by burning money Sjaak Hurkens y CentER, Tilburg University P.O. Box November 1994 Abstract

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "by burning money Sjaak Hurkens y CentER, Tilburg University P.O. Box November 1994 Abstract"

Transcription

1 Multi-sided pre-play communication by burning money Sjaak Hurkens y CentER, Tilburg University P.O. Box LE Tilburg, The Netherlands November 1994 Abstract We investigate the consequences of allowing some players to send a costly message before a game is played. Since messages have no literal meaning sending costly messages is also called `burning money'. We consider a setting with n players among which k have the possibility to burn money. We show that strategy proles in sets that are closed under rational behavior, yield all players that have the possibility to burn, their preferred outcome. Moreover, in such equilibria no money is actually burnt, the possibility alone suces. For the special case with two players all results go through for persistent retracts as well. Journal of Economic Literature Classication Number: C72. Copyright c1996 by Academic Press. This material has been published in Journal of Economic Theory, 69, , the only denitive repository of the content that has been certied and accepted after peer review. Copyright and all rights therein are retained by Academic Press. This material may not be copied or reposted without explicit permission. ythe author thanks Eric van Damme for many helpful discussions, and an anonymous referee and an associate editor for helpful comments. This research was sponsored by the Foundation for the Promotion of Research in Economic Sciences, which is part of the Netherlands Organization for Scientic Research (NWO). 1

2 1 Introduction Given a game in normal form, Ben-Porath and Dekel [4] investigate the consequences of allowing some players to signal future actions by incurring costs before the game is played. They consider equilibria that survive repeated elimination of weakly dominated strategies. Their main result is that, in a certain class of two person games, if only one player can signal, then repeated elimination of weakly dominated strategies selects her most preferred outcome. Moreover, the player does not have to incur any cost to achieve this. While this result is nice, it has some important limitations. First of all, Ben-Porath and Dekel consider only two player games. As we will show later by example, repeated elimination of weakly dominated strategies need not work in games with more than two players. Furthermore, they show that if both players have the opportunity to signal (simultaneously), then signaling future actions is not possible, not even if the game has common interests. Finally, they need that a player can burn a considerable amount of money. We consider a more general case. We extend n-person games by allowing k of the players to signal future actions by incurring costs. In order to obtain results similar to those of Ben-Porath and Dekel we work with a stronger solution concept. Van Damme [6] showed that stable equilibria do not necessarily lead to ecient outcomes. We show that, if the notion of curb or curb* retracts (Basu and Weibull [3]) is used, then signaling future actions is possible. In fact, our result is stronger than that, since even giving a dummy player the opportunity to burn money can inuence the outcome. Roughly speaking, if the players that can burn money have common interests in the underlying game, then curb and curb* select their preferred outcome. Furthermore, in all models of pre-play communication, no costs are actually incurred. Moreover, if there are two players then the notion of persistence (Kalai and Samet [8]) gives the same results. In the next section we will consider a simple example of a two person game where only one player can signal. From this example the reader can develop some feeling for the solution concept we employ. Moreover, this example shows a dierence between our 2

3 approach and that of Ben-Porath and Dekel's. At the same time it shows that it is important that messages are costly. In Section 3 the formal model and the notions of curb and curb* retracts are dened. In Section 4 we prove the theorem for these concepts for the general case. In Section 5 we consider persistent retracts in the special case of two person games. Moreover, it is shown that in games with more than two players persistence need not work. 2 An example: the battle of the sexes Consider the battle of the sexes game represented by the normal form in Figure 1. The woman (the row player) prefers to go to a soccer match (`S'), the man (the column player) prefers to go to the theater (`t'). s t S 9,5 0,4 T 4,4 6,7 Figure 1: the battle of the sexes. Suppose the woman can send one of two messages, m 0 or m 1. Message m 0 is costless and message m 1 costs c. Later we will consider the cases c = 0, c = 1 and c = 2. Let m i E denote the woman's strategy when she sends m i and visits event E. Let e 0 e 1 denote the man's strategy when he goes to event e i if he receives message m i. Then the game with one-sided pre-play communication can be represented by the normal form in Figure 2. ss st ts tt m 0 S 9,5 9,5 0,4 0,4 m 0 T 4,4 4,4 6,7 6,7 m 1 S 9? c; 5?c; 4 9? c; 5?c; 4 m 1 T 4? c; 4 6? c; 7 4? c; 4 6? c; 7 Figure 2. First we will consider Ben-Porath and Dekel's approach. Consider the case c = 2. Starting with deleting action m 1 T, we nd that repeated elimination of weakly domi- 3

4 nated strategies yields the equilibrium (m 0 S; ss). Hence, repeated elimination of weakly dominated strategies selects the outcome where both go to the soccer match and no money is actually being burnt. Notice that this reasoning does not go through if c = 0 or if c = 1. In these cases no player has a dominated strategy. For example, if c = 1, m 1 T can only be dominated by a strategy that puts at least weight 5 on 6 m0 T, and at least weight 1 on 5 m0 S. We will look at minimal sets of strategies that are closed under best responses. (Basu and Weibull [3] call this curb: closed under rational behavior.) A set of strategy proles is closed under best responses if with every strategy prole, all its best replies are contained in the set. Now look at our example. Suppose R 1 R 2 is closed under best responses. It is easy to check that we have the following implications (for all values of c under consideration). m 1 T 2 R 1 ) tt 2 R 2 ) m 0 T 2 R 1 ) ts 2 R 2 ) m 1 S 2 R 1 ) ss 2 R 2 ) m 0 S 2 R 1 ) ss; st 2 R 2 In the cases with c > 0, the set of strategy proles where the woman plays m 0 S and the man mixes between ss and st is closed under best responses. implications shows that this set is the unique minimal one. If c = 0 the series of implications continues. The series of ss; st 2 R 2 ) m 1 S 2 R 1 ) ts 2 R 2 Since m 0 T and m 1 T are best replies against 1 st + 1 ts, we conclude that the only set 2 2 that is closed under best responses is the set of all strategy proles. Hence, if talk is costless, then on the basis of curb no sharp predictions can be made in this game. 1 3 The model In this section we will formally set up the model of multi-sided pre-play communication in n-person games. Before we do that we recall the notions of curb and curb* (Basu and Weibull [3]). 4

5 We denote the set of mixed strategies of player i by i. For a set of pure strategies X let co(x) denote the convex hull of this set, which is equivalent to the set of all probability distributions over X. If is a strategy prole then?i denotes the prole of all players besides player i. The set of best replies of player i against?i is denoted by BR i (?i ). Dene BR() = Q n i=1 BR i (?i ). UBR() denotes the set of best replies against that are not weakly dominated. A retract is a cartesian product R = Q n i=1 R i, where R i i is non-empty, convex and compact. Denition 1. A retract R is said to have the curb property if for all 2 R, BR() R. A retract R is said to have the curb* property if for all 2 R, UBR() R. A retract which is minimal with respect to the curb (curb*) property is called a curb (curb*) retract. The minimality condition is imposed since the set of all strategy proles trivially satises the curb and curb* properties. A curb retract can be viewed as a set-valued generalization of a strict equilibrium, or as a self-enforcing agreement. If an outsider recommends all players to play strategies from some curb retract R, each player should follow this recommendation, whenever he expects the other players to do so. Even when there is no outsider to give such a recommendation, players may learn to play curb strategies (see Hurkens [7] or Appendix I for a summary of [7]). The comparison with strict equilibria is not completely valid since curb retracts may contain weakly dominated strategies. Curb* retracts do not contain pure weakly dominated strategies. The two dierent concepts are closely related and have some nice properties that are summarized in the following lemma. Lemma 1. Every curb retract contains a curb* retract. Every curb (curb*) retract is a cartesian product of convex hulls of pure strategies. The intersection of two retracts with the curb (curb*) property is either empty or it has the curb (curb*) property, hence dierent curb (curb*) retracts are disjoint. Proof. Easy and therefore omitted. 2 Let G = (S 1 ; : : : ; S n ; u 1 ; : : : ; u n ) be an n-person game with player set N. We split up the set of players into C and D. C is the set of players that can send a message 5

6 in the pre-play communication stage (communicating players); D is the set of players that cannot (dumb players). Note that the players in D are dumb but not deaf. It is important that they can hear. We assume that C is not empty. D may be empty. We will assume Assumption 1. There exists s 2 S such that u i (s ) > u i (s), for all i 2 C and all s 6= s and such that u j (s ) > u j (s?j ; s j) for all j 2 D and all s j 6= s j. Notice that if C = N then G is a common interest game (Aumann and Sorin [1]). Assumption 1 says that the game has a strict Nash equilibrium that gives all communicating players their highest payo. We assume that all communicating players have the same set of messages M = fm 0 ; m 1 ; : : : ; m L g at their disposal and that the cost of sending message m p is c(m p ) for all of them. These assumptions are made for notational convenience only. They do not play a role in the results we will derive. We assume that c(m 0 ) = 0, c(m 1 ) > 0 is `small' and c(m p ) > c(m 1 ) for all p > 1. In fact, c(m 1 ) is so small that c(m 1 ) < u i (s )? u i (s) for all i 2 C and all s 6= s This implies that any communicating player who can induce the play of s by sending message m 1, will do so, unless sending m 0 induces the play of s also. We denote the game with pre-play communication by P C (G) = (T 1 ; : : : ; T n ; v 1 ; : : : ; v n ), where T i = fm i f i jm i 2 M and f i : M Cnfig! S i g (i 2 C) T j = ff j jf j : M C! S j g (j 2 D) (We use the following convention if C = fig: f i : M ;! S i corresponds to a single element of S i.) With some abuse of notation we have for mf 2 T = Q n l=1 T l, v i (mf) = u i (f(m))? c(m i ) (i 2 C) v j (mf) = u j (f(m)) (j 2 D) Remark: The way we have dened the strategy space here means that we are looking at the reduced normal form (as did Ben-Porath and Dekel). In the normal form a communicating player's strategy also depends on his own message. It does not matter 6

7 for our results whether we analyze the normal form or the reduced normal form. However, in the normal form the communicating players have a lot of equivalent strategies and this makes the proof for persistence quite tedious. 4 Results for the general case In this section we will prove the theorem for the curb and curb* retracts. We will deal with the general case with n players among which the players in C can communicate. Theorem 1. P C (G) has a unique curb (curb*) retract, and every strategy prole in this retract yields player l u l (s ) (l 2 N). Proof. We will denote a vector with all coordinates equal to m 0 by m d0. (Depending on whether this vector is in the domain of a dumb or of a communicating player, it has #C or #C? 1 coordinates. No confusion will result.) Dene F = fmf 2 T jm = d m 0 ; f l ( d m 0 ) = s l for all l 2 Ng Notice that F consists of all pure strategy proles that yield the payo vector u(s ). We will show that every curb* retract has a non-empty intersection with F. If this is the case then every curb* retract is contained in R = Q n l=1 co(f l ), since R has the curb* property. Since every curb retract contains a curb* retract, we know then that every curb retract has a non-empty intersection with R. Since R has the curb property itself, any curb retract is contained in R. Since all strategy proles in R yield the payo u(s ), it follows that R is the unique curb retract, and that the unique curb* retract is obtained from R by deleting every strategy that has pure weakly dominated strategies in its support. Then the proof has been completed. Let R be a curb* retract and let m f 2 R n F. Now player l has a lot of undominated best replies against ( m f)?l. This is so because a player has a lot of freedom in how to react on tuples of messages that he does not receive. In particular there exists m 0 f 0 2 R such that (i) for all i 2 C and all m?i 6= m?i, f 0 i(m?i ) = s i, and (ii) for all j 2 D and all m 6= m, f 0 j(m) = s j. If m 0 f 0 2 F we are ready, because then F \ R 6= ;. 7

8 So suppose m 0 f 0 62 F. Case 1: m 6= d m 0. There exists i 2 C with m i 6= m 0. All best replies for i against m 0 f 0 involve sending m 0. In particular, if f 00 i (m) = s i for all m, then m 0 f 00 i is an undominated best reply to m 0 f 0 and hence contained in R i. Now for j 2 C, j 6= i, all best replies against z = (m 0 f 00 i ; m0 f 0?i) involve sending m 0. In particular, if f 00 j (m) = s j for all m, then m 0 f 00 j is an undominated best reply to z and hence contained in R j. Thus F \R 6= ;. Case 2: m = d m 0. Let i 2 C. All best replies for i against m 0 f 0 involve sending m 1. Hence, there exists m f 2 R n F with m 6= d m 0. This brings us back to case Further results for two player games Let us recall the notion of persistent retracts (Kalai and Samet [8]). Denition 2. A retract R is called absorbing if there exists an open neighborhood U R such that for all 2 U, we have that BR() \ R 6= ;. An absorbing retract is called persistent if it does not properly contain an absorbing retract. For an elaborate discussion of the relation between persistent retracts and other solution concepts the reader is referred to Balkenborg [2]. Two interesting facts on persistent retracts we will state here, without proofs. Every curb* retract contains a persistent retract (Balkenborg [2]) and every persistent retract contains a Nash equilibrium (Kalai and Samet [8]). Let us state the following lemma which will prove to be useful in the two player case. The proof is relegated to Appendix II. Lemma 2. Let G = (S 1 ; S 2 ; u 1 ; u 2 ) be a game. For F = F 1 F 2 S 1 S 2, let H i = S i n F i. If (1) for all f; f 0 2 F, u i (f) = u i (f 0 ), (2) for all f 2 F and h i 2 H i, u i (h i ; f j ) < u i (f), and (3) every persistent retract has a non-empty intersection with F, then every persistent retract is contained in R = co(f1 ) co(f 2 ). From now on we will assume 8

9 Assumption 2. No player has equivalent strategies in the game with pre-play communication. Then we have that every persistent retract of this game is a cartesian product of convex hulls of pure strategies. For a proof see Kalai and Samet [8]. 5.1 One-sided pre-play communication First we will consider the case with one-sided pre-play communication, hence C = f1g. Assumption 1 is now equivalent to saying that the underlying game has a strict Nash equilibrium yielding player 1 a higher payo than any other strategy prole. Theorem 2. Every strategy prole in a persistent retract of P f1g (G) yields player l u l (s ) (l 2 N). Proof. Let R be a persistent retract and let ms 1 2 R 1. Case 1: m 6= m 0. Then there exists g 2 R 2 with g(m 0 ) = s 2. This is so because all best replies against (1?)ms 1 + m 0 s 1 have this property. This implies that m 0 s 1 2 R 1, since it is the unique best reply against g. Case 2: m = m 0 and s 1 6= s 1. Using the same trick as before we see that there exists g 2 R 2 with g(m 1 ) = s 2. If g(m 0 ) = s 2, then m 0 s 1 2 R 1. If g(m 0 ) 6= s 2, then m 1 s 1 2 R 1. This brings us back to case 1. Hence, m 0 s 2 1 R 1. It is easy to check that the set of extreme points of F = fm 0 s 1g co(fg : M! S 2 jg(m 0 ) = s 2g) satises assumptions (1), (2) and (3) of Lemma 2. Then it follows from Lemma 2 that R F. Notice that every strategy prole in F yields player l u l (s ) and the theorem has been proved Two-sided pre-play communication Now we turn our attention to the two-sided pre-play communication game, i.e. C = f1; 2g. Recall that Assumption 1 now says that the underlying game has common interests. 9

10 Theorem 3. Every strategy prole in a persistent retract of P C (G) yields player l a payo of u l (s ) (l 2 N). Proof. Let R be a persistent retract and let mf 2 R i. Let j = 3? i. Case 1: m 6= m 0. Then there exists m 0 g 2 R j m 0 f 0 2 R i with f 0 (m 0 ) = s i. with g(m 0 ) = s j. Hence, there exists Case 2: m = m 0 and f(m 0 ) 6= s i. Then there exists m0 g 2 R j with g(m 1 ) = s j. If g(m 0 ) = s j, then there exists m 0 f 0 2 R i with f 0 (m 0 ) = s i. If g(m 0 ) 6= s j, then there exists m 1 f 00 2 R i. This brings us back to case 1. Let F i = fm 0 fjf(m 0 ) = s i g. The two cases showed that F i \ R i 6= ;. It is easy to check that F 1 and F 2 satisfy assumptions (1), (2) and (3) of Lemma 2. Hence, any persistent retract is contained in co(f 1 ) co(f 2 ). Notice that any strategy prole in this set yields player l u l (s ) and the theorem has been proved A three player counterexample The following example shows that persistence need not work in games with more than two players. Example. Let n = 3, C = f3g. Player 1 chooses between rows R 1 and R 2, player 2 chooses between columns C 1 and C 2 and player 3 chooses A. (Player 3 has only one action.) The payos are given in Figure 3. C 1 C 2 R 1 2,2,2 0,0,0 R 2 0,0,0 1,1,1 Figure 3. Now consider the following strategy prole: players 1 and 2 play their second strategy after all messages and player 3 sends the costless message and then `chooses' A. This yields the strictly dominated payo vector (1; 1; 1). Nevertheless, this strategy prole is a persistent retract as a singleton and hence a persistent equilibrium. In a small neighborhood of the retract player 3 has a unique best reply. Players 1 and 2 have a lot of best replies against the retract, but in a small neighborhood outside the retract they 10

11 have a unique best reply. This is due to the fact that players 1 and 2 have an interest in choosing the same action: in a small neighborhood player 1 plays R 2 with a very high probability, after any message, and hence player 2 has to choose C 2, after any message. Repeated elimination of weakly dominated strategies does not work either. In this example the messages are not important to signal the intended action of player 3, since he has only one action. Hence, our results are not related to forward induction. The reason that the dummy player has an eect on the outcome (when curb or curb* is applied), is that the other players may change their reply to (currently) unsent messages. The dummy player is willing to try a dierent (and possibly more costly) message, whenever the rst two players fail to coordinate on the ecient equilibrium. 2 Appendix I In Hurkens [7], we construct a dynamic learning process to support the concepts of curb retracts. We briey summarize that paper. Roughly speaking, the learning evolves as follows: A particular game is played at discrete points in time. For each role in this game there is a pool of players. At the beginning of each period one player is drawn from each pool. These players will play the game in that period. Players have a bounded memory. On the basis of strategies played in the recent past, they form expectations about the strategies the other players will use, and best respond to these expectations. It is assumed that dierent players within the same pool may have dierent beliefs and therefore they may choose dierent actions. It is shown that, if the memory is long enough, play will settle down in a minimal curb set. The intuition for this result is quite clear. By having a large enough memory, players may have beliefs with large supports. This means that best replies against all kinds of mixtures will be played now and then. This creates so much stochastic variability that players sooner or later will play curb strategies. When they keep drawing the \right" samples, they will keep best responding against curb strategies, and hence they will play curb strategies again. It might happen that they will do this many periods in a row. The probability that this happens at a specic point in time is only small, but with 11

12 probability one it will happen eventually. By that time all non-curb strategies will be forgotten. The strategies that will be played from that point on, will depend on the sample drawn, but it is sure that it will be curb strategies again. Appendix II Proof of Lemma 2. Let R be a persistent retract, and let V 1 V 2 R be an open neighborhood that is absorbed by R. Let x i = u i (f) for (all) f 2 F and dene m + i = max u i (s 1 ; s 2 ) m? i = min u i (s 1 ; s 2 ) (h 1 ) = x 1? max f 2 2F 2 u 1 (h 1 ; f 2 ) (h 1 2 H 1 ) (h 2 ) = x 2? max f 1 2F 1 u 2 (f 1 ; h 2 ) (h 2 2 H 2 ) Notice that (2) implies (h i ) > 0. Let i = min hi 2H i (h i ). Let j > 0 (j = 3? i) satisfy (1? j )(x i? i ) + j m + i < (1? j )x i + j m? i Let i (s i ) denote the weight that i puts on s i. Dene V i ( i ) = f i 2 V i j P h i 2H i i (h i ) < i g. Then V 1 ( 1 ) V 2 ( 2 ) is an open neighborhood of R \ R. We claim that this neighborhood is absorbed by R \ R. Let 2 2 V 2 ( 2 ), h 1 2 H 1, f 1 2 F 1. Now u 1 (h 1 ; 2 ) X F 2 2 (f 2 )(x 1? (h 1 )) + X H 2 2 (h 2 )m + 1 < (1? 2 )(x 1? 1 ) + 2 m + 1 < (1? 2 )x m? 1 X F 2 2 (f 2 )x 1 + X H 2 2 (h 2 )u 1 (f 1 ; h 2 ) = u 1 (f 1 ; 2 ) Hence, there are no best replies against strategies in V 2 ( 2 ) in H 1. Hence, the best replies are in F 1. Reversing the roles of the players then proves the claim. Hence, every persistent retract is contained in R. 2 12

13 References 1. R. Aumann and S. Sorin, Cooperation and bounded recall, Games Econ. Behav. 1 (1989), D. Balkenborg, \The properties of persistent retracts and related concepts," Ph.D. thesis, University of Bonn, October K. Basu and J.W. Weibull, Strategy subsets closed under rational behavior, Econ. Lett. 36 (1991), E. Ben-Porath and E. Dekel, Signaling future actions and the potential for sacrice, J. Econ. Theory 57 (1992), A. Blume, \Communication, risk and eciency in games," mimeo, University of Iowa, E. van Damme, Stable equilibria and forward induction, J. Econ. Theory 48 (1989), S. Hurkens, \Learning by forgetful players: From primitive formations to persistent retracts," CentER Discussion Paper 9437, Tilburg University, E. Kalai and D. Samet, Persistent equilibria in strategic games, Int. J. Game Theory 13 (1984),

14 Footnotes 1. Blume [5] shows that the equilibria in a curb retract of the one-sided cheap talk game select the equilibrium preferred by the sender, provided that the risk associated with this equilibrium in the underlying game is suciently low. Indeed, if the payo to (S; t) is changed from `0; 4' into `2; 4' (which reduces the risk of (S; s)), then the unique curb retract does not contain m 0 T, m 1 T or tt, and all equilibria in the curb retract yield 9; We have analyzed the game with pre-play communication in the reduced normal form. Our results for curb and curb* extend to the agent normal form, but the results for persistence do not. This need not come as a surprise, since the agent normal form has more than two players. 14

An axiomatization of minimal curb sets. 1. Introduction. Mark Voorneveld,,1, Willemien Kets, and Henk Norde

An axiomatization of minimal curb sets. 1. Introduction. Mark Voorneveld,,1, Willemien Kets, and Henk Norde An axiomatization of minimal curb sets Mark Voorneveld,,1, Willemien Kets, and Henk Norde Department of Econometrics and Operations Research, Tilburg University, The Netherlands Department of Economics,

More information

ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY

ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY Appendix B. Modeling Games as Decisions In this appendix we describe how one can move seamlessly

More information

SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION. Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson. December 2005

SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION. Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson. December 2005 SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION By Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson December 2005 COWLES FOUNDATION DISCUSSION AER NO. 1542 COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen Strategic Form Games In this part we will analyze games in which the players choose their actions simultaneously (or without the knowledge of other players

More information

Game Theory and Rationality

Game Theory and Rationality April 6, 2015 Notation for Strategic Form Games Definition A strategic form game (or normal form game) is defined by 1 The set of players i = {1,..., N} 2 The (usually finite) set of actions A i for each

More information

Refined best-response correspondence and dynamics

Refined best-response correspondence and dynamics Refined best-response correspondence and dynamics Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer, and Christoph Kuzmics February 18, 2007 Abstract We study a natural (and, in a well-defined sense, minimal) refinement

More information

The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games. Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics

The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games. Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics International Journal of Game Theory ISSN 0020-7276 Volume 44 Number 1 Int J Game Theory

More information

Virtual Robust Implementation and Strategic Revealed Preference

Virtual Robust Implementation and Strategic Revealed Preference and Strategic Revealed Preference Workshop of Mathematical Economics Celebrating the 60th birthday of Aloisio Araujo IMPA Rio de Janeiro December 2006 Denitions "implementation": requires ALL equilibria

More information

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra

More information

Nash Equilibrium without. Mutual Knowledge of Rationality 1. Kin Chung Lo. Department of Economics, University oftoronto, July, 1995.

Nash Equilibrium without. Mutual Knowledge of Rationality 1. Kin Chung Lo. Department of Economics, University oftoronto, July, 1995. Nash Equilibrium without Mutual Knowledge of Rationality 1 Kin Chung Lo Department of Economics, University oftoronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 1A1 July, 1995 Abstract This paper denes an equilibrium

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11 Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11 Perfect information A finite extensive game with perfect information

More information

Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games

Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games Geir B. Asheim a Andrés Perea b October 16, 2017 Abstract We provide comparable algorithms for the Dekel-Fudenberg procedure, iterated admissibility, proper rationalizability

More information

Observations on Cooperation

Observations on Cooperation Introduction Observations on Cooperation Yuval Heller (Bar Ilan) and Erik Mohlin (Lund) PhD Workshop, BIU, January, 2018 Heller & Mohlin Observations on Cooperation 1 / 20 Introduction Motivating Example

More information

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 18 To recap Tuesday: We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Two finite populations, call them Men and Women, who want to

More information

Persuasion Under Costly Lying

Persuasion Under Costly Lying Persuasion Under Costly Lying Teck Yong Tan Columbia University 1 / 43 Introduction Consider situations where agent designs learning environment (i.e. what additional information to generate) to persuade

More information

Economics Noncooperative Game Theory Lectures 3. October 15, 1997 Lecture 3

Economics Noncooperative Game Theory Lectures 3. October 15, 1997 Lecture 3 Economics 8117-8 Noncooperative Game Theory October 15, 1997 Lecture 3 Professor Andrew McLennan Nash Equilibrium I. Introduction A. Philosophy 1. Repeated framework a. One plays against dierent opponents

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions Walter Trockel University of California, Los Angeles and Bielefeld University Mai 1999 Abstract The paper presents a method of supporting

More information

Weak Dominance and Never Best Responses

Weak Dominance and Never Best Responses Chapter 4 Weak Dominance and Never Best Responses Let us return now to our analysis of an arbitrary strategic game G := (S 1,...,S n, p 1,...,p n ). Let s i, s i be strategies of player i. We say that

More information

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007 Costly Expertise Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz Current Version: December, 007 In many environments expertise is costly. Costs can manifest themselves in numerous ways, ranging from the time that is required

More information

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) Game Theory Bargaining Theory J International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) (International Game Theory: Doctorate Bargainingin Theory Economic Analysis (IDEA)

More information

Notes on Mechanism Designy

Notes on Mechanism Designy Notes on Mechanism Designy ECON 20B - Game Theory Guillermo Ordoñez UCLA February 0, 2006 Mechanism Design. Informal discussion. Mechanisms are particular types of games of incomplete (or asymmetric) information

More information

ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES

ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES PRISCILLA T. Y. MAN Abstract. Reputation is often modelled by a small but positive prior probability that a player is a behavioral type in repeated games. This paper

More information

Coordination and Cheap Talk in a Battle of the Sexes with Private Information

Coordination and Cheap Talk in a Battle of the Sexes with Private Information Department of Economics Coordination and Cheap Talk in a Battle of the Sexes with Private Information Department of Economics Discussion Paper 3-0 Chirantan Ganguly Indrajit Ray Coordination and Cheap

More information

Anna Bogomolnaia and Matthew O. Jackson. April, This Revision: January Forthcoming: Games and Economic Behavior.

Anna Bogomolnaia and Matthew O. Jackson. April, This Revision: January Forthcoming: Games and Economic Behavior. The Stability of Hedonic Coalition Structures Anna Bogomolnaia and Matthew O. Jackson April, 1998 This Revision: January 2001 Forthcoming: Games and Economic Behavior Abstract We consider the partitioning

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Price Competition and Endogenous Valuation in Search Advertising

Price Competition and Endogenous Valuation in Search Advertising Price Competition and Endogenous Valuation in Search Advertising Lizhen Xu Jianqing Chen Andrew Whinston Web Appendix A Heterogeneous Consumer Valuation In the baseline model, we assumed that consumers

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Game Theory and Social Psychology

Game Theory and Social Psychology Game Theory and Social Psychology cf. Osborne, ch 4.8 Kitty Genovese: attacked in NY in front of 38 witnesses no one intervened or called the police Why not? \Indierence to one's neighbour and his troubles

More information

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibrium Refinements Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game... subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium Play starting

More information

WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE *

WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE * WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE * Martin Dufwenberg ** & Mark Stegeman *** February 1999 Abstract: We demonstrate that iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies is an order

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

Monotonic models and cycles

Monotonic models and cycles Int J Game Theory DOI 10.1007/s00182-013-0385-7 Monotonic models and cycles José Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Accepted: 16 May 2013 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2013 Abstract A partitional model of knowledge

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Self-stabilizing uncoupled dynamics

Self-stabilizing uncoupled dynamics Self-stabilizing uncoupled dynamics Aaron D. Jaggard 1, Neil Lutz 2, Michael Schapira 3, and Rebecca N. Wright 4 1 U.S. Naval Research Laboratory, Washington, DC 20375, USA. aaron.jaggard@nrl.navy.mil

More information

Multiagent Systems Motivation. Multiagent Systems Terminology Basics Shapley value Representation. 10.

Multiagent Systems Motivation. Multiagent Systems Terminology Basics Shapley value Representation. 10. Multiagent Systems July 2, 2014 10. Coalition Formation Multiagent Systems 10. Coalition Formation B. Nebel, C. Becker-Asano, S. Wöl Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg July 2, 2014 10.1 Motivation 10.2

More information

Algorithmic Strategy Complexity

Algorithmic Strategy Complexity Algorithmic Strategy Complexity Abraham Neyman aneyman@math.huji.ac.il Hebrew University of Jerusalem Jerusalem Israel Algorithmic Strategy Complexity, Northwesten 2003 p.1/52 General Introduction The

More information

Conservative Belief and Rationality

Conservative Belief and Rationality Conservative Belief and Rationality Joseph Y. Halpern and Rafael Pass Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY, 14853, U.S.A. e-mail: halpern@cs.cornell.edu, rafael@cs.cornell.edu January

More information

6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, Lecture 2

6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, Lecture 2 6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, 2015 Lecture 2 Lecturer: Constantinos Daskalakis Scribe: Constantinos Daskalakis We formally define games and the solution concepts overviewed in Lecture

More information

Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium

Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium YUICHIRO KAMADA 1 Department of Economics, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 Abstract Fudenberg and Levine (1993a) introduce the notion of self-confirming

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Summer 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the four areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory A, (III) game theory B, and (IV) psychology & economics). Be sure

More information

Volume 31, Issue 1. A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities. Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid

Volume 31, Issue 1. A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities. Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Volume 31, Issue 1 A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Abstract Since the core of a housing market with externalities

More information

Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design

Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design Elliot Anshelevich Bugra Caskurlu Received: January 2010 / Accepted: Abstract We study the survivable

More information

ON FORWARD INDUCTION

ON FORWARD INDUCTION Econometrica, Submission #6956, revised ON FORWARD INDUCTION SRIHARI GOVINDAN AND ROBERT WILSON Abstract. A player s pure strategy is called relevant for an outcome of a game in extensive form with perfect

More information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Levent Koçkesen 1 Extensive Form Games The strategies in strategic form games are speci ed so that each player chooses an action (or a mixture of actions)

More information

A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon

A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon Chantal Marlats January 2010 Chantal Marlats () A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon January 2010 1 / 14 Introduction: A story

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen 1 Bayesian Games So far we have assumed that all players had perfect information regarding the elements of a game. These are called games with complete information.

More information

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED DOV SAMET Abstract. An informal argument shows that common knowledge of rationality implies the iterative elimination of strongly dominated strategies. Rationality

More information

Olivier Tercieux. 1. Introduction

Olivier Tercieux. 1. Introduction Journal of Economic Theory 131 (2006) 45 70 www.elsevier.com/locate/jet p-best response set Olivier Tercieux PSE, Paris-Jourdan Sciences Economiques and CNRS, 48 boulevard Jourdan, 75014 Paris, France

More information

HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY

HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY JEFFREY C. ELY AND MARCIN PESKI Abstract. In games with incomplete information, conventional hierarchies of belief are incomplete as descriptions of

More information

A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts

A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts Joseph Y. Halpern Cornell University Computer Science Department Ithaca, NY 14853 halpern@cs.cornell.edu http://www.cs.cornell.edu/home/halpern August 15, 2018

More information

ECO421: Reputation. Marcin P ski. March 29, 2018

ECO421: Reputation. Marcin P ski. March 29, 2018 ECO421: Reputation Marcin P ski March 29, 2018 Plan Chain store game Model of reputation Reputations in innite games Applications Model No pure strategy equilibria Mixed strategy equilibrium Basic model

More information

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy.

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy. Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy. Amrita Dhillon and Ben Lockwood This version: March 2001 Abstract De Sinopoli and Turrini (1999) present an example to show

More information

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Mehmet Barlo Nuh Aygun Dalkiran February 10, 2014 Abstract We provide necessary and sufficient conditions for epsilon ex post implementation. Our analysis extends Bergemann

More information

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation Chih-Chun Yang Institute of Economics, Academia Sinica, Taipei 115, Taiwan April 2016 Abstract We provide a characterization of (virtual) implementation in iterated

More information

Possibility and Impossibility of Learning with Limited Behavior Rules

Possibility and Impossibility of Learning with Limited Behavior Rules Possibility and Impossibility of Learning with Limited Behavior Rules Takako Fujiwara-Greve Dept. of Economics Keio University, Tokyo, Japan and Norwegian School of Management BI, Sandvika, Norway and

More information

Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge

Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge Christoph Schottmüller University of Copenhagen November 13 and 20, 2014 1 / 36 Outline 1 (Common) Knowledge The hat game A model of knowledge Common knowledge Agree

More information

Winter Lecture 10. Convexity and Concavity

Winter Lecture 10. Convexity and Concavity Andrew McLennan February 9, 1999 Economics 5113 Introduction to Mathematical Economics Winter 1999 Lecture 10 Convexity and Concavity I. Introduction A. We now consider convexity, concavity, and the general

More information

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY 1 / 32 BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY Heinrich H. Nax hnax@ethz.ch & Bary S. R. Pradelski bpradelski@ethz.ch May 15, 217: Lecture 1 2 / 32 Plan Normal form games Equilibrium invariance Equilibrium

More information

RESEARCH PAPER NO AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS. Srihari Govindan.

RESEARCH PAPER NO AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS. Srihari Govindan. RESEARCH PAPER NO. 2000 AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS Srihari Govindan Robert Wilson September 2008 This work was partially funded by a National Science

More information

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley**

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Published as: Bhaskar Chakravorti and John P. Conley (2004) Bargaining Efficiency and the repeated Prisoners

More information

Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics. Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017

Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics. Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017 Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017 1 Outline Introduction Syllabus Web demonstration Examples 2 About Me: Peter Cramton B.S. Engineering, Cornell University Ph.D. Business

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

Learning by (limited) forward looking players

Learning by (limited) forward looking players Learning by (limited) forward looking players Friederike Mengel Maastricht University April 2009 Abstract We present a model of adaptive economic agents who are k periods forward looking. Agents in our

More information

DETERMINISTIC AND STOCHASTIC SELECTION DYNAMICS

DETERMINISTIC AND STOCHASTIC SELECTION DYNAMICS DETERMINISTIC AND STOCHASTIC SELECTION DYNAMICS Jörgen Weibull March 23, 2010 1 The multi-population replicator dynamic Domain of analysis: finite games in normal form, G =(N, S, π), with mixed-strategy

More information

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden 1 Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning Jason R. Marden Abstract A learning rule is completely uncoupled if each player s behavior is conditioned only on his own realized

More information

Unmediated Communication in Games with Complete and Incomplete Information

Unmediated Communication in Games with Complete and Incomplete Information Unmediated Communication in Games with Complete and Incomplete Information Dino Gerardi Yale University First Version: September 2000 This Version: May 2002 Abstract In this paper we study the effects

More information

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny* Draft notes October 2011 http://home.uchicago.edu/~preny/papers/bigseqm.pdf Abstract:

More information

CPSC 320 Sample Solution, Reductions and Resident Matching: A Residentectomy

CPSC 320 Sample Solution, Reductions and Resident Matching: A Residentectomy CPSC 320 Sample Solution, Reductions and Resident Matching: A Residentectomy August 25, 2017 A group of residents each needs a residency in some hospital. A group of hospitals each need some number (one

More information

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games Joel Sobel April 4, 2016 Abstract This paper extends Milgrom and Robert s treatment of supermodular games in two ways. It points out that

More information

Solving Extensive Form Games

Solving Extensive Form Games Chapter 8 Solving Extensive Form Games 8.1 The Extensive Form of a Game The extensive form of a game contains the following information: (1) the set of players (2) the order of moves (that is, who moves

More information

Tjalling C. Koopmans Research Institute

Tjalling C. Koopmans Research Institute Tjalling C. Koopmans Research Institute Tjalling C. Koopmans Research Institute Utrecht School of Economics Utrecht University Janskerkhof 12 3512 BL Utrecht The Netherlands telephone +31 30 253 9800 fax

More information

CRITICAL TYPES. 1. Introduction

CRITICAL TYPES. 1. Introduction CRITICAL TYPES JEFFREY C. ELY AND MARCIN PESKI Abstract. Economic models employ assumptions about agents infinite hierarchies of belief. We might hope to achieve reasonable approximations by specifying

More information

Econ 618: Correlated Equilibrium

Econ 618: Correlated Equilibrium Econ 618: Correlated Equilibrium Sunanda Roy 1 Basic Concept of a Correlated Equilibrium MSNE assumes players use a random device privately and independently, that tells them which strategy to choose for

More information

C31: Game Theory, Lecture 1

C31: Game Theory, Lecture 1 C31: Game Theory, Lecture 1 V. Bhaskar University College London 5 October 2006 C31 Lecture 1: Games in strategic form & Pure strategy equilibrium Osborne: ch 2,3, 12.2, 12.3 A game is a situation where:

More information

Approval Voting: Three Examples

Approval Voting: Three Examples Approval Voting: Three Examples Francesco De Sinopoli, Bhaskar Dutta and Jean-François Laslier August, 2005 Abstract In this paper we discuss three examples of approval voting games. The first one illustrates

More information

Strategies under Strategic Uncertainty

Strategies under Strategic Uncertainty Discussion Paper No. 18-055 Strategies under Strategic Uncertainty Helene Mass Discussion Paper No. 18-055 Strategies under Strategic Uncertainty Helene Mass Download this ZEW Discussion Paper from our

More information

Epistemic Implementation and The Arbitrary-Belief Auction Jing Chen, Silvio Micali, and Rafael Pass

Epistemic Implementation and The Arbitrary-Belief Auction Jing Chen, Silvio Micali, and Rafael Pass Computer Science and Artificial Intelligence Laboratory Technical Report MIT-CSAIL-TR-2012-017 June 22, 2012 Epistemic Implementation and The Arbitrary-Belief Auction Jing Chen, Silvio Micali, and Rafael

More information

: Cryptography and Game Theory Ran Canetti and Alon Rosen. Lecture 8

: Cryptography and Game Theory Ran Canetti and Alon Rosen. Lecture 8 0368.4170: Cryptography and Game Theory Ran Canetti and Alon Rosen Lecture 8 December 9, 2009 Scribe: Naama Ben-Aroya Last Week 2 player zero-sum games (min-max) Mixed NE (existence, complexity) ɛ-ne Correlated

More information

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Spring 2013: 521 B Introduction game theoretic predictions are very sensitive to "information structure"

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

The Game of Normal Numbers

The Game of Normal Numbers The Game of Normal Numbers Ehud Lehrer September 4, 2003 Abstract We introduce a two-player game where at each period one player, say, Player 2, chooses a distribution and the other player, Player 1, a

More information

Selecting Cheap-Talk Equilibria

Selecting Cheap-Talk Equilibria Selecting Cheap-Talk Equilibria Ying Chen, Navin Kartik, and Joel Sobel September 30, 2007 Abstract There are typically multiple equilibrium outcomes in the Crawford-Sobel (CS) model of strategic information

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Winter 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the three areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory, and (III) psychology & economics). Be sure to indicate clearly

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo Game Theory Giorgio Fagiolo giorgio.fagiolo@univr.it https://mail.sssup.it/ fagiolo/welcome.html Academic Year 2005-2006 University of Verona Summary 1. Why Game Theory? 2. Cooperative vs. Noncooperative

More information

NASH IMPLEMENTING SOCIAL CHOICE RULES WITH RESTRICTED RANGES

NASH IMPLEMENTING SOCIAL CHOICE RULES WITH RESTRICTED RANGES NASH IMPLEMENTING SOCIAL CHOICE RULES WITH RESTRICTED RANGES by M.Remzi Sanver * 06.06.2004 ABSTRACT 1 We consider Nash implementation of social choice rules with restricted ranges and show that the appropriate

More information

Coordination without Common Knowledge

Coordination without Common Knowledge Stephen Morris and Hyun Song Shin Arizona State University March 006 Introduction Coordination games have multiple equilibria Relaxing common knowledge assumptions gives uniqueness { Carlsson and van Damme

More information

The Nash Bargaining Solution in Gen Title Cooperative Games. Citation Journal of Economic Theory, 145(6):

The Nash Bargaining Solution in Gen Title Cooperative Games. Citation Journal of Economic Theory, 145(6): The Nash Bargaining Solution in Gen Title Cooperative Games Author(s) OKADA, Akira Citation Journal of Economic Theory, 145(6): Issue 2010-11 Date Type Journal Article Text Version author URL http://hdl.handle.net/10086/22200

More information

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Lecture Notes on Bargaining Lecture Notes on Bargaining Levent Koçkesen 1 Axiomatic Bargaining and Nash Solution 1.1 Preliminaries The axiomatic theory of bargaining originated in a fundamental paper by Nash (1950, Econometrica).

More information

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France. Hölder Continuous Implementation. Oury Marion

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France. Hölder Continuous Implementation. Oury Marion Thema Working Paper n 2010-06 Université de Cergy Pontoise, France Hölder Continuous Implementation Oury Marion November, 2010 Hölder Continuous Implementation Marion Oury November 2010 Abstract Building

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment

The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment Umut Mert Dur North Carolina State University Thayer Morrill North Carolina State University May 2017 Abstract Top Trading Cycles

More information

Examples of frequentist probability include games of chance, sample surveys, and randomized experiments. We will focus on frequentist probability sinc

Examples of frequentist probability include games of chance, sample surveys, and randomized experiments. We will focus on frequentist probability sinc FPPA-Chapters 13,14 and parts of 16,17, and 18 STATISTICS 50 Richard A. Berk Spring, 1997 May 30, 1997 1 Thinking about Chance People talk about \chance" and \probability" all the time. There are many

More information

Notes on Coursera s Game Theory

Notes on Coursera s Game Theory Notes on Coursera s Game Theory Manoel Horta Ribeiro Week 01: Introduction and Overview Game theory is about self interested agents interacting within a specific set of rules. Self-Interested Agents have

More information

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים THE HEBREW UNIVERSITY OF JERUSALEM TOWARDS A CHARACTERIZATION OF RATIONAL EXPECTATIONS by ITAI ARIELI Discussion Paper # 475 February 2008 מרכז לחקר הרציונליות CENTER FOR THE

More information

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Nicolas Schutz Nicolas Schutz Game Theory 1 / 43 Introduction Why game theory? In the introductory lecture, we defined Industrial Organization as the economics

More information

Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize

Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize Dov Monderer and Moshe Tennenholtz Faculty of Industrial Engineering and Management Technion Israel Institute of Technology Haifa 32000,

More information