DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY"

Transcription

1 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY Abstract. This paper considers whether an analogy between distance and dissimilarity supports the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space. A traditional way to justify the thesis would be to prove representation and uniqueness theorems, according to which if comparative dissimilarity meets certain qualitative conditions, then it is representable by distance in a metric space. But I will argue that those qualitative conditions which are strong enough to capture the analogy between distance and dissimilarity are not met by either actual or possible particulars. 1. Introduction Imagine things arranged in space so that the more similar they are, the closer they are together. Then it is plausible that the degree of dissimilarity between those things is their distance apart in that space. If the merchandise in a department store, for example, were arranged so that more similar items were closer together, then the degree of dissimilarity between the shoes and the socks, for example, would be roughly proportional to the distance between the shoe section and the sock section. This paper considers to what extent this analogy between distance and dissimilarity supports the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space. The thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space is not trivial. The produce in a grocery store, for example, is not quite arranged so that more similar goods are closer together despite their dissimilarity, milk and bread, for example, are often together at the back of the store. Perhaps this problem is due merely to greed on the part of grocers, or a limitation of the physical geometry of the store. But perhaps it is impossible even in Date: March 2,

2 2 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY principle to arrange the store so that similar goods are closer together. So, despite the suggestiveness of the analogy between distance and dissimilarity, the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space requires a more thorough justification. A traditional way to justify the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space is via the proof of a representation and uniqueness theorem. According to a representation theorem, if a structure meets certain qualitative conditions, then it has a certain quantitative representation if goodness of films, for example, met certain qualitative conditions, then it would be possible to represent how good they are on a five star scale. Likewise, it is possible to prove a representation theorem to the effect that if comparative dissimilarity meets certain qualitative conditions, then it is representable by distance in a metric space. In addition to a representation theorem, it is desirable to prove a uniqueness theorem, according to which all alternative representations of a given structure are a certain kind of transformation of each other. A uniqueness theorem for the representation of temperature, for example, would show that the representation in terms of degrees Celsius is unique, since any alternative representations of temperature such as in terms of degrees Fahrenheit or degrees Kelvin are merely affine transformations of the representation in terms of degrees Celsius. In particular, if a structure is represented by an ordinal scale, then any other ordinal scale in other words, any scale preserving the same order representing that structure is an increasing function of the first [5, 11]. If goodness of films, for example, is representable on a five star scale, then a ten star scale would be equally as good, as long as it represents the films in the same order. But I will argue in section (3) that representations of degree of dissimilarity derived from an ordinal scale fail to capture the spirit of the analogy between distance and dissimilarity.

3 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 3 If a structure is represented by a ratio scale, on the other hand, then any other ratio scale representing that structure is a positive multiple of the first in other words, the ratio of two measurements will be the same according to every representation [5, 10]. Whereas an ordinal scale represents only whether a given quantity is greater than another, a ratio scale represents how much greater, since the representation of any two quantities will be in the same proportion to each other according to any ratio scale. If one quantity is, for example, twice as great as another according to one ratio scale, then it will be twice as great according to every ratio scale. If enough things are arranged in space so that the more similar they are, the closer they are together, then it s plausible not only that their degree of dissimilarity is their distance apart in that space, but also that if two things are twice as far in that space from each other as two other things are, then the first two things are twice as dissimilar to each other as the second two things are. So the analogy between distance and dissimilarity suggests that the representation of comparative dissimilarity by distance in a metric space is a ratio scale. I will concede in sections (4) and (5) that a representation of degree of dissimilarity based on a ratio scale would succeed in capturing the spirit of the analogy between distance and dissimilarity. Nevertheless, I will present a dilemma for the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is representable as distance in a metric space. If comparative dissimilarity is a relation between actual particulars, then even if it meets the conditions required for an ordinal scale, it might not meet those required for a ratio scale. But if comparative dissimilarity is a relation between possible particulars, then although it meets one of the two important conditions for representability by a ratio scale, it fails to meet the other. So the representation theorem fails to show that comparative dissimilarity is representable by a ratio scale. A closely related technical reason that possible particulars may not be representable by distance in a metric space has been pointed out before

4 4 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY (see especially [7, 51] and [15, 458-9]). But in the context of an ordinal scale, it is natural to dismiss this problem as a mere technicality: as David Lewis, for example, writes This limitation hardly seems serious [7, 51]. In contrast, I will argue that in the context of representation by a ratio scale, the problem is not merely technical, but seriously undermines the justification of the thesis that comparative dissimilarity is representable by distance in a metric space. The analogy between distance and dissimilarity has many philosophical applications, including to possible worlds semantics for conditionals [7, 50-52], the analysis of probability [1][2], the measurement of likeness to truth [9, 1-17][10, 34-38], and the philosophy of modality generally [12, 352]. Not every application of the analogy requires the more exact thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space possible worlds semantics for conditionals, for example, does not require dissimilarity to be measurable by numerical degrees [7, 50-52]. But some applications do for example, the analysis of numerical degree of probability in terms of numerical degree of similarity [2, 461]. A particularly important application of numerical degrees of dissimilarity is in the explanation of how overall similarity can be determined by weighing up similarity in various respects (see especially [6, ]). But the representation and uniqueness theorems relevant to this application are considerably more complex than those discussed here [13, ]. Moreover, it is only under special conditions that they support the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space, and thus the analogy between distance and dissimilarity [13, 186-7]. So I will not address this application in this paper. Regardless of its applications, the analogy between distance and dissimilarity, and the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space that it supports, is interesting not only for its applications, but also

5 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 5 in its own right. The nature of similarity is as central a topic in philosophy as, for example, the nature of probability. So the representation and uniqueness theorems purporting to show that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space should be as widely discussed as those purporting to show that credences satisfy the probability calculus. The discussion of similarity should not be confined to digressions in work on counterfactuals or truthlikeness, but should also be pursued for its own sake. The representation and uniqueness theorems discussed in this paper are extremely familiar (especially from [13, ]), but their relevance to the metaphysics of properties and resemblance, and so also their relevance to applications of the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space to problems in metaphysics and philosophy generally, has not been very widely noticed. I will argue that some conditions which may seem like harmless idealisations in applications to psychology and the social sciences, are in fact deeply controversial in the context of metaphysics, and so cannot be presupposed in philosophy generally. 2. Metric Spaces The analogy between distance and dissimilarity motivates the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space, where: Definition 1. [13, 46] A metric space is an ordered pair A, δ of a set A and a distance function δ : A A R such that: (1) δ(a, a) = 0 (minimality) (2) δ(a, b) > 0 if a b (non-colocation) (3) δ(a, b) = δ(b, a) (symmetry) (4) δ(a, b) + δ(b, c) δ(a, c) (the triangle inequality). In space, for example, (1) every point is at distance zero from itself, (2) all distinct points are at a positive distance from each other, (3) the distance from point a to point b is the same as the return distance from point b to a,

6 6 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY and (4) the distance from point a to point c via point b is always at least as great as the distance from point a directly to point c. A simple example of a metric space is distance between the points on the real line, or the set of real numbers R and their absolute difference δ(i, j) = i j. A more paradigmatically spatial example is three-dimensional Euclidean space, or the set of triples i = i 1, i 2, i 3 R 3 and their Pythagorean distance δ(i, j) = (i 1 j 1 ) 2 + (i 2 j 2 ) 2 + (i 3 j 3 ) 2. In general, the n- dimensional Euclidean space R n is a metric space, and a natural choice for representing overall comparisons of dissimilarity which depend on dissimilarity in n different respects. Another paradigmatic example is the unit circle with it intrinsic metric, or the distance around the arc connecting two points (in other words, the set of pairs i = i 1, i 2 R 2 such that i i2 2 = 1 and their intrinsic distance δ(i, j) = arcsin j 2 arcsin i 2 ). The unit circle with its intrinsic metric contrasts with the unit circle with its Euclidean metric, or the distance across the chord connecting two points (in other words, the set of pairs i = i 1, i 2 R 2 such that i i2 2 = 1 and their Pythagorean distance δ(i, j) = (i 1 j 1 ) 2 + (i 2 j 2 ) 2 )). So the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is measurable by distance in a metric space is compatible with many theses about the geometry of that space. Nevertheless, the conception of distance embodied in the definition of a metric space is too general to capture the analogy between distance and dissimilarity, because many metric spaces lack the spatial character of the paradigmatic examples. An extreme case is the discrete metric, which may be defined on any set by stipulating that the distance between any element and itself is zero, and the distance between any two distinct elements is one. If it turned out that everything was equally dissimilar to everything else, but nothing was at all dissimilar to itself, then degree of dissimilarity could be represented by the discrete metric. But this representation would hardly capture the analogy between dissimilarity and distance.

7 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 7 So the analogy between distance and dissimilarity suggests not only that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space, but also that that metric space should meet two further characteristically spatial conditions. The first condition is stated in terms of betweenness, where: Definition 2. A point b is between points a and c in a metric space A, δ if and only if δ(a, b) + δ(b, c) = δ(a, c). In other words, a point b is between points a and c if and only if the distance from point a to c via b is equal to the distance from point a directly to point c, or, in other words again, b lies on the shortest path from a to c. Since in a discrete metric space the distance between any two distinct elements is one, no distinct elements in the discrete metric space have any element in between them. In a dense metric space, on the other hand, all distinct elements have an element between them. Definition 3. A metric space A, δ is dense if and only if between any two distinct points a, c A there is a distinct point b A [3, 40]. Euclidean space, for example, is dense, since between any two distinct points in Euclidean space lie the points on the line segment connecting them. Likewise, between any two distinct points on the unit circle with its intrinsic metric, for example, lie the points on the arc of the circle connecting them. The unit circle with its Euclidean metric, in contrast, is not dense, since the chord connecting two points across the circle lies outside the space. Likewise, the discrete metric on a set is obviously not dense. The second characteristically spatial condition suggested by the analogy with distance is completeness: Definition 4. A metric space A, δ is complete if and only if for every sequence of elements a 1,..., a n,... in A such that the distance between successive pairs δ(a 1, a 2 ), δ(a 2, a 3 ),..., δ(a n, a n+1 ),... converges to zero, there is

8 8 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY an element a A such that the distance δ(a 1, a), δ(a 2, a),..., δ(a n, a),... between successive elements and a also converges to zero (where a sequence of real numbers r 1, r 2..., r n,... converges to zero if and only if for any ɛ > 0 there is an m such that r l < ɛ for all l > m) [3, 28]. In other words, if there is a sequence of elements all but finitely many of which are within an arbitrarily small distance of each other, then there is a particular element which all but finitely many are within an arbitrarily small distance of. In Euclidean space, every pair of distinct points are joined by a line segment consisting of the points in between them. Density and completeness are important properties of a metric space because they entail that every pair of distinct points in the space are joined by a metric segment, a subset of the space isometric to a Euclidean line segment (where subsets of two metric spaces are isometric if and only if there is a bijective distance-preserving function between them) [3, 40]. The arc between each pair of distinct points on the unit circle with its intrinsic metric, for example, is isometric to a straight Euclidean line segment of the same length. By generalising the fact that any two points in Euclidean space are joined by a line segment, the existence of metric segments encapsulates paradigmatically spatial characteristics of many metric spaces. So in addition to considering whether the analogy between distance and dissimilarity supports the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space, it is also worth considering whether that metric space is dense and complete. I will argue in section (5) that although the qualitative conditions on comparative dissimilarity corresponding to density and completeness suffice to capture the analogy between distance and dissimilarity, they also exacerbate its problems.

9 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 9 3. Ordinal Scales A traditional way to justify the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is distance in a metric space is to prove a representation theorem, according to which if a structure meets certain qualitative conditions, then it is representable by distance in a metric space, and then to argue that (possible) particulars under the relation of comparative dissimilarity meet those conditions. In the discussion below, the conditions are stated for an arbitrary set A and quaternary relation, but the intended interpretation is that A is the set of (possible) particulars and ab cd is the relation of a being at least as dissimilar to b as c is to d (as usual, ab cd abbreviates ab cd and cd ab; ab cd abbreviates ab cd but not cd ab). (Note that some discussions are conducted in terms of a ternary or threeplace relation such that b a c is interpreted as meaning that b is at least as similar to a as c is (see for example [7, 48-50]). The ternary relation is definable in terms of the quaternary relations, since b is as similar to a as c is if and only if a and b are as similar as a and c or, in other words, b a c if and only if ba ca. The quaternary relation, in contrast, cannot in general be defined in terms of the ternary relation. So it is the quaternary relation which is the more appropriate primitive [15].) The following definition gives simple qualitative necessary conditions for a structure A,, such as (possible) particulars under the relation of comparative dissimilarity, to be representable by a distance function: Definition 5. [13, 161] The structure A, of a set A and a quaternary relation on A A is a proximity structure if and only if for all a, b, c, d, e, f A the following conditions hold: (1) is a weak ordering, or in other words: (a) Either ab cd or cd ab (connectedness) (b) if ab cd and cd ef then ab ef (transitivity) (2) aa bb (minimality)

10 10 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY (3) ab aa if a b (identity of indissimilars) (4) ab ba (symmetry). If comparative dissimilarity, for example, is representable by a distance function, then it is necessary that the set of (possible) particulars under the relation of comparative dissimilarity be a proximity structure. Condition (1), weak ordering or connectedness and transitivity, is necessary for comparative dissimilarity to be representable by any function to the real numbers at all since the relation of being at least as great as between real numbers is connected and transitive, any relation it represents must be connected and transitive as well. (For criticism of connectedness see [4, 38-39][8, ]; for defence see [6, ]. For criticism of transitivity, see [15, 463] and [8, ]. Weak ordering is a presupposition of the application to counterfactuals see [7, 48].) The remaining three conditions of the definition of a proximity structure correspond to the first three conditions in (1), the definition of a metric space, except the former are qualitative whereas the latter are quantitative. However, note that there is no qualitative condition in the definition of a proximity structure corresponding to the triangle inequality, condition (4) in the definition of a metric space, for a reason that will be explained below. (For criticism of minimality, symmetry, and also the triangle inequality see [14, ]. Minimality is a presupposition of the application to counterfactuals [7, 48], but symmetry is not [7, 51].) Condition (3), the identity of indissimilars, is controversial, because it is closely related to the identity of indiscernibles, according to which if a and b are not identical, then a has different properties from b: supposing that a is more dissimilar to b than c is to d if and only if a has more properties not in common with b than c has not in common with b, then they are equivalent [15, 463-4]. So if there are distinct particulars which share all of their properties, and so are exactly alike, then neither the identity of indiscernibles nor the identity of indissimilars is satisfied.

11 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 11 But this controversy can be circumvented in the presence of the other conditions. Consider the relation of being as dissimilar to a particular as it is to itself, or xy yy. Minimality entails that that relation is reflexive, since it entails every particular is as similar to itself as it is to itself. And minimality, symmetry and transitivity entail that it is symmetric and transitive. So it follows that the relation of being as dissimilar to a particular as it is to itself is an equivalence relation, which partitions things into equivalence classes of exactly alike particulars [13, 47]. If a pair of equivalence classes are defined as being at least as dissimilar to each other as a second pair if and only if two representative particulars chosen from each of the first pair are at least as dissimilar to each other as two chosen from each of the second pair, then the set of equivalence classes of exactly alike particulars under this derived relation of comparative dissimilarity is a proximity structure, since it satisfies condition (3), and the reasoning below applies to the derived relation of comparative dissimilarity between equivalence classes of exactly alike particulars. Since the relation is itself reflexive, symmetric and transitive, it s also possible to divide A A into equivalence classes of equally dissimilar pairs A A/ with a derived order, B C if and only if ab cd for all a, b B and c, d C. So it s possible to reduce the problem of finding a representation of the weakly ordered set A A, to the problem of finding a representation for the totally ordered set A A/,. In other words, it s possible to reduce the problem of representing degree of dissimilarity between particulars to the problem of finding a representation of degree of dissimilarity between equivalence classes of equally dissimilar pairs. A necessary and sufficient condition for a simply ordered set such as the set of equivalence classes of equally dissimilar pairs under their derived order to be representable by an ordinal scale is that it have a countable order-dense subset, where:

12 12 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY Definition 6. [5, 40] If B, is a simple order and C is a subset of B, then C is order-dense in B if and only if for all a, c B such that a c there exists b C such that a b c. The paradigm case of definition (6) is the countable order-density of the rational numbers in the reals, since the rational numbers are a countable subset of the real numbers, and since between every two distinct real numbers there is a rational number. Countable order-density is sufficient for a totally ordered set to be represented by an ordinal scale, since each element of the countable subset can be represented by a rational number, and then each element not in the countable subset can be represented by the least upper bound of the rational numbers of the elements below it. And countable order-density is necessary for a totally ordered set to be represented by an ordinal scale, since the elements represented by the rational numbers must be countably order-dense in the elements represented by the real numbers [5, 40-42]. The definition of a proximity structure (5) together with (6) the definition of countable order-density allow the statement of the following representation theorem: Theorem 1. [13, 162] The structure A, of a set A and a quaternary relation on A A is representable by a distance function in a metric space if and only if A, is a proximity structure and A A/ has a countable order-dense subset. In particular, if A A/, has a countable order-dense subset, then it is representable by an ordinal scale which also represents A A,, and from which it is possible to derive a distance function. In order to derive a distance function from the ordinal scale representing A A,, it s necessary only to ensure it satisfies condition (4), the triangle inequality, since the other three conditions of the definition of a metric space are guaranteed by the corresponding qualitative conditions in the definition

13 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 13 of a proximity structure. That may be achieved by defining the degree of dissimilarity between each particular and itself as zero, and rescaling all the other degrees of dissimilarity to be between one and two, so that the sum of all the degrees of dissimilarity between distinct particulars will always be greater than two, and the condition δ(a, b) + δ(b, c) δ(a, c) will always be met [13, 162][15, 462]. Unfortunately, the justification of the thesis that degree of dissimilarity is representable by distance in a metric space encapsulated in this theorem has two problems with infinity. The first problem is that if there are more equivalence classes of equally dissimilar pairs than there are real numbers, then comparative dissimilarity can t be represented by a function to the real numbers, since then some unequally dissimilar pairs would have to be represented by the same real numbers. If there are more equivalence classes of equally dissimilar pairs than real numbers, then there are simply too many degrees of dissimilarity to be represented by real numbers (just as there are too many unequally good films to be represented by only five stars). Even if there are only as many equally dissimilar pairs as there are real numbers, comparative dissimilarity may not be representable by a function to the real numbers, since not every ordered set of continuum-many elements has a countable order-dense subset. Consider, for example, the coordinates of the plane i 1, i 2 R 2 under their lexicographic ordering, i 1, i 2 j 1, j 2 if and only if either i 1 < j 1 or else both i 1 = j 1 and i 2 j 2. Since every order-dense subset of the plane under the lexicographic ordering must contain at least one distinct element on each horizontal line, and there are as many horizontal lines as real numbers, every order-dense subset of the plane under the lexicographic ordering must contain as many elements as real numbers and so uncountably many elements. So the lexicographically ordered plane has no countable order-dense subset. This is not a problem if the number of particulars is finite or countable, since in that case the number of equally dissimilar pairs is also finite or

14 14 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY countable, and so is trivially an order-dense subset of itself. If the number of particulars is continuum many, then it s possible that the number of equally dissimilar pairs of particulars is also continuum many. And it is still not a problem if the equally dissimilar pairs of particulars under the order of comparative dissimilarity are isomorphic to a subset of the real numbers in their usual ascending order. But even if none of these favourable conditions obtain, countable order-density seems like a harmless idealisation. As David Lewis writes, this limitation hardly seems serious [7, 51]. The second problem is that the triangle inequality was obtained so easily only because the numbers chosen preserve only the order of the degrees of dissimilarity they represent, and so could be rescaled arbitrarily the proportions between the numbers were irrelevant [15, 462]. If a is more dissimilar to b than c is to d, for example, then the degree of dissimilarity of a to b must be greater than that of c to d, but how much greater is completely arbitrary. If the degree of dissimilarity of c to d is 3, for example, the degree 2 of dissimilarity of a to b could be any real number strictly between 3 2 and 2 at all, no matter how similar or dissimilar a and b are. So the justification encapsulated in the ordinal representation theorem fails to capture the analogy between distance and dissimilarity. The source of the problem is that the distance function representing comparative dissimilarity is derived from an ordinal scale, which represents only which pairs of particular are as or more dissimilar to others, but not how much more or less dissimilar they are than others. If dissimilarity is truly analogous to distance, it should be represented by a ratio scale, which would represent not only which things are more similar to each other, but also by how much. 4. Ratio Scales In order to capture the analogy between distance and dissimilarity, it is desirable to find a representation of comparative dissimilarity which represents not only whether one pair are more dissimilar to each other than

15 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 15 another pair are, but by how much. In the measurement of length, for example, it is possible not only to check that one rod is longer than another, but also how much longer, by concatenating rods together if the concatenation of two rods of equal length, for example, are the same length as a third rod, then we can conclude not only that the first rod is longer than the other two, but that it is twice as long. Dissimilarities cannot be concatenated like rods can. But if dissimilarity is analogous to distance, then we can think of some particulars as being between each other, in such a way that the dissimilarity between a pair of particulars can be calculated by adding up the dissimilarities of the particulars which lie between them. Suppose, for example, that venison is as dissimilar from beef as kangaroo is from venison, and moreover that venison is between beef and kangaroo. Then one can conclude that the dissimilarity between beef and kangaroo is twice as great as the dissimilarity between beef and venison. In section (2), betweenness was defined quantitatively in terms of distance or degree of dissimilarity. But in order to underwrite the justification of the analogy between distance and dissimilarity, betweenness must be defined qualitatively in terms of merely comparative similarity, as in the following definition: Definition 7. [13, 164] If A is a set and is a quaternary relation on A, then for all a, b, c A the ternary relation (abc holds if and only if for all d, e, f A: (1) if ab de and df ac, then ef bc, and (2) if either of the inequalities in the antecedent of (1) is strict, so is the inequality in the consequent. The betweenness relation abc holds if and only if the ternary relations abc) and (cba both hold.

16 16 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY The definition is motivated by the analogy with spatial distance. Suppose, for example, that Abu Dhabi is between Sydney and London. Then if there are two cities more distant than Sydney and London say Melbourne and Edinburgh and a city closer to Melbourne than Abu Dhabi is to Sydney say Singapore then the distance from Singapore to Edinburgh must exceed the distance from Abu Dhabi to London. Otherwise the possibility of flying further from Melbourne to Edinburgh via Singapore via a shorter path would show the route from Sydney to London via Abu Dhabi is not a shortest path, and thus that Abu Dhabi is not between Sydney and London. The conditions in (5), the definition of a proximity structure, are sufficient for the degrees of dissimilarity between particulars to be the sum of the dissimilarities of the particulars between them in combination with the conditions in the following definition: Definition 8. [13, 168] A proximity structure A, is segmentally additive if and only if for all a, b, c, d A: (1) if ab cd, then there is an e A such that ae cd and aeb (segmental solvability) (2) if c d then there is a sequence e 0,..., e n A such that e 0 = a, e n = b and cd e i e i+1 for all i < n (the Archimedean condition). If the set of particulars under comparative dissimilarity, for example, is a segmentally additive proximity structure, then comparative dissimilarity is representable by a ratio scale. According to condition (1), segmental solvability, whenever two particulars a and b are at least as dissimilar as c and d, there s a particular e between a and b such that a and e are just as dissimilar as c and d. Although beef is more dissimilar to kangaroo than chicken is to duck, for example, segmental solvability requires that there is a meat say, venison which is between beef and kangaroo, and which is exactly as dissimilar to beef as chicken is to duck.

17 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 17 The idea behind segmental solvability is that the numerical degree of dissimilarity between two particulars can be measured by counting the degrees of dissimilarity of the particulars between them. If between beef and whale, for example, there are at least three particulars venison, buffalo and kangaroo as dissimilar from each other as chicken is to duck, then we could conclude that the degree of dissimilarity between beef and whale is at least four times the degree of dissimilarity between chicken and duck. According to (2), the Archimedean condition, for any two particulars a and b, and any two different particulars c and d, there is a sequence of particulars beginning with a and ending with b, each successive pair of which are at least as similar to each other as c is to d. No matter how much gamier pterodactyl is than chicken, for example, there should be a sequence of meats say from chicken, to quail, to turkey, to emu,... to pterodactyl such that each successive pair in this sequence are at least as similar to each other as mutton is to goat. The idea behind the Archimedean condition is that nothing is so distant that it cannot be reached by a finite number of small steps. Even though my commute to work, for example, is very short, there is nowhere on earth that I cannot reach by taking a journey each leg of which is at least as short as my commute to work. So whereas segmental solvability ensures that between any points on my journey there are stops close enough for me to travel to, the Archimedean condition ensures that my destination is not so far away that I cannot reach it after passing only finitely many stops. Together segmental solvability and the Archimedean condition entail that for any particulars a and b and any two different particulars e and f, there is a sequence of particulars between a and b each successive pair of which are just as dissimilar to each other as e and f. How much more dissimilar a is to b than c is to d can then be approximated by how many more particulars there are in the sequence between a and b than in the sequence between c

18 18 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY and d, or in other words as the ratio of the length of the sequence between a and b to the length of the sequence between c and d. The more similar e is to f, the better the approximation, and in the limit, or else if no different particulars are more similar than e and f, it is exact. So together segmental solvability and the Archimedean condition entail the following theorem: Theorem 2. [13, 168] If A, is a segmentally additive proximity structure, then there exists a function δ : A A R such that: (1) A, δ is a metric space (2) ab cd if and only if δ(a, b) δ(c, d) (3) abc if and only if δ(a, c) = δ(a, b) + δ(b, c) (additivity) (4) If A, γ also satisfies (1)-(3), then γ(a, b) = rδ(a, b) for some r > 0. (uniqueness) Whereas the first two clauses of theorem (2) reassert the content of theorem (1) that there is a representation of degree of dissimilarity as distance in a metric space the third clause asserts that there is a representation in which the degrees of dissimilarity are additive, and the fourth clause asserts that these properties are unique to representations in which degrees of dissimilarity are in the same ratio to each other. Unlike the representation derived from an ordinal scale in section (3), the ratio scale established by theorem (2) establishes not only that the dissimilarities between pairs of particulars must have a certain order, but also that they must have certain proportions. Suppose, for example, that there are just three particulars a, b and c, and a is as dissimilar to b as b is to c, but a is more dissimilar to c than a is to b. Then it follows from (7) the definition of betweenness that b is between a and c, and so the dissimilarity between a and c must be exactly twice the dissimilarity between a and b. Nevertheless, like the representation derived from an ordinal scale, the justification of the analogy between distance and dissimilarity encapsulated

19 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 19 in theorem (2) still has two problems with infinity. To see the source of the first problem with infinity, note that the definition (8), of a segmentally additive proximity structure, and the statement of theorem (2) omit any mention of countable order-density. This is not because countable orderdensity is not a necessary condition of the theorem, but because countable order-density is entailed by the definition of a segmentally additive proximity structure. In the context of an ordinal scale the possibility that the countable orderdensity condition may not be met hardly seemed serious. But in the context of a ratio scale, the segmental solvability and the Archimedean condition face a dilemma. On the one hand, if the quaternary relation of comparative dissimilarity is interpreted as a relation between actual particulars, then the condition of segmental solvability is not met. On the other hand, if comparative dissimilarity is interpreted as a relation between merely possible particulars, then the Archimedean condition is not met. If comparative dissimilarity is interpreted as a relation between actual particulars, segmental solvability is not met because there are some pairs of dissimilar particulars which don t have any distinct particular between them, even though there are other pairs of particulars which are not so dissimilar as they are. Turkey, for example, is more dissimilar to duck than beef is to venison. But there is no actual meat between turkey and duck which is just as dissimilar to turkey as beef is to venison (tastes may vary, but you can substitute your own example). Segmental solvability is not a plausible condition for actual particulars, but it is more plausible for possible particulars, since it is more plausible that for every pair of dissimilar particulars, there are possible particulars between which are just as dissimilar as any pair of less dissimilar particulars are to each other. Although it s not obvious, for example, that there is any actual meat between turkey and duck, there is nothing impossible about the

20 20 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY existence of a meat which is just as dissimilar to turkey as beef is to venison say, for example, turducken occupying that position. But if comparative dissimilarity is a relation between possible particulars, then the Archimedean condition is not satisfied, since there is nothing impossible about particulars so dissimilar that no concatenation of ordinary dissimilarities can reach them. It is possible, for example, that there is an infinite library, which contains all finite books. If the Archimedean condition is met, then there should be a finite sequence of libraries, each successive pair of which differs by only one book, such that the first library in the sequence is my library and the last is the infinite library. But since my library has only finitely many books, each finite sequence of libraries beginning with my library, and each successive pair of which differs by only one book, can only end in a library containing finitely many books I cannot obtain an infinite library by purchasing only finitely many books. Moreover, the infinite library containing all finite books is just one amongst many possible libraries there are 2 ℵ 0 possible libraries corresponding to every combination of the ℵ 0 finite books, and more corresponding to combinations of infinite books. Whereas in the context of an ordinal scale the assumption of countable order-density appeared to be merely a harmless idealisation, in the context of a ratio scale the assumption of the Archimedean condition involves a serious disanalogy between distance and dissimilarity. There is no distance so great that it is not a large but finite multiple of an arbitrarily small distance. But there are possible dissimilarities so great that they are not a finite multiple, no matter how large, of an arbitrarily small dissimilarity. The Archimedean condition is not a harmless idealisation, but a serious limitation. Two objections. Firstly, whereas (5) the conditions of a proximity structure and (6) countable order-density are jointly necessary and sufficient for representations derived from an ordinal scale, the conditions of a segmentally additive proximity structure are sufficient for representation by a ratio

21 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 21 scale, but not necessary. So it is possible for a proponent of the analogy between distance and dissimilarity to argue that comparative dissimilarity between actual particulars is representable by a ratio scale, without defending segmental solvability. Suppose, for example, that the set A contains just four particulars: a, b, c and d. And suppose ad bd ac cd ab bc (imagine a line with c half way between a and d, and b half way between a and c). Then it follows from (7), the qualitative definition of betweenness, that c is between a and d as well as between b and d, b is between a and c as well as between a and d, c is between b and d as well as between a and d, but nothing is between c and d. In this case, condition (1), segmental solvability, is not satisfied, since, for example, cd ab, but there is no e such that ce ab and e is between c and d. Nevertheless, A, is representable by a distance function δ according to which δ(a, b) = δ(b, c), since b is as far from a as c is from b, δ(c, d) = δ(a, c) = δ(a, b) + δ(a, c) = 2δ(a, b), since b is equidistant between a and c, δ(a, d) = δ(a, c) + δ(c, d) = 2δ(a, c) = 4δ(a, b), since c is equidistant between a and d, and δ(b, d) = δ(b, c) + δ(c, d) = 3δ(a, b), since c is between b and d. These distances will be in the same ratios according to any distance function which represents b as equidistant between a and c and c as equidistant between a and d. So A, is representable by a ratio scale, even though it does not satisfy segmental solvability. But not every failure of segmental solvability is so favourable. Suppose, for example, that A contains just three particulars: a, b and c. And suppose ac ab bc (imagine a line with b between a and c, but closer to c than to a). Then it follows from (7), the qualitative definition of betweenness, that b is between a and c. And in this case, condition (1), segmental solvability, is still not satisfied, since ab bc, but there is no e such that ae bc and e is between a and b.

22 22 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY In this case A, is representable by a distance function δ according to which δ(a, c) > δ(a, b) > δ(b, c) and, since b is between a and c, δ(a, c) = δ(a, b) + δ(b, c). But these distances will not be in the same ratios according to every distance function which represents b as between a and c, since there is not enough information to determine how much closer b is to c than b is to a. If the distance between a and c is one, for example, then the respective distances between a and b and b and c could be two thirds and one third, so that b is twice as far from a as from c, or three quarters and one quarter, so that b is thrice as far from a as from c. So if segmental solvability is not satisfied, comparative dissimilarity is representable by a ratio scale only under favourable circumstances. But if comparative dissimilarity is a relation between actual particulars, then it s implausible that favourable circumstances obtain, for the same reasons as segmental solvability is implausible. At best, the representability of comparative dissimilarity by a ratio scale would be a lucky accident. But if the analogy between distance and dissimilarity is correct, then that comparative dissimilarity is representable by a ratio scale should not be contingent, but necessary (see [11] for a related point about physical measurement). Secondly, it might be objected that the field of comparative dissimilarity need not be extended to all possible particulars, but to just those possible particulars which are required in order to satisfy segmental solvability, and not to those possible particulars which would violate the Archimedean condition. The comparative dissimilarity between turkey and duck can be compared to that between beef and venison, for example, by a comparison with turducken, without requiring that these comparisons be extended to bunyips and dragons as well. But this response would also make the representability of comparative dissimilarity by a ratio scale merely contingent. If the infinite library containing all finite books actually existed, for example, then although a ratio scale could represent the degree of dissimilarity of all its finite subsections

23 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 23 to each other, a ratio scale could not represent the degree of dissimilarity of any of its finite sections to the whole library. Physical space, in contrast, can be represented on a ratio scale, regardless of whether it is finite or infinite in extent. Even if the infinite library containing all finite books actually existed, perhaps it may be excluded for the purpose of representing the relation of comparative dissimilarity between its finite subsections by a ratio scale. But even this concession would reveal a substantive disanalogy between distance and dissimilarity. There is no possible distance so great that it is not a large but finite multiple of an arbitrarily small distance. But there are possible dissimilarities so great that they are not a finite multiple, no matter how large, of an arbitrarily small dissimilarity. Dissimilarity is different from distance. 5. Completeness In the last section, I argued that there is a dilemma for the representation of degree of dissimilarity by a ratio scale, because the condition of segmental solvability is not necessarily met by actual particulars, but the Archimedean condition is necessarily not met by possible particulars. In this section I point out the representation of degree of dissimilarity by a ratio scale has a second problem with infinity, which arises from the fact that the conditions of a segmentally additive proximity structure still do not suffice to capture the whole spirit of the analogy between distance and dissimilarity. The second problem is that the conditions of a segmentally additive proximity structure still do not capture the analogy between distance and dissimilarity, since they still do not suffice to entail that degree of dissimilarity is representable by a dense and complete metric space in fact, they do not even suffice to entail that there is any irrational degree of dissimilarity. To see this, suppose there is a pair of least dissimilar particulars, or a minimum positive degree of dissimilarity. Then segmental solvability and the

24 24 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY Archimedean condition entail that between every pair of dissimilar particulars is a finite sequence of least dissimilar particulars, or successive pairs of particulars which are dissimilar to just that degree. It follows from clause (3), the additivity of the scale, in theorem (2) that the degree of dissimilarity between any two particulars is simply the number of these least dissimilar particulars multiplied by this minimum positive degree of dissimilarity or, in other words, simply proportional to the number of pairs of least dissimilar particulars between them. Supposing that there is only quail and turkey between chicken and duck, for example, it would follow that the degree of dissimilarity between chicken and turkey is simply the minimum distance multiplied by three (for the three pairs, chicken and quail, quail and turkey, and turkey and duck). And if the scale is chosen so that the minimum positive degree of dissimilarity is one, then it follows that the degree of dissimilarity between any two particulars is simply the number of pairs of least dissimilar particulars between them. In other words, it follows not only that the degree of dissimilarity between any two different particulars is rational, but that it is an integer. Supposing that there is only quail and turkey between chicken and duck, for example, it would follow that the degrees of dissimilarity between chicken and quail, chicken and turkey, and chicken and duck are respectively one, two and three. So in order to fully capture the analogy between distance and dissimilarity, it s desirable to add further qualitative conditions than those of a segmentally additive proximity structure. The following definition gives qualitative conditions which not only suffice for degree of dissimilarity to be represented by a distance function which delivers irrational values, but also defines a dense and complete metric space: Definition 9. [13, 168] A segmentally additive proximity structure is complete if and only if for all distinct a, b A: (1) There exist distinct c, d A such that ab cd (nonminimality)

25 DISTANCE AND DISSIMILARITY 25 (2) For all distinct c, d A and every sequence e 1,..., e n,... of elements of A, if there is an m such that cd e i e i+1 for all i > m, then there is an e A such that for all distinct f, g A there is an l such that fg a i e for all i > l (qualitative completeness) If particulars under the relation of comparative dissimilarity, for example, are a complete segmentally additive structure, then that suffices for some degrees of dissimilarity to be irrational. If comparative dissimilarity meets condition (1), nonminimality, then every pair of different particulars is strictly less dissimilar than some other pair of different particulars no matter how similar venison is to beef, for example, there must be some pair say, chicken and turkey which are even more similar. Nonminimality entails that there is no minimum positive distance or degree of dissimilarity since if some pair were that minimum positive distance apart, there would be a dissimilar pair which are less dissimilar, and so (impossibly) a positive distance less than the positive minimum apart. So nonminimality entails that not all degrees of dissimilarity are integers. But even though it entails that there is no no minimum positive degree of dissimilarity, nonminimality still does not entail that any degree of dissimilarity is irrational, since it is compatible with the conditions given so far that every degree of dissimilarity is rational. The rational numbers Q under the quaternary relation ij kl if and only if i j k l, for example, meet all the conditions of a segmentally additive proximity structure, and so are represented by the distance function corresponding to their absolute difference δ(i, j) = i j. But although this distance function has no positive minimum, it does not take irrational values. So in order to entail that some degrees of dissimilarity are irrational, condition (4), completeness, is also required. According to it, if the successive pairs in a sequence of particulars become arbitrarily similar to one another, then there is one particular in particular which the sequence of particulars becomes arbitrarily similar to. If my paternal ancestors, for example,

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a Solutions to Homework #6 1. Complete the proof of the backwards direction of Theorem 12.2 from class (which asserts the any interval in R is connected). Solution: Let X R be a closed interval. Case 1:

More information

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity Counterfactuals and comparative similarity Jeremy Goodman Draft of February 23, 2015 Abstract An analysis of counterfactuals in terms of the comparative similarity of possible worlds is widely attributed

More information

1 Euclidean geometry. 1.1 The metric on R n

1 Euclidean geometry. 1.1 The metric on R n 1 Euclidean geometry This chapter discusses the geometry of n-dimensional Euclidean space E n, together with its distance function. The distance gives rise to other notions such as angles and congruent

More information

*a * * *b * * *c *d *

*a * * *b * * *c *d * K. MCDANIEL DISTANCE AND DISCRETE SPACE Let us say that space is discrete if and only if every finite extended region of space is composed of finitely many atomic regions of space. I assume here that regions

More information

Commutative laws for addition and multiplication: If a and b are arbitrary real numbers then

Commutative laws for addition and multiplication: If a and b are arbitrary real numbers then Appendix C Prerequisites C.1 Properties of Real Numbers Algebraic Laws Commutative laws for addition and multiplication: If a and b are arbitrary real numbers then a + b = b + a, (C.1) ab = ba. (C.2) Associative

More information

First-Degree Entailment

First-Degree Entailment March 5, 2013 Relevance Logics Relevance logics are non-classical logics that try to avoid the paradoxes of material and strict implication: p (q p) p (p q) (p q) (q r) (p p) q p (q q) p (q q) Counterintuitive?

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013 March 20, 2013 The earliest attempts to devise a relevance logic that avoided the problem of explosion centered on the conditional. FDE, however, has no conditional operator, or a very weak one. If we

More information

Mathematics 3210 Spring Semester, 2005 Homework notes, part 8 April 15, 2005

Mathematics 3210 Spring Semester, 2005 Homework notes, part 8 April 15, 2005 Mathematics 3210 Spring Semester, 2005 Homework notes, part 8 April 15, 2005 The underlying assumption for all problems is that all points, lines, etc., are taken within the Poincaré plane (or Poincaré

More information

SUMS PROBLEM COMPETITION, 2000

SUMS PROBLEM COMPETITION, 2000 SUMS ROBLEM COMETITION, 2000 SOLUTIONS 1 The result is well known, and called Morley s Theorem Many proofs are known See for example HSM Coxeter, Introduction to Geometry, page 23 2 If the number of vertices,

More information

1.1 Line Reflections and Point Reflections

1.1 Line Reflections and Point Reflections 1.1 Line Reflections and Point Reflections Since this is a book on Transformation Geometry, we shall start by defining transformations of the Euclidean plane and giving basic examples. Definition 1. A

More information

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Incompatibility Paradoxes Chapter 22 Incompatibility Paradoxes 22.1 Simultaneous Values There is never any difficulty in supposing that a classical mechanical system possesses, at a particular instant of time, precise values of

More information

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions 1. Suppose k is a positive integer. Use induction to prove the following two statements. (a) For all n N 0, the inequality (k 2 + n)! k 2n holds.

More information

Week 2: Sequences and Series

Week 2: Sequences and Series QF0: Quantitative Finance August 29, 207 Week 2: Sequences and Series Facilitator: Christopher Ting AY 207/208 Mathematicians have tried in vain to this day to discover some order in the sequence of prime

More information

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets 1 Rational and Real Numbers Recall that a number is rational if it can be written in the form a/b where a, b Z and b 0, and a number

More information

6 Cosets & Factor Groups

6 Cosets & Factor Groups 6 Cosets & Factor Groups The course becomes markedly more abstract at this point. Our primary goal is to break apart a group into subsets such that the set of subsets inherits a natural group structure.

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS Article A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS Juan Pablo Ramírez 0000-0002-4912-2952 Abstract: We present the real number system as a generalization of the natural numbers. First, we prove the co-finite topology,

More information

Metric spaces and metrizability

Metric spaces and metrizability 1 Motivation Metric spaces and metrizability By this point in the course, this section should not need much in the way of motivation. From the very beginning, we have talked about R n usual and how relatively

More information

The main limitation of the concept of a. function

The main limitation of the concept of a. function Relations The main limitation of the concept of a A function, by definition, assigns one output to each input. This means that a function cannot model relationships between sets where some objects on each

More information

p-adic Analysis Compared to Real Lecture 1

p-adic Analysis Compared to Real Lecture 1 p-adic Analysis Compared to Real Lecture 1 Felix Hensel, Waltraud Lederle, Simone Montemezzani October 12, 2011 1 Normed Fields & non-archimedean Norms Definition 1.1. A metric on a non-empty set X is

More information

Metric Space Topology (Spring 2016) Selected Homework Solutions. HW1 Q1.2. Suppose that d is a metric on a set X. Prove that the inequality d(x, y)

Metric Space Topology (Spring 2016) Selected Homework Solutions. HW1 Q1.2. Suppose that d is a metric on a set X. Prove that the inequality d(x, y) Metric Space Topology (Spring 2016) Selected Homework Solutions HW1 Q1.2. Suppose that d is a metric on a set X. Prove that the inequality d(x, y) d(z, w) d(x, z) + d(y, w) holds for all w, x, y, z X.

More information

Axiomatizing changing conceptions of the geometric continuum

Axiomatizing changing conceptions of the geometric continuum Axiomatizing changing conceptions of the geometric continuum John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago October 16, 2014 John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago Axiomatizing () changing

More information

Philosophy of Religion. Notes on Infinity

Philosophy of Religion. Notes on Infinity Notes on Infinity Infinity in Classical and Medieval Philosophy Aristotle (Metaphysics 986 a 22) reports that limited (peras, πέρας) and unlimited or infinite (apeiron, ἄπειρον) occur as the first pairing

More information

The Metaphysical Significance of the Ugly Duckling. Theorem

The Metaphysical Significance of the Ugly Duckling. Theorem The Metaphysical Significance of the Ugly Duckling Theorem Abstract According to Satosi Watanabe s theorem of the ugly duckling, the number of (possible) predicates satisfied by any two different particulars

More information

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Chapter One. The Real Number System Chapter One. The Real Number System We shall give a quick introduction to the real number system. It is imperative that we know how the set of real numbers behaves in the way that its completeness and

More information

4 Arithmetic of Segments Hilbert s Road from Geometry

4 Arithmetic of Segments Hilbert s Road from Geometry 4 Arithmetic of Segments Hilbert s Road from Geometry to Algebra In this section, we explain Hilbert s procedure to construct an arithmetic of segments, also called Streckenrechnung. Hilbert constructs

More information

(x 1, y 1 ) = (x 2, y 2 ) if and only if x 1 = x 2 and y 1 = y 2.

(x 1, y 1 ) = (x 2, y 2 ) if and only if x 1 = x 2 and y 1 = y 2. 1. Complex numbers A complex number z is defined as an ordered pair z = (x, y), where x and y are a pair of real numbers. In usual notation, we write z = x + iy, where i is a symbol. The operations of

More information

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted Chapter 2 The Structure of R The purpose of this chapter is to explain to the reader why the set of real numbers is so special. By the end of this chapter, the reader should understand the difference between

More information

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10 Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10 Philosophy 691: Conditionals Northern Illinois University Fall 2011 Geoff Pynn terminology 1. Chapters 10-18 concern subjunctive conditionals, which Bennett distinguishes

More information

Numbers, proof and all that jazz.

Numbers, proof and all that jazz. CHAPTER 1 Numbers, proof and all that jazz. There is a fundamental difference between mathematics and other sciences. In most sciences, one does experiments to determine laws. A law will remain a law,

More information

9th Bay Area Mathematical Olympiad

9th Bay Area Mathematical Olympiad 9th Bay rea Mathematical Olympiad February 27, 2007 Problems with Solutions 1 15-inch-long stick has four marks on it, dividing it into five segments of length 1,2,3,4, and 5 inches (although not neccessarily

More information

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate Structuralism with an empiricist face? Bas Van Fraassen s Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective is a rich, masterful study of a wide range of issues arising from the manifold ways in which

More information

2 Metric Spaces Definitions Exotic Examples... 3

2 Metric Spaces Definitions Exotic Examples... 3 Contents 1 Vector Spaces and Norms 1 2 Metric Spaces 2 2.1 Definitions.......................................... 2 2.2 Exotic Examples...................................... 3 3 Topologies 4 3.1 Open Sets..........................................

More information

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3 Analysis Math Notes Study Guide Real Analysis Contents Ordered Fields 2 Ordered sets and fields 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts 2 Metric Spaces 3 Metric Spaces 3 Definitions 4 Separability

More information

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part II, Counting beyond infinity: Ordinal numbers

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part II, Counting beyond infinity: Ordinal numbers Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part II, Counting beyond infinity: Ordinal numbers Benedikt Löwe Universiteit van Amsterdam Grzegorz Plebanek Uniwersytet Wroc lawski ESSLLI, Ljubliana August 2011

More information

Linear and Partial Orderings by Sidney Felder

Linear and Partial Orderings by Sidney Felder by Sidney Felder When we are given the task of ordering a class of objects, whether concrete or abstract, it tends to be in a context in which it is appropriate to place them in an ordering that corresponds

More information

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS WINTER 2014 Problem 1 (15 points). For each statement below, circle T or F according to whether the statement is true or false. You do NOT need to justify your answers. T F

More information

Problem List MATH 5143 Fall, 2013

Problem List MATH 5143 Fall, 2013 Problem List MATH 5143 Fall, 2013 On any problem you may use the result of any previous problem (even if you were not able to do it) and any information given in class up to the moment the problem was

More information

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2. MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2. This text is based on the following books: Topology by James Dugundgji Fundamental concepts of topology by Peter O Neil Elements of Mathematics: General Topology

More information

Fundamentals of Pure Mathematics - Problem Sheet

Fundamentals of Pure Mathematics - Problem Sheet Fundamentals of Pure Mathematics - Problem Sheet ( ) = Straightforward but illustrates a basic idea (*) = Harder Note: R, Z denote the real numbers, integers, etc. assumed to be real numbers. In questions

More information

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Boolean Algebras Let X be an arbitrary set and let P(X) be the class of all subsets of X (the power set of X). Three natural set-theoretic operations on P(X) are the binary operations of union

More information

Lecture Notes 4. Issued 8 March 2018

Lecture Notes 4. Issued 8 March 2018 CM30073 Advanced Algorithms and Complexity 1. Structure of the class NP Lecture Notes 4 Issued 8 March 2018 Recall that it is not known whether or not P = NP, the widely accepted hypothesis being that

More information

Georgia Tech High School Math Competition

Georgia Tech High School Math Competition Georgia Tech High School Math Competition Multiple Choice Test February 28, 2015 Each correct answer is worth one point; there is no deduction for incorrect answers. Make sure to enter your ID number on

More information

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions Sect. 1.1.3: # 2, 3 (Page 7-8 Math 105A HW 1 Solutions 2(a ( Statement: Each positive integers has a unique prime factorization. n N: n = 1 or ( R N, p 1,..., p R P such that n = p 1 p R and ( n, R, S

More information

The Not-Formula Book for C2 Everything you need to know for Core 2 that won t be in the formula book Examination Board: AQA

The Not-Formula Book for C2 Everything you need to know for Core 2 that won t be in the formula book Examination Board: AQA Not The Not-Formula Book for C Everything you need to know for Core that won t be in the formula book Examination Board: AQA Brief This document is intended as an aid for revision. Although it includes

More information

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology Andrew Bacon 28th June 2013 1 The data You pick a card at random from a standard deck of cards. How confident should I be about asserting the following sentences?

More information

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 1 Real Numbers In these lectures, we are going to study a branch of mathematics called

More information

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1. I. Foundational material

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1. I. Foundational material SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1 Fall 2014 I. Foundational material I.1 : Basic set theory Problems from Munkres, 9, p. 64 2. (a (c For each of the first three parts, choose a 1 1 correspondence

More information

Foundations of Neutral Geometry

Foundations of Neutral Geometry C H A P T E R 12 Foundations of Neutral Geometry The play is independent of the pages on which it is printed, and pure geometries are independent of lecture rooms, or of any other detail of the physical

More information

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005 POL502: Foundations Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University October 10, 2005 Our first task is to develop the foundations that are necessary for the materials covered in this course. 1

More information

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2012 Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero Chapter Limits of Sequences Calculus Student: lim s n = 0 means the s n are getting closer and closer to zero but never gets there. Instructor: ARGHHHHH! Exercise. Think of a better response for the instructor.

More information

Hanoi Open Mathematical Competition 2017

Hanoi Open Mathematical Competition 2017 Hanoi Open Mathematical Competition 2017 Junior Section Saturday, 4 March 2017 08h30-11h30 Important: Answer to all 15 questions. Write your answers on the answer sheets provided. For the multiple choice

More information

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge 1 3 Conceivability and Modal Knowledge Christopher Hill ( 2006 ) provides an account of modal knowledge that is set in a broader context of arguing against the view that conceivability provides epistemic

More information

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp. 72-81. The Bundle Theory is compatible with distinct but indiscernible particulars GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. The Bundle Theory I shall discuss is a theory about

More information

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS 3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS Definition 3.1 Let X be a topological space. A subset D of X is dense in X iff D = X. X is separable iff it contains a countable dense subset. X satisfies the first

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

01. Review of metric spaces and point-set topology. 1. Euclidean spaces

01. Review of metric spaces and point-set topology. 1. Euclidean spaces (October 3, 017) 01. Review of metric spaces and point-set topology Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ [This document is http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/m/real/notes 017-18/01

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms Part 2: Theoretical Terms 1. What Apparatus Is Available for Carrying out Analyses?

More information

Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS. Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that:

Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS. Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that: Equivalence MA Relations 274 and Partitions Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that: (1) is reflexive. That is, (2) is

More information

Combinatorial Optimization

Combinatorial Optimization Combinatorial Optimization Problem set 8: solutions 1. Fix constants a R and b > 1. For n N, let f(n) = n a and g(n) = b n. Prove that f(n) = o ( g(n) ). Solution. First we observe that g(n) 0 for all

More information

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH ) Contents 1 Sets 1 2 The Real Numbers 9 3 Sequences 29 4 Series 59 5 Functions 81 6 Power Series 105 7 The elementary functions 111 Chapter 1 Sets It is very convenient to introduce some notation and terminology

More information

An attempt to intuitively introduce the dot, wedge, cross, and geometric products

An attempt to intuitively introduce the dot, wedge, cross, and geometric products An attempt to intuitively introduce the dot, wedge, cross, and geometric products Peeter Joot March 1, 008 1 Motivation. Both the NFCM and GAFP books have axiomatic introductions of the generalized (vector,

More information

1. Continuous Functions between Euclidean spaces

1. Continuous Functions between Euclidean spaces Math 441 Topology Fall 2012 Metric Spaces by John M. Lee This handout should be read between Chapters 1 and 2 of the text. It incorporates material from notes originally prepared by Steve Mitchell and

More information

M208 Pure Mathematics AA1. Numbers

M208 Pure Mathematics AA1. Numbers M208 Pure Mathematics AA1 Numbers Note to reader Mathematical/statistical content at the Open University is usually provided to students in printed books, with PDFs of the same online. This format ensures

More information

FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES

FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES I FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES 1. The laws of arithmetic The object of the higher arithmetic is to discover and to establish general propositions concerning the natural numbers 1, 2, 3,... of ordinary

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

Vectors and Matrices

Vectors and Matrices Vectors and Matrices Scalars We often employ a single number to represent quantities that we use in our daily lives such as weight, height etc. The magnitude of this number depends on our age and whether

More information

Math 320-2: Midterm 2 Practice Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 2015

Math 320-2: Midterm 2 Practice Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 2015 Math 30-: Midterm Practice Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 015 1. Give an example of each of the following. No justification is needed. (a) A metric on R with respect to which R is bounded. (b)

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs MAT 1362 Fall 2018 Alistair Savage Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0

More information

Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Axioms for the Real Numbers

Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Axioms for the Real Numbers Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Axioms for the Real Numbers PRIMITIVE TERMS To avoid circularity, we cannot give every term a rigorous mathematical definition; we have to accept

More information

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Chapter : Logic Topics:. Statements, Negation, and Compound Statements.2 Truth Tables and Logical Equivalences.3

More information

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007 Russell s logicism Jeff Speaks September 26, 2007 1 Russell s definition of number............................ 2 2 The idea of reducing one theory to another.................... 4 2.1 Axioms and theories.............................

More information

PHYSICS - CLUTCH CALC-BASED PHYSICS 1E CH 23: ELECTRIC POTENTIAL.

PHYSICS - CLUTCH CALC-BASED PHYSICS 1E CH 23: ELECTRIC POTENTIAL. !! www.clutchprep.com CONCEPT: ELECTRIC POTENTIAL ENERGY If you release 2 charges, they move gain. Where did it come from? - Two charges have a stored energy between them, called - ENERGY CONSERVATION:

More information

PTOLEMY DAY 10 PREPARING TO FIND OTHER ARCS BETWEEN THE ECLIPTIC AND EQUATOR. You might have noticed that in Day 9, when we found the arc

PTOLEMY DAY 10 PREPARING TO FIND OTHER ARCS BETWEEN THE ECLIPTIC AND EQUATOR. You might have noticed that in Day 9, when we found the arc PTOLEMY DAY 10 PREPARING TO FIND OTHER ARS BETWEEN THE ELIPTI AND EQUATOR You might have noticed that in Day 9, when we found the arc D between the tropics, we made no use of our table of chords. We simply

More information

Simply Possible. Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000):

Simply Possible. Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000): Simply Possible Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000): 585 590 Abstract In the process of arguing against all theories of extended material objects made up of simples, Dean

More information

1 Alphabets and Languages

1 Alphabets and Languages 1 Alphabets and Languages Look at handout 1 (inference rules for sets) and use the rules on some examples like {a} {{a}} {a} {a, b}, {a} {{a}}, {a} {{a}}, {a} {a, b}, a {{a}}, a {a, b}, a {{a}}, a {a,

More information

Some Function Problems SOLUTIONS Isabel Vogt Last Edited: May 24, 2013

Some Function Problems SOLUTIONS Isabel Vogt Last Edited: May 24, 2013 Some Function Problems SOLUTIONS Isabel Vogt Last Edited: May 24, 23 Most of these problems were written for my students in Math 23a/b at Harvard in 2/22 and 22/23. They cover basic function theory, countability,

More information

Lecture 6 SPHERICAL GEOMETRY

Lecture 6 SPHERICAL GEOMETRY 1 Lecture 6 SPHERICAL GEOMETRY So far we have studied finite and discrete geometries, i.e., geometries in which the main transformation group is either finite or discrete. In this lecture, we begin our

More information

A Class of Partially Ordered Sets: III

A Class of Partially Ordered Sets: III A Class of Partially Ordered Sets: III by Geoffrey Hemion 1 Definitions To begin with, let us fix a certain notation. Let the pair (X, ) be a given poset. For a X, let a = {x X : x < a} and a = {x X :

More information

HW 4 SOLUTIONS. , x + x x 1 ) 2

HW 4 SOLUTIONS. , x + x x 1 ) 2 HW 4 SOLUTIONS The Way of Analysis p. 98: 1.) Suppose that A is open. Show that A minus a finite set is still open. This follows by induction as long as A minus one point x is still open. To see that A

More information

Homework for MAT 603 with Pugh s Real Mathematical Analysis. Damien Pitman

Homework for MAT 603 with Pugh s Real Mathematical Analysis. Damien Pitman Homework for MAT 603 with Pugh s Real Mathematical Analysis Damien Pitman CHAPTER 1 Real Numbers 1. Preliminaries (1) In what sense is Euclid s method of reasoning superior to Aristotle s? (2) What role

More information

Preference and Utility

Preference and Utility Preference and Utility Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 3, 5 September Problem Set 1 is due in Kelly s mailbox by 5pm today Outline 1 Existence of Utility Functions 2 Continuous Preferences 3 Debreu s Representation

More information

Section 7.5: Cardinality

Section 7.5: Cardinality Section 7: Cardinality In this section, we shall consider extend some of the ideas we have developed to infinite sets One interesting consequence of this discussion is that we shall see there are as many

More information

Numbers 1. 1 Overview. 2 The Integers, Z. John Nachbar Washington University in St. Louis September 22, 2017

Numbers 1. 1 Overview. 2 The Integers, Z. John Nachbar Washington University in St. Louis September 22, 2017 John Nachbar Washington University in St. Louis September 22, 2017 1 Overview. Numbers 1 The Set Theory notes show how to construct the set of natural numbers N out of nothing (more accurately, out of

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: John J. Watkins: Topics in Commutative Ring Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, 2007, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part of this

More information

16 circles. what goes around...

16 circles. what goes around... 16 circles. what goes around... 2 lesson 16 this is the first of two lessons dealing with circles. this lesson gives some basic definitions and some elementary theorems, the most important of which is

More information

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS Chapter 6 MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS This chapter can be considered enrichment material containing also several more advanced topics and may be skipped in its entirety. You can proceed directly

More information

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds 1. Epistemically possible worlds David Chalmers Metaphysically possible worlds: S is metaphysically possible iff S is true in some metaphysically possible

More information

Beliefs, we will assume, come in degrees. As a shorthand, we will refer to these. Syracuse University

Beliefs, we will assume, come in degrees. As a shorthand, we will refer to these. Syracuse University AN OPEN ACCESS Ergo JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Calibration and Probabilism MICHAEL CAIE Syracuse University In this paper, I consider an argument due to Bas van Fraassen that attempts to show that considerations

More information

Chapter VI. Relations. Assumptions are the termites of relationships. Henry Winkler

Chapter VI. Relations. Assumptions are the termites of relationships. Henry Winkler Chapter VI Relations Assumptions are the termites of relationships. Henry Winkler Studying relationships between objects can yield important information about the objects themselves. In the real numbers,

More information

Definition: A vector is a directed line segment which represents a displacement from one point P to another point Q.

Definition: A vector is a directed line segment which represents a displacement from one point P to another point Q. THE UNIVERSITY OF NEW SOUTH WALES SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICS AND STATISTICS MATH Algebra Section : - Introduction to Vectors. You may have already met the notion of a vector in physics. There you will have

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011 Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011 (The Philosophical Review 122 (2013): 522 525) Jill North This is a neat little book (138 pages without appendices, under 200 with).

More information

Data preprocessing. DataBase and Data Mining Group 1. Data set types. Tabular Data. Document Data. Transaction Data. Ordered Data

Data preprocessing. DataBase and Data Mining Group 1. Data set types. Tabular Data. Document Data. Transaction Data. Ordered Data Elena Baralis and Tania Cerquitelli Politecnico di Torino Data set types Record Tables Document Data Transaction Data Graph World Wide Web Molecular Structures Ordered Spatial Data Temporal Data Sequential

More information

3. A square has 4 sides, so S = 4. A pentagon has 5 vertices, so P = 5. Hence, S + P = 9. = = 5 3.

3. A square has 4 sides, so S = 4. A pentagon has 5 vertices, so P = 5. Hence, S + P = 9. = = 5 3. JHMMC 01 Grade Solutions October 1, 01 1. By counting, there are 7 words in this question.. (, 1, ) = 1 + 1 + = 9 + 1 + =.. A square has sides, so S =. A pentagon has vertices, so P =. Hence, S + P = 9..

More information