Elements of Geometric Stability Theory

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Elements of Geometric Stability Theory"

Transcription

1 Elements of Geometric Stability Theory May Completeness and quantifier elimination for some classical theories We first work out a basic example, with a proof that demonstrates geometroalgebraic, as opposed to syntactical, methods in model theory. We denote ACF p the theory of algebraically closed fields of characteristic p. Theorem 1.1 ACF p language (+,, 0, 1) is complete and allows quantifier elimination in the First we prove Lemma (weak form of Steinitz Theorem) Let B and C of the same uncountable cardinality µ be in ACF p. Then any isomorphism α 0 : B 0 C 0 between subfields B 0 B and C 0 C of cardinality less than µ can be extended to an isomorphism α : B C. Proof We enumerate the fields and proceed back-and-forth constructing α i : B i C i of cardinality less than µ. Suppose B i and C i are isomorphic and of cardinality less than µ. Take the first b B not in B i. If b is transcendental over B i then by cardinality considerations we can find c transcendental over C i. Then B i (b) = B i (x) = C i (x) = C i (c). 1

2 If b is a root of f B (x) over B i, irreducible, then the correspondent f C (x) has a root c in C and B i (b) = B i [x]/{f B (x)} = C i [x]/{f C (x)} = C i [c]. Corollary 1.1 ACF p is µ-categorical for µ > ℵ 0, and hence complete. Lemma For any A F and any two n-tuples b and c TFAE: (i) qftp( b/a) = qftp( c/a); (ii) b is conjugated with c by an automorphism over A; (iii) tp( b/a) = tp( c/a). Proof We prove that (i) implies (ii). The rest is obvious. First consider n = 1. W.l.o.g. we assume that A is a subfield. If b is transcendental over A then so is c and A(b) = A(x) = A(c) over A. If b is a root of f(x) over A, minimal for b, then so is c and A(b) = A[x]/{f(x)} = A[c] over A. If b = b 1..., b n and qftp( b/a) = qftp( c/a) then qftp(b 1 /A) = qftp(c 1 /A) thus by induction there is an isomorphism α : A(b 1 ) A(c 1 ). Let b 2..., b n be the image of b 2..., b n under α. Then hence qftp( c 1, b 2..., b n /A) = qftp( b/a) = qftp( c/a), b 2..., b n conj with c 2,..., c n over Ac 1. Finally b is conjugated with c over A. 2

3 Proof of QE. Let ϕ( x) be any formula in the field language and Φ( x) = {ψ( x) qfree : F = ϕ(x) ψ( x)}. If Φ& ϕ is consistent then in monster F F there is a realization b of the type. qftp( b) must be consistent with ϕ for otherwise ξ( x) is in Φ for some ξ qftp( b). Then there exists c realizing qftp( b)&ϕ. A contradiction. Thus = Φ ϕ and so Φ is equivalent to its finite part and Φ ϕ. Exercise 1.2 Prove a corresponding theorem for the theory of vector spaces. We also consider the theory of differentially closed fields of characteristic zero DCF 0. It is based on the language of fields extended by a symbol of a unary operation D corresponding to a differentiation operator. D obeys the identities D(x + y) = Dx + Dy and Dxy = xdy + ydx. (1) DCF 0 is axiomatised as an algebraically closed field with an operator D satisfying (1) and the axiom scheme stating that for any differential polynomials g(y) of order n > 0 and f(y) of order m < n over the field there is a solution of the system g(y) = 0 & f(y) 0. Theorem 1.3 DCF 0 is complete and allows elimination of quantifiers. The proof of the theorem (see e.g. [P]) is quite similar to the proof of Theorem 1.1. One studies extensions of an isomorphism between differential subfields in a way similar to the proof of Lemma and then uses the back-and-forth method to establish an elementary equivalence between two models of DCF 0 and to prove QE. We also want to consider as one of our basic examples the structure on the complex numbers C e = (C, +, P (3) ), where P (3) (x, y, z) e x + e y = e z. 3

4 Notice that the subgroup 2πiZ is definable in C e as {v C : x, y, z e x + e y = e z e x + e y = e z+v }. Now, if we introduce a definable set C = C/2πiZ and a definable canonical homomorphism exp : C C we get an equivalent representation of the structure as a two-sorted structure (C, C {0}) with the additive group structure (C, +) on the first sort, the field structure (C {0},, +) on the second sort and exp mapping the first sort into the second sort. To capture the most interesting properties of this structure it is not enough to consider its first-order theory only. A more relevant language is the language L ω1,ω allowing conjunctions and disjunctions over countable sets of formulas with finite strings of variables. We state without proof (which can be found in [Z1]) Theorem 1.4 A natural L ω1,ω-sentence axiomatising C e has models and is categorical in all uncountable cardinalities. Any automorphism of the field on the second sort C {0} can be lifted to an automorphism of the structure C e. 2 Closure operators in abstract structures 2.1 Algebraic closure Definition Given A M, a formula ϕ(x) with parameters in A is called algebraic if for some m > 0 M = =m xϕ(x). A type over A containing an algebraic formula is said to be algebraic. acl(a) = {b M : there is an algebraic ϕ(v) over A such thatm = ϕ(b)}. Lemma The following properties of acl hold in any structure: A acl(a); (2) A B acl(a) acl(b); (3) acl(acl(a)) = acl(a). (4) 4

5 Proof Easy. Remark For any field F and A F, letting the field theoretic algebraic closure of A to be Acl(A), we have Acl(A) acl(a). By elimination of quantifiers, in algebraically closed fields we have Acl(A) = acl(a). We hence have a classical Corollary 2.1 If b and c are algebraic over A in a field F, then so are b + c and bc. Definition An elementary monomorphism α : A M, for A M and M, M structures in the same language L, is an injective map which preserves L-formulas. An elementary monomorphism which is a bijection of A M onto A M is called an elementary isomorphism between A and A. Proposition 2.1 (Uniqueness of closure) Any elementary isomorphism α between A M and A M can be extended to acl(a) acl(a ). Proof Let B = acl(a) and B = acl(a ). Enumerate B = {b i : i < µ}, µ = card B, and go by transfinite induction extending α to A {b i : i < γ}, finding for b γ a corresponding element b γ B such that A {b i : i γ} A {b i : i γ} is an elementary isomorphism. In order to see this is possible notice that the type p γ = tp(b γ /(A {b i : i < γ})) is algebraic by definition, and thus is principal. Hence the type p α γ obtained by replacing parameters in p γ by their images under α is also algebraic and principal. Hence p α γ is realised by some element of M which we can take for 5

6 b γ. Notice also that before reaching γ = µ we list all elements of p γ as some b i1,... b in, and hence we get all elements of p α γ as some b i 1,..., b in. It follows that by reaching step µ we have B as a domain of α and, since all the realisations of algebraic types over A are in B, we have α(b) = B. 2.2 λ-closure We now generalise slightly the definition of algebraic closure. Definition Given an infinite regular cardinal λ, a structure M of cardinality at least λ and A M we say that a formula ϕ(x) over A is λ-small in M if card ϕ(m) < λ. The λ-closure of A in M is defined as cl λ (A) = {ϕ(m) : ϕ(x) is a λ-small formula over A}. We say that λ-smallness is weakly definable in M if for any finite ā in M and b cl λ (ā) there exist formulas ϕ(x, ȳ) and <λ x ϕ(x, ȳ) (ȳ the only free variables in <λ x ϕ(x, ȳ) ) without parameters such that ϕ(b, ā) and <λ x ϕ(x, ā) hold in M, and for any ā in M M <λ x ϕ(x, ā ) card ϕ(m, ā ) < λ. Example It follows from Theorem 1.4, second clause, that in the structure C e, for λ = ω 1, the λ-closure for A C is exactly cl λ (A) = ln(acl(exp A)), where ln X = {z C : exp z X}. Hence we deduce that in C e b cl(a) iff b ϕ(c) for some A-definable analytic set ϕ(c) of (complex analytic) dimension 0. Also, ω 1 -smallness is weakly definable in C e by Theorem

7 Lemma The following properties of cl = cl λ hold in any structure: A cl(a); (5) A B cl(a) cl(b); (6) If also λ-smallness is weakly definable in the structure then cl(cl(a)) = cl(a). (7) Proof The first two are obvious. To prove (7) suppose B cl(a) and c cl(b). We may assume that B = {b 1,..., b m }. We then have ψ i (b i ) for some λ-small A-definable ψ i (y) and φ(x, b) for some λ-small φ(x, b) such that φ(x, ȳ) is A-definable. We obviously have M ȳφ(c, ȳ)& <λ xφ(x, ȳ)& ψ i (y i ) i and, on the other hand, the A-definable set {φ(m, b 1,..., b m) : & <λ xφ(x, b 1,..., b m) & ψ(b i)} is of cardinality less than λ. Remark The Uniqueness property for cl λ ( Proposition 2.1) does not hold in general, and does not hold in C e in particular. i 2.3 Closure in differentially closed fields This is a new type of closure which anyway is linked to a notion of smallness given in general by model theoretic means. Definition Given a differential field F and its subfield A we say that b F is differential-algebraic over A if b is a solution of a non-trivial differential equation f(y) = 0 over A. Define Dfcl(A) to be the set of all differential algebraic elements over A in a given model of DCF 0. 7

8 Lemma Given a differentially closed field F and letting cl = Dfcl we have that (5),(6) and (7) hold in F. Idea of Proof (5) and (6) are obvious. We discuss the proof of (7). One uses a dimension theory based on Morley rank. Assuming that the field C of constants of F (i.e. c F such that Dc = 0) is of dimension 1 we see F as an infinite dimensional object. Correspondingly the space of solutions of a differential equation f(y) = 0 of order m (that is D m y is the maximal differential occurring in f) is of dimension m, so is small. Hence, if b is a solution of a differential equation g(y) = 0 with coefficients a 1,..., a n which are differential-algebraic over some A, then b belongs to a finite-dimensional space (of dimension depending on the order of g and the orders of the corresponding equations for a 1,... a n ). This space, by elimination of quantifiers, is defined by an equation over A, and this proves that b Dfcl(A). Remark Uniqueness of closure holds for Dfcl in the following form Given A F, F a model of DCF 0, there is a unique up to isomorphism DCF 0 -model F (A), prime over A, and F (A) = Dfcl F (A) (A). The reasons that F (A) can be constructed in a unique way are similar to those used in the proof of Proposition 2.1. Namely, going by a similar inductive process we choose b γ so that p γ is of minimal Morley rank, then p γ turns out to be principal. 3 Minimal structures. For a structure M with a closure operator cl the exchange principle states that For any A M, b, c M : b cl(a, c) \ cl(a) c cl(a, b). (8) 8

9 Definition A structure M is said to be minimal if any definable (using parameters) subset of M is either finite or a complement of a finite. Lemma In minimal structures, letting cl = acl, the exchange principle holds. Proof Suppose b acl(a, c)\acl(a). Then for some ϕ(x, y) over A and some m M = ϕ(b, c)& m x ϕ(x, c). W.l.o.g. we assume M = ϕ(x, y) m x ϕ(x, y). Suppose, towards a contradiction, that ϕ(b, M) is infinite. Then card ( ϕ(b, M)) k for some k, i.e. M = k y ϕ(b, y) and B = {b M : M = k y ϕ(b, y)} is infinite, since b / acl(a). Choose distinct b 1,..., b m+1 B. Then ϕ(b 1, M) ϕ(b m+1, M) is infinite and thus contains a point c. It contradicts M m x ϕ(x, c ). Again, we would like to generalise the notion of a minimal structure. Definition A structure M is said to be λ-minimal if card M λ and any definable subset of M is either λ-small or a complement of a λ-small subset. We say that a formula φ(y, z) has the strict λ-order property in M if φ(y, z) defines on M a partial order (transitive but not necessarily antisymmetric) with a chain of ordinal type λ. Example C e is λ-minimal, by section 2.2. Lemma Suppose M is λ-minimal and λ-smallness is weakly definable in M. Then the exchange principle holds for cl λ, or card M = λ and M has the strict λ-order property. 9

10 Proof We follow the proof of Lemma Below cl stands for cl λ. Suppose b cl(a, c) \ cl(a). Then for some ϕ(x, y) over A and some m M = ϕ(b, c)& <λ x ϕ(x, c). By letting ϕ(x, y) := ϕ(x, y) & <λ x ϕ(x, y) we assume M ϕ(x, y) <λ x ϕ(x, y). If card ϕ(b, M) < λ then c cl(a, b), in correspondence with the exchange principle. Suppose that the exchange principle does not hold in M. Then, for some b, c and A as above, card ϕ(b, M) λ. Then card ϕ(b, M) < λ and b B = {b M : M = <λ y ϕ(b, y)} is of cardinality at least λ, since b / cl(a). Now, let {b i : i < λ} B be a λ-sequence of distinct elements of B. For any ordinal α < λ card ( i<α ϕ(b i, M)) < λ, hence ϕ(b i, M), i<α and thus the set contains a point, say c α. We have correspondingly {b i : i < α} ϕ(m, c α ). If card M > λ then card B = card M > λ and we can find c λ B such that {b i : i < λ} ϕ(m, c λ ), contradicting the definition of B. So card M = card B has to be λ. In particular, we may assume {b i : i < λ} = B. Let x 1 x 2 denote the formula stating that B ϕ(x 1, M) B ϕ(x 2, M). Obviously this defines a partial order. Suppose c 1 c i... is a chain in the partial order of ordinal type α, for some α < λ. We have then that B α = i<α B ϕ(c i, M) 10

11 is of cardinality less than λ. Let b α be an element in M \ B α, then by above there is c α M such that B α {b α } ϕ(c α, M). We then have c i c α for all i < α, which means that the α-chain is not maximal and can be extended to a chain of ordinal type λ. Example Let λ > ℵ 0 be a cardinal. Consider the structure (M λ, <) with M λ = λ Q and < the lexicographic order on the set. Then M λ is densely ordered without endpoints. This is known to have elimination of quantifiers and so any definable subset S of M λ is a union of finitely many intervals and points. If one of the intervals is given by x > a then card S = card M = λ. Otherwise card S < λ. Hence M λ is λ-minimal, but it does not obey the exchange principle. 3.1 The pregeometry and the geometry of a minimal structure. Definition An [abstract] pregeometry is a set M with an operator cl : 2 M 2 M such that, for any A M, cl(a) = {cl(a ) : A A finite} and conditions (5)-(8) above are satisfied. A pregeometry is said to be a geometry if for any a M cl({a}) = {a} (9) Getting a geometry from a pregeometry Lemma The relation on M \ cl( ) defined as is an equivalence relation. x y iff cl(x) = cl(y) 11

12 Proof Follows from the exchange principle. Definition For a pregeometry M define the set ˆM = (M \ cl )/ (quotient under the equivalence relation.) Then any point in ˆM is of the form â = cl{a} \ cl, for a corresponding a M \ cl emptyset. For a subset  = {â : a A} ˆM define cl(â) = {ˆb : b cl(a)}. The operator cl on ˆM satisfies then (5)-(9) and thus ˆM is a geometry. Definition Given a subset D M of a pregeometry we construct a pregeometry M D, the localisation of M with respect to D: the set of M D is just M and cl D (A) = cl(d A). Subspaces of a pregeometry are subset of the form cl(a). Pregeometry is said to be locally finite if cl(a) is finite whenever A is. Example Vector spaces over division rings are pregeometries if we let cl(a) = span(a). The projective space associated with a vector space M is defined exactly as the geometry ˆM. The affine space associated with a vector space M is defined on the same set M by the new closure-operator: cl aff (A) = A + span(a A) where A A = {a 1 a 2 : a 1, a 2 A}. Exercise Show that an affine space is a geometry and its localisation with respect to any point is isomorphic to the initial vector space pregeometry. 12

13 Definition A set A is said to be independent if cl(a) cl(a ) for any proper subset A A. A maximal independent subset of a set A is said to be a basis of A. Lemma Any two bases B and C of a set A are of the same cardinality. Proof First consider the case when, say B, is finite and consists of n elements b 1,... b n. There exists c C such that c cl(b 1,... b n ) \ cl(b 1,... b n 1 ), for otherwise B is not independent. By the exchange principle {c, b 1,... b n 1 } is a basis of A. In the localisation M c sets {b 1,... b n 1 } and C \ {c} are bases of A. By induction on n the statement follows. Consider now the case when both B and C are infinite. It follows from the finite character of cl that for any b B there is a minimal finite C b C such that b cl(c b ). Thus there is a mapping of B into P fin (C), the set of all finite subsets of C. The mapping is finite-to-one, since by the above analysis of the finite dimensional case the set {d B : C d = C b } is an independent subset of cl(c b ) and its size is not bigger than the size of C b. It follows card B card C. By symmetry card B = card C. Now we can give Definition For any subset A of a pregeometry define the dimension dim A to be the cardinality of a basis of A. If also B A then dim(a/b) is the dimension of A in pregeometry M B. Lemma (the addition formula) For any B A M dim(a/b) + dim(b) = dim(a). 13

14 Proof One can construct a basis of A by adjoining a basis of A in M B to a basis of B in M. Examples The transcendence degree tr.deg.a of a subset A of an algebraically closed field F is defined as dim A in the above sense with cl = Acl. Since any field is a subfield of an algebraically closed one, the definition is applicable for subsets of any field. Lemma For X, Y M, subspaces of a pregometry, dim(x Y ) dim X + dim Y dim(x Y ). Proof Let Z be a basis of X Y. Let Z X 0 and Z Y 0 be bases of X and Y, correspondingly. Then cl(x 0 Z Y 0 ) = cl(x Y ) and thus dim(x Y ) X 0 Z + Z Y 0 Z. Homogeneity Definition A subset A of a structure M is said to be indiscernible over B if tp(ā/b) = tp(ā /B) for any two n-tuples of distinct elements of A for any finite n. Proposition 3.1 Let M be a λ-minimal structure with λ-smallness weakly definable, cl = cl λ, A, B M and A independent over B. Then A is indiscernible over B. Proof Consider ā = a 1,... a n, ā = a 1,..., a n all with distinct coordinates from A. In case the size n = 1 tp(a/b) is just the set of those formulas ϕ(x) over B which have card ϕ(m) λ. The same characterises tp(a /B). Thus the types are equal. For n > 1 suppose, as an inductive hypothesis, the tuples have the same type over B. Then for a n+1 A \ {a 1,... a n } and any formula ϕ( x, y) over B M = ϕ(ā, a n+1 ) iff card ϕ(ā, M) λ iff M = <λ x ϕ(ā, x). 14

15 Since tp(ā/b) = tp(ā /B) we have card ϕ(ā, M) λ which yields M = ϕ(ā, a n+1) for any a n+1 A, distinct from the coordinates of ā. Corollary 3.1 Any subset A independent over B in a minimal structure M (with cl = acl) is indiscernible over B. Definition A structure M is said to be homogeneous if given subsets B, B M of cardinality less that card M and an elementary isomorphism α : B B there is an extension of α to an automorphism of M. Definition Given a structure M with a closure operator cl we say that M satisfies the countable closure property if cl(x) is at most countable for any finite X M. Remark It is obvious that a structure in a countable language has the countable closure property for cl = acl and indeed for cl = cl ℵ 1. Lemma Any minimal structure with a countable closure property is homogeneous. Proof Suppose B, B M are of cardinality less than card M and there is an elementary monomorphism α : B B. It follows dim B = dim B. By the addition formula dim M/B = dim M/B or dim B = dim M ℵ 0. The latter contradicts the cardinality assumptions since in this case card B dim B = card M. Let A and A be bases of M over B and B correspondingly. Since card A = card A there is a bijection β : A B A B extending α. By Corollary 3.1 β is elementary. Proposition 2.1 finishes the proof. Remark Homogeneity is very important in the study of pregeometries. The uniqueness of closure (Proposition 2.1) is essential for the proof of homogeneity, but often weaker versions suffice. E.g. if F (A) is a differentially 15

16 closed field of characteristic zero constructed as a prime model over a Dfclindependent subset A (see the remark in the end of section 2) then basically the same argument as above yields homogeneity of M. On the other hand it is possible to work effectively with a weaker version of homogeneity. Definition M is said to be ℵ 0 -homogeneous if for every two n-tuples ā and ā in M of equal types over and any b M there is a b M such that tp(āb/ ) = tp(ā b / ). M is said to be ℵ 0 -homogeneous over submodels, if it is ℵ 0 -homogeneous and for every two n-tuples ā and ā in M and any M 0 M, card M 0 < card M, such that tp(ā/m 0 ) = tp(ā /M 0 ) and any b M there is b M satisfying tp(āb/m 0 ) = tp(ā b /M 0 ). Exercise 3.1 If M is countable and ℵ 0 -homogeneous then M is homogeneous. Exercise 3.2 If M is ℵ 1 -minimal, satisfies the exchange principle for cl ℵ 1, card M = ℵ 1 and M is ℵ 0 -homogeneous over submodels then any bijection between two bases of M can be extended to an automorphism of M. Example C e is not homogeneous but is ℵ 0 -homogeneous over submodels. Moreover, any elementary substructure of C e of cardinality ℵ 1 satisfies the conditions of Exercise 3.2. Under GCH this holds for C e itself. 16

17 4 Dimension notion in strongly minimal structures 4.1 Strong minimality Theorem 4.1 Minimal structures of infinite dimension are ℵ 0 -saturated. Proof Let ϕ(x) be a formula over a finite A. Either ϕ(m) is finite, or M \ acl(a) ϕ(m). Thus for any type p over A p(m) = ϕ p ϕ(m) either contains the nonempty set M \ acl(a) or is a nonempty subset of some finite ϕ i (M). Remark If M has the countable closure property then the same argument proves that M is saturated. Definition We say finiteness is strongly definable in M if for every formula ϕ(x, ȳ) there is a number m ϕ such that for any ā in M card ϕ(m) > m ϕ card ϕ(m) ℵ 0. This is in fact a weak version of the negation of the finite cover property often referred to as not f.c.p. Remark The property defined above implies that for every ϕ(x, ȳ) we can state by a first order formula that for any ā both ϕ(m, ā) and ϕ(m, ā) are infinite. Remark One can naturally extend the definition to say λ-smallness is strongly definable in M. Lemma Finiteness is strongly definable in any minimal structure of infinite dimension. 17

18 Proof Suppose towards a contradiction that ϕ(x, ȳ) is a counterexample. Then for any m there is a ā m in M such that ϕ(m, ā m ) is finite of size bigger than m. Then its complement is infinite. Hence ā m realises the formula ψ m (ȳ) := >m x ϕ(x, ȳ) & >m x ϕ(x, ȳ). It follows that the type p = {ψ m : m N} is consistent. By ℵ 0 -saturatedness there is a realisation ā of p in M. By construction both ϕ(m, ā) and ϕ(m, ā) are infinite. The contradiction. Corollary 4.1 Any structure elementary equivalent to a minimal structure of infinite dimension is minimal too. Definition A minimal structure is said to be strongly minimal (abbreviated s.m.) if it is elementarily equivalent to a minimal structure of infinite dimension. An important property of a s.m. structure M is that its minimality is first order, i.e. the theory Th(M) of M forces every model of it to be minimal. Moreover, we have Lemma If M is minimal, A M and N = acl(a) an infinite substructure, then N M. Proof By Tarski s criterion we need to check that if a formula ϕ(x) over N has a realisation b in M then it has one in N. If ϕ(m) is finite then it is a subset of N by the properties of closure. If ϕ(m) is infinite then ϕ(m) is finite and so ϕ(m) N. Remark The lemma has an obvious generalisation to λ-minimal structures. Corollary 4.2 If an infinite dimensional M is minimal and has a countable closure property then Th(M) is categorical in any uncountable cardinality, in particular it has a model in any such cardinality independently on the cardinality of the language. 18

19 4.2 Rank notion for sets definable in s.m. structures. We assume below M is minimal of infinite dimension. To any definable subset S in M we attach a number called the (Morley) rank of S. This in fact is a dimension notion dual to the dimension introduced above. It measures the dimension of macrosets S M n in contrast with the dimension of microsets s M n. Definition Let A M be finite. For an A-definable subset S M n let the rank of S to be rk S = max dim({s 1,... s n }/A) s 1,...s n S Remark The rank notion coincides with the notion of Morley rank. Lemma (i) rk ϕ(m) has the same value in every infinite dimensional structure elementary equivalent to a given s.m. one and (ii)rk ϕ(m) does not depend on the choice of parameters A over which ϕ(m) is definable. Proof Suppose rk ϕ(m) = r and {s 1,..., s r } is a basis of s 1,... s n ϕ(m) of maximal dimension over A. If A A M, M of infinite dimension and M A A M then choose {s 1,..., s r} M independent over A A. Since s i, for all i n, are algebraic over {s 1,..., s r } the type p s1,...,s r = tp( s 1,..., s n /{s 1,..., s r } A) is algebraic and principal. Since tp( s 1,..., s r /A) = tp( s 1,..., s r /A), the type p s 1,...,s obtained by substituting r {s 1,..., s r} for {s 1,..., s r } in all the formulas of p s1,...,s r, is algebraic and principal too. Hence it has a realisation s 1,..., s n which the type says is a point in ϕ(m ) of dimension r over A A. This proves that rk ϕ(m) rk ϕ(m ). By symmetry we have rk ϕ(m) rk ϕ(m ), and the rank remains the same when we extend the set of parameters from A to A A. Then also the rank has to be the same as defined over A. 19

20 Definition For an arbitrary s.m. structure M, rk ϕ(m) is defined as the rank in a saturated elementary extensions of M. Lemma (Basic Rank Properties) For any s.m.structure M (i) rk M n = n; (ii) rk S = 0 iff S is finite (iii) rk (S 1 S 2 ) = max{rk S 1, rk S 2 } (iv) For projection pr : M n M k rk S rk pr(s) + max t pr(s) rk pr 1 (t). (v) Suppose rk pr 1 (t) is the same for all t pr(s). Then rk S = rk pr(s) + rk pr 1 (t). Proof (i)-(iii) are immediate from definition. (iv) Let s 1,... s n S be of maximal dimension in S. Then rk S = dim({s 1,... s n }/A) = dim({s 1,... s n }/{s 1,... s k } A)+ dim({s 1,... s k }/A) rk pr 1 ( s 1,... s k ) + rk prs. (v) If one chooses first a generic s 1,... s k prs and then extends it to s 1,... s n S of maximal possible dimension over {s 1,... s k } A, then dim({s 1,... s n }/{s 1,... s k } A) = rk pr 1 ( s 1,... s k ), and thus dim({s 1,... s k }/A) = rk prs rk S rk prs + rk pr 1 ( s 1,... s k ). 20

21 Lemma For any definable S M n there is an upper bound for m N such that S can be partitioned into k disjoint subsets each of rank equal to rk S. S = S 1 S m Proof We use induction on n. For n = 1 the statement follows by definition. For arbitrary n let rk S = k. This means there is a point s 1,... s n S of dimension k and thus some {s i1,... s ik } are independent. Let us assume i 1,... i k = 1,... k. Then s j acl{s 1,... s k } for all j = 1,..., n, thus for some natural number l = l i1,...i k Denote the formula M = =l x 1,... x n S : x 1,... x k = s 1,... s k. ψ(y 1,... y k ) := =l x 1,... x n S : x 1,... x k = y 1,... y k and notice that ψ(m) M k is of rank k. Let S i 1,...i k = { s 1,... s n S : ψ(s 1,... s k )} Calculating by rank properties above we get rk S i 1,...i k = rk ψ(m) = rk S. Suppose S i 1,...i k = S 1 S p is a partition and all the summands are A -definable of rank k, some A. Then necessarily for any j p there is s j,1,... s j,n S j with the first k coordinates independent over A. By indiscernibility we can choose s j,1,... s j,n S 0 j so that s j,1,... s j,k = s 1,... s k for all j. It follows immediately that p l. Taking into account all possibilities for i 1,... i k we get m l i1,...i k. {i 1,...i k } 21

22 Remark The definition of rank makes sense for any λ-minimal structure of infinite dimension. Part (ii) of Lemma holds for every λ-minimal ℵ 0 -homogeneous structure with the same proof. Correspondingly for such structures the statement of takes form Exercise 4.2 Given S of rank k, any family {S j : j J} of pairwise disjoint definable subsets of rank k of S is of cardinality less than λ. Example The rank notion makes sense in C e and the statement of the Exercise is in close connection with the fact that any analytic subset has at most countably many irreducible components. Definition The exact upper bound for equirank partition of S is called the (Morley) degree of S. A definable set of degree one is said to be irreducible. Definition For a type p( x) definable over A Morley rank of type is defined as rk (p) = min{rk ϕ( x) : ϕ p}. For a point s M n and a subset A M the Morley rank of the point over A is defined as rk ( s/a) = rk (tp( s/a)). Given an irreducible subset S defined over A, a point s S is said to be generic over A if rk ( s/a) = rk S. Exercise 4.3 rk ( s 1,..., s n /A) = dim({s 1,..., s n }/A). Lemma For S irreducible defined over A there is a unique complete type p over A containing S of rank rk S. More exactly, p = tp(s/a) for s generic in S. In particular, any two generic points have the same type over A. 22

23 Proof By irreducibility p = {ϕ( x) over A : rk (ϕ(m) S) = rk S} is a type. The rest follows from definitions. Lemma (The addition formula for tuples) rk ( b c/a) = rk ( b/a c) + rk ( c/a) (Here A c = A c, c is the set of the coordinates of c.) Proof This is just another form of the addition formula for dimensions Definition Two points b M k and c M n are said to be independent over A if rk ( b/a c) = rk ( b/a). Lemma The independence relation is symmetric Proof rk ( b c/a) = rk ( b/a c) + rk ( c/a) = rk ( c/a b) + rk ( b/a) by the addition formula. Then rk ( b/a c) = rk ( b/a) implies rk ( c/a b) + rk ( c/a). Lemma (Definability of Morley Rank) For any formula ϕ( x, ȳ) with length( x) = k, length(ȳ) = n, and any m the set is definable. {ā M k : rk ϕ(ā, M) m} Proof By induction on n. For n = 1 rk ϕ(a, M) 0 iff ϕ(a, M), and rk ϕ(a, M) 1 iff ϕ(a, M) is infinite iff card ϕ(a, M) n ϕ by strong definability of finiteness (not f.c.p.). For arbitrary n rk ϕ(a, y 1,..., y n ) m iff {b M : rk ϕ(a, b, y 2,..., y n ) m 1} is infinite or {b M : rk ϕ(a, b, y 2,..., y n ) m} = by the addition formula for ranks. The both conditions on the right hand side are definable by induction hypothesis. 23

24 4.3 Sets definable in M. We shall consider Morley rank for sets definable in strongly minimal M. Recall that any such set is of the form U = S/E, where S M n is a definable subset and E S 2 M 2n is a definable subset which is an equivalence relation. We consider only U such that E is equirank, i.e. rk E(s, M) is of the same value for all s S. Definition For U = S/E definable in M with E an equivalence relation with equirank classes rk U = rk S rk E(s, M) for s S. Lemma The definition is invariant under definable bijections, i.e. if there is a bijection f : S 1 /E 1 S 2 /E 2 and f is a definable function, then rk S 1 /E 1 = rk S 2 /E 2. Proof By definition f = F/E, where F S 1 S 2, E = E 1 E 2 and the following hold for any s 1, s 1 S 1, s 2, s 2 S 2 F (s 1, s 2 ) & F (s 1, s 2) (E 1 (s 1, s 1) E 2 (s 2, s 2)), pr S1 F = S 1 and pr S2 F = S 2. From the addition formula, projecting on S 1, we get and projecting on S 2 rk F = rk S 1 + rk E 2 (s 2, M) rk F = rk S 2 + rk E 1 (s 1, M). It follows rk S 1 rk E 1 (s 1, M) = rk S 2 rk E 2 (s 2, M). 24

25 Proposition 4.1 Basic Rank Properties (i)-(v) as well as Lemma and definability of rank hold for definable sets. Proof Follow the proofs of the statements mentioned. Notation For definable S 1, S 2 M n and S 1 S 2 rk (S 1 \ S 2 ) < rk S 1 S 1 S 2 S 1 S 2 & S 2 S 1. We also say in words that S 1 is almost a subset of S 2 or S 1 almost coincides with S 2, correspondingly. Proposition 4.2 (Finite Equivalence Relation Theorem) For any A- definable set S of rank k there is an A-definable subset S 0 S and an equivalence relation E on S 0 such that S 0 S, S 0 /E is finite and each equivalence class is of rank k and irreducible. Proof Let Morley degree of S be m and S = Ψ i (b i, M) i m be the partition of S into irreducible subsets of rank k with Ψ i (z, x) A- definable formulas and b i ranging in M n for some n. Our aim is to define an equivalence relation with m equirank classes such that each class almost coincides with one of Ψ i (b i, M). Claim 1. We may choose Ψ i = Ψ independently on i. To get this consider formula Ψ of parameters b 1,..., b m and c 1,... c m, where c 1,... c m are some distinct elements in M : Ψ(y, x) (y = c i Ψ(b i, x)). i m Evidently, Ψ(c i, x) Ψ i (b i, x), which proves the claim. 25

26 Put P = {b M n : Ψ(b, M) S & rk Ψ(b, M) = k & & c M n (rk (Ψ(b, M) Ψ(c, M)) = k (Ψ(b, M) Ψ(c, M)))}. This set is A-definable, b i P for all i m, and for any b P, Ψ(b, M) is an irreducible subset of S of rank k. Define an equivalence relation on P F (b, b ) iff Ψ(b, M) Ψ(b, M). There are exactly m equivalence classes of F with b 1,..., b m representatives of the classes. Claim 2. Let b P, s Ψ(b, M) and rk (s/ab) = k. Then F (b, M) Ψ(M, s). Proof of Claim. Let b F (b, M) be of maximal rank, i.e. rk (b /Abs) = rk F (b, M). Then rk (b /Abs) = rk (b /Ab), which means b and s are independent over Ab. Then rk (s/abb ) = rk (s/ab) = k. Since Ψ(b, M) Ψ(b, M) it follows s Ψ(b, M). In other words Ψ(b, s) holds for all such b and hence F (b, M) Ψ(M, s). Claim 3. For any s S with rk (s/ab 1,..., b m ) = k there is exactly one class F (b, M) such that F (b, M) Ψ(M, s). Indeed, suppose F (b, M) Ψ(M, s) for b = b 1 and b = b 2. Choose b 1, b 2 F (b 1, M) F (b 2, M) of maximal rank over Ab 1 b 2 s. Then rk (b 1b 2/Ab 1 b 2 s) = rk F (b 1, M) + rk F (b 2, M) = rk (b 1b 2/Ab 1 b 2 ). It follows rk (s/ab 1 b 2 b 1b 2) = rk (s/ab 1 b 2 ), and Ψ(b 1, s)&ψ(b 2, s) holds. Hence rk (Ψ(b 1, M)&Ψ(b 1, M)) = k, contradicting F (b 1, b 2). Claim proved. Define S 0 = {s S : there is exactly one class F (b, M) Ψ(M, s)} and E on S 0 to be E(s 1, s 2 ) iff b P F (b, M) Ψ(M, s 1 ) Ψ(M, s 2 ). By definition and claim 3 there is a one-to-one correspondence between E- classes and F -classes. By Claim 2 Ψ(b i, M) E(s i, M) for any generic s i Ψ(b i, M) for all i m. Thus Ψ(b i, M) E(s i, M). 26

27 Corollary 4.3 For A-definable S as above there is a finite A-definable set S 0 such that any irreducible equirank subset of S almost coinsides with an Ab-definable subset for b S 0. Exercise Generalise results of this section to λ-minimal ℵ 0 -homogeneous structures with λ-smallness weakly definable. 27

28 5 Macro-geometries and the Trichotomy Theorem We explore further the geometries of minimal structures. We show in this section that in cases when the geometry of a minimal structure becomes too complicated for analysis, another type of geometry play an important role. We call the new geometries macro-geometry as opposed to micro-geometries introduced in section Macro- and micro-geometries on a s.m. structure. Example 1. Macro-geometry of an algebraically closed field. Let F be a field and A 2 (F ) an affine plane over the field, i.e. A 2 (F ) = F F as a set of points. Let also L 2 (F ) be the set of straight lines on A 2 (F ) that can be identified as the set of triples (a, b, c) F 3, (a, b) (0, 0), modulo the equivalence relation E : (a, b, c)e(a, b, c) iff λ 0 (a, b, c) = λ(a, b, c ) which define a straight line by equation ax + by + c = 0. If we also add a triple (0, 0, 1) to L 2 (F ) we get the classical projective plane over F denoted P 2 (F ). (A 2, L 2 ) can be considered as a two-sorted structure with the incidence relation I A 2 L 2 defined by (x, y)i(a, b, c) iff ax + by = c. Through any two points there is a unique line. Any two lines intersect in at most one point and for almost any pair of lines the intersection is non-empty. By the Main Theorem of Projective Geometry the field is definable in the structure (A 2, L 2, I), in other words the macro-geometry bears all the information on F. 28

29 Example 2. Macro-geometry of a k-vector space. Let k be a field and V an infinite dimensional vector space over k. Consider V 2 as a set of points and, given α k, define a line in V 2 through a point (a, b) with a slope α to be {(x, y) V 2 : α(x a) = y b}. We have as many lines through (a, b) as there are elements in k, bounded independently on the cardinality of V. If k is a finite field the set of lines is definable in V and indeed we can define again a two-sorted structure of points and lines with an incidence relation I. Example 3. Macro-geometry of a trivial structure. Let M be a set. Consider M 2 as a set of points and define a left line through a, b to be { x, y M 2 : x = a}. Correspondingly define the right line. This geometry of points and lines is very simple. Lines almost never meet, and through almost no pair of points there is a common line. Definition An [abstract] projective geometry is a set of points and lines satisfying: (i) through any two points there is a line; (ii) there are at least three points on every line; (iii) two distinct lines intersect in at most one point; (iv) for any distinct points a, b, c, d : if lines (a, b) and (c, d) intersect then lines (a, c) and (b, d) do. Any 3 points a, b, c of a projective geometry which do not lie on a common line generate a projective plane as the set of points S(a, b, c) = {(a, z) : z (b, c)}. By (iv) the plane generated by any non-collinear a, b, c S(a, b, c) coincides with S(a, b, c). The n-subspaces of a projective geometry are defined by induction as S(a 1,..., a n+1 ) = {(a n+1, z) : z (a 1,..., a n )} for a 1,..., a n+1 not in a (n 1)-subspace. Again by axiom (iv) the definition is invariant on the choice of the points in the subspace. 29

30 Theorem 5.1 Any projective geometry of dimension greater than two (generated by no less than 4 points) is isomorphic to a projective geometry over a division ring. Proof See [Se]. Motivated by the definitions above A.Lachlan has introduced the notion of a pseudoplane. We specialise the notion for our purposes Definition A rank-two pseudo-plane is a two-sorted structure (P, L) of points and lines definable in a strongly minimal structure M with an incidence relation I P L such that if l 1, l 2 L, (Here Il = {p P : pil }.) P is irreducible, rk P = 2; rk L 2; rk Il = 1 for all l L; l 1 l 2 then Il 1 Il 2 is finite or empty. Proposition 5.1 Suppose M is a strongly minimal structure and there are a 1, a 2, b 1, b 2, c M every four of which are independent, c acl(a 1, a 2, b 1, b 2 ) and acl(a 1, a 2, c) acl(b 1, b 2, c) = acl(c). Then a rank-two pseudoplane is definable in M. Remark The condition in the Proposition can be stated more geometrically in the localisation M c of the micro-geometry of M : the lines (a 1, a 2 ) and (b 1, b 2 ) of the micro-geometry lie on the same plane (a 1, a 2, b 1, b 2 ) but do not meet. In other words the micro-geometry on (a 1, a 2, b 1, b 2 ) is not that of the projective plane. Proof of the proposition. Put P 0 = M M, L 0 = M M M, and let I 0 P 0 L 0 be an -definable relation such that b 1, b 2 I 0 a 1, a 2, c 30

31 x 1, x 2 I 0 y 1, y 2, z z acl(x 1, x 2, y 1, y 2 ). A definable relation witnessing the dependence between a 1, a 2, b 1, b 2, c has these properties. Our first aim is to transform the incidence relation we have defined to an incidence relation with iinfinite lines meeting in at most finitely many points. Denote l 0 = a 1, a 2, c. Then I 0 l 0 is an l 0 -definable set of Morley rank 1.By the Finite Equivalence Relation Theorem using l 0 one can define an equivalence relation E l0 on I 0 l 0 with finitely many classes, and, say m of them of rank 1 irreducible. Denote I 1 = { p, l I 0 : E l is an equivalence relation on I 0 l with exactly m infinite classes and p is in one of the infinite classes}. Denote a binary relation E on I 1 : Define p, l E p, l iff l = l & pe l p. L 1 = I 1 /E and for k L 1, p P 0 write pi 2 k iff k = p, l for some l L 0. By definitions there is a canonical mapping α : L 1 L 0, corresponding to the projection I 1 L 0, which is exactly m-to-one mapping. Also, for all k L 1 rk (I 2 k) = 1. By definitions, for k 0 corresponding to l 0 via α, I 2 k 0 is irreducible. Define L 2 = {k L 1 : k L 1 rk (I 2 k I 2 k ) = 1 I 2 k I 2 k }. It follows from the above remark that k 0 L 2 and, for all k L 2, rk (I 2 k) = 1. Any two lines represented in L 2 either almost coincide or meet in at most finitely many points. 31

32 Define an equivalence relation on L 2 kf k iff I 2 k I 2 k. We are now in the situation of Claim 2 of the proof of the Finite Equivalence Relation Theorem. It follows that kf pi 2 whenever p is generic in I 2 k over k and p is generic in P 0. Define L 3 = L 2 /F and, for l L 3, p P 0, pi 3 l iff l pi2. From the above proved p 0 I 3 l0 holds, where l 0 is obtained throughout the construction from l 0, p 0. Also, by the construction l 0 acl(l 0 ). Since p 0 I 3 l0 it follows rk (I 3 l0 ) 1. On the other hand, if p I 3 l0 is of maximal rank over l 0 and k l 0 F is of maximal rank over p, l 0 then by definition pi 2 l holds and k and p are independent over l 0. It follows rk (p/ l 0 ) = rk (p/ l 0, k) 1. Thus rk (I 3 l0 ) = 1. Let L = { l L 3 : rk (I 3 l0 ) = 1}, I = I 3 (P L). P = {p P 0 : l L pi 3 l}, Now we need to show that for distinct l 1, l 2 from L I l 1 I l 2 is finite. So, suppose p is a point in the intersection. Choose k 1, k 2 l 1 F l 2 F of maximal rank over p, l 1, l 2. Then p I 2 k 1 I 2 k 2 and p is independent from k 1, k 2 over l 1, l 2. Then rk (p/ l 1, l 2 ) = rk (p/ l 1, l 2, k 1, k 2 ) < 1 since k 1 F k 2. To finish the proof we need to show that rk (L) 2 which would follow from rk ( l 0 / ) 2. Suppose towards the contradiction rk ( l 0 / ) 1. Then, since rk (p 0 / l 0 ) = 1 < rk (p 0 / ), we have rk ( l 0 /p 0 ) < rk ( l 0 / ), i.e. l0 acl(p 0 ) = acl(b 1, b 2 ). Then, from the assumptions of the proposition c / acl( l 0 ). 32

33 On the other hand l 0 acl(l 0 ) = acl(a 1, a 2, c). It follows b 1 / acl(l 0 ), b 2 / acl(l 0 ). Therefore there exists c M such that Thus rk (cc / l 0 ) = 1 and so tp(cc / l 0 ) = tp(b 1 b 2 / l 0 ) = tp(p 0 / l 0 ). c acl( l 0, c) acl(a 1, a 2, c) acl(b 1, b 2, c). Hence acl(c ) = acl(c), contradicting acl(b 1 ) acl(b 2 ). Remark Note that P and L are coordinatised by M in a very strong sense. That is P is a subset of M M, by construction and L is in finite to finite correspondence with M M. To see the latter note that from the very beginning of the construction we could replace L 0 by L 0 (c) = M M {c}, and carry on with the same construction to obtain L 1 (c), L 2 (c), L 3 (c) and finally L(c). The observation at the end of the proof that c / acl( l 0 ) implies that almost all equivalence classes are represented in the smaller sets, that is rk L(c) = 2 and L(c) is in finite to finite correspondence with a rank 2 subset of L. 5.2 The Trichotomy Theorem The condition detected in the Proposition 5.1 can be interpreted as an abstract notion of non-linearity of the geometry. The alternative to the condition is, as follows from the remark to the proposition, that the planes of the geometry of M localised in a generic point are abstract projective or trivial. In this section we study the trichotomy in more details. Theorem 5.2 (weak Trichotomy Theorem) For any strongly minimal M either (i) a rank-two pseudoplane is definable in M or one of the following hold: (ii) the geometry of M is trivial, i.e. for any X ˆM, acl(x) = (X) in ˆM; (iii) the geometry of M is locally projective, i.e. for generic c M the geometry ˆM c is isomorphic to a projective geometry over a division ring. 33

34 Proof Assume no pseudoplane is definable in M and c is a fixed generic element in M. Claim 1. For any x, y M and Z M finite x acl(y, c, Z) implies z acl(c, Z) : x acl(y, z, c). We may assume that Z is independent over c and proceed by induction on #Z. For #Z = 1 there is nothing to prove. Suppose Z = {z 1, z 2 } Z, x acl(y, c, Z), y / acl(c, Z). Then, by Proposition 5.1, in M Z either (i) some quadruple from x, y, z 1, z 2, c is dependent or (ii) z M \ acl Z (c) acl Z (z 1, z 2, c) acl Z (x, y, c) acl Z (z, c). In case (i) only x acl Z (y, z 1, z 2 ) is non-trivial. Which means in M x acl(y, z 1, {z 2 Z }). Since #{z 2, Z } < #Z by induction hypothesis there is z acl(z 1, z 2, Z ) : x acl(y, z 1, z). If then dim(y, z 1, z, c) = 3, we have x acl(y, z 1, c) or x acl(y, z, c) and we get the desired. Otherwise, there is a point z 1 acl(z 1, z, c) \ (acl(z 1, z) acl(c, z 1 ) acl(c, z)). Assuming x / acl(y, z) we have then that any four points of {x, y, z, z 1, c} are independent. Again, using the Proposition and our assumption, there must exist z M \ acl(c) such that acl(z, z 1, c) acl(x, y, c) acl(z, c). Clearly z acl(c, Z) acl(x, y, c), so x acl(y, z, c) and we are done. In case (ii) z acl(c, Z) and x acl Z (y, z, c), i.e. x acl(y, c, z, Z ). By the induction hypothesis there is z acl(c, z, Z ) such that x acl(y, z, c). Claim proved. Claim 2. If acl(x, y, c) = acl(x, c) = acl(y, c) for some x, y independent over c then the geometry ˆM is degenerate, i.e. acl(x 0,..., x n ) = acl(x 0 ) acl(x n ) for any x 0,..., x n M. Indeed, under the assumption, acl(x 0, x 1, x 2 ) = acl(x 0, x 1 ) acl(x 0, x 2 ) for any independent triple. We show first that the claim is true for n = 1. 34

35 Assume towards a contradiction y acl(x 1, x 2 ) \ (acl(x 1 ) acl(x 2 )). Choose x 0 / acl(x 1, x 2 ). Then y acl(x 0, x 1, x 2 ) = acl(x 0, x 1 ) acl(x 0, x 2 ). But if y acl(x 0, x i ) for i = 1 or i = 2 then x 0 acl(y, x i ) = acl(x 1, x 2 ), the contradiction. Now we proceed by induction on n. Suppose y acl(x 0,..., x n ). Then by Claim 1 there is x acl(x 0,..., x n 1 ) such that y acl(x n, x, x 0 ). From what is proved already y acl(x, x 0 ) acl(x n, x 0 ). Hence y acl(x 0,..., x n 1 ) acl(x 0, x n ) = acl(x 0,..., x n 1 ) acl(x n ) acl(x n ) = acl(x 0 ) acl(x n ). This finishes the proof of the claim and of the Theorem Geometries with finite closure property Definition A pregeometry (or a minimal structure) M is said to have the finite closure property (sometimes also said locally finite) if for any finite set X M, cl(x) is finite. It is useful to note that if the theory of a structure M is ℵ 0 -categorical (or definable in such one) then, as a direct consequence of the Ryll-Nardzewski Theorem, M has the finite closure property. In particular the following theorem fully characterises the geometries of strongly minimal structures definable in ℵ 0 -categorical theories. A very important consequence of the finite closure property is the possibility to introduce a stronger counting function on definable sets. Notation For a definable set S in M eq and a subset X M denote S(X) = cl(x) S, where cl(x) is taken in M eq. In particular, M(X) = cl(x) M. Proposition 5.2 Assuming the finite closure property holds in a s.m. structure M, for every set S in M eq over parameters C there is a polynomial p S Q[x] and a number n S such that for every finite C X M : 35

36 (i) letting M(X) = x n S, we have S(X) = p S (x); (ii) rk S = deg p S, the degree of the polynomial; (iii) if g(s)=t for some automorphism g of M then p S = p T and n S = n T. Proof We construct the polynomial for a given S. W.l.o.g. we may assume that S is an atom over C, that is defined by a principal type over C. It then has a form S = U/E where U M n is an atom over C of rank k n and E a C-definable equivalence relation on U. Claim 1. For any finite X C where U(X) = m U (x u 0 ) (x u k 1 ) = p U (x), u 0 = M(C),..., u k 1 = M(C {d 1,..., d k 1 }),... d 1,..., d k 1 any independent over C elements of M, and given such d 1,..., d k 1, m U = { d k,..., d n M n k : d 1,..., d k 1, d k,..., d n U} when we assume that enumeration of coordinates is such that, for a 1,..., a n U, a 1,..., a k are independent over C. Proof Indeed U(X) consists of all possible n-tuples independent over C in the first k coordinates in M(X) and the rest of the coordinates algebraic over them. We also see from the description of p U that it is invariant under automorphisms and n U = 0. As a corollary of the claim we have polynomials with the same properties for any definable subset of M n. Claim 2. Let s S and E s M n be the s-definable E-equivalence class representing s. Then p Es (x) = E s (X) for any x n s, some n s, and S(X) = p U(x) p Es (X) = p S(x) for a polynomial p S Q[x]. Proof Choose n s to be the cardinality of M(C {s} {d 1,..., d l }) for a minimal {d 1,..., d l } M independent over C {s} such that E s (C {s} 36

37 {d 1,..., d l }). Using automorphisms one sees that E s is an atom over C {s}, thus the construction of Claim 1 applies and we get a polynomial p Es (x) = m s (x e 0 ) (x e l 1 ), for some e i of the same description as u j in the definition of p S, l = rk E s k. More precisely e 0 = u r,..., e l 1 = u r+l 1 for some r k l. The claim and the proposition follow. Notation We thus introduced a counting function S = p S, the polynomial of a definable set S and in particular m(s) the leading coefficient of the polynomial S. m S is called also the (relative) multiplicity of S. Theorem 5.3 The geometry of a minimal structure with the finite closure property is either trivial or isomorphic to an affine or a projective geometry over a finite field. Idea of Proof. First notice that the structure is saturated and thus is strongly minimal. We first want to establish that the geometry of M is locally projective or trivial. In order to do this, by the Trichotomy Theorem, we only need to prove that there is no two-rank pseudoplane in M. It is done by developing a combinatorial-geometric analysis of the pseudoplane (P, I, L), assuming it exists. The main tool of the analysis is the powerful rank notion S introduced above for a structure with the finite closure property, or rather the multiplicity m(s) in combination with the Morley rank rk (S). See [Z] for the proof. After one proves that M is locally projective or trivial one can use a combinatorial result by Doyen and Hubaut which states that any finite locally projective geometry of dimension 4 with equal number of points on all its lines is either affine or projective. Corollary 5.1 Any geometry satisfying the finite closure property and the homogeneity assumption (any bijection between bases can be extended to an automorphism) is either trivial or isomorphic to an affine or a projective geometry over a finite field. 37

38 Proof In an appropriate language such a geometry can be represented as a strongly minimal structure with finite closure property (see [Z]). The weak Trichotomy Theorem generates the natural question: Does the definability of a rank-two pseudoplane in M imply that the micro-geometry of M is isomorphic to that of an algebraically closed field F. The answer is NO in general (E.Hrushovski [H]) and YES if one assumes some extra topological-kind (Zariski) assumptions for M (E.Hrushovski and B.Zilber [HZ]). Both results have been actively developed and applied in model theory and elsewhere in mathematics. Problem Generalise results of this section to λ-minimal ℵ 0 -homogeneous structures with λ-smallness weakly definable. 38

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

ω-stable Theories: Introduction ω-stable Theories: Introduction 1 ω - Stable/Totally Transcendental Theories Throughout let T be a complete theory in a countable language L having infinite models. For an L-structure M and A M let Sn

More information

An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set

An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set Martin Ziegler Barcelona, July 2011 In [5] E. Hrushovski proved the following theorem: Theorem 0.1 (Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set). There

More information

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 Instructions: Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 If you signed up for Computability Theory, do two E and two C problems. If you signed up for Model Theory, do two E and two M problems. If you signed up

More information

Stable embeddedness and N IP

Stable embeddedness and N IP Stable embeddedness and N IP Anand Pillay University of Leeds January 14, 2010 Abstract We give some sufficient conditions for a predicate P in a complete theory T to be stably embedded. Let P be P with

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. In this paper, we will introduce some of the most basic concepts in geometric stability theory, and attempt to state a dichotomy theorem

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minim. Minimal Structures

On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minim. Minimal Structures On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minimal Structures BPGMT 2013 Definition - Strongly Minimal In this talk, when we say a set is definable in a model M, we mean it is definable in the language

More information

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY VICTOR ZHANG Abstract. We demonstrate how several problems of algebraic geometry, i.e. Ax-Grothendieck, Hilbert s Nullstellensatz, Noether- Ostrowski, and Hilbert s

More information

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries Marko Djordjevi bstract We prove, by a probabilistic argument, that a class of ω-categorical structures, on which algebraic closure

More information

Introduction to Model Theory

Introduction to Model Theory Introduction to Model Theory Charles Steinhorn, Vassar College Katrin Tent, University of Münster CIRM, January 8, 2018 The three lectures Introduction to basic model theory Focus on Definability More

More information

INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY

INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY ARTEM CHERNIKOV Lecture notes for the IMS Graduate Summer School in Logic, National University of Singapore, Jun 2017. The material is based on a number of sources including:

More information

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson American Institute of Mathematics Workshop September 2006 Outline Continuous logic 1 Continuous logic 2 The metric on S n (T ) Origins Continuous logic Many classes of (complete)

More information

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0 BENJAMIN LEDEAUX Abstract. This expository paper introduces model theory with a focus on countable models of complete theories. Vaught

More information

SUPPLEMENT TO DENSE PAIRS OF O-MINIMAL STRUCTURES BY LOU VAN DEN DRIES

SUPPLEMENT TO DENSE PAIRS OF O-MINIMAL STRUCTURES BY LOU VAN DEN DRIES SUPPLEMENT TO DENSE PIRS OF O-MINIML STRUCTURES BY LOU VN DEN DRIES LLEN GEHRET Introduction If in doubt, all notations and assumptions are with respect to [7]. Generally speaking, exercises are things

More information

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures Roman Wencel 1 Instytut Matematyczny Uniwersytetu Wroc lawskiego ABSTRACT We consider a class of weakly o-minimal structures admitting

More information

Pregeometries and minimal types

Pregeometries and minimal types Pregeometries and minimal types Enrique Casanovas Universidad de Barcelona May 9, 2006. Revised November 11, 2008 1 Pregeometries Definition 1.1 Let Ω be a set (more generally, a class) and let cl be a

More information

GEOMETRIC STRUCTURES WITH A DENSE INDEPENDENT SUBSET

GEOMETRIC STRUCTURES WITH A DENSE INDEPENDENT SUBSET GEOMETRIC STRUCTURES WITH A DENSE INDEPENDENT SUBSET ALEXANDER BERENSTEIN AND EVGUENI VASSILIEV Abstract. We generalize the work of [13] on expansions of o-minimal structures with dense independent subsets,

More information

Hrushovski s Fusion. A. Baudisch, A. Martin-Pizarro, M. Ziegler March 4, 2007

Hrushovski s Fusion. A. Baudisch, A. Martin-Pizarro, M. Ziegler March 4, 2007 Hrushovski s Fusion A. Baudisch, A. Martin-Pizarro, M. Ziegler March 4, 2007 Abstract We present a detailed and simplified exposition of Hrushovki s fusion of two strongly minimal theories. 1 Introduction

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

Stability Theory and its Variants

Stability Theory and its Variants Model Theory, Algebra, and Geometry MSRI Publications Volume 39, 2000 Stability Theory and its Variants BRADD HART Abstract. Dimension theory plays a crucial technical role in stability theory and its

More information

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background. Model Theory II. 80824 22.10.2006-22.01-2007 (not: 17.12) Time: The first meeting will be on SUNDAY, OCT. 22, 10-12, room 209. We will try to make this time change permanent. Please write ehud@math.huji.ac.il

More information

Classifying classes of structures in model theory

Classifying classes of structures in model theory Classifying classes of structures in model theory Saharon Shelah The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel, and Rutgers University, NJ, USA ECM 2012 Saharon Shelah (HUJI and Rutgers) Classifying classes

More information

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007 Modern Model Theory Begins Theorem (Morley 1965) If a countable first order theory is categorical in one uncountable cardinal it is categorical in all uncountable cardinals. Outline 1 2 3 SELF-CONSCIOUS

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Joint work with: W. Boney, S. Friedman, C. Laskowski, M. Koerwien, S. Shelah, I. Souldatos University of Illinois at Chicago AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Cantor s Middle Attic Uncountable

More information

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 s to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 In the problems below L is a signature and X is a set of variables. Problem 0. Define a function λ from the set of finite nonempty sequences of elements

More information

MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM

MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM NICK RAMSEY Abstract. A theory is called κ-categorical, or categorical in power κ, if it has one model up to isomorphism of cardinality κ. Morley s Categoricity Theorem states

More information

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Department of Mathematics Bachelor Thesis (7.5 ECTS) Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Author: Dionijs van Tuijl Supervisor: Dr. Jaap van Oosten June 15, 2016 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminaries

More information

Disjoint n-amalgamation

Disjoint n-amalgamation October 13, 2015 Varieties of background theme: the role of infinitary logic Goals 1 study n- toward 1 existence/ of atomic models in uncountable cardinals. 2 0-1-laws 2 History, aec, and Neo-stability

More information

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin large and large and March 3, 2015 Characterizing cardinals by L ω1,ω large and L ω1,ω satisfies downward Lowenheim Skolem to ℵ 0 for sentences. It does not satisfy upward Lowenheim Skolem. Definition sentence

More information

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. MAT 200, Logic, Language and Proof, Fall 2015 Summary Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. Definition. A proposition is a sentence which is either true or false. Truth table for the connective or :

More information

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems Logic SEP: Day 1 July 15, 2013 1 Some references Syllabus: http://www.math.wisc.edu/graduate/guide-qe Previous years qualifying exams: http://www.math.wisc.edu/ miller/old/qual/index.html Miller s Moore

More information

Isomorphisms between pattern classes

Isomorphisms between pattern classes Journal of Combinatorics olume 0, Number 0, 1 8, 0000 Isomorphisms between pattern classes M. H. Albert, M. D. Atkinson and Anders Claesson Isomorphisms φ : A B between pattern classes are considered.

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2010) 944 955 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Types directed by constants

More information

Topics in relational Hrushovski constructions - Fall

Topics in relational Hrushovski constructions - Fall Topics in relational Hrushovski constructions - Fall 2018-2019 Omer Mermelstein UW-Madison Fall 2018 1 Notation Denote by P(X) the set of subsets of X and by Fin(X) the set of finite subsets of X. Write

More information

INDEPENDENCE RELATIONS IN RANDOMIZATIONS

INDEPENDENCE RELATIONS IN RANDOMIZATIONS INDEPENDENE RELATIONS IN RANDOMIZATIONS URI ANDREWS, ISAA GOLDBRING, AND H. JEROME KEISLER Abstract. The randomization of a complete first order theory T is the complete continuous theory T R with two

More information

MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS

MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS MOSHE KAMENSKY Lecture 1, Aug. 28, 2009 1. Introduction The purpose of this course is to learn the fundamental results about the model theory of difference fields, as

More information

Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin

Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin Math 5A Model Theory Speirs, Martin Autumn 013 General Information These notes are based on a course in Metamathematics taught by Professor Thomas Scanlon at UC Berkeley in the Autumn of 013. The course

More information

Winter School on Galois Theory Luxembourg, February INTRODUCTION TO PROFINITE GROUPS Luis Ribes Carleton University, Ottawa, Canada

Winter School on Galois Theory Luxembourg, February INTRODUCTION TO PROFINITE GROUPS Luis Ribes Carleton University, Ottawa, Canada Winter School on alois Theory Luxembourg, 15-24 February 2012 INTRODUCTION TO PROFINITE ROUPS Luis Ribes Carleton University, Ottawa, Canada LECTURE 2 2.1 ENERATORS OF A PROFINITE ROUP 2.2 FREE PRO-C ROUPS

More information

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2. 20 Definition 20.1. A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2. (a) Each natural number n is an ordinal. (b) ω is an ordinal. (a) ω {ω} is an ordinal.

More information

An Introduction to Equations and Equational Theories. Allen O Hara - University Of Waterloo

An Introduction to Equations and Equational Theories. Allen O Hara - University Of Waterloo n Introduction to Equations and Equational Theories llen O Hara - University Of Waterloo Contents 1 Introduction 3 Model Theory Background.............................................. 4 Some Chain Conditions................................................

More information

Foundations. September 4, Foundations. A Model Theoretic Perspective. John T. Baldwin. sociology. Thesis I. Thesis II. A Concept Analysis

Foundations. September 4, Foundations. A Model Theoretic Perspective. John T. Baldwin. sociology. Thesis I. Thesis II. A Concept Analysis September 4, 2009 Outline 1 2 3 4 A Data point for PBPL Practice based philosophy of logic Are model theorists logicians? They do not analyze methods of reasoning. A Data point for PBPL Practice based

More information

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS URI ANDREWS AND H. JEROME KEISLER Abstract. Every complete first order theory has a corresponding complete theory in continuous logic, called the randomization theory.

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs

Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs Gabriel Conant UIC Graduate Student Conference in Logic University of Notre Dame April 28-29, 2012 Gabriel Conant (UIC) Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs April

More information

The number of countable models

The number of countable models The number of countable models Enrique Casanovas March 11, 2012 1 Small theories Definition 1.1 T is small if for all n < ω, S n ( ) ω. Remark 1.2 If T is small, then there is a countable L 0 L such that

More information

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago May 22, 2005 1 Is the Vaught Conjecture model

More information

Intermediate Model Theory

Intermediate Model Theory Intermediate Model Theory (Notes by Josephine de la Rue and Marco Ferreira) 1 Monday 12th December 2005 1.1 Ultraproducts Let L be a first order predicate language. Then M =< M, c M, f M, R M >, an L-structure

More information

arxiv: v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014

arxiv: v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014 ON SETS WITH RANK ONE IN SIMPLE HOMOGENEOUS STRUCTURES OVE AHLMAN AND VERA KOPONEN arxiv:1403.3079v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014 Abstract. We study definable sets D of SU-rank 1 in M eq, where M is a countable

More information

Computability Theoretic Properties of Injection Structures

Computability Theoretic Properties of Injection Structures Computability Theoretic Properties of Injection Structures Douglas Cenzer 1, Valentina Harizanov 2 and Jeffrey B. Remmel 3 Abstract We study computability theoretic properties of computable injection structures

More information

A trichotomy of countable, stable, unsuperstable theories

A trichotomy of countable, stable, unsuperstable theories A trichotomy of countable, stable, unsuperstable theories Michael C. Laskowski Department of Mathematics University of Maryland S. Shelah Department of Mathematics Hebrew University of Jerusalem Department

More information

MODEL THEORY OF GROUPS (MATH 223M, UCLA, SPRING 2018)

MODEL THEORY OF GROUPS (MATH 223M, UCLA, SPRING 2018) MODEL THEORY OF GROUPS (MATH 223M, UCLA, SPRING 2018) ARTEM CHERNIKOV Lecture notes in progress. All comments and corrections are very welcome. Last update: May 21, 2018 Contents 1. Introduction 1 1.1.

More information

Continuum Harvard. April 11, Constructing Borel Models in the. Continuum Harvard. John T. Baldwin. University of Illinois at Chicago

Continuum Harvard. April 11, Constructing Borel Models in the. Continuum Harvard. John T. Baldwin. University of Illinois at Chicago April 11, 2013 Today s Topics 1 2 3 4 5 6 Pseudo-minimal 7 Further Applications Section 1: { Models in L ω1,ω L ω1,ω satisfies downward Löwenheim Skolem to ℵ 0 for sentences. It does not satisfy upward

More information

Stable embeddedness and N IP

Stable embeddedness and N IP Stable embeddedness and N IP arxiv:1001.0515v1 [math.lo] 4 Jan 2010 Anand Pillay University of Leeds January 4, 2010 Abstract We give some sufficient conditions for a predicate P in a complete theory T

More information

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n 10. Algebraic closure Definition 10.1. Let K be a field. The algebraic closure of K, denoted K, is an algebraic field extension L/K such that every polynomial in K[x] splits in L. We say that K is algebraically

More information

1 Introductory notes on the model theory of valued fields

1 Introductory notes on the model theory of valued fields 1 Introductory notes on the model theory of valued fields Zoé Chatzidakis a (CNRS - Université Paris 7) These notes will give some very basic definitions and results from model theory. They contain many

More information

Reducts of Stable, CM-trivial Theories

Reducts of Stable, CM-trivial Theories Reducts of Stable, CM-trivial Theories Herwig Nübling 27th July 2004 Abstract We show that every reduct of a stable, CM-trivial theory of finite Lascar rank is CM-trivial. AMS classification: 03C45 Keywords:

More information

Definitions. Notations. Injective, Surjective and Bijective. Divides. Cartesian Product. Relations. Equivalence Relations

Definitions. Notations. Injective, Surjective and Bijective. Divides. Cartesian Product. Relations. Equivalence Relations Page 1 Definitions Tuesday, May 8, 2018 12:23 AM Notations " " means "equals, by definition" the set of all real numbers the set of integers Denote a function from a set to a set by Denote the image of

More information

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS AARON LANDESMAN CONTENTS 1. Introduction to finite fields 2 2. Definition and constructions of fields 3 2.1. The definition of a field 3 2.2. Constructing field extensions by adjoining

More information

GROUPS DEFINABLE IN O-MINIMAL STRUCTURES

GROUPS DEFINABLE IN O-MINIMAL STRUCTURES GROUPS DEFINABLE IN O-MINIMAL STRUCTURES PANTELIS E. ELEFTHERIOU Abstract. In this series of lectures, we will a) introduce the basics of o- minimality, b) describe the manifold topology of groups definable

More information

10. Smooth Varieties. 82 Andreas Gathmann

10. Smooth Varieties. 82 Andreas Gathmann 82 Andreas Gathmann 10. Smooth Varieties Let a be a point on a variety X. In the last chapter we have introduced the tangent cone C a X as a way to study X locally around a (see Construction 9.20). It

More information

Model Theory of Differential Fields

Model Theory of Differential Fields Model Theory, Algebra, and Geometry MSRI Publications Volume 39, 2000 Model Theory of Differential Fields DAVID MARKER Abstract. This article surveys the model theory of differentially closed fields, an

More information

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Peter J. Cameron and D. Lockett School of Mathematical Sciences Queen Mary, University of London Mile End Road London E1 4NS, U.K. Abstract Jarik Nešetřil suggested

More information

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS SOLUTIONS

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS SOLUTIONS MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS PURE MATHEMATICS OPTION SPRING 010 SOLUTIONS Algebra A1. Let F be a finite field. Prove that F [x] contains infinitely many prime ideals. Solution: The ring F [x] of

More information

Imaginaries in Boolean algebras.

Imaginaries in Boolean algebras. Imaginaries in Boolean algebras. Roman Wencel 1 Instytut Matematyczny Uniwersytetu Wroc lawskiego ABSTRACT Given an infinite Boolean algebra B, we find a natural class of -definable equivalence relations

More information

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) VI.1 : Indexed families and set theoretic operations (Halmos, 4, 8 9; Lipschutz, 5.3 5.4) Lipschutz : 5.3 5.6, 5.29 5.32, 9.14 1. Generalize

More information

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1 Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1 2.1) By definition, 2 Ω is the set of all subsets of Ω. Therefore, to show that 2 Ω is a σ-algebra we must show that the conditions of the definition σ-algebra are

More information

Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures

Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures Rose-Hulman Undergraduate Mathematics Journal Volume 18 Issue 1 Article 14 Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures Brian Tyrrell Trinity College Dublin Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.rose-hulman.edu/rhumj

More information

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS.

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS. FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS. Let A be a ring, for simplicity assumed commutative. A filtering, or filtration, of an A module M means a descending sequence of submodules M = M 0

More information

GENERALIZED AMALGAMATION IN SIMPLE THEORIES AND CHARACTERIZATION OF DEPENDENCE IN NON-ELEMENTARY CLASSES

GENERALIZED AMALGAMATION IN SIMPLE THEORIES AND CHARACTERIZATION OF DEPENDENCE IN NON-ELEMENTARY CLASSES GENERALIZED AMALGAMATION IN SIMPLE THEORIES AND CHARACTERIZATION OF DEPENDENCE IN NON-ELEMENTARY CLASSES By Alexei Kolesnikov Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor

More information

What is the right type-space? Humboldt University. July 5, John T. Baldwin. Which Stone Space? July 5, Tameness.

What is the right type-space? Humboldt University. July 5, John T. Baldwin. Which Stone Space? July 5, Tameness. Goals The fundamental notion of a Stone space is delicate for infinitary logic. I will describe several possibilities. There will be a quiz. Infinitary Logic and Omitting Types Key Insight (Chang, Lopez-Escobar)

More information

Axioms for Set Theory

Axioms for Set Theory Axioms for Set Theory The following is a subset of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms for set theory. In this setting, all objects are sets which are denoted by letters, e.g. x, y, X, Y. Equality is logical identity:

More information

Lecture notes - Applied Stability Theory (Math 414) Autumn 2003.

Lecture notes - Applied Stability Theory (Math 414) Autumn 2003. Lecture notes - Applied Stability Theory (Math 414) Autumn 2003. Anand Pillay December 17, 2003 1 Differential fields: first properties. All the rings we deal with are assumed to be commutative, with a

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Ivan Avramidi New Mexico Institute of Mining and Technology Socorro, NM 87801 June 3, 2004 Author: Ivan Avramidi; File: absmath.tex; Date: June 11,

More information

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. This paper attempts to serve as an introduction to abstract model theory. We introduce the notion of abstract logics, explore first-order logic as an instance

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Set theory and topology

Set theory and topology arxiv:1306.6926v1 [math.ho] 28 Jun 2013 Set theory and topology An introduction to the foundations of analysis 1 Part II: Topology Fundamental Felix Nagel Abstract We provide a formal introduction into

More information

1 Fields and vector spaces

1 Fields and vector spaces 1 Fields and vector spaces In this section we revise some algebraic preliminaries and establish notation. 1.1 Division rings and fields A division ring, or skew field, is a structure F with two binary

More information

Fields and Galois Theory. Below are some results dealing with fields, up to and including the fundamental theorem of Galois theory.

Fields and Galois Theory. Below are some results dealing with fields, up to and including the fundamental theorem of Galois theory. Fields and Galois Theory Below are some results dealing with fields, up to and including the fundamental theorem of Galois theory. This should be a reasonably logical ordering, so that a result here should

More information

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ NICOLAS FORD Abstract. The goal of this paper is to present a proof of the Nullstellensatz using tools from a branch of logic called model theory. In

More information

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces Chapter 2 Metric Spaces The purpose of this chapter is to present a summary of some basic properties of metric and topological spaces that play an important role in the main body of the book. 2.1 Metrics

More information

ON SATURATION AND THE MODEL THEORY OF COMPACT KÄHLER MANIFOLDS

ON SATURATION AND THE MODEL THEORY OF COMPACT KÄHLER MANIFOLDS ON SATURATION AND THE MODEL THEORY OF COMPACT KÄHLER MANIFOLDS RAHIM MOOSA Abstract. A hypothesis is introduced under which a compact complex analytic space, X, viewed as a structure in the language of

More information

Math 145. Codimension

Math 145. Codimension Math 145. Codimension 1. Main result and some interesting examples In class we have seen that the dimension theory of an affine variety (irreducible!) is linked to the structure of the function field in

More information

The most important result in this section is undoubtedly the following theorem.

The most important result in this section is undoubtedly the following theorem. 28 COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA 6.4. Examples of Noetherian rings. So far the only rings we can easily prove are Noetherian are principal ideal domains, like Z and k[x], or finite. Our goal now is to develop theorems

More information

NOTES ON O-MINIMALITY

NOTES ON O-MINIMALITY NOTES ON O-MINIMALITY 1. O-minimality In what follows, < is a binary relation symbol and L ord is the language with just this symbol, that is to say, L ord is the language of ordered structures. We will

More information

Mathematical Logic II

Mathematical Logic II Mathematical Logic II Dag Normann January 7, 2004 Contents 1 Classical Model Theory 5 1.1 Embeddings and isomorphisms................... 5 1.2 Elementary embeddings....................... 10 1.3 Complete

More information

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order. October 12, 2010 Sacks Dicta... the central notions of model theory are absolute absoluteness, unlike cardinality, is a logical concept. That is why model theory does not founder on that rock of undecidability,

More information

Weight and measure in NIP theories

Weight and measure in NIP theories Weight and measure in NIP theories Anand Pillay University of Leeds September 18, 2011 Abstract We initiate an account of Shelah s notion of strong dependence in terms of generically stable measures, proving

More information

Groups of Prime Power Order with Derived Subgroup of Prime Order

Groups of Prime Power Order with Derived Subgroup of Prime Order Journal of Algebra 219, 625 657 (1999) Article ID jabr.1998.7909, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Groups of Prime Power Order with Derived Subgroup of Prime Order Simon R. Blackburn*

More information

Basics of Model Theory

Basics of Model Theory Chapter udf Basics of Model Theory bas.1 Reducts and Expansions mod:bas:red: defn:reduct mod:bas:red: prop:reduct Often it is useful or necessary to compare languages which have symbols in common, as well

More information

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES ISAAC GODBRING AND HENRY TOWSNER Abstract. We show that any countable model of a model complete theory has an elementary extension with a pseudofinite-like

More information

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u.

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u. 5. Fields 5.1. Field extensions. Let F E be a subfield of the field E. We also describe this situation by saying that E is an extension field of F, and we write E/F to express this fact. If E/F is a field

More information

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12 MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 2 CİHAN BAHRAN 3.2.. Let Y be a Noetherian scheme. Show that any Y -scheme X of finite type is Noetherian. Moreover, if Y is of finite dimension, then so is X. Write f

More information

Fundamentals of Model Theory

Fundamentals of Model Theory Fundamentals of Model Theory William Weiss and Cherie D Mello Department of Mathematics University of Toronto c 2015 W.Weiss and C. D Mello 1 Introduction Model Theory is the part of mathematics which

More information

Lecture notes on strongly minimal sets (and fields) with a generic automorphism

Lecture notes on strongly minimal sets (and fields) with a generic automorphism Lecture notes on strongly minimal sets (and fields) with a generic automorphism Anand Pillay October 5, 2005 1 Introduction These lecture notes develop the theory of strongly minimal sets with a generic

More information

The Countable Henkin Principle

The Countable Henkin Principle The Countable Henkin Principle Robert Goldblatt Abstract. This is a revised and extended version of an article which encapsulates a key aspect of the Henkin method in a general result about the existence

More information