y ). The corresponding diagram η X X v Spec O v f Y

9 commutes. BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I Remark. Any morphism which is a irational isomorphism is compatile with the identical place. This applies in particular to open immersions Proposition. Let X, Y, v e as in Definition 1.4. Suppose that v is finite on Y, and let y Y e its centre. Then a morphism f : X Y is compatile with v if and only if y = f(η X ) and the diagram of fields F (v) v f F (y) F (X) commutes. In particular, there is at most one such f. Proof. Suppose v and f compatile. Then y = f(η X ) ecause v (η X ) is the closed point of Spec O v. The commutation of the diagram then follows from the one in Definition 1.4. Conversely, if f verifies the two conditions, then it is oviously compatile with v. The last assertion follows from Lemma Corollary. a) Let Y e an integral variety, and let O e a valuation ring of F (Y )/F with residue field K and centre y Y. Assume that F (y) K. Then, for any morphism f : X Y with X integral, such that f(η X ) = y, there exists a unique place v : F (Y ) F (X) with valuation ring O which is compatile with f. ) If f is an immersion, the condition F (y) K is also necessary for the existence of v. The following lemma generalises Remark 1.5: 1.8. Lemma. Let f : X Y e dominant. Then f is compatile with the trivial place F (Y ) F (X), and this place is the only one with which f is compatile. Proof. This follows immediately from Proposition Proposition. Let f : X Y, g : Y Z e two morphisms of integral separated varieties. Let v : F (Y ) F (X) and w : F (Z) F (Y ) e two places. Suppose that f and v are compatile and that g and w are compatile. Then g f and v w are compatile.

10 10 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA Proof. diagram We first show that v w is finite on Z. By definition, the η Y w Spec O w Spec O v Spec O v w is cocartesian. Since the two compositions η Y w Spec O w Z and η Y Spec O v Y g Z coincide (y the compatiility of g and w), there is a unique induced (dominant) map Spec O v w Z. In the diagram η X v Spec O v f Spec O v w X Y Z the left square commutes y compatiility of f and v, and the right square commutes y construction. Therefore the ig rectangle commutes, which means that g f and v w are compatile Definition. We denote y SmP(F ) the following category: Ojects are smooth F -schemes of finite type. Let X, Y SmP(F ). A morphism ϕ SmP(X, Y ) is a pair (v, f) with f : X Y, v : F (Y ) F (X) and v, f compatile. The composition of morphisms is given y Proposition 1.9. We denote y Sm proj P(F ) the full sucategory of SmP(F ) consisting of smooth projective varieties Lemma. Let f : X Y e a morphism from an integral variety to a regular variety. Then there is a place v : F (Y ) F (X) compatile with f. Proof. Let y = f(η X ). The local ring A = O Y,y is regular: By Corollary 1.7 a), it is sufficient to produce a valuation ring O containing A and with the same residue field as A. The following construction is certainly classical. Let m e the maximal ideal of A and let (x 1,..., x d ) e a regular sequence generating m, with d = dim A = codim Y y. For 0 i < j d + 1, let A i,j = A[x 1 1,..., x 1 i ]/(x j,..., x d ) (for i = 0 we invert no x k, and for j = d+1 we mod out no x k ). Then, for any (i, j), A i,j is a regular local g

11 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 11 ring of dimension j i 1. In particular, F i = A i,i+1 is the residue field of A i,j for any j i + 1. We have A 0,d+1 = A and there are ovious maps A i,j A i+1,j A i,j A i,j 1 (injective) (surjective). Consider the discrete valuation v i associated to the discrete valuation ring A i,i+2 : it defines a place, still denoted y v i, from F i+1 to F i. The composition of these places is a place v from F d = F (Y ) to F 0 = F (y), whose valuation ring dominates A and whose residue field is clearly F (y) Lemma. Suppose F perfect. Let place(f ) e the category of function fields over F with morphisms the F -places, and let Sm(F ) e the category of integral separated F -schemes of finite type. There are forgetful essentially surjective functors SmP(F ) Φ 2 Φ 1 Sm(F ) place(f ) op with Φ 1 full and Φ 2 faithful. The restriction of Φ 2 to Sm proj P(F ) is essentially surjective when F is of characteristic 0. Proof. The definitions and essential surjectivity of Φ 1 and Φ 2 are ovious. The restricted case of essential surjectivity for Φ 2 is clear y Hironaka s resolution of singularities. The fullness of Φ 1 follows from Lemma 1.11 and the faithfulness of Φ 2 follows from Proposition Lemma. Let Z, Z e two models of a function field K, with Z separated, and v a place of K with centres z, z respectively on Z and Z. Assume that there is a morphism g : Z Z which is a irational isomorphism. Then g(z) = z. Proof. Let f : Spec O v Z e the dominant map determined y z. Then f = g f is a dominant map Spec O v Z. By the valuative criterion of separatedness, it must correspond to z.

12 12 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA Lemma. Consider a diagram Z f X g f with g a irational isomorphism. Let K = F (X), L = F (Z) = F (Z ) and suppose given a place v : L K compatile oth with f and f. Then f = g f. Proof. This follows from Proposition 1.6 and Lemma Lemma. Let X, Y, v, y e as in Proposition 1.6. Then there exists an open suset U X and a morphism f : U Y compatile with v. Proof. Let V = Spec R e an affine neighourhood of y in Y, so that R O v, and let S e the image of R in F (v). Choose a finitely generated F -sualgera T of F (X) containing S, with quotient field F (X). Then X = Spec T is an affine model of F (X)/F. The composition X Spec S V Y is then compatile with v. Its restriction to a common open suset U of X and X defines the desired map f Definition. A projective irational isomorphism f : X Y of smooth varieties will e called an astract low-up. The isomorphism locus of f is the largest open suset U of Y such that f : f 1 (U) U is an isomorphism. The complement Z of U is the centre of f: it is considered as a reduced suscheme of X. The following proposition strengthens Lemma Proposition. a) Let v : L K e a morphism in place(f ), and let Y e a projective model of L. Then there exists a normal projective model X of K and a morphism f : X Y compatile with v. If F is perfect, we may choose X smooth affine instead. If char F = 0, we may choose X smooth projective. ) Suppose that char F = 0, and let X 0 e a smooth projective model of K. Then there exists another smooth projective model X 1 of K, an astract low-up u : X 1 X 0 and a map f 1 : X 1 Y compatile with v. Proof. a) By the valuative criterion of properness, v has a centre y in Y. Let N = F (y) e the residue field of y: it maps into K y v. Z

13 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 13 Let Z = {y}: this is a projective model of N. Choose a projective model X 0 of K/N and spread X 0 Spec N to a projective map X 1 Z. Then X 1 is projective. Let X e the normalisation of X 1. The composition X X 1 Z Y is clearly compatile with v. If F is perfect, we may replace X y a smooth dense open suset. Finally, if char F = 0, we may take X 0 projective and end y desingularising X 1 instead of normalising it. ) Let U e a common open suset to X and X 0 (where X has een constructed in a)). We may view U as diagonally emedded into X X 0. Let X 1 e a desingularisation of the closure of U in X X 0 : we have a diagram of astract low-ups X 1 u g X X 0. By Proposition 1.9, f 1 = f g is compatile with v. 2. Calculus of fractions Let C e a category and S a set of morphisms of C. Recall from [14, I.1] the category C[S 1 ] and the canonical functor P S : C C[S 1 ]: P S is universal among functors from C that render all arrows of S invertile. We shall denote y S the set of morphisms s of C such that P S (s) is invertile: this is the saturation of S. Recall (loc. cit., I.2) that S admits a calculus of left fractions when it verifies the following conditions: (1) The identities are in S; S is stale under composition. (2) Each diagram (2.1) X s u Y X where s S can e completed in a commutative diagram X s u Y s X u Y

14 14 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA with s S. (3) If f, g : X Y are two morphisms and if s : X X is a morphism of S such that fs = gs, there exists a morphism t : Y Y of S such that tf = tg: X s X f g Y t Y. Under calculus of left fractions, the category C[S 1 ] has a very nice description S 1 C (loc. cit. I.2.3). In this article, we shall encounter situations where Condition 2 is verified only for certain pairs (u, s) and where Condition 3 is not verified. This leads us to give more careful definitions Definition. A pair (u, s) as in Condition 2 aove admits a calculus of left fractions within S if there exists a pair (u, s ) as in the said condition. It admits cocartesian calculus of left fractions within S if the pushout of (2.1) exists and provides such a pair (u, s ). We won t repeat the dual definitions for calculus of right fractions. 3. Equivalences of categories In this section, we assume that char F = 0. We shall work with several multiplicative susets of Sm(F ) and Sm proj (F ): S o = {open immersions}. S = {irational isomorphisms}. S p = {projective morphisms in S }. S h = the multiplicative suset generated y morphisms of the form X A 1 pr 1 X. S r = {rational isomorphisms} (a morphism is a rational isomorphism if the corresponding extension of function fields is purely transcendental). Sr p = {projective morphisms in S r }. For S of this form, we also write S for the multiplicative suset of SmP(F ) or Sm proj P(F ) formed y the pairs (v, f) with f S. We shall write S 1 C for the localisation of a category instead of the heavier notation C[S 1 ], even when there is no calculus of fractions Lemma. a) We have the inclusions S o S S o and S S r. In particular, So 1 Sm(F ) = S 1 Sm(F ) and So 1 SmP(F ) = S 1 SmP(F ). ) Suppose char F = 0. In SmP(F ), any morphism of Sr p can e covered y the composition of a morphism in S p and morphisms of the form X P 1 pr 1 X.

15 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 15 Proof. a) is ovious. For ), we can forget aout places thanks to Lemma 1.8. Let s : X Y Sr p. By assumption, X is irationally equivalent to X = Y (P 1 ) n for some n 0. We proceed as usual: let U e a common open suset of X and X and X the closure of the diagonal emedding of U in X Y X. Then X is also a model of F (X). Since s and pr 1 : Y (P 1 ) n Y are projective, so is the composition X X Y X Y. It remains to resolve the singularities of X via a succession of low-ups Proposition. Let X u Y e a diagram in SmP(F ), with s S p (resp. s Sp r ). Then (u, s) admits calculus of right fractions within S p (resp. within Sr p ). The same holds in Sm(F ). Proof. Note that the statement for Sm(F ) follows from the case of SmP(F ), thanks to Lemma Moreover, the case of Sr p follows from that of S p y Lemma 3.1 ), since calculus of fractions is ovious for a morphism of the form X P 1 X. Here is the proof for S p SmP(F ). Let v : F (Y ) F (X) e the place compatile with u which is implicit in the statement. By assumption v has a centre z on Y. Since s is proper, v therefore has also a centre z on Y. By Lemma 1.13, s(z ) = z. Hence we have inclusions of fields (3.1) F (z) F (z ) F (v) F (X). Let Z = {z} and Z = {z }. The map u factors through a map ū : X Z. The chain (3.1) shows that ū lifts to a rational map from X to Z. Blowing up X suitaly, we get a commutative diagram X ū Y Z Y s s ū X Z Y in which s is an astract low-up; moreover, the composition u : X Y is compatile with v (compare Corollary 1.7 )) Lemma. Any morphism in S 1 SmP(F ) of the form fj 1 with j an open immersion is equal to a morphism of the form a 1 gp 1, where p is an astract low-up and a, are open immersions. s

16 16 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA Proof. Consider a diagram j X U f where j is an open immersion. Choose open emeddings a : Y Ȳ and : X X, with X, Ȳ smooth projective. This reduces us to the case where X and Y are projective. By proposition 1.17, choose a smooth projective model X of F (X) and a morphism f : X Y compatile with the underlying place v. Let X e a third smooth projective model of F (X) mapping oth to X and X, and let U e a common open suset of X, X and X contained in U: U j f f X U Y. j p j X p X By Lemma 1.14, all paths in this diagram commute. Hence we find f fj 1 = f p p Lemma. In S 1 SmP(F ), any morphism q S r can e written in the form q = j 1 qp 1 j with j, j S o, p S p and q Sp. Same statement within S 1 r SmP(F ) for q S r, with q Sr p. Proof. We don t need to take care of the places, thanks to Lemma 1.8. Let us prove the first statement. By resolution of singularities, we can find a commutative diagram Y X j X j 1 p q j 2 Y U X1 j q Ȳ

17 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 17 where j, j, j 1, j 2 are open immersions, X, X1 and Ȳ are smooth projective, p is an astract low-up and q Sr p. Lemma 3.4 now follows from a small computation. The proof of the second statement is exactly the same Proposition. Any morphism in S 1 SmP(F ) can e written as j 1 fq 1, with j S o and q S p. Same statement for S 1 r SmP(F ), with q Sr p. Proof. We first show that any morphism in either category can e written as a composition of morphisms of the form j 1 fq 1 as in the statement of Proposition 3.5. It is sufficient to prove this for a morphism of the form fq 1, with q S (resp. q S r ). Write q = j 1 qp 1 j as in Lemma 3.4. Then we have fq 1 = fj 1 p q 1 j with j, j S o, p S p and q Sp (resp. q Sp r ). Applying now Lemma 3.3 to fj 1, we get fq 1 = a 1 gp 1 p q 1 j = (a 1 gp 1 )(p q 1 )j with a, S o and p S p. It now suffices to prove that the composition j1 1 f 1 q1 1 j2 1 f 2 q2 1 of two morphisms of this form is still of this form. By Lemma 3.4, write j 2 q 1 = j 1 q 3 p 1 j 3, with j 3, j S o, p S p and q 3 S p, so that f 1 q 1 1 j 1 2 = f 1 j 1 3 pq 1 3 j. By Lemma 3.3, write f 1 j3 1 = a 1 gp 1 1, where p 1 S p and a, S o, so that f 1 j3 1 pq3 1 j = a 1 gp 1 1 pq3 1 j and j1 1 f 1 q1 1 j2 1 f 2 q2 1 = j1 1 a 1 gp 1 1 pq3 1 j f 2 q2 1. It now suffices to apply Proposition 3.2 twice Proposition. Consider a diagram in Sm proj P(F ) Z f p X Y f p Z

18 18 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA where p and p are astract low-ups. Let K = F (Z) = F (Z ) = F (Y ), L = F (X) and suppose given a place v : L K compatile oth with f and f. Then (v, fp 1 ) = (v, f p 1 ) in S 1 Sm proj P(F ). Proof. Complete the diagram as follows: Z f p p 1 X Z Y p 1 f p Z where p 1 and p 1 are astract low-ups and Z is smooth. Then we have pp 1 = p p 1, fp 1 = f p 1 (the latter y Lemma 1.14), hence the claim Definition. We extend the functor Φ 2 of Lemma 1.12 to functors Φ 2 : S 1 SmP(F ) place(f ) op Φ r 2 : Sr 1 SmP(F ) T 1 place(f ) op via Remark 1.5, where T is the multiplicative set of morphisms in place(f ) given y rational extensions. Let also JP : Sm proj P(F ) SmP(F ) J : Sm proj (F ) Sm(F ) denote the inclusion functors. Finally, we recall the forgetful functor Φ 1 : SmP(F ) Sm(F ) and its restriction to Sm proj P(F ), denoted y the same letter Theorem. The functors Φ 2, S 1 JP, Φ 2 S 1 JP and S 1 J are equivalences of categories, while the two functors S 1 Φ 1 are full and

19 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 19 essentially surjective: S 1 Sm proj P(F ) S S 1 JP S Φ 1 SmP(F ) S Φ 1 Φ 2 place(f ) op. S 1 Sm proj (F ) S 1 J S 1 Sm(F ) The same holds y replacing Φ 2 y Φ r 2 and S y S r : S 1 r Sm proj P(F ) S 1 r Φ 1 S 1 r JP S 1 r SmP(F ) S 1 r Φ 1 Φ r 2 T 1 place(f ) op. S 1 r Sm proj (F ) S 1 r J S 1 r Sm(F ) Proof. It is enough to prove the first assertion: the second one follows y localising the first with respect to S r. A) We first prove that Φ 2 S 1 JP is an equivalence of categories. By Lemma 1.12, this functor is essentially surjective. Proposition 1.17 shows that it is full. It remains to see that it is faithful. Let us construct a functor Ψ : place(f ) S 1 Sm proj P(F ) o as follows: To a function field K we associate a smooth projective model Ψ(K), chosen once and for all. Let v : L K e a place. By Proposition 1.17, there exists a pair (f, p) with f : X 1 Ψ(L) compatile with v and p : X 1 Ψ(K) an astract low-up. We define Ψ(v) as (v, fp 1 ). The map v Ψ(v) is well-defined y Proposition 3.6. To prove that it respects composition, consider two composale places K v L w

20 20 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA M and the following diagram X 3 h r Ψ(M) Ψ(L) Ψ(K) q p g f X 2 X 1 with (v, fp 1 ) = Ψ(v), (w, gq 1 ) = Ψ(w) and (wv, hr 1 ) = Ψ(wv). We may complete it into a commutative diagram X 3 h r q 1 Ψ(M) Ψ(L) Ψ(K) X 4 q p g f X 2 X 1 q f Y where q, q 1, r 1 S p (the existence of (f, q ) comes from Proposition 3.2). The equality Ψ(wv) = Ψ(v)Ψ(w) now easily follows from this diagram. The equality Φ 2Sr 1 JP Ψ = Id is ovious and Ψ is clearly full. Therefore Φ 2S 1 JP is faithful, hence an equivalence of categories (with quasi-inverse Ψ). B) We now prove that S 1 JP is an equivalence of categories. The aove shows that it is faithful, and it is also essentially surjective thanks to resolution of singularities. It remains to see that it is full. By Proposition 3.5, for two ojects X, Y S 1 SmP(F ), any morphism ϕ : X Y is of the form j 1 fp 1 with j an open immersion and p a projective rational map. If Y is projective, j is necessarily an isomorphism. If furthermore X is projective, the source of p is projective too. Hence ϕ comes from S 1 Sm proj P(F ), as desired. C) Now the functor Φ 1 : SmP(F ) Sm(F ) is full and essentially surjective y Lemma 1.12, and this is preserved y localisation. Similarly for its restriction to Sm proj P(F ). As a consequence, S 1 J is full (and essentially surjective). r 1

21 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 21 D) It remains to show that S 1 J is faithful. For this, we proceed exactly as in A): define a functor Π : Sm(F ) S 1 Sm proj (F ) y sending a smooth connected variety X to a smooth compactification Π(X) chosen once and for all, and a map f : X Y to a map Π(f) = s 1 f, where s : X Π(X) is a suitale astract low-up with centre disjoint from X and f : X Π(Y ) restricts to f on s 1 (X) = X. By an analogous statement to Proposition 3.6, Π(f) is well-defined. That Π is indeed a functor now is proven exactly as in A), y using Proposition 3.2, and Π is oviously full. Then Π factors through S 1 Sm(F ) into a full functor, which is a quasi-inverse to S 1 J Definition. We call place(f ) the coarse irational category of F and S 1 Sm proj (F ) the fine irational category of F. Similarly, we call T 1 place(f ) the coarse stale irational category of F and Sr 1 Sm proj (F ) the fine stale irational category of F. By Theorem 3.8, we have a commutative diagram of categories and functors place(f ) op Φ1 S 1 Sm proj (F ) T 1 place(f ) op T 1 Φ 1 S 1 r Sm proj (F ) where the horizontal functors are full and essentially surjective. 4. Birational finite correspondences We shall need the following proposition, which is an additive analogue of part of Theorem 3.8, in Section 6: 4.1. Proposition. Let SmCor(F ) e Voevodsky s category of finite correspondences on smooth varieties [38], and let SmCor proj (F ) e its full sucategory consisting of smooth projective varieties. Let J denote the inclusion functor SmCor proj (F ) SmCor(F ). Let further S SmCor(F ) e the set of [graphs of] morphisms that are irational isomorphisms, as well as its restriction to SmCor proj (F ). Then the equivalence of categories S 1 J of Theorem 3.8 extends to an equivalence of categories S 1 J : S 1 SmCor proj (F ) S 1 SmCor(F ) via the canonical functors Sm(F ) SmCor(F ) and Sm proj (F ) SmCor proj (F ). The same holds when replacing S y S r.

22 22 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA The proof will occupy the entire section. Proof. We limit ourselves to S, the proofs for S r eing exactly the same. The functor S 1 J is clearly full and essentially surjective. We prove its faithfulness y constructing a quasi-inverse. In order to do this, we proceed using the notation and arguments as in part D) of the proof of Theorem 3.8. Thus we first extend the functor Π of loc. cit.to an additive functor Π : SmCor(F ) S 1 SmCor proj (F ). Given two smooth varieties X, Y, we need to define a homomorphism Π : c(x, Y ) S 1 SmCor proj (F )(Π(X), Π(Y )). Since the left-hand side is y definition the free aelian group on the set (X, Y ) of closed integral suschemes of X Y which are finite and surjective over a connected component of X, it would e sufficient to define a map Π : (X, Y ) S 1 SmCor proj (F )(Π(X), Π(Y )). To check functoriality, however, it will e more convenient to define Π directly on the monoid of positive correspondences 1 c + (X, Y ) = N(X, Y ), and to check that it is additive. We shall use the idea of Suslin-Voevodsky [34]: a cycle Z (X, Y ) of generic degree d over X defines a map [Z] : X S d (Y ). This rule extends to a homomorphism of aelian monoids (4.1) c + (X, Y ) n 0 Map F (X, S n (Y )) which is an isomorphism y [34, Th. 6.8] (ecause F is of characteristic 0). Let then Z c + (X, Y ), and [Z] : X S d (Y ) the corresponding map. Composing with the open immersion Y Π(Y ), we get a map X S d (Π(Y )). Consider its graph Γ in X S d (Π(Y )) and its closure Γ in Π(X) S d (Π(Y )). Clearly Γ is projective and irational to X (since the projection Γ X is an isomorphism). Desingularising it, we get s : X Π(X) with s S and a map f : X S d (Π(Y )) 1 We prefer to use the term positive rather than effective, in order not to create a possile confusion with effective motives later in this text.

23 extending f on some open suset of X: BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 23 X f s Π(X) Γ S d (Π(Y )). f Γ X On the other hand, y the ijectivity of (4.1), f corresponds to a unique positive cycle c c + ( X, Π(Y )). We may now define Π(Z) = cγ 1 s. We now proceed to check successively various compatiilities: 1) If Z is the graph Γ f of a morphism f : X Y, then d = 1 and [Z] = f, so we get exactly the same construction as in part D) of the proof of Theorem ) We check that cγ 1 s is independent of the choice of X. This follows from an argument analogous to that in Proposition 3.6. Indeed, if X 1 and X 2 are two different astract low-ups which give maps f 1 and f 2 into S d (Π(Y )), then we have a diagram as follows where t 1, t 2 are astract low-ups and hence t 1, t 2 S : f 1 t 1 S d (Π(Y )) f 2 X 1 s 1 X3 Π(X) s 2 X 2 t 2 If c 1, c 2 are the positive cycles corresponding to f 1 and f 2, then we have c 1 Γ t1 = c 2 Γ t2 in SmCor(F ), and also s 1 t 1 = s 2 t 2, hence c 1 Γ 1 s 1 = c 2 Γ 1 s 2. 3) We now check that Π(Z+Z ) = Π(Z)+Π(Z ) for two positive finite correspondences Z and Z. Let f : X S d (Y ) and f : X S d (Y ) e the two corresponding maps. Then to Z + Z is associated the composite f : X (f,f ) S d (Y ) S d (Y ) S d+d (Y ).

24 24 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA Let s : X Π(X) and s : X Π(X) e two irational isomorphisms chosen as aove respectively for f and for f, and let t : X X, t : X X e two astract low-ups ( X smooth projective), defining two equal compositions s = s t = s t : X Π(X). Then we get a diagram X (f,f ) S d (Y ) S d (Y ) S d+d (Y ) Π(X) S d (Π(Y )) S d (Π(Y )) S d+d (Π(Y )) (ft,f t ) s X Let f : X S d+d (Π(Y )) e the composition from this diagram. Then, y 2), Π(Z + Z ) corresponds to f s 1, and the diagram concludes the check of 3). 4) We check that Π is a functor. Let α c + (X, Y ) and β c + (Y, Z) e positive correspondences, with f : X S d (Y ) (where d = n i [F (U i ) : F (X)] if α = n i α i with α i irreducile with supports U i in X Y ), and g : Y S k (Z) the corresponding maps coming from the Suslin-Voevodsky isomorphism Lemma. The composition β α c + (X, Z) maps under (4.1) to the composite X f S d (Y ) S d (g) S d (S k (Z)) S dk (Z). Proof. (Friedlander and Voevodsky) We give it using that F is of characteristic 0, although this assumption is proaly not necessary (Faien Morel has indicated us that he has a proof ased on the results of [34], at least after inverting the exponential characteristic). We have to show that the image of β α in Map F (X, S dk (Z)) equals S d (g) f. We may assume X connected. Let η = Spec K e its generic point. Since Map F (X, S dk (Z/F )) Map F (η, S dk (Z/F )) = Map K (Spec K, S dk (Z K /K)), we may assume that X = Spec F. Then Map F (Spec F, S dk (Z)) is the set of positive zero-cycles of degree dk on Z. Since F is of characteristic 0, this set injects into Map F (Spec F, S dk (Z F )) and we further reduce to the case where F is algeraically closed and finally where α

25 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 25 is irreducile. Then it corresponds to a rational point of Y, d = 1 and the claim is ovious. With notation as aove, we now have a (not very) commutative diagram: X Π(X) f S d (Y ) s f S d (Π(Y )) X S d (g) S d (S k (Z)) S d (t) S d (Ỹ ) S d ( g) S d (S k (Π(Z)) S dk (Z) S dk (Π(Z)) and the proof will e finished if we can complete it into a (rather more) commutative diagram X Π(X) f S d (Y ) S d (g) S d (S k (Z)) s f S d (Π(Y )) S d (t) S d (S k (Π(Z)) S d ( g) X u X h S d (Ỹ ) S dk (Z) S dk (Π(Z))

26 26 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA where X is smooth and u is a irational isomorphism. (The commutativity means that S d (t)h = fu, or equivalently S d (t) 1 f = hu 1, which implies S d ( g) S d (t) 1 fs 1 = S d ( g)hu 1 s 1.) This means extending Proposition 3.2 to a case (with its notation) where X and Y are not smooth. Examining the proof of this proposition, still with its notation, smoothness is irrelevant everywhere provided we have a place v compatile with u. Referring to Lemma 1.11, we do use that Y is regular. However, all we use is that u(η X ) is a regular point of Y. Therefore, coming ack to the aove notation, the proof of Proposition 4.1 will e complete if we can prove that f(η X ) is a smooth point of S d (Π(Y )). But this point is the image of f(η X ) y the open immersion S d (Y ) S d (Π(Y )), so it suffices to know that f(η X ) is a smooth point of S d (Y ). For any scheme T (over some ase), let Ũd (T ) e the open suset of T d defined y the conditions that all coordinates are distinct, and let U d (T ) e the image of Ũd (T ) in S d (T ): the projection Ũd (T ) U d (T ) is finite étale. If T is smooth, U d (T ) is smooth as well. Note that if i : S T is an immersion, then the immersion S d (i) carries U d (S) into U d (T ). Therefore, to check 4) we are reduced to proving the following 4.3. Lemma. Let U X e a finite surjective morphism of schemes, with U integral and X normal connected. Let d = [κ(u) : κ(x)], and assume the extension κ(x)/κ(u) separale. Then the Suslin-Voevodsky map [34, p. 81] X S d (U) sends the generic point η X in U d (U). Note that the assumption char F = 0 is needed to e ale to apply Lemma 4.3! Proof. We have a commutative diagram η X S d (η U ) X S d (U). Since the vertical maps are immersions, we are reduced to the case where X, hence U, is the spectrum of a field, say X = Spec K, U = Spec L. We shall prove the lemma in the slightly more general case where L is an étale K-algera. Suppose first that L = K d. Let x 1,..., x d e the d rational points Spec K Spec L. Then the image of Spec K in S d (Spec L)

27 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 27 is (x 1,..., x d ), which is clearly in U d (Spec L). In general, we reduce to this case y passing to a separale closure of K. S 1 5) Finally we need to check that Π induces a functor S 1 SmCor(F ) SmCor proj (F ), i.e. that Π(Γ s ) is invertile if s S. This follows immediately from 1). The fact that Π is a quasi-inverse to S 1 immediate. 5. Triangulated category of irational motives J is In this section, we construct a triangulated category of irational geometric motives and an additive category of irational Chow motives, and construct a functor from the second to the first. We assume that the reader is familiar with Voevodsky s triangulated categories of motives [38]; for a smooth variety X over F, we simplify his notation M gm (X) into M(X) for the motive of X in DM eff gm(f ) Definition. We denote y DMgm(F o ) the pseudo-aelian envelope of the quotient of DMgm(F eff ) [38] y the thick triangulated sucategory C generated y the cones of maps M(U) j M(X) where X is a smooth variety and j is an open immersion. We denote y M(X) the image of M(X) in DM o gm(f ). By [2], DM o gm(f ) is still triangulated Proposition. a) The tensor structure of DMgm(F eff ) passes to DMgm(F o ). ) Suppose F perfect. Then C consists of those motives of the form M(1) and the functor DMgm(F eff ) C given y M M(1) is an equivalence of categories. Proof. a) Recall that the category DMgm(F eff ) is generated y the M(Y ) (Y smooth) and there is a canonical isomorphism M(X 1 X 2 ) M(X 1 ) M(X 2 ). Clearly the tensor structure is compatile on further localising with respect to morphisms M(U) M(X) where U X is an open immersion. ) Since Z Z(1)[2] = M(P 1 ) = M(A 1 ) = Z in DMgm(F o ), Z(1) = 0 in DMgm(F o ). By a), DMgm(F o ) is therefore a localisation of DMgm(F eff )/C. To see conversely that Ker(DMgm(F eff ) DMgm(F o )) C, we have to j prove that cone(m(u) M(X)) is in C for any open immersion j. We argue y Noetherian induction on the (reduced) closed complement Z in a standard way. If Z is smooth of pure codimension

28 28 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA c, then the cone is isomorphic to M(Z)(c)[2c] [38, Prop ]. In general, let Z sing Z e the singular locus of Z. Then Z Z sing is smooth in X Z sing. Let C and C denote respectively cones of the maps M(U) M(X) and M(X Z sing ) M(X). By the axioms of triangulated categories, we may complete the diagram M(U) M(U) M(X Z sing ) M(X) C M(Z Z sing )(c)[2c] M(U)[1] C M(U)[1] into a commutative diagram of exact triangles M(U) M(U) 0 M(X Z sing ) M(X) C M(Z Z sing )(c)[2c] C C M(U)[1] M(U)[1] 0 where C is y definition a cone of the map M(Z Z sing )(c)[2c] C. Hence we get an exact triangle C [ 1] M(Z Z sing )(c)[2c] C C. Since F is perfect, Z sing is strictly smaller than Z and we have C C y Noetherian induction, hence also C C. To conclude, we have to show that, if M, N DM eff gm(f ) and f Hom(M(1), N(1)), then the cone of f is of the form P (1). This follows from the cancellation theorem [40], which is now valid over any perfect field. (We are indeted to Faien Morel for pointing out this issue.) The last assertion similarly follows from the cancellation theorem.

29 BIRATIONAL MOTIVES, I 29 Let Cor eff (F ) denote the category of effective correspondences, i.e. the category whose ojects are smooth projective varieties and morphisms are Chow correspondences. The category Chow eff (F ) of effective Chow motives is the pseudo-aelian envelope of Cor eff (F ). Recall the functor [38, Prop ] (5.1) Chow eff (F ) DM eff gm(f ) from the category of effective Chow motives (viewed as a homological category: the natural functor Sm proj (F ) Chow eff (F ) is covariant). We would like to descrie a similar functor to DM o gm(f ). To this effect we quotient Chow eff (F ) in a parallel way. In Chow eff (F ), we write h(x) for the Chow motive associated to a smooth projective variety X, 1 for h(spec F ) and L for the Lefschetz motive, defined y h(p 1 ) = 1 L. Then L Z(1)[2] under (5.1). For M Chow eff (F ), we write M(n) for M L n, rather than the traditional notation M( n) Lemma. For two smooth projective varieties X, Y, let I(X, Y ) e the sugroup of CH dim X (X Y ) consisting of those classes vanishing in CH dim X (U Y ) for some open suset U of X. Then I is a monoidal ideal in Cor eff (F ) (i.e. is closed with respect to composition and tensor products on the left and right). In the factor category Cor o (F ), one has the formula Hom( h(x), h(y )) = CH 0 (Y F (X) ) where h h denotes the natural composite functor Sm proj (F ) Cor eff (F ) Cor o (F ). Proof. Let X, Y, Z e 3 smooth projective varieties. If U is an open suset of X, it is clear that the usual formula defines a composition of correspondences CH dim X (U Y ) CH dim Y (Y Z) CH dim X (U Z) and that this composition commutes with restriction to smaller and smaller open susets. Passing to the limit on U, we get a composition or CH dim Y (Y F (X) ) CH dim Y (Y Z) CH dim Z (Z F (X) ) CH 0 (Y F (X) ) CH dim Y (Y Z) CH 0 (Z F (X) ). This pairing is actually nothing else than the action of correspondences on Chow groups of 0-cycles (it extends to an action of CH dim Y (Y F (X) Z F (X) )). We now need to prove that this action factors through an action of CH dim Y (V Z) for any open suset V of

30 30 BRUNO KAHN AND R. SUJATHA Y. Without loss of generality, we may pass to F (X) and hence assume that X = Spec F. The proof is asically a generalisation of Fulton s proof of the Colliot- Thélène Coray theorem that CH 0 is a irational invariant of smooth projective varieties [7], [13, Ex ]. Let M e a proper closed suset of Y, and i : M Y e the corresponding closed immersion. We have to prove that for any α CH 0 (Y ) and β CH dim Y (M Z), (i 1 Z ) (β)(α) := (p 2 ) ((i 1 Z ) β p 1α) = 0 where p 1 and p 2 are respectively the first and second projections on Y Z. We shall actually prove that (i 1 Z ) β p 1α = 0. For this, we may assume that α is represented y a point y Y (0) and β y some integral variety W M Z. Then (i 1 Z ) β p 1α has support in (i 1 Z )(W ) ({y} Z) (M Z) ({y} Z). If y / M, this suset is empty and we are done. Otherwise, up to linear equivalence we may replace y y a 0-cycle disjoint from M (cf. [30]), and we are ack to the previous case. This shows that I is an ideal of Cor eff (F ). The fact that it is a monoidal ideal is essentially ovious. We extend the ideal I from the category of effective Chow correspondences to the category of effective Chow motives (its pseudo-aelian envelope) in the ovious way, keeping the same notation. Let us define Chow o (F ) = (Chow eff (F )/I) where denotes pseudo-aelian envelope Lemma. In Chow eff (F ), I contains the morphisms factoring through an oject of the form M(1). If char F = 0, any morphism in I is of this form. If char F > 0, this is true at least after tensoring morphisms with Q. Proof. Consider the Lefschetz motive L. As it is defined y the projector P 1 CH 1 (P 1 P 1 ), L 0 Chow o (F ). Since I is monoidal, the first statement is clear. For the converse, it is enough to handle morphisms f I(h(X), h(y )) for two smooth projective varieties X, Y. Assume that the cycle f CH dim X (X Y ) is of the form (i 1 Y ) g for some closed immersion i : Z X, where g CH dim X (Z Y ). If Z is smooth of codimension c, then f factors through h(z)(c). Without loss of generality, we may assume that Z is an integral divisor. We may further assume that g is the class of an integral variety W Z Y. Moreover, let Z e the singular locus of

A NOTE ON RELATIVE DUALITY FOR VOEVODSKY MOTIVES

A NOTE ON RELATIVE DUALITY FOR VOEVODSKY MOTIVES A NOTE ON RELATIVE DUALITY FOR VOEVODSKY MOTIVES LUCA BARBIERI-VIALE AND BRUNO KAHN Abstract. Let k be a perfect field which admits resolution of singularities in the sense of Friedlander and Voevodsky

More information

A NOTE ON RELATIVE DUALITY FOR VOEVODSKY MOTIVES

A NOTE ON RELATIVE DUALITY FOR VOEVODSKY MOTIVES A NOTE ON RELATIVE DUALITY FOR VOEVODSKY MOTIVES LUCA BARBIERI-VIALE AND BRUNO KAHN Introduction Relative duality is a useful tool in algebraic geometry and has been used several times. Here we prove a

More information

Voevodsky s Construction Important Concepts (Mazza, Voevodsky, Weibel)

Voevodsky s Construction Important Concepts (Mazza, Voevodsky, Weibel) Motivic Cohomology 1. Triangulated Category of Motives (Voevodsky) 2. Motivic Cohomology (Suslin-Voevodsky) 3. Higher Chow complexes a. Arithmetic (Conjectures of Soulé and Fontaine, Perrin-Riou) b. Mixed

More information

where Σ is a finite discrete Gal(K sep /K)-set unramified along U and F s is a finite Gal(k(s) sep /k(s))-subset

where Σ is a finite discrete Gal(K sep /K)-set unramified along U and F s is a finite Gal(k(s) sep /k(s))-subset Classification of quasi-finite étale separated schemes As we saw in lecture, Zariski s Main Theorem provides a very visual picture of quasi-finite étale separated schemes X over a henselian local ring

More information

Tunisian Journal of Mathematics an international publication organized by the Tunisian Mathematical Society

Tunisian Journal of Mathematics an international publication organized by the Tunisian Mathematical Society unisian Journal of Mathematics an international publication organized by the unisian Mathematical Society Ramification groups of coverings and valuations akeshi Saito 2019 vol. 1 no. 3 msp msp UNISIAN

More information

0.1 Spec of a monoid

0.1 Spec of a monoid These notes were prepared to accompany the first lecture in a seminar on logarithmic geometry. As we shall see in later lectures, logarithmic geometry offers a natural approach to study semistable schemes.

More information

1 Notations and Statement of the Main Results

1 Notations and Statement of the Main Results An introduction to algebraic fundamental groups 1 Notations and Statement of the Main Results Throughout the talk, all schemes are locally Noetherian. All maps are of locally finite type. There two main

More information

Notes on p-divisible Groups

Notes on p-divisible Groups Notes on p-divisible Groups March 24, 2006 This is a note for the talk in STAGE in MIT. The content is basically following the paper [T]. 1 Preliminaries and Notations Notation 1.1. Let R be a complete

More information

Math 249B. Nilpotence of connected solvable groups

Math 249B. Nilpotence of connected solvable groups Math 249B. Nilpotence of connected solvable groups 1. Motivation and examples In abstract group theory, the descending central series {C i (G)} of a group G is defined recursively by C 0 (G) = G and C

More information

6. Lecture cdh and Nisnevich topologies. These are Grothendieck topologies which play an important role in Suslin-Voevodsky s approach to not

6. Lecture cdh and Nisnevich topologies. These are Grothendieck topologies which play an important role in Suslin-Voevodsky s approach to not 6. Lecture 6 6.1. cdh and Nisnevich topologies. These are Grothendieck topologies which play an important role in Suslin-Voevodsky s approach to not only motivic cohomology, but also to Morel-Voevodsky

More information

CHEVALLEY S THEOREM AND COMPLETE VARIETIES

CHEVALLEY S THEOREM AND COMPLETE VARIETIES CHEVALLEY S THEOREM AND COMPLETE VARIETIES BRIAN OSSERMAN In this note, we introduce the concept which plays the role of compactness for varieties completeness. We prove that completeness can be characterized

More information

Chern classes à la Grothendieck

Chern classes à la Grothendieck Chern classes à la Grothendieck Theo Raedschelders October 16, 2014 Abstract In this note we introduce Chern classes based on Grothendieck s 1958 paper [4]. His approach is completely formal and he deduces

More information

MA 206 notes: introduction to resolution of singularities

MA 206 notes: introduction to resolution of singularities MA 206 notes: introduction to resolution of singularities Dan Abramovich Brown University March 4, 2018 Abramovich Introduction to resolution of singularities 1 / 31 Resolution of singularities Let k be

More information

4. Images of Varieties Given a morphism f : X Y of quasi-projective varieties, a basic question might be to ask what is the image of a closed subset

4. Images of Varieties Given a morphism f : X Y of quasi-projective varieties, a basic question might be to ask what is the image of a closed subset 4. Images of Varieties Given a morphism f : X Y of quasi-projective varieties, a basic question might be to ask what is the image of a closed subset Z X. Replacing X by Z we might as well assume that Z

More information

3. Lecture 3. Y Z[1/p]Hom (Sch/k) (Y, X).

3. Lecture 3. Y Z[1/p]Hom (Sch/k) (Y, X). 3. Lecture 3 3.1. Freely generate qfh-sheaves. We recall that if F is a homotopy invariant presheaf with transfers in the sense of the last lecture, then we have a well defined pairing F(X) H 0 (X/S) F(S)

More information

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS JEROEN SIJSLING

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS JEROEN SIJSLING ALGEBRAIC GROUPS JEROEN SIJSLING The goal of these notes is to introduce and motivate some notions from the theory of group schemes. For the sake of simplicity, we restrict to algebraic groups (as defined

More information

Some remarks on Frobenius and Lefschetz in étale cohomology

Some remarks on Frobenius and Lefschetz in étale cohomology Some remarks on obenius and Lefschetz in étale cohomology Gabriel Chênevert January 5, 2004 In this lecture I will discuss some more or less related issues revolving around the main idea relating (étale)

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 28 Dec 2018

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 28 Dec 2018 Gysin triangles in the category of motifs with modulus arxiv:1812.189v1 [math.ag] 28 Dec 218 Keiho Matsumoto Abstract We construct a Gysin triangle in the category of motifs with modulus which specialises

More information

MOTIVES OF SOME ACYCLIC VARIETIES

MOTIVES OF SOME ACYCLIC VARIETIES Homology, Homotopy and Applications, vol.??(?),??, pp.1 6 Introduction MOTIVES OF SOME ACYCLIC VARIETIES ARAVIND ASOK (communicated by Charles Weibel) Abstract We prove that the Voevodsky motive with Z-coefficients

More information

Lecture 6: Etale Fundamental Group

Lecture 6: Etale Fundamental Group Lecture 6: Etale Fundamental Group October 5, 2014 1 Review of the topological fundamental group and covering spaces 1.1 Topological fundamental group Suppose X is a path-connected topological space, and

More information

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY COURSE NOTES, LECTURE 9: SCHEMES AND THEIR MODULES.

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY COURSE NOTES, LECTURE 9: SCHEMES AND THEIR MODULES. ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY COURSE NOTES, LECTURE 9: SCHEMES AND THEIR MODULES. ANDREW SALCH 1. Affine schemes. About notation: I am in the habit of writing f (U) instead of f 1 (U) for the preimage of a subset

More information

APPENDIX 3: AN OVERVIEW OF CHOW GROUPS

APPENDIX 3: AN OVERVIEW OF CHOW GROUPS APPENDIX 3: AN OVERVIEW OF CHOW GROUPS We review in this appendix some basic definitions and results that we need about Chow groups. For details and proofs we refer to [Ful98]. In particular, we discuss

More information

Algebraic v.s. Analytic Point of View

Algebraic v.s. Analytic Point of View Algebraic v.s. Analytic Point of View Ziwen Zhu September 19, 2015 In this talk, we will compare 3 different yet similar objects of interest in algebraic and complex geometry, namely algebraic variety,

More information

14. Rational maps It is often the case that we are given a variety X and a morphism defined on an open subset U of X. As open sets in the Zariski

14. Rational maps It is often the case that we are given a variety X and a morphism defined on an open subset U of X. As open sets in the Zariski 14. Rational maps It is often the case that we are given a variety X and a morphism defined on an open subset U of X. As open sets in the Zariski topology are very large, it is natural to view this as

More information

NONSINGULAR CURVES BRIAN OSSERMAN

NONSINGULAR CURVES BRIAN OSSERMAN NONSINGULAR CURVES BRIAN OSSERMAN The primary goal of this note is to prove that every abstract nonsingular curve can be realized as an open subset of a (unique) nonsingular projective curve. Note that

More information

SCHEMES. David Harari. Tsinghua, February-March 2005

SCHEMES. David Harari. Tsinghua, February-March 2005 SCHEMES David Harari Tsinghua, February-March 2005 Contents 1. Basic notions on schemes 2 1.1. First definitions and examples.................. 2 1.2. Morphisms of schemes : first properties.............

More information

Morita Equivalence. Eamon Quinlan

Morita Equivalence. Eamon Quinlan Morita Equivalence Eamon Quinlan Given a (not necessarily commutative) ring, you can form its category of right modules. Take this category and replace the names of all the modules with dots. The resulting

More information

DERIVED CATEGORIES OF STACKS. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Conventions, notation, and abuse of language The lisse-étale and the flat-fppf sites

DERIVED CATEGORIES OF STACKS. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Conventions, notation, and abuse of language The lisse-étale and the flat-fppf sites DERIVED CATEGORIES OF STACKS Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Conventions, notation, and abuse of language 1 3. The lisse-étale and the flat-fppf sites 1 4. Derived categories of quasi-coherent modules 5

More information

1 Replete topoi. X = Shv proét (X) X is locally weakly contractible (next lecture) X is replete. D(X ) is left complete. K D(X ) we have R lim

1 Replete topoi. X = Shv proét (X) X is locally weakly contractible (next lecture) X is replete. D(X ) is left complete. K D(X ) we have R lim Reference: [BS] Bhatt, Scholze, The pro-étale topology for schemes In this lecture we consider replete topoi This is a nice class of topoi that include the pro-étale topos, and whose derived categories

More information

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 27

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 27 FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 27 RAVI VAKIL CONTENTS 1. Proper morphisms 1 2. Scheme-theoretic closure, and scheme-theoretic image 2 3. Rational maps 3 4. Examples of rational maps 5 Last day:

More information

PART II.1. IND-COHERENT SHEAVES ON SCHEMES

PART II.1. IND-COHERENT SHEAVES ON SCHEMES PART II.1. IND-COHERENT SHEAVES ON SCHEMES Contents Introduction 1 1. Ind-coherent sheaves on a scheme 2 1.1. Definition of the category 2 1.2. t-structure 3 2. The direct image functor 4 2.1. Direct image

More information

Math 248B. Applications of base change for coherent cohomology

Math 248B. Applications of base change for coherent cohomology Math 248B. Applications of base change for coherent cohomology 1. Motivation Recall the following fundamental general theorem, the so-called cohomology and base change theorem: Theorem 1.1 (Grothendieck).

More information

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS BRIAN OSSERMAN The notions o separatedness and properness are the algebraic geometry analogues o the Hausdor condition and compactness in topology. For varieties over the

More information

1. Algebraic vector bundles. Affine Varieties

1. Algebraic vector bundles. Affine Varieties 0. Brief overview Cycles and bundles are intrinsic invariants of algebraic varieties Close connections going back to Grothendieck Work with quasi-projective varieties over a field k Affine Varieties 1.

More information

Logarithmic geometry and moduli

Logarithmic geometry and moduli Logarithmic geometry and moduli Lectures at the Sophus Lie Center Dan Abramovich Brown University June 16-17, 2014 Abramovich (Brown) Logarithmic geometry and moduli June 16-17, 2014 1 / 1 Heros: Olsson

More information

where m is the maximal ideal of O X,p. Note that m/m 2 is a vector space. Suppose that we are given a morphism

where m is the maximal ideal of O X,p. Note that m/m 2 is a vector space. Suppose that we are given a morphism 8. Smoothness and the Zariski tangent space We want to give an algebraic notion of the tangent space. In differential geometry, tangent vectors are equivalence classes of maps of intervals in R into the

More information

The motive of a classifying space

The motive of a classifying space The motive of a classifying space Burt Totaro The Chow group of algebraic cycles generally does not satisfy the Künneth formula. Nonetheless, there are some schemes X over a field k that satisfy the Chow

More information

3 Lecture 3: Spectral spaces and constructible sets

3 Lecture 3: Spectral spaces and constructible sets 3 Lecture 3: Spectral spaces and constructible sets 3.1 Introduction We want to analyze quasi-compactness properties of the valuation spectrum of a commutative ring, and to do so a digression on constructible

More information

(1) is an invertible sheaf on X, which is generated by the global sections

(1) is an invertible sheaf on X, which is generated by the global sections 7. Linear systems First a word about the base scheme. We would lie to wor in enough generality to cover the general case. On the other hand, it taes some wor to state properly the general results if one

More information

BERTRAND GUILLOU. s G q+r

BERTRAND GUILLOU. s G q+r STABLE A 1 -HOMOTOPY THEORY BERTRAND GUILLOU 1. Introduction Recall from the previous talk that we have our category pointed A 1 -homotopy category Ho A 1, (k) over a field k. We will often refer to an

More information

Smooth morphisms. Peter Bruin 21 February 2007

Smooth morphisms. Peter Bruin 21 February 2007 Smooth morphisms Peter Bruin 21 February 2007 Introduction The goal of this talk is to define smooth morphisms of schemes, which are one of the main ingredients in Néron s fundamental theorem [BLR, 1.3,

More information

9. Birational Maps and Blowing Up

9. Birational Maps and Blowing Up 72 Andreas Gathmann 9. Birational Maps and Blowing Up In the course of this class we have already seen many examples of varieties that are almost the same in the sense that they contain isomorphic dense

More information

DERIVED CATEGORIES OF COHERENT SHEAVES

DERIVED CATEGORIES OF COHERENT SHEAVES DERIVED CATEGORIES OF COHERENT SHEAVES OLIVER E. ANDERSON Abstract. We give an overview of derived categories of coherent sheaves. [Huy06]. Our main reference is 1. For the participants without bacground

More information

1 Existence of the Néron model

1 Existence of the Néron model Néron models Setting: S a Dedekind domain, K its field of fractions, A/K an abelian variety. A model of A/S is a flat, separable S-scheme of finite type X with X K = A. The nicest possible model over S

More information

CHAPTER 0 PRELIMINARY MATERIAL. Paul Vojta. University of California, Berkeley. 18 February 1998

CHAPTER 0 PRELIMINARY MATERIAL. Paul Vojta. University of California, Berkeley. 18 February 1998 CHAPTER 0 PRELIMINARY MATERIAL Paul Vojta University of California, Berkeley 18 February 1998 This chapter gives some preliminary material on number theory and algebraic geometry. Section 1 gives basic

More information

10. Smooth Varieties. 82 Andreas Gathmann

10. Smooth Varieties. 82 Andreas Gathmann 82 Andreas Gathmann 10. Smooth Varieties Let a be a point on a variety X. In the last chapter we have introduced the tangent cone C a X as a way to study X locally around a (see Construction 9.20). It

More information

What are stacks and why should you care?

What are stacks and why should you care? What are stacks and why should you care? Milan Lopuhaä October 12, 2017 Todays goal is twofold: I want to tell you why you would want to study stacks in the first place, and I want to define what a stack

More information

3. Categories and Functors We recall the definition of a category: Definition 3.1. A category C is the data of two collections. The first collection

3. Categories and Functors We recall the definition of a category: Definition 3.1. A category C is the data of two collections. The first collection 3. Categories and Functors We recall the definition of a category: Definition 3.1. A category C is the data of two collections. The first collection is called the objects of C and is denoted Obj(C). Given

More information

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal semigroup rings and formal power series rings We next want to explore the notion of a (formal) power series ring in finitely

More information

AFFINE PUSHFORWARD AND SMOOTH PULLBACK FOR PERVERSE SHEAVES

AFFINE PUSHFORWARD AND SMOOTH PULLBACK FOR PERVERSE SHEAVES AFFINE PUSHFORWARD AND SMOOTH PULLBACK FOR PERVERSE SHEAVES YEHAO ZHOU Conventions In this lecture note, a variety means a separated algebraic variety over complex numbers, and sheaves are C-linear. 1.

More information

Motives. Basic Notions seminar, Harvard University May 3, Marc Levine

Motives. Basic Notions seminar, Harvard University May 3, Marc Levine Motives Basic Notions seminar, Harvard University May 3, 2004 Marc Levine Motivation: What motives allow you to do Relate phenomena in different cohomology theories. Linearize algebraic varieties Import

More information

1 Categorical Background

1 Categorical Background 1 Categorical Background 1.1 Categories and Functors Definition 1.1.1 A category C is given by a class of objects, often denoted by ob C, and for any two objects A, B of C a proper set of morphisms C(A,

More information

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions 24 Andreas Gathmann 3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions After having defined affine varieties, our next goal must be to say what kind of maps between them we want to consider as morphisms, i. e. as nice

More information

Lecture 9 - Faithfully Flat Descent

Lecture 9 - Faithfully Flat Descent Lecture 9 - Faithfully Flat Descent October 15, 2014 1 Descent of morphisms In this lecture we study the concept of faithfully flat descent, which is the notion that to obtain an object on a scheme X,

More information

h M (T ). The natural isomorphism η : M h M determines an element U = η 1

h M (T ). The natural isomorphism η : M h M determines an element U = η 1 MODULI PROBLEMS AND GEOMETRIC INVARIANT THEORY 7 2.3. Fine moduli spaces. The ideal situation is when there is a scheme that represents our given moduli functor. Definition 2.15. Let M : Sch Set be a moduli

More information

Homology and Cohomology of Stacks (Lecture 7)

Homology and Cohomology of Stacks (Lecture 7) Homology and Cohomology of Stacks (Lecture 7) February 19, 2014 In this course, we will need to discuss the l-adic homology and cohomology of algebro-geometric objects of a more general nature than algebraic

More information

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12 MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 2 CİHAN BAHRAN 3.2.. Let Y be a Noetherian scheme. Show that any Y -scheme X of finite type is Noetherian. Moreover, if Y is of finite dimension, then so is X. Write f

More information

Logarithmic geometry and rational curves

Logarithmic geometry and rational curves Logarithmic geometry and rational curves Summer School 2015 of the IRTG Moduli and Automorphic Forms Siena, Italy Dan Abramovich Brown University August 24-28, 2015 Abramovich (Brown) Logarithmic geometry

More information

Categories and functors

Categories and functors Lecture 1 Categories and functors Definition 1.1 A category A consists of a collection ob(a) (whose elements are called the objects of A) for each A, B ob(a), a collection A(A, B) (whose elements are called

More information

14 Lecture 14: Basic generallities on adic spaces

14 Lecture 14: Basic generallities on adic spaces 14 Lecture 14: Basic generallities on adic spaces 14.1 Introduction The aim of this lecture and the next two is to address general adic spaces and their connection to rigid geometry. 14.2 Two open questions

More information

NOTES ON BASIC HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA 0 L M N 0

NOTES ON BASIC HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA 0 L M N 0 NOTES ON BASIC HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA ANDREW BAKER 1. Chain complexes and their homology Let R be a ring and Mod R the category of right R-modules; a very similar discussion can be had for the category of

More information

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 24

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 24 FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 24 RAVI VAKIL CONTENTS 1. Vector bundles and locally free sheaves 1 2. Toward quasicoherent sheaves: the distinguished affine base 5 Quasicoherent and coherent sheaves

More information

Zeta and L functions of Voevodsky motives Bruno Kahn ICM Satellite conference on Galois representations Goa, Aug. 10, 2010.

Zeta and L functions of Voevodsky motives Bruno Kahn ICM Satellite conference on Galois representations Goa, Aug. 10, 2010. Zeta and L functions of Voevodsky motives Bruno Kahn ICM Satellite conference on Galois representations Goa, Aug. 10, 2010. Work in progress Aim of talk: associate to a Voevodsky motive M over a global

More information

Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009

Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009 MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 18.726 Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. 18.726: Algebraic Geometry

More information

Introduction to Chiral Algebras

Introduction to Chiral Algebras Introduction to Chiral Algebras Nick Rozenblyum Our goal will be to prove the fact that the algebra End(V ac) is commutative. The proof itself will be very easy - a version of the Eckmann Hilton argument

More information

COMPLEX VARIETIES AND THE ANALYTIC TOPOLOGY

COMPLEX VARIETIES AND THE ANALYTIC TOPOLOGY COMPLEX VARIETIES AND THE ANALYTIC TOPOLOGY BRIAN OSSERMAN Classical algebraic geometers studied algebraic varieties over the complex numbers. In this setting, they didn t have to worry about the Zariski

More information

BEZOUT S THEOREM CHRISTIAN KLEVDAL

BEZOUT S THEOREM CHRISTIAN KLEVDAL BEZOUT S THEOREM CHRISTIAN KLEVDAL A weaker version of Bézout s theorem states that if C, D are projective plane curves of degrees c and d that intersect transversally, then C D = cd. The goal of this

More information

LECTURE 7: STABLE RATIONALITY AND DECOMPOSITION OF THE DIAGONAL

LECTURE 7: STABLE RATIONALITY AND DECOMPOSITION OF THE DIAGONAL LECTURE 7: STABLE RATIONALITY AND DECOMPOSITION OF THE DIAGONAL In this lecture we discuss a criterion for non-stable-rationality based on the decomposition of the diagonal in the Chow group. This criterion

More information

Rigid Geometry and Applications II. Kazuhiro Fujiwara & Fumiharu Kato

Rigid Geometry and Applications II. Kazuhiro Fujiwara & Fumiharu Kato Rigid Geometry and Applications II Kazuhiro Fujiwara & Fumiharu Kato Birational Geometry from Zariski s viewpoint S U D S : coherent (= quasi-compact and quasi-separated) (analog. compact Hausdorff) U

More information

Lecture 2 Sheaves and Functors

Lecture 2 Sheaves and Functors Lecture 2 Sheaves and Functors In this lecture we will introduce the basic concept of sheaf and we also will recall some of category theory. 1 Sheaves and locally ringed spaces The definition of sheaf

More information

LOCALIZATION, UNIVERSAL PROPERTIES, AND HOMOTOPY THEORY

LOCALIZATION, UNIVERSAL PROPERTIES, AND HOMOTOPY THEORY LOCLIZTION, UNIVERSL PROPERTIES, ND HOMOTOPY THEORY DVID WHITE Localization in lgebra Localization in Category Theory ousfield localization 1. The right way to think about localization in algebra Localization

More information

Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 4. Proposition (4.1.6). The canonical homomorphism ( ) is surjective [(3.2.4)].

Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 4. Proposition (4.1.6). The canonical homomorphism ( ) is surjective [(3.2.4)]. Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 4 4.1. Definition of projective bundles. 4. Projective bundles. Ample sheaves Definition (4.1.1). Let S(E) be the symmetric algebra of a quasi-coherent O Y -module.

More information

x X p K i (k(x)) K i 1 (M p+1 )

x X p K i (k(x)) K i 1 (M p+1 ) 5. Higher Chow Groups and Beilinson s Conjectures 5.1. Bloch s formula. One interesting application of Quillen s techniques involving the Q construction is the following theorem of Quillen, extending work

More information

Algebraic Cobordism Lecture 1: Complex cobordism and algebraic cobordism

Algebraic Cobordism Lecture 1: Complex cobordism and algebraic cobordism Algebraic Cobordism Lecture 1: Complex cobordism and algebraic cobordism UWO January 25, 2005 Marc Levine Prelude: From homotopy theory to A 1 -homotopy theory A basic object in homotopy theory is a generalized

More information

INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 12

INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 12 INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 12 RAVI VAKIL CONTENTS 1. Rational equivalence on bundles 1 1.1. Intersecting with the zero-section of a vector bundle 2 2. Cones and Segre classes of subvarieties 3 2.1. Introduction

More information

A GLIMPSE OF ALGEBRAIC K-THEORY: Eric M. Friedlander

A GLIMPSE OF ALGEBRAIC K-THEORY: Eric M. Friedlander A GLIMPSE OF ALGEBRAIC K-THEORY: Eric M. Friedlander During the first three days of September, 1997, I had the privilege of giving a series of five lectures at the beginning of the School on Algebraic

More information

15 Lecture 15: Points and lft maps

15 Lecture 15: Points and lft maps 15 Lecture 15: Points and lft maps 15.1 A noetherian property Let A be an affinoid algebraic over a non-archimedean field k and X = Spa(A, A 0 ). For any x X, the stalk O X,x is the limit of the directed

More information

ORIENTABLE HOMOTOPY MODULES

ORIENTABLE HOMOTOPY MODULES ORIENTABLE HOMOTOPY MODULES Contents Introduction 1 Notations and conventions 3 1. The conjecture of Morel 3 1.1. The homotopy t-structure 3 1.2. Homotopy modules 4 1.3. Homotopy modules with transfers

More information

Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 3

Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 3 Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 3 3. Homogeneous spectrum of a sheaf of graded algebras 3.1. Homogeneous spectrum of a graded quasi-coherent O Y algebra. (3.1.1). Let Y be a prescheme. A sheaf

More information

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS BRIAN OSSERMAN Last quarter, we introduced the closed diagonal condition or a prevariety to be a prevariety, and the universally closed condition or a variety to be complete.

More information

NOTES ON FLAT MORPHISMS AND THE FPQC TOPOLOGY

NOTES ON FLAT MORPHISMS AND THE FPQC TOPOLOGY NOTES ON FLAT MORPHISMS AND THE FPQC TOPOLOGY RUNE HAUGSENG The aim of these notes is to define flat and faithfully flat morphisms and review some of their important properties, and to define the fpqc

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

The Adjoint Functor Theorem.

The Adjoint Functor Theorem. The Adjoint Functor Theorem. Kevin Buzzard February 7, 2012 Last modified 17/06/2002. 1 Introduction. The existence of free groups is immediate from the Adjoint Functor Theorem. Whilst I ve long believed

More information

UNIVERSAL DERIVED EQUIVALENCES OF POSETS

UNIVERSAL DERIVED EQUIVALENCES OF POSETS UNIVERSAL DERIVED EQUIVALENCES OF POSETS SEFI LADKANI Abstract. By using only combinatorial data on two posets X and Y, we construct a set of so-called formulas. A formula produces simultaneously, for

More information

Math 210B. Artin Rees and completions

Math 210B. Artin Rees and completions Math 210B. Artin Rees and completions 1. Definitions and an example Let A be a ring, I an ideal, and M an A-module. In class we defined the I-adic completion of M to be M = lim M/I n M. We will soon show

More information

Derived Algebraic Geometry IX: Closed Immersions

Derived Algebraic Geometry IX: Closed Immersions Derived Algebraic Geometry I: Closed Immersions November 5, 2011 Contents 1 Unramified Pregeometries and Closed Immersions 4 2 Resolutions of T-Structures 7 3 The Proof of Proposition 1.0.10 14 4 Closed

More information

Special Precovered Categories of Gorenstein Categories

Special Precovered Categories of Gorenstein Categories Special Precovered Categories of Gorenstein Categories Tiwei Zhao and Zhaoyong Huang Department of Mathematics, Nanjing University, Nanjing 9, Jiangsu Province, P. R. China Astract Let A e an aelian category

More information

SUMMER COURSE IN MOTIVIC HOMOTOPY THEORY

SUMMER COURSE IN MOTIVIC HOMOTOPY THEORY SUMMER COURSE IN MOTIVIC HOMOTOPY THEORY MARC LEVINE Contents 0. Introduction 1 1. The category of schemes 2 1.1. The spectrum of a commutative ring 2 1.2. Ringed spaces 5 1.3. Schemes 10 1.4. Schemes

More information

FORMAL GLUEING OF MODULE CATEGORIES

FORMAL GLUEING OF MODULE CATEGORIES FORMAL GLUEING OF MODULE CATEGORIES BHARGAV BHATT Fix a noetherian scheme X, and a closed subscheme Z with complement U. Our goal is to explain a result of Artin that describes how coherent sheaves on

More information

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 26

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 26 FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 26 RAVI VAKIL CONTENTS 1. Proper morphisms 1 Last day: separatedness, definition of variety. Today: proper morphisms. I said a little more about separatedness of

More information

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) Contents. 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) Contents. 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY (NMAG401) JAN ŠŤOVÍČEK Contents 1. Affine varieties 1 2. Polynomial and rational maps 9 3. Hilbert s Nullstellensatz and consequences 23 References 30 1. Affine varieties The basic objects

More information

Math 210B. Profinite group cohomology

Math 210B. Profinite group cohomology Math 210B. Profinite group cohomology 1. Motivation Let {Γ i } be an inverse system of finite groups with surjective transition maps, and define Γ = Γ i equipped with its inverse it topology (i.e., the

More information

The Hurewicz Theorem

The Hurewicz Theorem The Hurewicz Theorem April 5, 011 1 Introduction The fundamental group and homology groups both give extremely useful information, particularly about path-connected spaces. Both can be considered as functors,

More information

Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 5

Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 5 Synopsis of material from EGA Chapter II, 5 5. Quasi-affine, quasi-projective, proper and projective morphisms 5.1. Quasi-affine morphisms. Definition (5.1.1). A scheme is quasi-affine if it is isomorphic

More information

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS.

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS. FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS. Let A be a ring, for simplicity assumed commutative. A filtering, or filtration, of an A module M means a descending sequence of submodules M = M 0

More information

Factorization of birational maps on steroids

Factorization of birational maps on steroids Factorization of birational maps on steroids IAS, April 14, 2015 Dan Abramovich Brown University April 14, 2015 This is work with Michael Temkin (Jerusalem) Abramovich (Brown) Factorization of birational

More information

ABSTRACT NONSINGULAR CURVES

ABSTRACT NONSINGULAR CURVES ABSTRACT NONSINGULAR CURVES Affine Varieties Notation. Let k be a field, such as the rational numbers Q or the complex numbers C. We call affine n-space the collection A n k of points P = a 1, a,..., a

More information

Hochschild homology and Grothendieck Duality

Hochschild homology and Grothendieck Duality Hochschild homology and Grothendieck Duality Leovigildo Alonso Tarrío Universidade de Santiago de Compostela Purdue University July, 1, 2009 Leo Alonso (USC.es) Hochschild theory and Grothendieck Duality

More information

NOTES ON THE CONSTRUCTION OF THE MODULI SPACE OF CURVES

NOTES ON THE CONSTRUCTION OF THE MODULI SPACE OF CURVES NOTES ON THE CONSTRUCTION OF THE MODULI SPACE OF CURVES DAN EDIDIN The purpose of these notes is to discuss the problem of moduli for curves of genus g 3 1 and outline the construction of the (coarse)

More information

12. Linear systems Theorem Let X be a scheme over a ring A. (1) If φ: X P n A is an A-morphism then L = φ O P n

12. Linear systems Theorem Let X be a scheme over a ring A. (1) If φ: X P n A is an A-morphism then L = φ O P n 12. Linear systems Theorem 12.1. Let X be a scheme over a ring A. (1) If φ: X P n A is an A-morphism then L = φ O P n A (1) is an invertible sheaf on X, which is generated by the global sections s 0, s

More information