Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved."

Transcription

1 Topology Proceedings Web: Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & tatistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, UA IN: COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

2 TOPOLOGY PROCEEDING Volume 29, No.2, 2005 Pages QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE AND OF DITOPOLOGICAL TEXTURE PACE LAWRENCE M. BROWN Abstract. The author considers equivalence direlations and the corresponding quotients of textures, using the interior relation on the texture as a tool in this investigation. A close relationship with surjective difunctions is shown, and the notions of quotient ditopology and quotient difunction are defined and studied. Finally, the existence of a T 0 reflection on the category dfditop is established. 1. Introduction In this section we recall some basic notions regarding textures and ditopological texture spaces, which should make the article accessible to the casual reader. Full details, motivation and background material may be obtained from [2 9, 17]. Textures Let be a set. We work within a subset of the power set P() called a texturing. A texturing is a point-separating, complete, completely distributive lattice with respect to inclusion, which contains and, and for which arbitrary meets coincide with intersections, and finite joins with unions Mathematics ubject Classification. 54B15, 54B30, 03G10, 06D10. Key words and phrases. Texture, Locally supercompact space, Core space, C-space, Interior relation, Equivalence direlation, Quotient texture, Difunction, Canonical quotient difunction, Ditopology, Bicontinuity, Quotient ditopology, Quotient difunction, T 0 reflection. 337

3 338 L. M. BROWN If is a texturing of the pair (, ) is called a texture [2]. The internal definition of textural concepts are expressed using the p sets and q sets, namely, for s, the sets P s = {A s A}, Q s = {A s / A}. Examples 1.1. (1) The discrete texture (X, P(X)) on the set X. For x X, P x = {x}, Q x = X \ {x}. (2) The texture (L, L), where L=(0, 1] and L={(0, r] 0 r 1}. Here, for r L, P r = Q r = (0, r]. (3) The unit interval texture (I, I), I=[0, 1], I={[0, r) r I} {[0, r] r I}. Here, for r I, P r = [0, r] and Q r = [0, r). (4) The product texture ( T, T) of textures (, ) and (T, T). Here the product texturing T of T consists of arbitrary intersections of sets of the form (A T ) ( B), A and B T. For (s, t) T, P (s,t) = P s P t and Q (s,t) = (Q s T ) ( Q t ). For A, the set A = { {Aj j J} {A j j J}, A = } {A j j J}, called the core of A is also of importance, although in general it need not belong to. We note the following fundamental properties of p sets and q sets. These expose a form of duality which is useful in defining pairs of dual properties. Lemma 1.2. [6, Theorem 1.2] (1) s / A = A Q s = s / A for all s, A. (2) For A, A = {s A Q s }. (3) For A, A is the smallest element of containing A. (4) For A, B, if A B then there exists s with A Q s and P s B. (5) A = {Q s P s A} for all A. (6) A = {P s A Q s } for all A.

4 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 339 Ditopology: ince a texturing of need not be closed under set complementation we must forego the traditional relationship between open and closed sets. Hence we define a dichotomous topology, or ditopology for short, as a pair (τ, κ) of generally unrelated subsets τ, κ of satisfying, τ,, κ, G 1, G 2 τ = G 1 G 2 τ, G i τ, i I = i G i τ. K 1, K 2 κ = K 1 K 2 κ, K i κ, i I = K i κ. The elements of τ are called open and those of κ closed. We refer to τ as the topology and to κ as the cotopology of (τ, κ). Any bitopology (u, v) on X gives rise to the ditopology (u, v c ) on the discrete texture (X, P(X)), while τ = {[0, r) 0 r 1} {I}, κ = {[0, r] 0 r 1} { } is a natural ditopology on the unit interval texture (I, I). Textures and ditopological texture spaces were first conceived as a means of representing fuzzy sets and topologies in a point-based setting, and this aspect of the theory continues to be of interest [4 8]. However, much of the theory has been developed quite independently of this context, and has concentrated on developing concepts appropriate to a complement-free setting which enable the expression of powerful results in the context of often quite minimal structures. As a case in point the unit interval texture with its natural ditopology is seen to play a role analogous to that of the unit interval in classical topology, despite the fact that we work within a very small subset of P(I). These aspects of the theory are likely to find applications in the modelling of negation-free logics, and in the development of structures for computation. In this paper we give a systematic method of constructing and studying quotients of textures and of ditopological texture spaces by using the notion of direlation [6]. The reader may refer to [5] for some early ideas concerning subtextures and quotient textures. At the suggestion of the referee we characterize the basic notions relating to direlations and difunctions in terms of the interior relation, thereby making the interior relation available as a tool in this investigation. For terms from lattice theory not defined here the reader may consult [14], while we follow [1] for terms from category theory.

5 340 L. M. BROWN 2. Textures and the Interior Relation It is clear that if is a texturing of then c = {A c A } is a T 0 topology on, that is may be regarded as the set of closed sets of the T 0 topological space (, c ). Viewed in this light, textures are just the closed set version of the locally supercompact spaces, core spaces or C-spaces studied initially by Hoffmann [15], Erné [11], Erné and Wilke [13]; and later by Erné [12], Lawson [16], and others. ince, in general, the sets of c do not belong to the texture, this link with C-spaces has not been exploited in the literature on textures so far 1. The referee has pointed out, however, that the interior relation for the topology (, c ), used by the aforementioned authors to characterize and study the C-spaces, can be used to give an algebraic characterization of textural concepts and results that may be more economic than the internal expression using p-sets and q-sets, and which at the same time could make the work on ditopological texture spaces of more immediate interest to workers in the field of C-spaces. With this in mind, therefore, we devote this section to a sketch of the relation between the internal and algebraic characterizations of the principle concepts used in the study of textures, particularly those involved in the main part of this paper on quotients. We recall that for a topological space (X, T) the interior relation ω is defined by x ω y y ( {G T x G}) o. For the topology (, c ) of the texture (, ) we therefore have s ω t t ( {A c A, s / A}) o t ( \ {A s / A}) o t / {A s / A} P t Q s, which immediately shows the relevance of the relation ω to the study of textures. In particular we note that the idempotency, ω = ω 2, of ω in this case can be read off directly from Lemma 1.2 (1) and (4). We will refer to ω as the interior relation of (, ), and denote it by ω if necessary, to avoid confusion. 1 With the exception of a subsection in [9] relating simple textures with sober topologies

6 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 341 For a relation ϕ from X to Y, A X and B Y, we set Aϕ = {y Y a A, aϕy} and ϕb = {x X b B, xϕb} as usual, abbreviating {a}ϕ to a ϕ and ϕ{b} to ϕ b, respectively. As above we will often write s ϕ t in preference to (s, t) ϕ. We note that: Lemma 2.1. Let (, ) be a texture with interior relation ω. (1) A A c ω = A c. (2) For A, A Q s s ω s A s Aω 1 (3) For A we have A = ω A = Aω 1. (4) For s, P s ω 1 = sω 1 and Q s = (sω ) c. In the present paper membership of a given set in a given texture will generally be known, so Lemma 2.1 (3) will be particularly useful in establishing A B from Aω 1 Bω 1. Direlations: Direlations give a suitable notion of (binary) relation for textures. For example, along with the notion of dicover, they play an important role in defining uniformities on textures [17]. Let (, ), (T, T) be textures. Generally, T is too small to support a useful notion of relation from (, ) to (T, T). We consider instead P() T. We use P (s,t), Q (s,t) to denote the p sets and q sets for ( T, P() T), and likewise P (t,s), Q (t,s) those for P(T ). An element of P() T is related to T but not to. We add conditions relating it to in two different ways, producing dual concepts of relation and corelation [6]. r P() T is called a relation from (, ) to (T, T) if it satisfies R1 r Q (s,t), P s Q s = r Q (s,t).. R2 r Q (s,t) = s such that P s Q s and r Q (s,t). R P() T is called a corelation from (, ) to (T, T) if it satisfies CR1 P (s,t) R, P s Q s = P (s,t) R. CR2 P (s,t) R = s such that P s Q s and P (s,t) R. A pair (r, R) consisting of a relation r and corelation R is now called a direlation.

7 342 L. M. BROWN Where necessary we will refer to an arbitrary relation between the base sets as a point relation to avoid possible confusion with the relations and corelations in the above sense. Example 2.2. For any texture (, ) the identity direlation (i, I) on (, ) is given by i = {P (s,s) s } and I = {Q (s,s) s }. Direlations are ordered by (r 1, R 1 ) (r 2, R 2 ) r 1 r 2 and R 2 R 1, and the direlation (r, R) on (, ) is called reflexive if (i, I) (r, R). Now we characterize direlations in terms of the interior relations ω, ω T of (, ), (T, T), respectively. First we note the following: Lemma 2.3. Let ϕ be a point relation from to T. (1) ϕ P() T ϕ c = ϕ c ω T. (2) If ϕ P() T then ϕ Q (s,t) s ϕω 1 T t. (3) If ϕ P() T then ϕ = ϕω 1 T. Proof. (1) Left to the interested reader. (2) If ϕ Q (s,t) then by Lemma 1.2 (4) applied to the texture ( T, P() T) we have t T with ϕ Q (s,t ) and P (s,t ) Q (s,t). By Lemma 1.2 (6) we have s ϕ t, while on the other hand P t Q t, so t ω 1 T t. Hence s ϕω 1 T t. The converse is straightforward, and we omit the details. (3) Immediate from (2) and Lemma 1.2 (2). If ϕ P() T then by (3), ϕωt 1 determines ϕ as the smallest set in the texture containing it, that is as its closure in the corresponding topology. ee the comments following Lemma 2.1. Proposition 2.4. Let r, R be point relations from to T. (1) r is a relation from (, ) to (T, T) if and only if R a : r c = r c ω T and R b : rω 1 T = ω 1 rω 1 T. (2) R is a corelation from (, ) to (T, T) if and only if CR a : R c = R c ω T and CR b : R c = ω R c.

8 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 343 Proof. (1) R a is just Lemma 2.3 (1). On the other hand it is easy to verify that r satisfies R1 if and only if ω 1 rω 1 T rωt 1, and that it satisfies R2 if and only if rωt 1 ω 1 rω 1 T. (2) Left to the interested reader. We note in passing that the identity direlation (i, I ) on (, ) is characterized by i ω 1 = ω 1 and I = ω c, as the reader may easily verify. Inverse of direlations: The inverse of (r, R) from (, ) to (T, T) is the direlation (r, R) = (R, r ) from (T, T) to (, ) given by r = {Q (t,s) r Q (s,t) }, R = {P (t,s) P (s,t) R}. The direlation (r, R) on (, ) is called symmetric if (r, R) = (r, R). Proposition 2.5. Let (r, R) be a direlation from (, ) to (T, T). Then (r, R) = (R, r ) : (T, T) (, ) is characterized by: (1) (R )ω 1 = (Rc ) 1, and (2) r = (ω T r 1 ) c. Proof. (1) In view of CR b it will be sufficient to prove (R )ω 1 = (ω R c ) 1. If t (R )ω 1 s then R Q (t,s) by Lemma 2.3 (2), so we have s with P (t,s ) Q (t,s) and P (s,t) R. This gives s ω s, s R c t, so s ω R c t and we have shown (2.1) (R )ω 1 (ω T R c ) 1. Conversely, if t(ω R c ) 1 s then s(ω R c )t and so for some s we have s ω s and s R c t. This gives P (s,t) R, whence P (t,s ) R and so t R s, while s ω 1 s and so t (R )ω 1 s. Thus (2.2) (ω R c ) (R )ω 1. The result now follows from (2.1) and (2.2). (2) Left to the interested reader.

9 344 L. M. BROWN Composition of direlations: If (r 1, R 1 ) : ( 1, 1 ) ( 2, 2 ) and (r 2, R 2 ) : ( 2, 2 ) ( 3, 3 ) are direlations, their composition (r 2, R 2 ) (r 1, R 1 ) = (r 2 r 1, R 2 R 1 ) from ( 1, 1 ) to ( 3, 3 ) is given by r 2 r 1 = {P (s,u) t 2 with r 1 Q (s,t) and r 2 Q (t,u) }, R 2 R 1 = {Q (s,u) t 2 with P (s,t) R 1 and P (t,u) R 2 }. It is known [6] that composition is associative and that (i, I) is the identity under composition. The direlation (r, R) on (, ) is transitive if (r, R) (r, R) (r, R). Proposition 2.6. With the notation above, and denoting by ω k the interior point relation for ( k, k ), 1 k 3, we have (1) (r 2 r 1 )ω3 1 = r 1 r 2 ω3 1, (2) R 2 R 1 = (R c 1 Rc 2 )c. Proof. traightforward. ections: Let (r, R) : (, ) (T, T) be a direlation, A. The A-sections of r, R are given by respectively. r A = {Q t s, r Q (s,t) = A Q s } T, R A = {P t s, P (s,t) R = P s A} T, Proposition 2.7. With the notation above: (1) (r A)ω 1 T = Arω 1 T, (2) (R A) = (A c R c ) c. Proof. (1) t (r A)ω 1 T gives r A Q t by Lemma 2.1 (2), so we have s with r Q (s,t) and A Q s. Now s (rω 1 ) t by Lemma 2.3 (2), and s Aω 1 by Lemma 2.1 (2), so t Aω 1 rω 1 T. Hence (2.3) (r A)ω 1 T Aω 1 rω 1 T. Conversely take t Aω 1 rω 1 T = Aω 1 rω 1 T ω 1 T since ω T is idempotent. Now we have s A with s (Aω 1 rω 1 T ω 1 T ) t, and hence there exist s, t T with s ω 1 s, s (rωt 1 ) t and t ωt 1 t. From Lemma 2.3 (2) we have r Q (s,t ). We claim that P t r A.

10 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 345 To see this assume the contrary. Then there exists t T with P t Q t for which (2.4) r Q (z,t ) = A Q z for all z. However we easily deduce r Q (s,t ), so implication (2.4) with z = s gives A Q s, which contradicts s ω 1 s since s A. This establishes P t r A, and P t Q t so r A Q (s,t) which gives t (r A)ω 1 T by Lemma 2.3 (2). Thus, (2.5) Aω 1 rω 1 T (r A)ωT 1. From (2.3), (2.5) and R b we have (r A)ω 1 T as required. = Aω 1 rω 1 T = Arω 1 T, (2) Essentially dual to (1), and is omitted. Presections: For B T, the B-presections of r, R, are the B- sections (r ) B, (R ) B of the inverses r, R, respectively. Normally these are written as r B, R B, respectively. Proposition 2.8. With the notation as above we have: (1) r B = (rω T B c ) c, (2) (R B)ω 1 = Rc B. Proof. (1) Noting that r is a corelation from (T, T) to (, ), we have r B = (r ) B = (B c (r ) c ) c by Proposition 2.7 (2). Now using Proposition 2.5 (2), r B = (B c ω T r 1 ) c = (B c (rω 1 T ) 1 ) c = (rω T B c ) c, as required. (2) In a similar way, using Propositions 2.7 (1) and 2.5 (1), (R B)ω 1 as required. = ((R ) B)ω 1 = B(R )ω 1 = B(Rc ) 1 = R c B, Difunctions: A difunction from (, ) to (T, T) is a direlation (f, F ) from (, ) to (T, T) satisfying the conditions DF1 For s, s, P s Q s = t T with f Q (s,t) and P (s,t) F. DF2 For t, t T and s, f Q (s,t) and P (s,t ) F = P t Q t.

11 346 L. M. BROWN A difunction (f, F ) is surjective if the inverse direlation (f, F ) satisfies DF1, and injective if (f, F ) satisfies DF2. A characteristic property of a difunction (f, F ) is that f B = F B for all B T [6]. Proposition 2.9. Given textures (, ), (T, T): (1) Let (r, R) : (, ) (T, T) be a direlation. (a) (r, R) satisfies DF1 if and only if ω R c ω T r 1. (b) (r, R) satisfies DF2 if and only if ω T r 1 R c ω T (2) Let (f, F ) : (, ) (T, T) be a difunction. (a) (f, F ) is surjective if and only if ω T ω T f 1 F c. (b) (f, F ) is injective if and only if F c ω T r 1 ω. Proof. (1) According to [6, Lemma 2.23 (1 ii)], (r, R) satisfies DF1 if and only if r R I. Now using Propositions 2.6 (2), 2.5 (2) and I = ω c gives r R I (R c (r ) c ) c ω c (R c ω T r 1 ) c ω c, which is equivalent to ω R c ω T r 1 on negating each side. This gives (a), and (b) follows similarly using [6, Lemma 2.23 (2 ii)]. (2) (f, F ) is surjective if and only if (F, f ) : (T, T) (, ) satisfies DF1, so using (1 i) we obtain ω T (r ) c ω (R ) 1, which by Proposition 2.5 (2) is equivalent to ω T ω T r 1 ω (R ) 1 = ω T r 1 ((R )ω 1 ) 1. Applying Proposition 2.5 (1) now gives (a), and the proof of (b) is similar and is omitted. In case (f, F ) : ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ) is a difunction we make the following definitions: Also: (1) (f, F ) is continuous if G τ 2 = F G τ 1. (2) (f, F ) is cocontinuous if K κ 2 = f K κ 1. (3) (f, F ) is bicontinuous if it is continuous and cocontinuous. (1) (f, F ) is open (co-open) if G τ 1 = f G τ 2 ( F G τ 2 ). (2) (f, F ) is closed (coclosed) if K κ 1 = f K κ 2 (F K κ 2 ).

12 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 347 It is shown in [7] that the category dfditop of ditopological texture spaces and bicontinuous difunctions is topological over the category dftex of textures and difunctions, thereby justifying our use of the term topology in naming the pair (τ, κ). Difunctions and Point Functions: Only in certain special cases do difunctions correspond to point functions between the base sets. We recall in particular [6, Lemma 3.4] that if (, ), (T, T) are textures and the point function ϕ : T satisfies (a) s, s, P s Q s = P ϕ(s) Q ϕ(s ), then the equalities f = f ϕ = {P (s,t) v with P s Q v and P ϕ(v) Q t }, F = F ϕ = {Q (s,t) v with P v Q s and P t Q ϕ(v) }, define a point function (f, F ) : (, ) (T, T). Moreover [6, Lemma 3.9], if ϕ also satisfies (b) s, P ϕ(s) B, B T = s with P ϕ(s ) B, then f B = ϕ 1 [B] = F B for all B T. Proposition With the notation as above: (1) ϕ satisfies (a) if and only if ω 1 ϕ ϕω 1 (2) (f, F ) = (f ϕ, F ϕ ) is characterized by fω 1 T T. = ω 1 ϕω 1 T and F = (ω ϕω T ) c. (3) ϕ satisfies (b) if and only if ω T ϕ 1 ω T ϕ 1 ω. Proof. (1) uppose (a) holds. Then if s ω 1 ϕ t then we have s with s ω 1 s and s ϕ t, that is t = ϕ(s ). Now P s Q s so P ϕ(s) Q t by (a). This gives s ϕωt 1 t, whence ω 1 ϕωt 1. The proof of the converse is similar, and is omitted. (2) s fω 1 T t f Q (s,t) t T, v with P (s,t ) Q (s,t), P s Q v and P ϕ(v) Q t s ω 1 ϕω 1 T ω 1 T t. Hence fωt 1 = ω 1 ϕω 1 T since ω T is idempotent. The proof of the formula for F is left to the reader. (3) traightforward on noting that in the definition of (b) it is sufficient to take B to be a q-set.

13 348 L. M. BROWN Finally we present a result which will be needed in the next section. Proposition Let ϕ be onto and satisfy (a) and (b). Then (f ϕ, F ϕ ) is surjective. Proof. For (f, F ) = (f ϕ, F ϕ ) we have ω T f 1 F c = (fω 1 T ) 1 F c = (ω 1 ϕ 1 ωt 1 ) 1 ω ϕω T = ω T ϕ 1 ω ϕω T by Proposition 2.10 (2). On the other hand, since ϕ is onto we have T ϕ 1 ϕ, where T is the diagonal of T, so using the above characterization of (b), ω T = ω T T ω T ω T ϕ 1 ϕω T ω T ϕ 1 ω ϕω T. This shows that ω T ω T f 1 F c, whence (f, F ) is surjective by Proposition 2.9 (2 a). The converse of this result is false, even if (f, F ) is bijective [7, Example 2.14]. 3. Equivalence Direlations and the Quotient Texture Definition 3.1. Let (, ) be a texture. A direlation (r, R) on (, ) is called an equivalence direlation if it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. We have at once: Lemma 3.2. (r, R) is an equivalence direlation if and only if ω 1 rω 1, (rω 1 ) 2 rω 1 and R = r = (ωr 1 ) c. Corollary 3.3. Let (r, R) is a equivalence direlation. Then rω 1 is idempotent. We also note the following: Lemma 3.4. Let (r, R) be an equivalence direlation on (, ). Then for s, t the following are equivalent. (i) v, P s Q v = r Q (t,v). (ii) s ω 1 t rω 1. (iii) v, P s Q v = P (v,t) R. (iv) P s r P t.

14 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 349 Proof. (1) (2) Immediate from Lemma 2.3 (2). (3) (2) Clearly (3) is equivalent to s ω 1 t (R c ) 1, while (R c ) 1 = (R )ω 1 = rω 1 by Proposition 2.5 (1) and the fact that (r, R) is symmetric. (4) (2) P s r P t is equivalent to P s ω 1 (r P t )ω 1, and by Proposition 2.7 (1) and R b we have (r P t )ω 1 = P t rω 1 = P t ω 1 rω 1. The proof is now completed by applying Lemma 2.1 (4), and using R b again. The sense in which an equivalence direlation gives rise to a quotient texture is described in the following theorem. Theorem 3.5. Let (r, R) be an equivalence direlation on (, ). Then there exists a point equivalence relation ρ on, a texturing U of the quotient set U = /ρ and a surjective difunction (f, F ) on (, ) to (U, U) satisfying r = F f and R = f F. Proof. We will present the proof as a series of lemmas. Let us begin by associating an equivalence point relation ρ with (r, R). Lemma 3.6. If (r, R) is an equivalence direlation on (, ) then the point relation ρ defined by s ρ t s ω 1 t rω 1 and t ω 1 s rω 1 is an equivalence point relation on. Proof. By Lemma 3.2 we have ω 1 rω 1, whence s ω 1 s rω 1, which gives s ρ s for all s. It is immediate that ρ is symmetric, so it remains to show transitivity. For s, t, v let s ρ t and t ρ v. Then s ω 1 t rω 1 = t ω 1 rω 1 v rω 1 rω 1 v rω 1 by R b and Lemma 3.2. Likewise, v ω 1 s rω 1, so s ρ v as required. Lemma 3.7. Let (r, R) be an equivalence direlation on (, ) and ρ the equivalence point relation defined above. Then (1) For all s, t, s ρ t P s r P t and P t r P s. (2) For A, r A = A R A = A r A = R A. We denote by R the family of all A satisfying these equivalent conditions. (3) A R Arω 1 = Aω 1. In particular the elements of R are saturated with respect to ρ.

15 350 L. M. BROWN (4) r A R and R A R for all A. (5) R is closed under arbitrary joins and intersections. (6) For A, r A = {B R A B} and R A = {B R B A}. Proof. (1) This is just the equivalence of (ii) and (iv) in Lemma 3.4. (2) If r A = A then A r (r A) = r (A) = R A by [6, Proposition 2.10 (2)] and the fact that (r, R) is symmetric. On the other hand R A A since R is reflexive, so R A = A. The converse is proved likewise, so r A = A R A = A. The second equivalence is clear since R A A r A for all A by reflexivity. (3) A R f A = A (f A)ω 1 = Aω 1 Arω 1 = Aω 1 by Proposition 2.7 (1). For s A R, s ρ t, we have tω 1 srω 1 Arω 1 = Aω 1, whence t A and so A is saturated. (4) For A let B = r A. Then Brω 1 = (r A)ω 1 rω 1 = Arω 1 rω 1 = Arω 1 = Bω 1 by R b, Proposition 2.7 (1) and Corollary 3.3, so B R by (3). The proof of R A R is left to the interested reader. (5) Take A i R, i I. For B = i I A i, r B = r ( i I A i) = i I r A i = i I A i = B by [6, Corollary 2.12 (2)] and (2), so again by (2), i I A i R. In the same way B = i I A i satisfies R B = B, so we also have i I A i R. (6) Take A. If A B for B R then r A r B = B, so r A {B R A B}. The reverse inclusion is clear on noting that B = r A satisfies B R and A B. The dual proof of the second equality is omitted. We will denote by U the quotient set /ρ and by ϕ the canonical quotient mapping ϕ : U, ϕ : s s, where s denotes the equivalence class of s. Let us define U = {A U ϕ 1 [A] R}. Note that, since the sets in R are saturated with respect to ρ, we also have U = {ϕ[a] A R}. Now let us verify that U is a texturing of U, and identify the p-sets and q-sets in (U, U).

16 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 351 Lemma 3.8. With the notation above U = {A ϕ 1 [A] R} is a texturing of U. Moreover, for all s, (i) P s = ϕ[r P s ], and (ii) Q s = {ϕ[r Q s ] P s Q s } ϕ[r Q s ]. Proof. Note first that = r R implies U = ϕ[] U. Likewise, = R R gives = ϕ[ ] U. Now let us take A j U, j J, and put A = j J A j. Then ϕ 1 [A] = j J ϕ 1 [A j ] R by Lemma 3.7 (5), so j J A j U. Thus, U is a complete lattice of subsets of U. Now let A = j J A j. We will verify that ϕ 1 [A] = j J ϕ 1 [A j ]. It is clear that j J ϕ 1 [A j ] ϕ 1 [A]. On the other hand by Lemma 3.7 (5) we have j J ϕ 1 [A j ] R, so [ ] A j ϕ ϕ 1 [A j ] j J i I [ ϕ j J ] ϕ 1 [A j ] U. Thus A ϕ[ j J ϕ 1 [A j ]] U, which gives [ ] ϕ 1 [A] ϕ 1 [ϕ ϕ 1 [A i ] ] = ϕ 1 [A j ] j J j J since the sets of R are saturated. Thus ϕ 1 [A] = j J ϕ 1 [A j ]. We see from the above that both joins and intersections are preserved under the mapping ϕ 1 : U. Moreover, this mapping is 1-1 since ϕ is onto. Hence, since is completely distributive, U is completely distributive too. We have already seen that meet in U coincides with intersection, but we need to verify that finite joins coincide with unions. Let I be finite. Then ϕ 1 [ i I A i] = i I ϕ 1 [A i ] = i I ϕ 1 [A i ] = ϕ 1[ i I A i] since I is finite, whence i I A i = i I A i for A i U, i I and I finite, as required. In order to show U is a texturing it remains to show that it separates the points of U. Take s, t with ϕ(s) ϕ(t). Then s ρ c t, so by Lemma 3.7 (1) we have P s r P t or P t r P s. In the first case we have t ϕ[r P t ] U since t P t r P t and s / ϕ[r P t ] since r P t R is saturated. Likewise, the second case gives s ϕ[r P s ] and t / ϕ[r P s ], which completes the proof that (U, U) is a texture.

17 352 L. M. BROWN Finally, let us verify (i) and (ii). For (i), first note that s ϕ[r P s ] U, so P s ϕ[r P s ]. On the other hand, every element of U has the form ϕ[a] for A R and, since the elements of R are saturated, s ϕ[a] = P s A = r P s r A = A = ϕ[r P s ] ϕ[a], whence P s = ϕ[r P s ]. For (ii), first note that Q s = {ϕ[a] A R, P s ϕ[a]} and that P s ϕ[a] is equivalent to P s A since A R is saturated. Hence, for P s Q s we have ϕ 1 (Q s ) = ϕ 1 ( {ϕ[a] A R, P s A}) = {ϕ 1 [ϕ[a]] A R, P s A} = {A R P s A} since A R is saturated {A R A Q s } = R Q s = ϕ 1 [ϕ[r Q s ]], where we have used Lemma 3.7 (6). Hence ϕ[r Q s ] Q s, so {ϕ[r Q s ] P s Q s } Q s. For the reverse inclusion take t with P s P t, whence P s r P t. By the equivalence of (iii) and (iv) in Lemma 3.4 we have s with P s Q s and P (s,t) R. Now P t R Q s by [6, Lemma 2.6 (2)], whence r P t R Q s since R Q s R, and we deduce P t = ϕ[r P t ] ϕ[r Q s ]. Hence we have shown P s P t = P t ϕ[r Q s ] for some P s Q s, which gives us Q s {ϕ[r Q s ] P s Q s }, as required. To complete the proof of (ii) we need only note that if P s Q s then Q s Q s and so ϕ[r Q s ] ϕ[r Q s ], from which the required inclusion is clear. Corollary 3.9. (1) For (U, U) the interior point relation ω U is given by ϕ(s) ωu 1 ϕ(t) s ( rω 1 {rω 1 t t ω 1 t } ). (2) For s, t, r Q (s,t) = P ϕ(s) Q ϕ(t). (3) ϕ satisfies the conditions (a) and (b) mentioned earlier. Proof. (1) Using the facts proved above we have: P ϕ(s) Q ϕ(t) ϕ 1 [P ϕ(s) ] ϕ 1 [Q ϕ(t) ] r P s {R Q t P t Q t } u (r P s )ω 1 with u / R Q t t ω 1 t.

18 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 353 By Proposition 2.7 (1), u (r P s )ω 1 is equivalent to u srω 1, while for t ω 1 t we have u (R Q t ) c = (r Q t ) c = rω 1 Qc t by Proposition 2.8 (1). By Lemma 2.1 (4) we deduce that u rω 1 t, whence u {rω 1 t t ω 1 t }, as required. (2) uppose r Q (s,t). Then s rω 1 have t rω 1 t for all t ω 1 P ϕ(s) Q ϕ(t). t, and since ω 1 rω 1 we ϕ(t) by (1), that is t. Hence ϕ(s) ω 1 U (3) (a) If s ω 1 ϕ u then we have s ω 1 s and u = ϕ(s ). Now s rω 1 s and by (2) we deduce s ϕω 1 U u. Hence ω 1 ϕ ϕω 1 U, so ϕ satisfies (a) by Proposition 2.10 (1). (b) If we take s ϕωu 1 ϕ(t) then ϕ(s) ω 1 T ϕ(t), so by (1) s rω 1 u with u rω 1 u t ω 1 u. But by R b we have s ω 1 rω 1 u, whence s ω 1 ϕω 1 U ϕ(t). Thus ϕω 1 U ω 1 ϕω 1 U and (b) is satisfied by Proposition 2.10 (3). It follows from Corollary 3.9 (3) that ϕ gives rise to a difunction (f, F ) = (f ϕ, F ϕ ) : (, ) (U, U), which we will call the canonical quotient difunction. Moreover f B = ϕ 1 [B] = F B for all B U, while from Proposition 2.11 we see that the canonical quotient difunction (f, F ) is surjective since ϕ is onto. Moreover: Lemma f A = ϕ[a] = F A for all A R. Proof. Take A R. ince (f, F ) is surjective we have F A f A by [6, Corollary 2.33 (1 i)], so it will be sufficient to prove f A ϕ[a] F A. ince ϕ[a] U, the first inclusion will follow from (f A)ωU 1 AϕωU 1, which by Proposition 2.7 (1) is equivalent to Aω 1 ϕω 1 U Aϕω 1. By Proposition 2.10 (1) this follows from (a). U By Propositions 2.7 (2) and 2.10 (2) we have F A=(A c ω ϕω U ) c, so ϕ[a] F A gives the existence of u Aϕω 1 U Ac ω ϕω U. Hence we have a A, b / A with a ϕω 1 U ϕ 1 ω 1 b since ω U is idempotent. Now for some b with b ω 1 b we have ϕ(a) ω 1 U ϕ(b ), so by Corollary 3.9 (1) a rω 1 rω 1 b, that is a rω 1 b. Thus b A by Lemma 3.7 (3), which is a contradiction. Arω 1

19 354 L. M. BROWN Finally, we must show that r = F f, R = f F following by taking the inverse of both sides. Further, since r, F f P(), it will be sufficient to show rω 1 = (F f)ω 1. Now by Proposition 2.6 (1) and R b for F we have (F f)ω 1 = f(f )ω 1 = fωu 1 (F )ω 1, whence using Propositions 2.5 (1), 2.10 (2) and the idempotency of ωu 1 we obtain (F f)ω 1 ϕω 1ϕ 1 ω 1 = ω 1 If s ω 1 ϕω 1 U ϕ 1 ω 1 t we have s, t satisfying s ω 1 s, t ω 1 t and ϕ(s ) ω 1 U ϕ(t ). We deduce s rω 1 rω 1 t from Corollary 3.9 (1), whence s rω 1 t. Conversely let s rω 1 t. Then s ω 1 rω 1 ω 1 t, so we have s, t with s ω 1 s, s rω 1 t and t ω 1 t. By Corollary 3.9 (2) we have ϕ(s ) ωu 1 ϕ(t ), so s ω 1 ϕω 1 U ϕ 1 ω 1 t. This shows r = F f, and the proof is complete. U. Example For a discrete texture (X, P(X)) the interior relation is just the identity relation on X, so (r, R) is an equivalence direlation if and only if the point relation r is reflexive and transitive, and R = r = (r c ) 1. Clearly ρ = r r 1 and (f, F ) = (ϕ, ϕ c ). Finally ϕ(x) ωu 1 ϕ(y) x r y, so (U, U) will be a discrete texture if and only if r = ρ, that is if and only if r is also symmetric as a point relation. In the reverse direction we have: Theorem Let (, ), (T, T) be textures and (g, G) a difunction on (, ) to (T, T). Then (r, R) defined by r = G g and R = g G is an equivalence direlation on (, ). Moreover, if (U, U) is the quotient texture associated with (r, R) as in Theorem 3.5, and (f, F ) the canonical quotient difunction from (, ) to (U, U), then (h, H) = (g, G) (f, F ) is an injective difunction on (U, U) to (T, T) satisfying (h, H) (f, F ) = (g, G). Finally, if (g, G) is surjective then (h, H) is bijective. (, ) (g,g) (T, T) (f,f ) (h,h) (U, U)

20 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 355 Proof. ince r = (G g) = g (G ) = g G = R by [6, Proposition 2.17 (2) and Lemma 2.4 (2)], we see (r, R) is symmetric. ince (g, G) is a difunction we have R = g G I by [6, Lemma 2.23 (1 ii)], whence i = I R = r and the direlation (r, R), is reflexive. To show that (r, R) is transitive note first that r r = (G g) (G g) = G [(g G ) g] by [6, Proposition 2.17 (3)]. ince (g, G) is a difunction, g G i T by [6, Lemma 2.23 (2 ii)]. Hence by [6, Proposition 2.17 (4)] we have G [(g G ) g] G (i T g), and i T g = g by [6, Proposition 2.17 (1)], so r r G g = r. R R R follows by symmetry, whence (r, R) is transitive and hence an equivalence direlation. Let us now show that (g, G) (f, F ) = (g F, G f ) is a difunction. For B T we have g B = G B R by [6, Theorem 2.24] and the fact that r (g B) = (G g) (g B) = G (g (g B)) G B = g B by [6, Lemma 2.9 (1), Lemma 2.7], which proves r (g B) = g B since r is reflexive. Now, using Lemma 2.8 (2) we have (g F ) B = F (g B) = f (g B) = f (G B) = (G f ) B which gives the required result by [6, Theorem 2.24]. To show (g, G) (f, F ) is injective we must show that ((g, G) (f, F ) ) = (f G, F g ) satisfies DF2. Note that for B T we have (f G ) ((F g ) B) = f (G g) (F B)) = f (r (F B)). ince F B = ϕ 1 [B] R we have r (F B) = F B, while f (F B) B by [6, Theorem 2.24 (2 b)]. Hence (f G ) ((F g ) B) B and so (f G, F g ) satisfies DF2 by [6, Lemma 2.23 (2)]. It remains to show that if (g, G) is surjective, then so is (g, G) (f, F ). But in this case the direlation (g, G) satisfies DF1 by [6, Theorem 2.31 (1)], whence [(g, G) (f, F ) ] = (f, F ) (g, G) also satisfies DF1 since (f, F ) does. But now (g, G) (f, F ) is surjective, again by [6, Theorem 2.31 (1)], and the proof of the theorem is complete.

21 356 L. M. BROWN Example If (g, G) : (X, P(X)) (Y, P(Y )) is a difunction then g : X Y is a point function, r = gg 1 is symmetric as a point relation, and x ρ x g(x) = g(x ). Hence in this case Theorem 3.12 gives the discrete texturing on the usual quotient associated with g. Naturally, difunctions (g, G) from (X, P(X)) to non-discrete textures will generally produce quotients of (X, P(X)) which are not discrete. The following result will also prove useful: Theorem For k = 1, 2 let ( k, k ) be a texture, (r k, R k ) an equivalence direlation on ( k, k ), (U k, U k ) the corresponding quotient texture and (g, G) : ( 1, 1 ) ( 2, 2 ) a difunction which is compatible in the sense that A R 2 = g A R 1. Then there exists a difunction (ḡ, Ḡ) : (U 1, U 1 ) (U 2, U 2 ) making the following diagram commutative. ( 1, 1 ) (g,g) ( 2, 2 ) (f 1,F 1 ) (f 2,F 2 ) (U 1, U 1 ) (ḡ,ḡ) (U 2, U 2 ) Proof. Consider the mapping θ : U 2 U 1 defined by θ(a) = ϕ 1 [g ϕ 1 2 [A]] for all A U 2. We have noted above that the mapping A ϕ 1 2 [A] from U 2 to R 2, being an isomorphism, preserves arbitrary intersections and joins. By hypothesis, for B R 2 we have g B R 1, so B g B is a mapping from R 2 to R 1, and this too preserves arbitrary intersections and joins by [6, Corollary 2.26]. Finally the mapping C ϕ 1 [C] from R 1 to U 1 is an isomorphism and therefore preserves arbitrary intersections and joins. Thus, the same is true of the mapping θ, and by [7, Proposition 4.1] we deduce the existence of a difunction (ḡ, Ḡ) : (U 1, U 1 ) (U 2, U 2 ) satisfying ḡ A = Ḡ A = θ(a) for all A U 2. It remains to show the commutativity of the above diagram. We will establish ḡ f 1 = f 2 g, leaving the dual proof of Ḡ F 1 = F 2 G to the interested reader. It will be sufficient to show that (ḡ f 1 ) = (f 2 g), whence by [6, Lemma 2.7] we need only show

22 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 357 that (ḡ f 1 ) A = (f 2 g) A for all A U 2. However (ḡ f 1 ) A = f 1 (ḡ A) = ϕ 1 1 [θ(a)] which gives the required result. = ϕ 1 1 [ϕ 1[g ϕ 1 2 [A]] = g ϕ 1 2 [A] = g (f 2 A) = (f 2 g) A, We end this section by presenting a method for generating equivalence direlations. Proposition Let (, ) be a texture, B and define the direlation (r, R) on (, ) by r = {P (s,t) u with P s Q u and P t B or B Q u B B}, R = {Q (s,t) v with P v Q s and P v B or B Q t B B}. Then: (1) (a) s rω 1 t u sω 1, v ω 1 t satisfying u Bω 1 = v Bω 1 B B, (b) (s, t) R c v ω 1 s, u tω 1 satisfying u Bω 1 = v Bω 1. (2) (r, R) is an equivalence direlation on (, ). (3) B generates the set R associated with (r, R) in the sense that B R and every element of R can be written as an intersection of joins of elements of B. Proof. (1) If s rω 1 t then r Q (s,t), which gives P t Q t, P s Q u satisfying B Q u = P t B. Taking P t Q v, P v Q t now gives u sω 1, v ω 1 with u Bω 1 = v Bω 1, and the converse is easily established. This shows (a), and the proof of (b) is similar and is left to the reader. (2) If s ω 1 t then s ω 1 ω 1 t so we have u with s ω 1 u, u ω 1 t, and taking v = u in (1 a) gives s rω 1 t. Hence ω 1 rω 1. uppose s rω 1 rω 1 t and take w with s rω 1 w, w rω 1 t. Now by (1 a) we have u sω 1, v ω 1 w and u wω 1, v ω 1 t satisfying the appropriate implications. Hence u Bω 1 = v Bω 1 = v Bω 1, which shows that s rω 1 = u Bω 1 t by (1 a), and so rω 1 ω 1 ω 1 = Bω 1 rω 1 rω 1.

23 358 L. M. BROWN Finally from (1) we note that s rω 1 t t Rc s so rω 1 = (R c ) 1 = (R )ω 1 by Proposition 2.5 (1), whence r = R and so R = r. By Corollary 3.2 this completes the proof that (r, R) is an equivalence direlation. (3) Take B 0 B. By Lemma 3.7 (3), B 0 R if and only if B 0 rω 1 = B 0 ω 1, and since ω 1 rω 1 it will clearly suffice to show B 0 rω 1 B 0 ω 1. Take t B 0rω 1. Then for some b B we have b rω 1 t, so there exists u bω 1, v ω 1 t with u Bω 1 = v Bω 1 for all B B by (1 a). But u B 0 ω 1 so v B 0 ω 1, whence t B 0ω 1 ω 1 = B 0 ω 1, as required. This establishes B R. Finally, we take A R. uppose that P t A. Then P t r A since r A = A for A R, so we have t with P t Q t satisfying r Q (s,t ) = A Q s. Take any s with A Q s and take s with A Q s, P s Q s. By the above implication r Q (s,t ), whence P (s,t) r and we may choose Bs t B satisfying P t Bs t Q s. Let B t = {Bs t A Q s }. Then A B t. Indeed, if not we shall have s satisfying A Q s, P s B t and so the contradiction P s Bs t Bs. t Hence A {B t P t A}. If we do not have equality we may take w satisfying {B t P t A} Q w, P w A. In particular this gives B w Q w, so there exists s satisfying Bs w Q w, which contradicts P w Bs w. This shows that A = {B t P t A}, so A has the required representation. Corollary If (r, R) is the equivalence direlation generated by B as in Proposition 3.15, the elements of B are saturated for (r, R). Proof. Immediate from Lemma 3.7 (3). Example Consider the texture (L, L) of Examples 1.1 (2), and set B = {(0, 1 2 ]}. Then the corresponding equivalence direlation is easily seen to be: r = {(s, t) 0 < t 1 2 or 1 2 < s 1}, and R = {(s, t) 0 < t 1 2 or 1 2 s 1}.

24 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 359 r R Clearly, R = {, (0, 1 2 ], L}, while sρt 0 < s 1 2, 0 < t 1 2 or 1 2 < s 1, 1 2 < t 1. Hence there are two equivalence { classes which we denote by 1 2 and 12 0 < s 1 1. This gives us ϕ(s) = < s 1, U = { 2 1, 1} and U = {, { 1 2 }, U}. The following result will be useful when applying Theorem 3.14 to equivalence direlations obtained as in Proposition Lemma Let (r k, R k ) be equivalence direlations on ( k, k ) generated by B k k, k = 1, 2 as in Proposition Then if the difunction (g, G) : ( 1, 1 ) ( 2, 2 ) satisfies B B 2 = g B R 1 it satisfies A R 2 = g A R 1. Proof. By Proposition 3.15, A R 2 may be written as an intersection of joins of sets of B 2. On the other hand the mapping (g ) preserves arbitrary intersections and joins, so by hypothesis g A = (g ) A can be written as an intersection of joins of elements of R 1. However, R 1 is closed under arbitrary intersections and joins by Lemma 3.7 (5), whence g A R Quotient Ditopologies and Quotient Difunctions Now let (τ, κ) be a ditopology on (, ). If, as above, (r, R) is an equivalence direlation on (, ), (U, U) the corresponding quotient texture and (f, F ) : (, ) (U, U) the canonical quotient difunction then clearly τ U = {H U F H τ} is a topology and κ U = {K U f K κ} a cotopology on (U, U). Definition 4.1. With the notation above, (τ U, κ U ) is called the quotient ditopology of (τ, κ) on (U, U), and (U, U, τ U, κ U ) the quotient ditopological texture space of (,, τ, κ) modulo (r, R).

25 360 L. M. BROWN Clearly the quotient ditopology is the finest ditopology on the quotient (U, U) making the canonical quotient difunction bicontinuous. Just as for quotients of topological spaces we have: Proposition 4.2. Let (U, U, τ U, κ U ) be a quotient of (,, τ, κ) and (f, F ) the canonical quotient difunction. If (g, G) : (U, U, τ U, κ U ) (,, τ, κ ) is a difunction, then (g, G) is continuous (cocontinuous, bicontinuous) if and only if (g, G) (f, F ) is continuous (respectively, cocontinuous, bicontinuous). Proof. This follows from the equalities (g f) A = f (g A) and (G F ) A = F (G A) for all A, established in [6, Lemma 2.16 (2)]. Before proceeding it will be useful to have a notion of homeomorphism for difunctions. Definition 4.3. An isomorphism in the category dftex of textures and difunctions which, together with its inverse, is bicontinuous, will be called a difunctional homeomorphism, or dihomeomorphism for short. Dihomeomorphisms, therefore, coincide with the isomorphisms of the category dfditop of ditopological texture spaces and bicontinuous difunctions. It is proved in [6, Proposition 3.14 (5)] that a difunction (h, H) is an isomorphism if and only if it is bijective, and it is clear from the proof of that proposition that the inverse is then the inverse direlation (h, H) = (H, h ). The following gives several useful characterizations of a dihomeomorphism, and is the textural analogue of [10, Proposition ]. Proposition 4.4. Let (h, H) : ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ) be a bijective difunction. Then the following are equivalent. (i) (h, H) is a dihomeomorphism. (ii) (h, H) is bicontinuous, open and coclosed. (iii) (h, H) is bicontinuous, closed and co-open. (iv) h A = H A τ 2 A τ 1, and h A = H A κ 2 A κ 1. (v) h B = H B τ 1 B τ 2, and h B = H B κ 1 B κ 2.

26 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 361 Proof. (i) = (ii) The inverse (H, h ) of (h, H) is continuous, so U 1 τ 1 = h U 1 = ((h ) ) U 1 = (h ) U 1 τ 2, which shows that (h, H) is open. Likewise, the cocontinuity of (H, h ) implies the coclosedness of (h, H). (ii) = (iii) By [6, Corollary 2.33 (1, 2)] we see that since (h, H) is bijective, h A = H A for all A 1. Hence (h, H) is closed if and only if it is coclosed, and open if and only if it is co-open. (iii) = (iv) A τ 1 = H A τ 2 since (h, H) is co-open, and we have already noted that h A = H A since (h, H) is bijective. On the other hand if h A = H A τ 2 then A = H (h A) τ 1 by the continuity of (h, H), the injectivity of (h, H) and [6, Corollary 2.33 (2)]. The proof of the second result is dual to this and is omitted. (iv) = (v) Take B 2 and set A = H B. Then, since (h, H) is surjective, B = h (H B) = h A by [6, Corollary 2.33 (1)]. If B τ 2 then h A τ 2 and we deduce H B = A τ 1 by (iv), and we know that H B = h B since (h, H) is a difunction. On the other hand if we assume that h B = H B τ 1 then A τ 1 and by (iv) we have B = h A τ 2. The proof of the remaining results is dual to this, and is omitted. (v) = (i) It is clear from (v) that (h, H) is bicontinuous. To show (H, h ) is continuous take U 1 τ 1. Then U 1 = H (h U 1 ) τ 1 by [6, Corollary 2.33 (2)] since (h, H) is injective, whence h U 1 τ 2 by (v) applied to B = h U 1. But, as noted above, h U 1 = (h ) U 1, so (h, H ) is continuous. Likewise (H, h ) is cocontinuous and we have shown that (h, H) is a dihomeomorphism. Now let ( k, k, τ k, κ k ), k = 1, 2 be ditopological texture spaces and (g, G) : ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ) a bicontinuous difunction. As in Theorem 3.12, (g, G) gives rise to a quotient texture (U, U), a canonical quotient difunction (f, F ) and an injective difunction (h, H) from (U, U) to ( 2, 2 ) satisfying (h, H) (f, F ) = (g, G). We take the quotient ditopology (τ U, κ U ) on (U, U).

27 362 L. M. BROWN (g,g) ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ) (h,h) (f,f ) (U, U, τ U, κ U ) By Proposition 4.2 we see that the difunction (h, H) is bicontinuous. In case (g, G) is surjective (h, H) is a bijection, but in general it need not be a dihomeomorphism because the inverse may not be bicontinuous. Definition 4.5. (g, G) : ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ) is called a quotient difunction if it can be expressed as the composition of a canonical quotient difunction on ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) and a dihomeomorphism onto ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ). Proposition 4.6. The following are equivalent for a surjective difunction (g, G) from ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) to ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ) : (1) The difunction (g, G) is quotient. (2) G B τ 1 B τ 2 and g B κ 1 B κ 2. (3) With the notation as in Theorem 3.12 and the commutative diagram above, the difunction (h, H) is a dihomeomorphism. Proof. (1) = (2) Let (g, G) = (k, K) (f, F ), where (f, F ) : ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) (U, U, τ U, κ U ) is a canonical quotient difunction and (k, K) : (U,, τ U, κ U ) ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ) a dihomeomorphism. By the definition of (τ U, κ U ) we have G B = F (K B) τ 1 K B τ U, while by Proposition 4.4 (v) we have K B τ U B τ 2. The proof of the second equivalence is dual to this and is omitted. (2) = (3) ince (h, H) is bijective because (g, G) is surjective we need only verify Proposition 4.4 (iv). Take A U. Then G (h A) = (H F ) (h A) = F (H (h A)) = F A by [6, Corollary 2.33 (2)] since (h, H) is injective. Hence A τ U F A τ 1 G (h A) τ 1 h A τ 2 by (2). In just the same way A κ U H A κ 2. (3) = (1) Immediate.

28 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE 363 Corollary 4.7. A composition of quotient difunctions is a quotient difunction. On the other hand if (g 1, G 1 ), (g 2, G 2 ) are bicontinuous difunctions whose composition (g 2, G 2 ) (g 1, G 1 ) is a quotient difunction then (g 2, G 2 ) is a quotient difunction. Proof. The first statement is clear from Proposition 4.6 (2). If (g 2 g 1, G 2 G 1 ) is a quotient difunction it is surjective so by [6, Theorem 3.32 (1)] we have i (g 2 g 1 ) (G 2 G 1 ) = g 2 (g 1 G 1 ) G 2 g 2 G 2 since g 1 G 1 i by [6, Lemma 2.23 (2)] applied to the difunction (g 1, G 1 ). Hence (g 2, G 2 ) is surjective. ince (g 1, G 1 ), (g 2, G 2 ) are bicontinous the result now follows easily from Proposition 4.6. Corollary 4.8. An injective quotient difunction is a dihomeomorphism. Proof. In view of Proposition 4.6 (3) it will be sufficient to show that the canonical quotient difunction (f, F ) of the quotient generated by a bijective difunction (g, G) as in Theorem 3.12 is a dihomeomorphism. But since, as we have noted before, (G, g ) is now the inverse of (g, G) we have r = G g = i and R = g G = I. Lemma 3.7 (1) now gives sρt P s P t and P t P s P s = P t s = t. It follows that the quotient (U, U, τ U, κ U ) may be identified with (,, τ, κ), ϕ becomes the identity and so (f, F ) = (i, I), which is a dihomeomorphism. Corollary 4.9. urjective bicontinuous difunctions which are open or co-open, and closed or coclosed, are quotient difunctions. Proof. Clear from Proposition 4.6 (2) and [6, Corollary 2.33 (1) and Theorem 2.24 (3)]. Proposition Let (r, R) be an equivalence direlation on (,, τ, κ) and (f, F ) the canonical quotient difunction. Then (f, F ) is: (1) open if and only if A τ = r A τ. (2) co-open if and only if A τ = R A τ. (3) closed if and only if A κ = r A κ. (4) coclosed if and only if A κ = R A τ.

29 364 L. M. BROWN Proof. We establish (1), leaving the other cases to the interested reader. By Theorem 3.5 we have r = F f, so for A we have r A = (F f) A = F (f A). By the definition of the quotient topology we deduce that r A τ f A τ U, from which (1) follows at once. Corollary Let (g, G) : ( 1, 1, τ 1, κ 1 ) ( 2, 2, τ 2, κ 2 ) be a quotient difunction. Then (g, G) is: (1) open if and only if A τ 1 = G (g A) τ 1. (2) co-open if and only if A τ 1 = G (G A) τ 1. (3) closed if and only if A κ 1 = g (g A) κ 1. (4) coclosed if and only if A κ 1 = g (G A) κ 1. Proof. With the notation as in Theorem 3.12 we have (g, G) = (h, H) (f, F ), where (f, F ) is the canonical quotient difunction for the equivalence direlation (r, R) given by r = G g, R = g G, and (h, H) is a dihomeomorphism by Proposition 4.6. Hence (g, G) and (f, F ) share the properties in question, so the results follow at once from Proposition Definition An equivalence direlation (r, R) on a ditopological texture space is called open (co-open, closed, coclosed) if the canonical quotient difunction is open (co-open, closed, coclosed). We recall from [8] that (,, τ, κ) is T 1 if each set A can be written in the form A = j J K j with K j κ, j J; and that it is co-t 1 if each A can be written in the form A = j J G j with G j τ, j J. Proposition Let (,, τ, κ) be a ditopological texture space and (r, R) an equivalence direlation on (, ). (1) If (,, τ, κ) is T 1 and (r, R) is closed then every set in R can be written as a join of closed sets in R. (2) If (,, τ, κ) is co-t 1 and (r, R) is co-open then every set in R can be written as an intersection of open sets in R. Proof. (1) For K j κ, j J, we have r ( j J K j) = j J r K j by [6, Corollary 2.12 (2)], and r K j κ by Proposition 4.10 (3). ince R = {r A A } by Lemma 3.7 (2,4), the required result follows at once. (2). Dual to (1).

30 QUOTIENT OF TEXTURE The T 0 reflector We begin by showing that every ditopological texture space has a quotient that is a T 0 ditopological texture space. Let us recall the following characteristic property of T 0 ditopological spaces [8]. Definition 5.1. The ditopology (τ, κ) on (, ) is T 0 if given Q s Q t there exists B τ κ satisfying P s B Q t. Now we may give: Theorem 5.2. Let (,, τ, κ) be a ditopological texture space, (r, R) the equivalence direlation generated by B = τ κ as in Proposition 3.15, (U, U) the quotient texture of (, ) with respect to (r, R) and (τ U, κ U ) the quotient ditopology on (U, U). Then the quotient ditopological space (U, U, τ U, κ U ) is T 0. Proof. Take s, t with Q s Q t. By Lemma 3.8 (ii) we have Q s = {ϕ[r Q s ] P s Q s } and so there exists s with P s Q s satisfying ϕ[r Q s ] Q t. On the other hand Q t U so we have A R with ϕ[a] = Q t, whence ϕ[r Q s ] ϕ[a] and so R Q s A. Now we have w with P w A for which P (z,w) R = P z Q s. If we choose s with P s Q s, P s Q s, and set z = s in the above implication we obtain P (s,w) R. If now take w with P w Q w and P w A we obtain R Q (s,w ). From the definition of R, and bearing in mind that P s Q s, we see that there exists B B = τ κ satisfying P s B Q w. From P s / B, and the fact that B is saturated with respect to ρ gives s / ϕ[b], that is P s ϕ[b]. Also, B A and since A and B are both saturated with respect to ρ we obtain ϕ[b] ϕ[a] = Q t. Finally, ϕ[b] ϕ[b] = ϕ[τ κ] = τ U κ U, and we have established that (U, U, τ U, κ U ) is T 0. We obtain the subcategory dfditop 0 of dfditop by restricting to T 0 ditopological texture spaces. Theorem 5.3. The category dfditop 0 is a full reflexive subcategory of dfditop. Proof. It is clear that dfditop 0 is a full subcategory of dfditop. Take (,, τ, κ) ObdfDitop and let (f, F ) : (,, τ, κ) (U, U, τ U, κ U ) be the canonical difunction onto the T 0 quotient.

31 366 L. M. BROWN We claim (f, F ) is a reflection [1]. To show this take ( 0, 0, τ 0, κ 0 ) ObdfDitop 0 and (g, G) dfditop((,, τ, κ), ( 0, 0, τ 0, κ 0 )). We must show the existence of a dfditop 0 morphism (ḡ, Ḡ) making the following diagram commutative. (f,f ) (,, τ, κ) (U, U, τ U, κ U ) (ḡ,ḡ) (g,g) ( 0, 0, τ 0, κ 0 ) Let us now show that since ( 0, 0, τ 0, κ 0 ) is T 0 the corresponding equivalence direlation (r 0, R 0 ) is the identity (i 0, I 0 ) on ( 0, 0 ). By symmetry it will be sufficient to show that R 0 = I 0, and by reflexivity that I 0 R 0. uppose that I 0 R 0 and take s, t with I 0 Q (s,t) and P (s,t) I 0. The first result leads to Q s Q t, whence we have B 0 τ κ satisfying P s B 0 Q s. From the second result we have t with P (s,t) Q (s,t ), and then v with P v Q s for which P v B or B Q t for all B τ κ. But P t Q t gives Q t Q t, and P v Q s gives P s P v, so P s B or B Q t B τ κ. Taking B = B 0 now gives a contradiction, so (r 0, R 0 ) = (i 0, I 0 ) as required. Arguing as in the proof of Corollary 4.8 we may identify the quotient with ( 0, 0, τ 0, κ 0 ), and the canonical quotient difunction becomes (i 0, I 0 ). Also, the bicontinuity of (g, G) implies that g (τ 0 κ 0 ) τ κ = B R, so by Lemma 3.18, Theorem 3.14 gives a difunction (ḡ, Ḡ) making the diagram (,, τ, κ) (f,f ) (U, U, τ U, κ U ) (g,g) ( 0, 0, τ 0, κ 0 ) (i 0,I 0 ) (ḡ,ḡ) ( 0, 0, τ 0, κ 0 ) commutative. Finally, let us show that (ḡ, Ḡ) is bicontinuous. For A 0 we have ḡ A = Ḡ A = ϕ[g ϕ 1 0 [A]] = ϕ[g A] by the

Quotient Structure of Interior-closure Texture Spaces

Quotient Structure of Interior-closure Texture Spaces Filomat 29:5 (2015), 947 962 DOI 10.2298/FIL1505947D Published by Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, University of Niš, Serbia Available at: http://www.pmf.ni.ac.rs/filomat Quotient Structure of Interior-closure

More information

Metric spaces and textures

Metric spaces and textures @ Appl. Gen. Topol. 18, no. 1 (2017), 203-217 doi:10.4995/agt.2017.6889 c AGT, UPV, 2017 Metric spaces and textures Şenol Dost Hacettepe University, Department of Mathematics and Science Education, 06800

More information

INTUITIONISTIC TEXTURES REVISITED

INTUITIONISTIC TEXTURES REVISITED Hacettepe Journal of Mathematics and Statistics Volume 34 S (005), 115 130 Doğan Çoker Memorial Issue INTUITIONISTIC TEXTURES REVISITED Şenol Dost and Lawrence M. Brown Received 9 : 04 : 005 : Accepted

More information

The Journal of Nonlinear Science and Applications

The Journal of Nonlinear Science and Applications J. Nonlinear Sci. Appl. 3 (2010), no. 1, 12 20 The Journal of Nonlinear Science and Applications http://www.tjnsa.com α-open SETS AND α-bicontinuity IN DITOPOLOGICAL TEXTURE SPACES ŞENOL DOST Communicated

More information

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property Congruence Boolean Lifting Property George GEORGESCU and Claudia MUREŞAN University of Bucharest Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Academiei 14, RO 010014, Bucharest, Romania Emails: georgescu.capreni@yahoo.com;

More information

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Hongtaek Jung December 27, 2017 Abstract This is a part of a supplementary note for a Logic and Set Theory course. The main goal is to

More information

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SERGIO A. CELANI AND MARÍA ESTEBAN Abstract. Distributive Hilbert Algebras with infimum, or DH -algebras, are algebras with implication

More information

Introduction to generalized topological spaces

Introduction to generalized topological spaces @ Applied General Topology c Universidad Politécnica de Valencia Volume 12, no. 1, 2011 pp. 49-66 Introduction to generalized topological spaces Irina Zvina Abstract We introduce the notion of generalized

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

A bitopological point-free approach to compactifications

A bitopological point-free approach to compactifications A bitopological point-free approach to compactifications Olaf Karl Klinke a, Achim Jung a, M. Andrew Moshier b a School of Computer Science University of Birmingham Birmingham, B15 2TT England b School

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces

A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces A Non-Topological View of Dcpos as Convergence Spaces Reinhold Heckmann AbsInt Angewandte Informatik GmbH, Stuhlsatzenhausweg 69, D-66123 Saarbrücken, Germany e-mail: heckmann@absint.com Abstract The category

More information

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS BRIAN OSSERMAN We discuss the inverse limit construction, and consider the special case of inverse limits of finite groups, which should best be considered as topological

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

Completely regular Bishop spaces

Completely regular Bishop spaces Completely regular Bishop spaces Iosif Petrakis University of Munich petrakis@math.lmu.de Abstract. Bishop s notion of a function space, here called a Bishop space, is a constructive function-theoretic

More information

Math 249B. Geometric Bruhat decomposition

Math 249B. Geometric Bruhat decomposition Math 249B. Geometric Bruhat decomposition 1. Introduction Let (G, T ) be a split connected reductive group over a field k, and Φ = Φ(G, T ). Fix a positive system of roots Φ Φ, and let B be the unique

More information

Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies

Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies BS V c Gabriel Nagy Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies Notes from the Functional Analysis Course (Fall 07 - Spring 08) In this section we discuss two important, but highly non-trivial,

More information

Q-Convergence in graded ditopological texture spaces

Q-Convergence in graded ditopological texture spaces Mathematica Moravica Vol. 21, No. 1 (2017), 27 36 Q-Convergence in graded ditopological texture spaces Ramazan Ekmekç ı and Rıza Ertürk Abstract. Convergence of graded difilters have been presented and

More information

Math 145. Codimension

Math 145. Codimension Math 145. Codimension 1. Main result and some interesting examples In class we have seen that the dimension theory of an affine variety (irreducible!) is linked to the structure of the function field in

More information

TROPICAL SCHEME THEORY

TROPICAL SCHEME THEORY TROPICAL SCHEME THEORY 5. Commutative algebra over idempotent semirings II Quotients of semirings When we work with rings, a quotient object is specified by an ideal. When dealing with semirings (and lattices),

More information

Lecture 6. s S} is a ring.

Lecture 6. s S} is a ring. Lecture 6 1 Localization Definition 1.1. Let A be a ring. A set S A is called multiplicative if x, y S implies xy S. We will assume that 1 S and 0 / S. (If 1 / S, then one can use Ŝ = {1} S instead of

More information

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a Solutions to Homework #6 1. Complete the proof of the backwards direction of Theorem 12.2 from class (which asserts the any interval in R is connected). Solution: Let X R be a closed interval. Case 1:

More information

On the Structure of Rough Approximations

On the Structure of Rough Approximations On the Structure of Rough Approximations (Extended Abstract) Jouni Järvinen Turku Centre for Computer Science (TUCS) Lemminkäisenkatu 14 A, FIN-20520 Turku, Finland jjarvine@cs.utu.fi Abstract. We study

More information

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees Francesc Rosselló 1, Gabriel Valiente 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Research Institute

More information

BRUNO L. M. FERREIRA AND HENRIQUE GUZZO JR.

BRUNO L. M. FERREIRA AND HENRIQUE GUZZO JR. REVISTA DE LA UNIÓN MATEMÁTICA ARGENTINA Vol. 60, No. 1, 2019, Pages 9 20 Published online: February 11, 2019 https://doi.org/10.33044/revuma.v60n1a02 LIE n-multiplicative MAPPINGS ON TRIANGULAR n-matrix

More information

The Logic of Partitions

The Logic of Partitions The Logic of Partitions Introduction to the Dual of "Propositional" Logic David Ellerman Philosophy U. of California/Riverside U. of Ljubljana, Sept. 8, 2015 David Ellerman Philosophy U. of California/Riverside

More information

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions 24 Andreas Gathmann 3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions After having defined affine varieties, our next goal must be to say what kind of maps between them we want to consider as morphisms, i. e. as nice

More information

Schemes via Noncommutative Localisation

Schemes via Noncommutative Localisation Schemes via Noncommutative Localisation Daniel Murfet September 18, 2005 In this note we give an exposition of the well-known results of Gabriel, which show how to define affine schemes in terms of the

More information

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12 MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 2 CİHAN BAHRAN 3.2.. Let Y be a Noetherian scheme. Show that any Y -scheme X of finite type is Noetherian. Moreover, if Y is of finite dimension, then so is X. Write f

More information

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Boolean Algebras Let X be an arbitrary set and let P(X) be the class of all subsets of X (the power set of X). Three natural set-theoretic operations on P(X) are the binary operations of union

More information

MTH 428/528. Introduction to Topology II. Elements of Algebraic Topology. Bernard Badzioch

MTH 428/528. Introduction to Topology II. Elements of Algebraic Topology. Bernard Badzioch MTH 428/528 Introduction to Topology II Elements of Algebraic Topology Bernard Badzioch 2016.12.12 Contents 1. Some Motivation.......................................................... 3 2. Categories

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.ag] 24 Jun 2015

arxiv: v2 [math.ag] 24 Jun 2015 TRIANGULATIONS OF MONOTONE FAMILIES I: TWO-DIMENSIONAL FAMILIES arxiv:1402.0460v2 [math.ag] 24 Jun 2015 SAUGATA BASU, ANDREI GABRIELOV, AND NICOLAI VOROBJOV Abstract. Let K R n be a compact definable set

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato September 10, 2015 ABSTRACT. This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato June 23, 2015 This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a more direct connection

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps

1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps 1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps Last updated: April 14, 2011. 1.1 Examples and definitions Roughly, manifolds are sets where one can introduce coordinates. An n-dimensional manifold is a set

More information

MV-algebras and fuzzy topologies: Stone duality extended

MV-algebras and fuzzy topologies: Stone duality extended MV-algebras and fuzzy topologies: Stone duality extended Dipartimento di Matematica Università di Salerno, Italy Algebra and Coalgebra meet Proof Theory Universität Bern April 27 29, 2011 Outline 1 MV-algebras

More information

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra SET THEORY Basic concepts Notations Subset Algebra of sets The power set Ordered pairs and Cartesian product Relations on sets Types of relations and their properties Relational matrix and the graph of

More information

AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION

AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION Daniel Halpern-Leistner 6/20/08 Abstract. I propose an algebraic framework in which to study measures of information. One immediate consequence

More information

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Fundamenta Informaticae 69 (2006) 1 20 1 IOS Press On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Lirong Xia State Key Laboratory of Intelligent Technology and Systems Department of Computer Science

More information

Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos. Martino Garonzi. Universidade de Brasília. Primeiro semestre 2018

Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos. Martino Garonzi. Universidade de Brasília. Primeiro semestre 2018 Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos Martino Garonzi Universidade de Brasília Primeiro semestre 2018 1 Le risposte uccidono le domande. 2 Contents 1 Topology 4 2 Profinite spaces 6 3 Topological groups 10 4

More information

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Sergiu Rudeanu University of Bucharest Romania Closure operators are abundant in mathematics; here are a few examples. Given an algebraic structure, such

More information

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS J. WARNER

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS J. WARNER ALGEBRAIC GROUPS J. WARNER Let k be an algebraically closed field. varieties unless otherwise stated. 1. Definitions and Examples For simplicity we will work strictly with affine Definition 1.1. An algebraic

More information

A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY

A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY KEITH A. KEARNES Abstract. We show that a locally finite variety satisfies a nontrivial congruence identity

More information

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015)

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015) 18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015) 1. Introduction The goal for this course is to provide a quick, and hopefully somewhat gentle, introduction to the task of formulating

More information

A textural view of the distinction between uniformities and quasi-uniformities

A textural view of the distinction between uniformities and quasi-uniformities Topology and its Applications 153 (2006) 3294 3307 www.elsevier.com/locate/topol A textural view of the distinction between uniformities and quasi-uniformities Selma Özçağ 1,LawrenceM.Brown Hacettepe University,

More information

A topological duality for posets

A topological duality for posets A topological duality for posets RAMON JANSANA Universitat de Barcelona join work with Luciano González TACL 2015 Ischia, June 26, 2015. R. Jansana 1 / 20 Introduction In 2014 M. A. Moshier and P. Jipsen

More information

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31 Contents 1 Lecture 1: Introduction 2 2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction 7 3 Lecture 3: Induction and Well-Ordering Principle 11 4 Lecture 4: Definition of a Group and examples 15

More information

7 Lecture 7: Rational domains, Tate rings and analytic points

7 Lecture 7: Rational domains, Tate rings and analytic points 7 Lecture 7: Rational domains, Tate rings and analytic points 7.1 Introduction The aim of this lecture is to topologize localizations of Huber rings, and prove some of their properties. We will discuss

More information

Banach Spaces II: Elementary Banach Space Theory

Banach Spaces II: Elementary Banach Space Theory BS II c Gabriel Nagy Banach Spaces II: Elementary Banach Space Theory Notes from the Functional Analysis Course (Fall 07 - Spring 08) In this section we introduce Banach spaces and examine some of their

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

DYNAMICAL CUBES AND A CRITERIA FOR SYSTEMS HAVING PRODUCT EXTENSIONS

DYNAMICAL CUBES AND A CRITERIA FOR SYSTEMS HAVING PRODUCT EXTENSIONS DYNAMICAL CUBES AND A CRITERIA FOR SYSTEMS HAVING PRODUCT EXTENSIONS SEBASTIÁN DONOSO AND WENBO SUN Abstract. For minimal Z 2 -topological dynamical systems, we introduce a cube structure and a variation

More information

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS MARINA SEMENOVA AND FRIEDRICH WEHRUNG Abstract. For a partially ordered set P, let Co(P) denote the lattice of all order-convex

More information

Set theory and topology

Set theory and topology arxiv:1306.6926v1 [math.ho] 28 Jun 2013 Set theory and topology An introduction to the foundations of analysis 1 Part II: Topology Fundamental Felix Nagel Abstract We provide a formal introduction into

More information

G. de Cooman E. E. Kerre Universiteit Gent Vakgroep Toegepaste Wiskunde en Informatica

G. de Cooman E. E. Kerre Universiteit Gent Vakgroep Toegepaste Wiskunde en Informatica AMPLE FIELDS G. de Cooman E. E. Kerre Universiteit Gent Vakgroep Toegepaste Wiskunde en Informatica In this paper, we study the notion of an ample or complete field, a special case of the well-known fields

More information

Lecture 6: Etale Fundamental Group

Lecture 6: Etale Fundamental Group Lecture 6: Etale Fundamental Group October 5, 2014 1 Review of the topological fundamental group and covering spaces 1.1 Topological fundamental group Suppose X is a path-connected topological space, and

More information

BOOLEAN SUBALGEBRAS OF ORTHOALGEBRAS

BOOLEAN SUBALGEBRAS OF ORTHOALGEBRAS OOLEAN SUALGERAS OF ORTHOALGERAS JOHN HARDING, CHRIS HEUNEN, AND MIRKO NAVARA Abstract. Earlier work had shown that every nontrivial orthomodular lattice is characterized by its poset of oolean subalgebras

More information

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra Tamar Lando Abstract We study the measure semantics for propositional modal logics, in which formulas are interpreted in the Lebesgue measure algebra M,

More information

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. MAT 200, Logic, Language and Proof, Fall 2015 Summary Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. Definition. A proposition is a sentence which is either true or false. Truth table for the connective or :

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

Notes on p-divisible Groups

Notes on p-divisible Groups Notes on p-divisible Groups March 24, 2006 This is a note for the talk in STAGE in MIT. The content is basically following the paper [T]. 1 Preliminaries and Notations Notation 1.1. Let R be a complete

More information

Introduction to Topology

Introduction to Topology Introduction to Topology Randall R. Holmes Auburn University Typeset by AMS-TEX Chapter 1. Metric Spaces 1. Definition and Examples. As the course progresses we will need to review some basic notions about

More information

Topological Vector Spaces III: Finite Dimensional Spaces

Topological Vector Spaces III: Finite Dimensional Spaces TVS III c Gabriel Nagy Topological Vector Spaces III: Finite Dimensional Spaces Notes from the Functional Analysis Course (Fall 07 - Spring 08) Convention. Throughout this note K will be one of the fields

More information

Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization

Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization Zachary Mesyan March 11, 2018 Abstract The goal of this paper is to generalize the theory of triangularizing matrices to linear transformations of an arbitrary vector

More information

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories PART I Abstract algebraic categories It should be observed first that the whole concept of category is essentially an auxiliary one; our basic concepts are those of a functor and a natural transformation.

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

The overlap algebra of regular opens

The overlap algebra of regular opens The overlap algebra of regular opens Francesco Ciraulo Giovanni Sambin Abstract Overlap algebras are complete lattices enriched with an extra primitive relation, called overlap. The new notion of overlap

More information

Axioms for Set Theory

Axioms for Set Theory Axioms for Set Theory The following is a subset of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms for set theory. In this setting, all objects are sets which are denoted by letters, e.g. x, y, X, Y. Equality is logical identity:

More information

A Version of the Grothendieck Conjecture for p-adic Local Fields

A Version of the Grothendieck Conjecture for p-adic Local Fields A Version of the Grothendieck Conjecture for p-adic Local Fields by Shinichi MOCHIZUKI* Section 0: Introduction The purpose of this paper is to prove an absolute version of the Grothendieck Conjecture

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Relational semantics for a fragment of linear logic

Relational semantics for a fragment of linear logic Relational semantics for a fragment of linear logic Dion Coumans March 4, 2011 Abstract Relational semantics, given by Kripke frames, play an essential role in the study of modal and intuitionistic logic.

More information

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz Algebraic Structures and Their Applications Vol. 2 No. 2 ( 2015 ), pp 57-66. z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) R. MOHAMADIAN Communicated by B. Davvaz Abstract. In this article we introduce the concept

More information

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal semigroup rings and formal power series rings We next want to explore the notion of a (formal) power series ring in finitely

More information

How does universality of coproducts depend on the cardinality?

How does universality of coproducts depend on the cardinality? Volume 37, 2011 Pages 177 180 http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ How does universality of coproducts depend on the cardinality? by Reinhard Börger and Arno Pauly Electronically published on July 6, 2010 Topology

More information

Joseph Muscat Universal Algebras. 1 March 2013

Joseph Muscat Universal Algebras. 1 March 2013 Joseph Muscat 2015 1 Universal Algebras 1 Operations joseph.muscat@um.edu.mt 1 March 2013 A universal algebra is a set X with some operations : X n X and relations 1 X m. For example, there may be specific

More information

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces Chapter 2 Metric Spaces The purpose of this chapter is to present a summary of some basic properties of metric and topological spaces that play an important role in the main body of the book. 2.1 Metrics

More information

Definably amenable groups in NIP

Definably amenable groups in NIP Definably amenable groups in NIP Artem Chernikov (Paris 7) Lyon, 21 Nov 2013 Joint work with Pierre Simon. Setting T is a complete first-order theory in a language L, countable for simplicity. M = T a

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Abstract Algebra II Groups ( )

Abstract Algebra II Groups ( ) Abstract Algebra II Groups ( ) Melchior Grützmann / melchiorgfreehostingcom/algebra October 15, 2012 Outline Group homomorphisms Free groups, free products, and presentations Free products ( ) Definition

More information

FROM COHERENT TO FINITENESS SPACES

FROM COHERENT TO FINITENESS SPACES FROM COHERENT TO FINITENESS SPACES PIERRE HYVERNAT Laboratoire de Mathématiques, Université de Savoie, 73376 Le Bourget-du-Lac Cedex, France. e-mail address: Pierre.Hyvernat@univ-savoie.fr Abstract. This

More information

On topologies defined by irreducible sets

On topologies defined by irreducible sets On topologies defined by irreducible sets Zhao Dongsheng and Ho Weng Kin Abstract. In this paper, we define and study a new topology constructed from any given topology on a set, using irreducible sets.

More information

Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013)

Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013) Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013) Navid Alaei September 17, 2013 1 Lattice Basics There are, in general, two equivalent approaches to defining a lattice; one is rather

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO THE FUNDAMENTAL GROUP

AN INTRODUCTION TO THE FUNDAMENTAL GROUP AN INTRODUCTION TO THE FUNDAMENTAL GROUP DAVID RAN Abstract. This paper seeks to introduce the reader to the fundamental group and then show some of its immediate applications by calculating the fundamental

More information

On a quasi-ordering on Boolean functions

On a quasi-ordering on Boolean functions Theoretical Computer Science 396 (2008) 71 87 www.elsevier.com/locate/tcs On a quasi-ordering on Boolean functions Miguel Couceiro a,b,, Maurice Pouzet c a Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University

More information

Math 216A. A gluing construction of Proj(S)

Math 216A. A gluing construction of Proj(S) Math 216A. A gluing construction o Proj(S) 1. Some basic deinitions Let S = n 0 S n be an N-graded ring (we ollows French terminology here, even though outside o France it is commonly accepted that N does

More information

Extending Algebraic Operations to D-Completions

Extending Algebraic Operations to D-Completions Replace this file with prentcsmacro.sty for your meeting, or with entcsmacro.sty for your meeting. Both can be found at the ENTCS Macro Home Page. Extending Algebraic Operations to D-Completions Klaus

More information

The prime spectrum of MV-algebras based on a joint work with A. Di Nola and P. Belluce

The prime spectrum of MV-algebras based on a joint work with A. Di Nola and P. Belluce The prime spectrum of MV-algebras based on a joint work with A. Di Nola and P. Belluce Luca Spada Department of Mathematics and Computer Science University of Salerno www.logica.dmi.unisa.it/lucaspada

More information

Skew Boolean algebras

Skew Boolean algebras Skew Boolean algebras Ganna Kudryavtseva University of Ljubljana Faculty of Civil and Geodetic Engineering IMFM, Ljubljana IJS, Ljubljana New directions in inverse semigroups Ottawa, June 2016 Plan of

More information

USING FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS AND SOBOLEV SPACES TO SOLVE POISSON S EQUATION

USING FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS AND SOBOLEV SPACES TO SOLVE POISSON S EQUATION USING FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS AND SOBOLEV SPACES TO SOLVE POISSON S EQUATION YI WANG Abstract. We study Banach and Hilbert spaces with an eye towards defining weak solutions to elliptic PDE. Using Lax-Milgram

More information

14 Lecture 14: Basic generallities on adic spaces

14 Lecture 14: Basic generallities on adic spaces 14 Lecture 14: Basic generallities on adic spaces 14.1 Introduction The aim of this lecture and the next two is to address general adic spaces and their connection to rigid geometry. 14.2 Two open questions

More information

INFINITE-DIMENSIONAL DIAGONALIZATION AND SEMISIMPLICITY

INFINITE-DIMENSIONAL DIAGONALIZATION AND SEMISIMPLICITY INFINITE-DIMENSIONAL DIAGONALIZATION AND SEMISIMPLICITY MIODRAG C. IOVANOV, ZACHARY MESYAN, AND MANUEL L. REYES Abstract. We characterize the diagonalizable subalgebras of End(V ), the full ring of linear

More information

int cl int cl A = int cl A.

int cl int cl A = int cl A. BAIRE CATEGORY CHRISTIAN ROSENDAL 1. THE BAIRE CATEGORY THEOREM Theorem 1 (The Baire category theorem. Let (D n n N be a countable family of dense open subsets of a Polish space X. Then n N D n is dense

More information

Modal-Like Operators in Boolean Lattices, Galois Connections and Fixed Points

Modal-Like Operators in Boolean Lattices, Galois Connections and Fixed Points Fundamenta Informaticae 76 (2007) 129 145 129 IOS Press Modal-Like Operators in Boolean Lattices, Galois Connections and Fixed Points Jouni Järvinen Turku Centre for Computer Science, University of Turku,

More information

Lecture 9: Sheaves. February 11, 2018

Lecture 9: Sheaves. February 11, 2018 Lecture 9: Sheaves February 11, 2018 Recall that a category X is a topos if there exists an equivalence X Shv(C), where C is a small category (which can be assumed to admit finite limits) equipped with

More information

Chapter 2 Linear Transformations

Chapter 2 Linear Transformations Chapter 2 Linear Transformations Linear Transformations Loosely speaking, a linear transformation is a function from one vector space to another that preserves the vector space operations. Let us be more

More information

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Department of Mathematics Bachelor Thesis (7.5 ECTS) Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Author: Dionijs van Tuijl Supervisor: Dr. Jaap van Oosten June 15, 2016 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminaries

More information

Lectures - XXIII and XXIV Coproducts and Pushouts

Lectures - XXIII and XXIV Coproducts and Pushouts Lectures - XXIII and XXIV Coproducts and Pushouts We now discuss further categorical constructions that are essential for the formulation of the Seifert Van Kampen theorem. We first discuss the notion

More information

Lattice Theory Lecture 5. Completions

Lattice Theory Lecture 5. Completions Lattice Theory Lecture 5 Completions John Harding New Mexico State University www.math.nmsu.edu/ JohnHarding.html jharding@nmsu.edu Toulouse, July 2017 Completions Definition A completion of a poset P

More information

B. Appendix B. Topological vector spaces

B. Appendix B. Topological vector spaces B.1 B. Appendix B. Topological vector spaces B.1. Fréchet spaces. In this appendix we go through the definition of Fréchet spaces and their inductive limits, such as they are used for definitions of function

More information