Order Embeddings with Irrational Codomain: Debreu Properties of Real Subsets

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Order Embeddings with Irrational Codomain: Debreu Properties of Real Subsets"

Transcription

1 Order (2006) 23: DOI /s y Order Embeddings with Irrational Codomain: Debreu Properties of Real Subsets M. J. Campión J. C. Candeal E. Induráin G. B. Mehta Received: 24 March 2006 / Accepted: 13 December 2006 / Published online: 27 January 2007 Springer Science + Business Media B.V Abstract The objective of this paper is to investigate the role of the set of irrational numbers as the codomain of order-preserving functions defined on topological totally preordered sets. We will show that although the set of irrational numbers does not satisfy the Debreu property it is still nonetheless true that any lower (respectively, upper) semicontinuous total preorder representable by a real-valued strictly isotone function (semicontinuous or not) also admits a representation by means of a lower (respectively, upper) semicontinuous strictly isotone function that takes values in the set of irrational numbers. These results are obtained by means of a direct construction. Moreover, they can be related to Cantor s characterization of the real line to obtain much more general results on the semicontinuous Debreu properties of a wide family of subsets of the real line. Key words total preorders semicontinuous strictly isotone functions irrational numbers Debreu properties Mathematics Subject Classifications (2000) Primary: 54 F 05 Secondary: 06 A 06 M. J. Campión E. Induráin (B) Departamento de Matemáticas, Campus Arrosadía, Universidad Pública de Navarra, Pamplona, Spain steiner@unavarra.es M. J. Campión mjesus.campion@unavarra.es J. C. Candeal Facultad de Ciencias Económicas y Empresariales, Departamento de Análisis Económico, Universidad de Zaragoza, c/ Doctor Cerrada 1 3, Zaragoza, Spain candeal@unizar.es G. B. Mehta Departament of Economics, University of Queensland, 4072 Brisbane, Queensland, Australia g.mehta@economics.uq.edu.au

2 344 Order (2006) 23: Introduction Let (X, ) and (Y, ) be totally preordered sets. Then a function f : X Y is said to be strictly isotone (oranorder monomorphism or order embedding) if x y is equivalent to f (x) f (y). We say that the function f is a representation of the preorder and the problem of proving the existence of such a function is said to be a representation problem. IfthesetX also has a topology τ X and the set Y has a topology τ Y then the problem of proving the existence of a continuous strictly isotone function f : (X,τ X ) (Y,τ Y ) is said to be a topological representation problem. Similarly, if the set X also has a differentiable or algebraic structure then the function f is also required to be a morphism with respect to these structures. There is now a very vast literature on the representation problem in mathematics and applied mathematics (see, e.g. [9, 18]). It is undeniable that the main emphasis in the literature has been on the case where the codomain (Y, ) is the set of real numbers with the natural ordering and the Euclidean topology. One consequence of this practice is that many total preorders, even ones with quite good properties, do not have real-valued representations. Also, from a purely mathematical point of view there is no reason or justification for studying only the very special case where R is the codomain. For further discussion of these ideas we refer the reader to [4] and[14]. Therefore, it is desirable to develop a general theory of representations of ordered structures in which the codomain is not necessarily the set of real numbers. One way to proceed is to consider codomains such as the long line or the lexicographic plane as in [14]. In this paper we follow a somewhat different approach by studying codomains of strictly isotone functions that are subsets of R but not necessarily order-isomorphic to R. (For initial results in this direction see [8] where order-monomorphisms are studied with codomains consisting of the rational numbers and the real algebraic numbers.) In this paper we continue the study of order-monomorphisms with codomains that are important subsets of the real numbers. As pointed out in [14], the most desirable codomains Y in studying continuity properties of strictly isotone functions are those for which the analogue of Debreu gap lemma holds, because in that case the existence of a strictly isotone function (which is not necessarily continuous) with such a codomain Y implies the existence of another strictly isotone function, that is continuous, and which also takes values in Y. We will prove that the set of irrational real numbers does not satisfy the Debreu property, so that, in a sense, it cannot be considered a good codomain for strictly isotone functions. Nevertheless, the set of irrational numbers R \ Q still has a good property if we consider semicontinuous representations instead of continuous ones. Thus, we shall also prove that a lower (respectively, upper) semicontinuous total preorder defined on a topological space (X,τ)admits a representation in the real line R if and only if it also admits a lower (respectively, upper) semicontinuous representation in the set R \ Q R of irrational numbers (that we will consider endowed with the inherited Euclidean topology). Unlike some general results concerning the Debreu property (see e.g. [14]) the proof we include here is given by means of a direct and explicit construction. In connection with the semicontinuous Debreu properties it is important to point out that the results achieved for the (at first glance) particular case of order-

3 Order (2006) 23: embeddings into the set of irrational numbers can be combined with other result (the Cantor characterization of the real line) to infer a much more general result, namely: All the subsets of the real line whose complement is countable and dense, do not satisfy the continuous Debreu property, but do satisfy both the upper and lower semicontinuous Debreu properties. In other words, the properties analyzed through a direct construction on the set of irrationals are shared by a wide family of real subsets. We also provide an example of a real subset that shares with the irrationals the same Debreu properties, but whose complement is uncountable. Finally, we provide an example to show that the semicontinuous Debreu properties cannot be taken for granted on every subset of the real line. We mean that, after showing that the irrationals (as well as many other real subsets) satisfy the semicontinuous Debreu properties, we could ask ourselves if such properties are satisfied by everyrealsubset.we prove that this is not the case, furnishing an example of a real subset that neither satisfies the upper semicontinuous Debreu property nor the lower semicontinuous one. For related ideas we refer the reader to [12]and[13]. 2 Preliminaries Let X be a nonempty set. Let be a total preorder (i.e.: a reflexive, transitive and complete binary relation) on X. (If is also antisymmetric, it is said to be a total order and the totally ordered structure (X, ) is said to be a chain). We denote x y instead of (y x). Alsox y will stand for (x y) (y x) for every x, y X. The total preorder is said to be dense in itself if for every x, y X with x y, there exist t X such that x t y. The total preorder is said to be representable if there exists a real-valued strictly isotone function f : X R such that x y f (x) f (y) (x, y X). This fact is characterized (see e.g. [9], p. 23) by equivalent conditions of orderseparability that must satisfy. Thus, the total preorder is said to be orderseparable in the sense of Debreu if there exists a countable subset D X such that for every x, y X with x y there exists an element d D with x d y. Such a subset D is said to be order-dense in (X, ). If X is endowed with a topology τ, the total preorder is said to be continuously representable if there exists a real-valued strictly isotone function f that is continuous with respect to the topology τ on X and the usual topology on the real line R. The total preorder is said to be τ-continuous if the sets U(x) ={y X, x y} and L(x) ={y X, y x} are τ-open, for every x X. In this case, the topology τ is said to be natural with respect to the preorder. (See[9], p. 19). The coarsest natural topology is the order topology θ whose subbasis is the collection {L(x) : x X} {U(x) : x X}. The total preorder defined on X is said to be τ-lower semicontinuous if the set U(x) ={y X, x y} is τ-open, for every x X. Ina similar way, is said to be τ-upper semicontinuous if the set L(x) ={y X, y x} is τ-open, for every x X. Now Debreu s open gap lemma is a powerful tool to obtain continuous representations of an order-separable totally preordered set (X, ) endowed with a natural topology τ.(see[11], or Ch. 3 in [9]). To explain this lemma let S be a subset of the

4 346 Order (2006) 23: real line R. Alacuna S corresponding to S is a nondegenerate interval of R that has both a lower bound and upper bound in S and that has no points in common with S. A maximal lacuna is said to be a Debreu gap. Debreu s open gap lemma states that if S is a subset of the extended real line R, then there exists a strictly increasing map, called a gap function, g : S R such that all the Debreu gaps of g(s) are open. Using Debreu s open gap lemma, the classical method to get a continuous realvalued strictly isotone function goes as follows: First, one constructs a strictly isotone function (which may not necessarily be continuous) f (see e.g. [6], Theorem 24 on p. 200, or else [9], Theorem on p. 14). Then Debreu s open gap lemma is applied to find a strictly increasing function g : f (X) R such that all the Debreu gaps of g( f (X)) are open. Consequently, the composition F = g f : X R is also a representation (X, ), but now F is continuous with respect to any given natural topology τ on X. If is a τ-upper (respectively τ-lower) semicontinuous total preorder on X, and it is also representable (or, equivalently, order-separable in the sense of Debreu), a similar argument allows us to get a τ-upper (respectively τ-lower) semicontinuous real-valued strictly isotone map that represents. The process is the same as above: Construct a strictly isotone function f representing (X, ) and apply Debreu s open gap lemma to find a strictly increasing function g : f (X) R such that all the Debreu gaps of g( f (X)) are open. The composition F = g f : X R becomes also a strictly isotone function that represents (X, ), but now F is τ-upper (respectively τ-lower) semicontinuous. An appealing proof of a variant of Debreu s gap lemma, due to Beardon, appears in [2]. In order to understand the significance of Beardon s version of the gap lemma it should be noted that the continuity of a strictly isotone function u : (X,τ, ) (R, ) depends upon the fact that the image u(x) R has no gaps of the form [a, b) which are half-closed half-open and no gaps of the form (a, b] which are halfopen half-closed. These are the bad gaps" which should be removed by the gap function g. The existence of a closed gap does not preclude the continuity of the strictly isotone function u. (See[9], pp ). Now let S be an arbitrary subset of R. Beardon proves that if S R then there is a strictly increasing function g : S R such that g(s) has no half-closed half-open or half-open half-closed gaps. It is important to point out that if a strictly isotone function u : (X,τ, ) (R, ) has no half-open half-closed gap (a, b],then it is upper semicontinuous. In the same way, if u has no half-closed half-open gap [a, b), then it is lower semicontinuous. In [3] the following question regarding the gap lemma appears: Does the Debreu gap lemma hold only for the real numbers R or can it be extended to more general totally preordered sets? This question is very important for representation theory because of the almost universal practice of using R as the codomain of any strictly isotone function. At this point, it is important to know some characterization of chains that are order-isomorphic to the reals. In this direction, the fundamental Cantor theorem on the linear continuum solves the question. A standard set-theoretical proof of this theorem may be found in pp of [15]. For a proof of this theorem that is based on concepts of utility theory we refer the reader to [5] where the Cantor theorem is proved by using Debreu s gap lemma.

5 Order (2006) 23: Lemma 2.1 (Cantor s fundamental theorem) Let (X, ) be a totally ordered set which satisfies the following properties: (a) (b) (X, ) is order-unbounded and has a countable order-dense subset. (X,θ) is a connected topological space (where θ stands for the order topology induced by on X). Then (X, ) is order-isomorphic to the real line R. Observe now that if the gap lemma of Debreu can be extended to totally ordered sets that are quite different from R with its usual Euclidean order, then it will be possible to begin the development of a theory of continuity of strictly isotone functions with other codomains. (For a complete account of the latest achievements about this question, consult [14]). Totally ordered sets where the analogue of the Debreu s gap lemma holds are said to have the Debreu property. In what follows, we shall say that a totally preordered set (X, ),hasthedebreu property if for an arbitrary subset S X there is a strictly increasing function g : S X such that g(s) has no half-open half-closed or halfclosed half-open gaps. Equivalently, a totally preordered set (X, ), endowed with a natural topology τ, has the Debreu property if for any strictly isotone function f defined on a totally preordered space (Y, Y ), and taking values in X there is another continuous strictly isotone function g : Y X, where we supposethat Y is endowed with the order topology. As an immediate consequence of the definition of the Debreu property, and the Debreu s gap lemma, we obtain the following result for subsets of the real line. Proposition 2.2 (a) Let X be a subset of the real line that contains an open interval (a, b) X R. Then (X, ) satisfies the Debreu property. (b) Let X be a nonempty subset of the real line that does not satisfy the Debreu property. Then its complement R \ XisdenseinR. Equivalently, X is totally disconnected. Wecan generalizethe conceptofdebreu property, in the following two directions: (a) (b) A totally preordered set (X, ), endowed with a natural topology τ, hasthe lower Debreu property if for any strictly isotone function f defined on a totally preordered space (Y, Y ), and taking values in X there is another lower semicontinuous strictly isotone function g : Y X, where we suppose that Y is endowed with the order topology, A totally preordered set (X, ), endowed with a natural topology τ, hasthe upper Debreu property if for any strictly isotone function f defined on a totally preordered space (Y, Y ), and taking values in X there is another upper semicontinuous strictly isotone function g : Y X, where we suppose that Y is endowed with the order topology.

6 348 Order (2006) 23: It is clear that if (X, ) has the Debreu property, then it also has both the lower and the upper Debreu properties. However the converse is not true, as we shall prove later. 3 Strictly Isotone Functions with Irrational Values Let (X, ) be a totally preordered set that is representable in (R, ) by means of a (not necessarily continuous) strictly isotone function u : X R. We wonder if it is possible to get another strictly isotone function v : X R such that v(x) is an irrational number (i.e.: v(x) / Q, where Q denotes the set of rational numbers) for every x X. The answer is positive, and it is a consequence of next proposition, in which we furnish a direct and explicit construction. Proposition 3.1 There is a strictly increasing map h : R R that only takes irrational values (i.e.: h(r) / Q for every r R). Proof Consider the decimal expansion of a real number r as the series a n N + 10, n where N is an integer and a n {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9} (n N). Observe that there are some real numbers that admit two possible such expansions, for instance: 1 = (0)...= = n 9 = (9)... 10n In these situations, we shall only use the expansion in which the periodic digit is 9. (In the above example, we shall use (9)... disregarding the use of 1 as (0)...). Now, given we define r = N + h(r) = N + a n, (r R) 10n a n 10 n2 +n 2, (r R). (For instance h(1) = h( (9)...)= ). Observe that after the digit a n and just before the digit a n+1 asetofnzeroes has been inserted. By definition, the map h is strictly increasing. Notice also that, by construction, the decimal expansion of h(r) has no periods, so that it corresponds to an irrational number h(r) / Q. Remark 3.2 (a) As a consequence of Debreu s open gap lemma, the map h constructed in Proposition 3.1 has the property that the image h(r) is not all of R \ Q. Asa

7 Order (2006) 23: (b) matter of fact, observe that: There is no strictly increasing and surjective map H : R R \ Q. The reason is that such a map, if any, would be continuous because it has no gaps and the order and Euclidean induced topology on R \ Q coincide. Moreover, such a function would be plainly open. Therefore, R would be homeomorphic to R \ Q. But this is not true because the real line is connected but R \ Q is totally disconnected. The map h that appears in the proof of Proposition 3.1 is lower semicontinuous. Indeed, if (x n ) is a strictly increasing sequence of real numbers that has a limit l R, it is plain, by construction, that lim n + h(x n) = h(l). However, h fails to be upper semicontinuous: If we consider the strictly decreasing sequence (x n = n ) + whose limit as n goes to + is obviously 1,we observe that (c) But lim h(x n) = 1. n + h(1) = 9 10 n2 +n 2 = 1. As a matter of fact, we can also point out that h(r) contains half-open halfclosed gaps: For instance ( + ] 9 10 n2 +n 2, 1 is one of such gaps. Therefore h cannot be continuous. Suppose now that the decimal expansion of a real number r is given as the series r = N + a n 10 n. Assume now that in the case of real numbers that admit two possible such expansions we always choose the expansion in which the periodic digit is 0. (As an example, we would use 1 but not (9)...). Now, given we define where b n = a k r = N + j(r) = N + if n = k2 + k 2 a n, (r R) 10n b n 10 n (r R), for some k N ; b n = 9 otherwise.

8 350 Order (2006) 23: (For instance j(1) = ). Observe that after the digit a n and just before the digit a n+1 asetofndigits 9 has been inserted. By definition, the map j is strictly increasing. It is straightforward to see now that j : R R is upper semicontinuous but not lower semicontinuous and takes only irrational values, and j(r) contains in this case half-closed half-open gaps. For instance [ ) c n 1, 1 +, 10 n with c n = 0 if n = k2 +k 2 for some k N; c n = 9 otherwise, is one of such gaps. Therefore j cannot be continuous. Corollary 3.3 Let (X, ) a totally preordered set that admits a representation in R through a real-valued strictly isotone function u : X R. Then it also admits a representation v : X R which only takes irrational values (i.e.: v(x) Q = ). Proof Just consider v as the composition h u where h is the map given in Proposition 3.1, or, alternatively, take v = j u, where j is the map given in Remark 3.2 (c). Now we are ready to analyze the behaviour of the set of irrational numbers with respect to the Debreu property. Theorem 3.4 The set R \ Q of irrational numbers, endowed with its usual order and Euclidean topology, does not satisfy the Debreu property. However, it satisfies the lower Debreu property and the upper Debreu property. Proof Consider the real line R endowed with the usual total order, that is obviously continuous with respect to the usual Euclidean topology. Moreover, (R, ) is representable in (R \ Q, ) by means of the function h considered in Proposition 3.1 above (or, alternatively, by means of the function j introduced in Remark 3.2 (c)). Suppose that the set R \ Q of irrational numbers has the Debreu property with respect to its usual Euclidean topology inherited from R. This would imply the existence of another strictly isotone representation H : (R, ) (R \ Q, ), but now H being continuous. IfweconsiderthesetH(R) (R \ Q), endowed with the order topology, it is clear that the map H : R H(R) is bijective (because it is strictly isotone) and continuous (becausetheordertopologyon H(R) iscoarserthan the induced Euclidean topology). But, in adition, such map H is also open. Thisis because H maps a basic open subset (a, b) R into (H(a), H(b)), which is obviously a basic open subset in the order topology of H(R). Thus, H : (R, usual topology) (H(R), order topology) would be a topological homeomorphism. But, with the same arguments used in Remark 3.2 (a), this is plainly a contradiction,sincer is connected with respect to the usual Euclidean topology, and, however, H(R) is a subset of irrational numbers that has more than one element, so that it is not connected with respect to its order topology.

9 Order (2006) 23: Therefore, the set R \ Q of irrational numbers, endowed with its usual order and Euclidean topology, does not satisfy the Debreu property. 1 To see that R \ Q satisfies the lower Debreu property, let(y, Y ) beatotally preordered set endowed with its order topology. Let u : Y R \ Q be a strictly isotone map. In particular, considered as a function that takes values in the real line R, it is clear that u : Y R is a strictly isotone function (perhaps discontinuous!). Since, as a consequence of Debreu s gap lemma, the real line R, endowed with its usual order and Euclidean topology satisfies the Debreu property, there exists another strictly isotone function U : Y R that represents Y and is continuous with respecttothe ordertopology in Y andthe usualtopology in R. The composition v = h U, whereh is the map given in Proposition 3.1 is now a real-valued lower semicontinuous map that takes only irrational values. Since on R \ Q the induced Euclidean topology is the order topology, we conclude that R \ Q satisfies the lower Debreu property. To see that R \ Q satisfies the upper Debreu property, we can argue in an entirely analogous manner, now using, instead of h,themap j that appears in Remark 3.2 (c). Suppose now that we are interested in finding continuous or semicontinuous strictly isotone functions from a totally ordered set (Y, Y ) endowed with a topology τ Y (not necessarily a natural topology) that take only irrational values. The next result follows now as a consequence of Theorem 3.4. Corollary 3.5 Let (Y, Y ) be a totally preordered set endowed with a topology τ Y. Suppose also that Y is τ Y -lower semicontinuous (respectively, τ Y -upper semicontinuous) and order-separable in the sense of Debreu. Then there exists a lower semicontinuous (respectively, upper semicontinuous) strictly isotone function u : (Y, Y ) R that takes only irrational values. Proof Let θ Y be the order topology on Y associated to Y.Since Y is τ Y -lower (respectively, τ Y - upper semicontinuous), the identity map i : (Y,τ Y ) (Y,θ Y ) is lower semicontinuous (respectively, upper semicontinuous). Since Y is orderseparable in the sense of Debreu, using the Debreu s open gap lemma it follows that Y is representable through a continuous strictly isotone function u : (Y,θ Y ) R. Finally, the composition h u i : (Y,τ Y ) (R, usual Euclidean topology), (or, respectively, the composition j u i : (Y,τ Y ) (R, usual Euclidean topology)), where h is the map introduced in Proposition 3.1 (respectively, where j is the map introduced in Remark 3.2 (c)), is a lower semicontinuous (respectively, upper semicontinuous) strictly isotone function that also represents Y and takes only irrational values. Observe, however, that it is not true, in general, that any τ Y -continuous and order-separable total preorder Y defined on Y admits a continuous real-valued strictly isotone function taking only irrational values. Once more, the reason is that the set R \ Q does not satisfy the Debreu property. 1 An alternative proof of the fact that the irrationals do not have the Debreu property was communicated to the last author by Professor G. Herden (Essen, Germany) in October 2003.

10 352 Order (2006) 23: Definition Given a topological space (X,τ), the topology τ is said to satisfy the continuous representability property (CRP) if every τ-continuous total preorder defined on X admits a numerical representation by means of a continuous realvalued strictly isotone function. Also, the topology τ is said to satisfy the semicontinuous representability property (SRP) if every τ-upper (respectively τ-lower) semicontinuous total preorder defined on X admits a numerical representation by means of an upper (respectively lower) semicontinuous real-valued map. It is known that SRP implies CRP, but the converse is not true (See Proposition 4.4 in [7]). We can extend the definitions of CRP and SRP to the case of representations taking only irrational values, in the following sense: (a) The topology τ is said to satisfy the continuous representability property on irrationals (CRPI) if every τ-continuous total preorder defined on X admits a numerical representation by means of a continuous real-valued strictly isotone function that only takes irrational values. (b) The topology τ is said to satisfy the semicontinuous representability property on irrationals (SRPI) if every τ-upper (respectively τ-lower) semicontinuous total preorder defined on X admits a numerical representation by means of an upper (respectively lower) semicontinuous real-valued map that only takes irrational values. Now, we observe that it is not true that SRPI implies CRPI: It follows from the previous results that the usual Euclidean topology of R satisfies SRPI. However, it is straightforward to see that it does not satisfy CRPI, again because the set of irrationals fails to satisfy the Debreu property. Remark 3.6 In General Topology, a result in the context of metric spaces, known as the Alexandroff s lemma (see [1], p. 83), states that: << Let X be a nonempty set endowed with a complete metric d. LetY be a G δ subset (i.e.: a countable intersection of open subsets) of X. ThenY can be endowed with a complete metric d, perhaps different from d, such that d and d induce the same topology on Y. >> Since the set R \ Q of irrational numbers is a G δ subset of the real line R, which is a complete metric space with respect to the usual Euclidean topology, it follows that it can be given a complete metric, obviously different from the usual Euclidean one (that fails to be complete on R \ Q), such that this new metric also induces the usual Euclidean topology on R \ Q. As an immediate consequence of this fact and Theorem 3.4, we obtain an example of a totally ordered complete metric space that does not satisfy the Debreu property. 4 Debreu Properties of Certain Real Subsets Let us see now how we can use the results obtained in Section 3, as well as the explicit construction given there to get general results concerning the satisfaction of Debreu properties on certain families of real subsets. 2 2 Certain lines of enquiry pursued in this section have resulted from comments of an anonymous referee (although several proofs given in the present paper, based on direct constructions, are somewhat different from the referee s original ones).

11 Order (2006) 23: Lemma 4.1 (Cantor s characterization of the rationals) Let (X, ) be a totally ordered set which satisfies the following properties: (a) (b) (X, ) is order-unbounded and countable. (X, ) is dense-in-itself. Then (X, ) is order-isomorphic to the set Q of rational numbers, endowed with its usual order. Proof See e.g. [6], Theorem 23 on p Proposition 4.2 Let S be a real subset whose complement R \ S is countable and dense in R. Then, with respect to the usual Euclidean order, S is order-isomorphic to the set R \ Q of irrational numbers. Proof By Lemma 4.1, it follows that (R \ S, ) is order-isomorphic to (Q, ). Now we may apply the well-known argument of the classical proof of Lemma 2.1 (see [15]) in order to start with an order-isomorphism φ : (R \ S, ) (Q, ) and extend it to an order-isomorphism from (R, ) to (R, ). Then the restriction S : (S, ) (R \ Q, ) furnishes the desired isomorphism from S onto the irrationals. Corollary 4.3 Let S be a real subset whose complement R \ S is countable and dense in R. Then the following properties hold. (a) (b) (c) There exist order-monomorphisms α : (R, ) (S, ) and β : (R, ) (S, ) that are lower, respectively upper, semicontinuous with respect to the usual Euclidean topology on the real line R. (S, ) satisfies the lower and upper semicontinuous Debreu properties. (S, ) does not satisfy the Debreu property. Proof (a) Consider the composition α = i S φ h : R R where h : R R is the lower semicontinuous map that appears in the construction given in Proposition 3.1, so that, in particular, h(r) R \ Q ; φ : R \ Q S is an order-isomorphism (whose existence is guaranteed by Proposition 4.2), and i S : S R is the inclusion map. It is obvious that α is a lower semicontinuous order-monomorphism (simply, observe that the only Debreu gaps that α provokes in R are half-open half-closed, as those of the map h). Similarly, the composition β = i S φ j : R where j : R R \ Q is the upper semicontinuous map that appears in the construction given in Remark 3.2 (part iii) is also an upper semicontinuous order-monomorphism. (b) and (c) This is analogous to the proof of Theorem 3.4. The next Theorem 4.4. shows that the result in part iii) of Corollary 4.3 may still be improved, looking for a even bigger family of real subsets that do not satisfy the (continuous) Debreu property.

12 354 Order (2006) 23: Theorem 4.4 Let S be a real subset whose complement R \ SisdenseinR. Suppose that the real line R is order-embeddable in S (i.e.: there exists an order-monomorphism ψ : R S). Then (S, ) does not satisfy the Debreu property. Proof Suppose that the set S has the Debreu property with respect to its usual Euclidean topology inherited from R. This would imply the existence of a continuous order-embedding J : (R, ) (S, ). Again as in the proof of Theorem 3.4, if we consider the set J(R) S, endowed with the order topology, it is clear that the map J : R J(R) is bijective, continuous and open. Thus, J : (R, usual topology) (J(R), order topology) would be a topological homeomorphism. But this is a contradiction, since(r, ) is connected, and J(R) is not connected with respect to its order topology, because it has uncountably many points and its complement is dense in R. Remark 4.5 Theorem 4.4 completes the panorama of Proposition 2 in [14], that states that: << Given a dense-in-itself subchain (X, ) of the real line that contains a copy of the real line, it holds that (X, ) has the Debreu property if and only if the order topology on X that is induced by the Euclidean ordering is not totally disconnected >>. Notice that in Theorem 4.4 we do not ask the subchain to be dense-in-itself. Let us put an example of the situation considered in Theorem 4.4. To do so, we introduce some necessary facts. Definition (a) (b) An irrational number α R \ Q is said to be: Transcendental if it is not a root of a polynomials with rational coefficients, A Liouville number if, for every natural number n N, there exists a rational number p q Q with q 2 such that α p q < 1. q n It is well-known that Liouville s numbers are transcendental (see e.g. [10], pp ). However, not every transcendental number is a Liouville number. For instance π is a transcendental number but not a Liouville number, as proved in [17]. There are classical examples of Liouville numbers: For instance, if (a n ) {n 1, n N} is a sequence of digits such that a n {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9} (n 1; n N) and, in addition it has a subsequence whose terms are all different from zero, then, as proved in [10], p. 105, the real number: z = a n 10 n! = 0.a 1 a 2 000a a is a Liouville number (actually, these were the first numbers that were proved to be transcendental by Liouville in 1844, see [16]), so that in particular it belongs to the set T of transcendental numbers. Also, if (b n ) {n 1, n N} is a sequence of numbers such that b n {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9} (n 1; n N) and, in addition it has a subsequence whose terms are all different from 9, then the real number: w = 0.b 1 b 2 999b b = k=1 α k 10 k, where α k = b n if k = n! and α k = 9 otherwise, is also a Liouville number. Arguing as in Proposition 3.1 or Remark 3.2 (c) we can also obtain semicontinuous strictly isotone representations with values in the set T of transcendental numbers, using a suitable explicit construction. In addition, T does not have the Debreu

13 Order (2006) 23: property. The conventions here are as in the proof of Proposition 3.1. Now, given r = N + + a n (r R) we define H(r) = N + + a n 10 n (r R). As in Remark 10 n! 3.2 (b), this map H : R R is lower semicontinuous but not upper semicontinuous, strictly increasing, and takes values of the set of Liouville transcendental numbers. In the same way, but using now the conventions of Remark 3.2 (c), given r = N + + a n, (r R) we define J(r) = N + + b n 10 n (r R), where b 10 n n = a k if n = k! for some k N; b n = 9 otherwise. Now, the map J : R R is upper semicontinuous but not lower semicontinuous, strictly increasing, and takes values of the set of transcendental numbers. Example 4.6 Similarly to what happens for the set R \ Q of irrational numbers, the complement of the set T of transcendental numbers is countable (see e.g. [10], p. 103) and dense (because it contains the set Q of rational numbers). This set R \ T is also known as the set A of real algebraic numbers. Therefore, by Corollary 4.3, it follows that : <<The set T of transcendental numbers satisfies the semicontinuous Debreu properties, but not the (continuous) Debreu property>>. If we consider just the set of Liouville numbers L instead of the whole set T of transcendental numbers, we cannot make use of Corollary 4.3, since the Lebesgue measure and the Hausdorff dimension of the set L of Liouville numbers are equal to zero (see Ch. 2 in [19]),sothatitscomplementD = R \ L, calledthesetof diophantine numbers, is, in particular, dense in R and uncountable. But now, instead of Corollary 4.3 we can use Theorem 4.4 to conclude that: <<The set L of Liouville numbers does not satisfy the Debreu property>>. Notice, in addition, that by the above construction it follows that: << The set L of Liouville numbers satisfies both the lower and upper semicontinuous Debreu properties>>. In general, we find a difficulty if we try to apply Theorem 4.4 to concrete real subsets S. Notice that we must have at hand an order-embedding of the real line R into the given subset S. Although in the present paper we have considered two concrete cases, namely S = R \ Q and S = L, where we can explicitly exhibit the embedding, in other situations such kind of embeddings are not easy to be found, or even to be proved to exist. Let us give now a third example, that shows another situation where a direct construction can be given. Example 4.7 (Cantor ternary set) If we consider the closed interval [0, 1] in R, then we remove the open middle third ( 1 3, 2 ), and then we remove the open middle thirds 3 ( 1 9, 2 9 ) and ( 7 9, 8 ) of the two remaining intervals, and then we remove the open middle 9 thirds of the four remaining intervals; and so on, indefinitely, what remains is the Cantor ternary set C. It can be described as consisting precisely of those numbers of [0, 1] that have expansions in base 3 containing no 1s. To define an order-embedding from R into the set C we first map R into (0, 1) by means of the strictly increasing function μ : R R given by μ(x) = ex (x R). Then we interpret each number of e x +1 (0, 1) in base 2, using an expansion with 0 s and 1 s. Observe that there are some real

14 356 Order (2006) 23: numbers that admit two possible such expansions, for instance: (1)...= (1)... (in base 2). In these situations, we shall only use the expansion in which the periodic digit is 1. Finally, we define an order-embedding ρ : (0, 1) C such that ρ( + a n ) = ( + 2a n 2 n ) (where a 3 n n {0, 1}, n N). The composition ρ μ is the desired order-embedding from the real line R into the Cantor set C. Itis well-known that the Cantor set is an uncountable Borel set whose Lebesgue measure is equal to zero. However, its Hausdorff dimension is not zero but log 2, so that the log 3 analytical structure of the Cantor set C is different from that of the set L of Liouville numbers, which is also a Borel set. The complement R \ C of the Cantor ternary set is uncountable and dense in R. Thus, by Theorem 4.4, it follows that: << The Cantor set C does not satisfy the Debreu property>>. In addition, as in Proposition 3.1 and part (b) of Remark 3.2, it is straightforward to see that the composition ρ μ is lower semicontinuous. Suppose now that for real numbers in [0, 1] that admit two different expansions in base 2, we decide now to use only the expansion in which the periodic digit is 0. In this case, the composition ρ μ is upper semicontinuous, asin part (c) ofremark 3.2. Consequently, we also obtain that: << The Cantor set C satisfies both the lower and upper semicontinuous Debreu properties>>. To conclude our study, it is worthwhile to furnish an example of a real subset that does not satisfy any of the semicontinous Debreu properties. This example is important in order to say that the semicontinuous Debreu properties are non trivial, i.e., it is not true that every real subset satisfies both of them. Example 4.8 Let X ={ n 1 : n > 1, n N} { n+1 : n > 1, n N} R, endowed n n with the usual order and the discrete topology (indeed that is the induced Euclidean topology on X). Let us see that X fails to satisfy the lower Debreu property. To see this, let Y ={ n 1 : n > 1, n N} {2}. n Let us prove now that every strictly increasing map g : Y X has half-closed half-open gaps: For any n > 1, n N there must exist m(n) >n, m(n) N such that g( n 1 n ) = m(n) 1. Also, there must exist r > 1, r N such that g(2) = r+1. All this follows m(n) r from a cardinality argument: If for some k > 1, k N it holds that g( k 1 k ) = q+1 q, then, as there are infinitely many elements of Y that are bigger than k 1 and g is k increasing, we would obtain infinitely many terms of X that are bigger than q+1 q, but this is impossible (notice that only finitely many such elements are available). In the same way it is proved that g(2) cannot be of the form n 1 for any n > 1, n N. We n conclude that g gives raise to the Debreu gap [1, g(2)) that is half-closed half-open. To prove that X fails to satisfy the upper Debreu property we proceed in an entirely analogous manner, now taking Z ={0} { n+1 : n > 1, n N} and proving that n every strictly increasing map h : Z X has half-open half-closed gaps. Acknowledgements We want to express our gratitude to an anonymous referee, to whom we are indebted for the detailed reading of the manuscript and his/her very helpful suggestions and ideas.

15 Order (2006) 23: A preliminary version of this paper was presented at the Sixth Iberoamerican Congress of Topology and its Applications (CITA 2005), held in Puebla, Mexico in July Also, the ideas introduced in this paper were discussed with other participants in the International Mediterranean Congress of Mathematics (CIMMA 2005) held in Almería, Spain in June The authors are indebted to the colleagues that took part in the sections of Topology during such meetings. Thanks are also given to Professors G. Bosi (Trieste) and G. Herden (Essen) for their valuable comments related to this paper. This work has been partially supported by the research grant MTM (Spain). References 1. Aliprantis, Ch. D., Border, K.C.: Infinite Dimensional Analysis: A Hitchiker s Guide. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York (1999) 2. Beardon, A.F.: Debreu s gap theorem. Econ. Theory 2, (1992) 3. Beardon, A.F.: Utility theory and continuous monotonic functions. Econ. Theory 4, (1994) 4. Beardon, A.F., Candeal, J.C., Herden, G., Induráin, E., Mehta, G.B.: The non-existence of a utility function and the structure of non-representable preference relations. J. Math. Econ. 37, (2002) 5. Beardon, A.F., Mehta, G.B.: Utility functions and the order type of the continuum. J. Math. Econ. 23, (1994) 6. Birkhoff, G.: Lattice Theory (Third edition). American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI (1967) 7. Bosi G., Herden G.: On the structure of completely useful topologies. Appl. Gen. Topol. 3(2), (2002) 8. Bosi G., Mehta, G.B.: Existence of a semicontinuous or continuous utility function: a unified approach and an elementary proof. J. Math. Econ. 38, (2002) 9. Bridges, D.S., Mehta, G.B.: Representations of preference orderings. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York (1995) 10. Courant, R., Robbins, H.: What is Mathematics? Oxford University Press, London, UK (1941) 11. Debreu, G.: Representation if a preference ordering by a numerical function. In: Thrall, R., Coombs, C., Davies, R. (eds.) Decision Processes, pp Wiley, New York (1954) 12. Herden, G., Mehta, G.B.: Debreu s Gap Lemma for Semicontinuous Utility Functions (Preprint). Universität GH Essen and University of Queensland (2003a) 13. Herden, G., Mehta, G.B.: Semicontinuous Utility Functions (Preprint). Universität GH Essen and University of Queensland (2003b) 14. Herden, G., Mehta, G.B.: The Debreu gap lemma and some generalizations. J. Math. Econ. 40(7), (2004) 15. Jech, T.: Set Theory. Academic, New York (1978) 16. Liouville, J.: Sur des classes très étendues de quantités dont la valeur n est ni algébrique ni même réductible à des traditionnelles algébriques. Comptes Rendus de l Académie des Sciences de Paris 18, (1844) 17. Mahler, K.: On the approximation of π. Proceedings of the Nederland Akademie Wetenschappen, Series A 56, (1953) 18. Mehta, G.B.: Preference and utility. In: Barberà, S., Hammond, P., Seidl, C. (eds.) Handbook of Utility Theory, pp Kluwer, Dordrecht (1998) 19. Oxtoby, J.C.: Measure and Category (Second edition). Springer, New York (1980)

Existence of Order-Preserving Functions for Nontotal Fuzzy Preference Relations under Decisiveness

Existence of Order-Preserving Functions for Nontotal Fuzzy Preference Relations under Decisiveness axioms Article Existence of Order-Preserving Functions for Nontotal Fuzzy Preference elations under Decisiveness Paolo Bevilacqua 1 ID, Gianni Bosi 2, *, ID and Magalì Zuanon 3 1 Dipartimento di Ingegneria

More information

The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results)

The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results) The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results) Ehrhard Behrends Abstract A metric space (M, d) is said to have the small ball property (sbp) if for every ε 0 > 0 there exists a sequence

More information

Chapter 8. P-adic numbers. 8.1 Absolute values

Chapter 8. P-adic numbers. 8.1 Absolute values Chapter 8 P-adic numbers Literature: N. Koblitz, p-adic Numbers, p-adic Analysis, and Zeta-Functions, 2nd edition, Graduate Texts in Mathematics 58, Springer Verlag 1984, corrected 2nd printing 1996, Chap.

More information

OUTER MEASURE AND UTILITY

OUTER MEASURE AND UTILITY ECOLE POLYTECHNIQUE CENTRE NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE OUTER MEASURE AND UTILITY Mark VOORNEVELD Jörgen W. WEIBULL October 2008 Cahier n 2008-28 DEPARTEMENT D'ECONOMIE Route de Saclay 91128 PALAISEAU

More information

Richter-Peleg multi-utility representations of preorders

Richter-Peleg multi-utility representations of preorders Richter-Peleg multi-utility representations of preorders José Carlos R. Alcantud a, Gianni Bosi b,, Magalì Zuanon c a Facultad de Economía y Empresa and Multidisciplinary Institute of Enterprise (IME),

More information

Documentos de trabajo. A full characterization of representable preferences. J. Dubra & F. Echenique

Documentos de trabajo. A full characterization of representable preferences. J. Dubra & F. Echenique Documentos de trabajo A full characterization of representable preferences J. Dubra & F. Echenique Documento No. 12/00 Diciembre, 2000 A Full Characterization of Representable Preferences Abstract We fully

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

Extension of continuous functions in digital spaces with the Khalimsky topology

Extension of continuous functions in digital spaces with the Khalimsky topology Extension of continuous functions in digital spaces with the Khalimsky topology Erik Melin Uppsala University, Department of Mathematics Box 480, SE-751 06 Uppsala, Sweden melin@math.uu.se http://www.math.uu.se/~melin

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY by arxiv:170109087v1 [mathca] 9 Jan 017 MAGNUS D LADUE 0 Abstract In [1] Grossman Turett define the Cantor game In [] Matt Baker proves several results

More information

Existence of a Limit on a Dense Set, and. Construction of Continuous Functions on Special Sets

Existence of a Limit on a Dense Set, and. Construction of Continuous Functions on Special Sets Existence of a Limit on a Dense Set, and Construction of Continuous Functions on Special Sets REU 2012 Recap: Definitions Definition Given a real-valued function f, the limit of f exists at a point c R

More information

VARIETIES OF ABELIAN TOPOLOGICAL GROUPS AND SCATTERED SPACES

VARIETIES OF ABELIAN TOPOLOGICAL GROUPS AND SCATTERED SPACES Bull. Austral. Math. Soc. 78 (2008), 487 495 doi:10.1017/s0004972708000877 VARIETIES OF ABELIAN TOPOLOGICAL GROUPS AND SCATTERED SPACES CAROLYN E. MCPHAIL and SIDNEY A. MORRIS (Received 3 March 2008) Abstract

More information

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Peter J. Cameron and D. Lockett School of Mathematical Sciences Queen Mary, University of London Mile End Road London E1 4NS, U.K. Abstract Jarik Nešetřil suggested

More information

Whitney topology and spaces of preference relations. Abstract

Whitney topology and spaces of preference relations. Abstract Whitney topology and spaces of preference relations Oleksandra Hubal Lviv National University Michael Zarichnyi University of Rzeszow, Lviv National University Abstract The strong Whitney topology on the

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES

COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES Karin DLASKA, Nurettin ERGUN and Maximilian GANSTER Abstract In this paper we introduce the class of countably S-closed spaces which lies between the familiar classes of S-closed

More information

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3 Analysis Math Notes Study Guide Real Analysis Contents Ordered Fields 2 Ordered sets and fields 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts 2 Metric Spaces 3 Metric Spaces 3 Definitions 4 Separability

More information

1 Measure and Category on the Line

1 Measure and Category on the Line oxtoby.tex September 28, 2011 Oxtoby: Measure and Category Notes from [O]. 1 Measure and Category on the Line Countable sets, sets of first category, nullsets, the theorems of Cantor, Baire and Borel Theorem

More information

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Chapter : Logic Topics:. Statements, Negation, and Compound Statements.2 Truth Tables and Logical Equivalences.3

More information

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Fundamenta Informaticae 69 (2006) 1 20 1 IOS Press On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Lirong Xia State Key Laboratory of Intelligent Technology and Systems Department of Computer Science

More information

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers Page 1 Theorems Wednesday, May 9, 2018 12:53 AM Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property Suppose is an ordered set with the least-upper-bound property Suppose, and is bounded below be the set of lower

More information

B 1 = {B(x, r) x = (x 1, x 2 ) H, 0 < r < x 2 }. (a) Show that B = B 1 B 2 is a basis for a topology on X.

B 1 = {B(x, r) x = (x 1, x 2 ) H, 0 < r < x 2 }. (a) Show that B = B 1 B 2 is a basis for a topology on X. Math 6342/7350: Topology and Geometry Sample Preliminary Exam Questions 1. For each of the following topological spaces X i, determine whether X i and X i X i are homeomorphic. (a) X 1 = [0, 1] (b) X 2

More information

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries Chapter 1 Measure Spaces 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets 1.1.1 Notation and preliminaries We shall denote by X a nonempty set, by P(X) the set of all parts (i.e., subsets) of X, and by the empty set.

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, 2017 1 Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski Class of August 17: Course and syllabus overview. Topology

More information

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS BRIAN OSSERMAN We discuss the inverse limit construction, and consider the special case of inverse limits of finite groups, which should best be considered as topological

More information

Math 676. A compactness theorem for the idele group. and by the product formula it lies in the kernel (A K )1 of the continuous idelic norm

Math 676. A compactness theorem for the idele group. and by the product formula it lies in the kernel (A K )1 of the continuous idelic norm Math 676. A compactness theorem for the idele group 1. Introduction Let K be a global field, so K is naturally a discrete subgroup of the idele group A K and by the product formula it lies in the kernel

More information

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand KC Border Revised Fall 2011; Winter 2017 Preferences For the purposes of this note, a preference relation

More information

THE CLOSED-POINT ZARISKI TOPOLOGY FOR IRREDUCIBLE REPRESENTATIONS. K. R. Goodearl and E. S. Letzter

THE CLOSED-POINT ZARISKI TOPOLOGY FOR IRREDUCIBLE REPRESENTATIONS. K. R. Goodearl and E. S. Letzter THE CLOSED-POINT ZARISKI TOPOLOGY FOR IRREDUCIBLE REPRESENTATIONS K. R. Goodearl and E. S. Letzter Abstract. In previous work, the second author introduced a topology, for spaces of irreducible representations,

More information

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions 1. Suppose k is a positive integer. Use induction to prove the following two statements. (a) For all n N 0, the inequality (k 2 + n)! k 2n holds.

More information

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005 POL502: Foundations Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University October 10, 2005 Our first task is to develop the foundations that are necessary for the materials covered in this course. 1

More information

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees Francesc Rosselló 1, Gabriel Valiente 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Research Institute

More information

P.S. Gevorgyan and S.D. Iliadis. 1. Introduction

P.S. Gevorgyan and S.D. Iliadis. 1. Introduction MATEMATIČKI VESNIK MATEMATIQKI VESNIK 70, 2 (208), 0 9 June 208 research paper originalni nauqni rad GROUPS OF GENERALIZED ISOTOPIES AND GENERALIZED G-SPACES P.S. Gevorgyan and S.D. Iliadis Abstract. The

More information

Group construction in geometric C-minimal non-trivial structures.

Group construction in geometric C-minimal non-trivial structures. Group construction in geometric C-minimal non-trivial structures. Françoise Delon, Fares Maalouf January 14, 2013 Abstract We show for some geometric C-minimal structures that they define infinite C-minimal

More information

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2. MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2. This text is based on the following books: Topology by James Dugundgji Fundamental concepts of topology by Peter O Neil Elements of Mathematics: General Topology

More information

2 RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 We thank the referee for a number of useful comments. We need the following result: Theorem 0.1. [2]

2 RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 We thank the referee for a number of useful comments. We need the following result: Theorem 0.1. [2] CHARACTERIZING! 1 AND THE LONG LINE BY THEIR TOPOLOGICAL ELEMENTARY REFLECTIONS RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 Abstract. Given a topological space hx; T i 2 M; an elementary submodel of

More information

1 of 8 7/15/2009 3:43 PM Virtual Laboratories > 1. Foundations > 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 6. Cardinality Definitions and Preliminary Examples Suppose that S is a non-empty collection of sets. We define a relation

More information

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Chapter One. The Real Number System Chapter One. The Real Number System We shall give a quick introduction to the real number system. It is imperative that we know how the set of real numbers behaves in the way that its completeness and

More information

Topologies, ring norms and algebra norms on some algebras of continuous functions.

Topologies, ring norms and algebra norms on some algebras of continuous functions. Topologies, ring norms and algebra norms on some algebras of continuous functions. Javier Gómez-Pérez Javier Gómez-Pérez, Departamento de Matemáticas, Universidad de León, 24071 León, Spain. Corresponding

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University February 7, 2007 2 Contents 1 Metric Spaces 1 1.1 Basic definitions...........................

More information

Introduction to generalized topological spaces

Introduction to generalized topological spaces @ Applied General Topology c Universidad Politécnica de Valencia Volume 12, no. 1, 2011 pp. 49-66 Introduction to generalized topological spaces Irina Zvina Abstract We introduce the notion of generalized

More information

Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9)

Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9) The University of Sydney School of Mathematics and Statistics Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9) MATH3961: Metric Spaces (Advanced) Semester 1, 2018 Web Page: http://www.maths.usyd.edu.au/u/ug/sm/math3961/

More information

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions vanrooijschikhof.tex April 25, 2018 van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions Notes from [vrs]. Introduction A monotone function is Riemann integrable. A continuous function is Riemann integrable.

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations D. R. Wilkins Academic Year 1996-7 1 Number Systems and Matrix Algebra Integers The whole numbers 0, ±1, ±2, ±3, ±4,...

More information

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets Countable and Uncountable Sets The concept of countability will be important in this course

More information

Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models

Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models Samuel Trautwein, Esther Röder, Giorgio Barozzi November 3, 20 Topology of Q p vs Topology of R Both R and Q p are normed fields and complete

More information

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS BJORN POONEN 1 Some terminology of set theory N := {0, 1, 2, 3, } Z := {, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, } Q := the set of rational numbers R := the set of real numbers C := the set of complex

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

Measures and Measure Spaces

Measures and Measure Spaces Chapter 2 Measures and Measure Spaces In summarizing the flaws of the Riemann integral we can focus on two main points: 1) Many nice functions are not Riemann integrable. 2) The Riemann integral does not

More information

Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications. Riemann integrability and Lebesgue measurability of the composite function

Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications. Riemann integrability and Lebesgue measurability of the composite function J. Math. Anal. Appl. 354 (2009) 229 233 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications www.elsevier.com/locate/jmaa Riemann integrability and Lebesgue measurability

More information

MATH 4200 HW: PROBLEM SET FOUR: METRIC SPACES

MATH 4200 HW: PROBLEM SET FOUR: METRIC SPACES MATH 4200 HW: PROBLEM SET FOUR: METRIC SPACES PETE L. CLARK 4. Metric Spaces (no more lulz) Directions: This week, please solve any seven problems. Next week, please solve seven more. Starred parts of

More information

NOTES ON DIOPHANTINE APPROXIMATION

NOTES ON DIOPHANTINE APPROXIMATION NOTES ON DIOPHANTINE APPROXIMATION Jan-Hendrik Evertse January 29, 200 9 p-adic Numbers Literature: N. Koblitz, p-adic Numbers, p-adic Analysis, and Zeta-Functions, 2nd edition, Graduate Texts in Mathematics

More information

s P = f(ξ n )(x i x i 1 ). i=1

s P = f(ξ n )(x i x i 1 ). i=1 Compactness and total boundedness via nets The aim of this chapter is to define the notion of a net (generalized sequence) and to characterize compactness and total boundedness by this important topological

More information

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz Algebraic Structures and Their Applications Vol. 2 No. 2 ( 2015 ), pp 57-66. z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) R. MOHAMADIAN Communicated by B. Davvaz Abstract. In this article we introduce the concept

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

Measure and Category. Marianna Csörnyei. ucahmcs

Measure and Category. Marianna Csörnyei.   ucahmcs Measure and Category Marianna Csörnyei mari@math.ucl.ac.uk http:/www.ucl.ac.uk/ ucahmcs 1 / 96 A (very short) Introduction to Cardinals The cardinality of a set A is equal to the cardinality of a set B,

More information

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS REAL AND COMPLE ANALYSIS Third Edition Walter Rudin Professor of Mathematics University of Wisconsin, Madison Version 1.1 No rights reserved. Any part of this work can be reproduced or transmitted in any

More information

ON SPACE-FILLING CURVES AND THE HAHN-MAZURKIEWICZ THEOREM

ON SPACE-FILLING CURVES AND THE HAHN-MAZURKIEWICZ THEOREM ON SPACE-FILLING CURVES AND THE HAHN-MAZURKIEWICZ THEOREM ALEXANDER KUPERS Abstract. These are notes on space-filling curves, looking at a few examples and proving the Hahn-Mazurkiewicz theorem. This theorem

More information

EQUIVALENCE OF TOPOLOGIES AND BOREL FIELDS FOR COUNTABLY-HILBERT SPACES

EQUIVALENCE OF TOPOLOGIES AND BOREL FIELDS FOR COUNTABLY-HILBERT SPACES EQUIVALENCE OF TOPOLOGIES AND BOREL FIELDS FOR COUNTABLY-HILBERT SPACES JEREMY J. BECNEL Abstract. We examine the main topologies wea, strong, and inductive placed on the dual of a countably-normed space

More information

P-Spaces and the Prime Spectrum of Commutative Semirings

P-Spaces and the Prime Spectrum of Commutative Semirings International Mathematical Forum, 3, 2008, no. 36, 1795-1802 P-Spaces and the Prime Spectrum of Commutative Semirings A. J. Peña Departamento de Matemáticas, Facultad Experimental de Ciencias, Universidad

More information

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS Chapter 6 MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS This chapter can be considered enrichment material containing also several more advanced topics and may be skipped in its entirety. You can proceed directly

More information

A Short Review of Cardinality

A Short Review of Cardinality Christopher Heil A Short Review of Cardinality November 14, 2017 c 2017 Christopher Heil Chapter 1 Cardinality We will give a short review of the definition of cardinality and prove some facts about the

More information

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS NATHAN BOWLER AND STEFAN GESCHKE Abstract. We extend the notion of a uniform matroid to the infinitary case and construct, using weak fragments of Martin s Axiom,

More information

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces Chapter 2 Metric Spaces The purpose of this chapter is to present a summary of some basic properties of metric and topological spaces that play an important role in the main body of the book. 2.1 Metrics

More information

MAPPING CHAINABLE CONTINUA ONTO DENDROIDS

MAPPING CHAINABLE CONTINUA ONTO DENDROIDS MAPPING CHAINABLE CONTINUA ONTO DENDROIDS PIOTR MINC Abstract. We prove that every chainable continuum can be mapped into a dendroid such that all point-inverses consist of at most three points. In particular,

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS

INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS STEVEN P. LALLEY AND ANDREW NOBEL Abstract. It is shown that there are no consistent decision rules for the hypothesis testing problem

More information

Homogeneity and rigidity in Erdős spaces

Homogeneity and rigidity in Erdős spaces Comment.Math.Univ.Carolin. 59,4(2018) 495 501 495 Homogeneity and rigidity in Erdős spaces KlaasP.Hart, JanvanMill To the memory of Bohuslav Balcar Abstract. The classical Erdős spaces are obtained as

More information

LOCAL CONNECTEDNESS AND CONNECTED OPEN FUNCTIONS

LOCAL CONNECTEDNESS AND CONNECTED OPEN FUNCTIONS PORTUGALIAE MATHEMATICA Vol. 53 Fasc. 4 1996 LOCAL CONNECTEDNESS AND CONNECTED OPEN FUNCTIONS J.J. Charatonik Abstract: Localized versions are proved of some results concerning preservation of local connectivity

More information

Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment

Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment Lukasz Balbus Kevin Reffett Lukasz Woźny April 2014 Abstract Recently Yang and Qi (2013) stated an interesting theorem on existence of complete

More information

Introduction to Topology

Introduction to Topology Introduction to Topology Randall R. Holmes Auburn University Typeset by AMS-TEX Chapter 1. Metric Spaces 1. Definition and Examples. As the course progresses we will need to review some basic notions about

More information

On α-embedded subsets of products

On α-embedded subsets of products European Journal of Mathematics 2015) 1:160 169 DOI 10.1007/s40879-014-0018-0 RESEARCH ARTICLE On α-embedded subsets of products Olena Karlova Volodymyr Mykhaylyuk Received: 22 May 2014 / Accepted: 19

More information

Strictly monotonic preferences on continuum of goods commodity spaces

Strictly monotonic preferences on continuum of goods commodity spaces Strictly monotonic preferences on continuum of goods commodity spaces Carlos Hervés-Beloso RGEA. Universidad de Vigo. Paulo K. Monteiro Fundação Getúlio Vargas. VI Encuentro de Análisis Funcional y Aplicaciones

More information

The Lebesgue Integral

The Lebesgue Integral The Lebesgue Integral Brent Nelson In these notes we give an introduction to the Lebesgue integral, assuming only a knowledge of metric spaces and the iemann integral. For more details see [1, Chapters

More information

THE GEOMETRY OF CONVEX TRANSITIVE BANACH SPACES

THE GEOMETRY OF CONVEX TRANSITIVE BANACH SPACES THE GEOMETRY OF CONVEX TRANSITIVE BANACH SPACES JULIO BECERRA GUERRERO AND ANGEL RODRIGUEZ PALACIOS 1. Introduction Throughout this paper, X will denote a Banach space, S S(X) and B B(X) will be the unit

More information

A Countably-Based Domain Representation of a Non-Regular Hausdorff Space

A Countably-Based Domain Representation of a Non-Regular Hausdorff Space A Countably-Based Domain Representation of a Non-Regular Hausdorff Space Harold Bennett and David Lutzer April 4, 2006 Abstract In this paper we give an example of a countably-based algebraic domain D

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

Chapter 3 Continuous Functions

Chapter 3 Continuous Functions Continuity is a very important concept in analysis. The tool that we shall use to study continuity will be sequences. There are important results concerning the subsets of the real numbers and the continuity

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

MATH 54 - TOPOLOGY SUMMER 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION. Problem 1

MATH 54 - TOPOLOGY SUMMER 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION. Problem 1 MATH 54 - TOPOLOGY SUMMER 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION ELEMENTS OF SOLUTION Problem 1 1. Let X be a Hausdorff space and K 1, K 2 disjoint compact subsets of X. Prove that there exist disjoint open sets U 1 and

More information

CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES

CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES XI CHEN Abstract. Following Kukie la, we show how to generalize some results from May s book [4] concerning cores of finite spaces to cores of Alexandroff spaces. It turns out

More information

Reflexive cum Coreflexive Subcategories in Topology*

Reflexive cum Coreflexive Subcategories in Topology* Math. Ann. 195, 168--174 (1972) ~) by Springer-Verlag 1972 Reflexive cum Coreflexive Subcategories in Topology* V. KANNAN The notions of reflexive and coreflexive subcategories in topology have received

More information

Linear distortion of Hausdorff dimension and Cantor s function

Linear distortion of Hausdorff dimension and Cantor s function Collect. Math. 57, 2 (2006), 93 20 c 2006 Universitat de Barcelona Linear distortion of Hausdorff dimension and Cantor s function O. Dovgoshey and V. Ryazanov Institute of Applied Mathematics and Mechanics,

More information

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem Set 2: s Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem 1. (a) Prove that a closed subset of a complete metric space is complete. (b) Prove that a closed subset of a compact metric space is compact. (c) Prove that

More information

Semicocycle extensions and the stroboscopic property

Semicocycle extensions and the stroboscopic property Topology and its Applications 153 (2005) 97 106 www.elsevier.com/locate/topol Semicocycle extensions and the stroboscopic property Tomasz Downarowicz, Jacek Serafin Institute of Mathematics, Technical

More information

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION Introduction to Proofs in Analysis updated December 5, 2016 By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION Purpose. These notes intend to introduce four main notions from

More information

ATOMIC AND AP SEMIGROUP RINGS F [X; M], WHERE M IS A SUBMONOID OF THE ADDITIVE MONOID OF NONNEGATIVE RATIONAL NUMBERS. Ryan Gipson and Hamid Kulosman

ATOMIC AND AP SEMIGROUP RINGS F [X; M], WHERE M IS A SUBMONOID OF THE ADDITIVE MONOID OF NONNEGATIVE RATIONAL NUMBERS. Ryan Gipson and Hamid Kulosman International Electronic Journal of Algebra Volume 22 (2017) 133-146 DOI: 10.24330/ieja.325939 ATOMIC AND AP SEMIGROUP RINGS F [X; M], WHERE M IS A SUBMONOID OF THE ADDITIVE MONOID OF NONNEGATIVE RATIONAL

More information

Numerical representations of binary relations with thresholds: A brief survey 1

Numerical representations of binary relations with thresholds: A brief survey 1 Numerical representations of binary relations with thresholds: A brief survey 1 Fuad Aleskerov Denis Bouyssou Bernard Monjardet 11 July 2006, Revised 8 January 2007 Typos corrected 1 March 2008 Additional

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

Houston Journal of Mathematics. c 1999 University of Houston Volume 25, No. 4, 1999

Houston Journal of Mathematics. c 1999 University of Houston Volume 25, No. 4, 1999 Houston Journal of Mathematics c 1999 University of Houston Volume 25, No. 4, 1999 FINITISTIC SPACES AND DIMENSION YASUNAO HATTORI Communicated by Jun-iti Nagata Abstract. We shall consider two dimension-like

More information

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi Real Analysis Math 3AH Rudin, Chapter # Dominique Abdi.. If r is rational (r 0) and x is irrational, prove that r + x and rx are irrational. Solution. Assume the contrary, that r+x and rx are rational.

More information

Measures. 1 Introduction. These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland.

Measures. 1 Introduction. These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland. Measures These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland. 1 Introduction Our motivation for studying measure theory is to lay a foundation

More information

1.A Topological spaces The initial topology is called topology generated by (f i ) i I.

1.A Topological spaces The initial topology is called topology generated by (f i ) i I. kechris.tex December 12, 2012 Classical descriptive set theory Notes from [Ke]. 1 1 Polish spaces 1.1 Topological and metric spaces 1.A Topological spaces The initial topology is called topology generated

More information

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS MARCIN KYSIAK AND TOMASZ WEISS Abstract. We discuss the question which properties of smallness in the sense of measure and category (e.g. being a universally

More information

GENERALIZED CANTOR SETS AND SETS OF SUMS OF CONVERGENT ALTERNATING SERIES

GENERALIZED CANTOR SETS AND SETS OF SUMS OF CONVERGENT ALTERNATING SERIES Journal of Applied Analysis Vol. 7, No. 1 (2001), pp. 131 150 GENERALIZED CANTOR SETS AND SETS OF SUMS OF CONVERGENT ALTERNATING SERIES M. DINDOŠ Received September 7, 2000 and, in revised form, February

More information

2.2 Some Consequences of the Completeness Axiom

2.2 Some Consequences of the Completeness Axiom 60 CHAPTER 2. IMPORTANT PROPERTIES OF R 2.2 Some Consequences of the Completeness Axiom In this section, we use the fact that R is complete to establish some important results. First, we will prove that

More information

Construction of a general measure structure

Construction of a general measure structure Chapter 4 Construction of a general measure structure We turn to the development of general measure theory. The ingredients are a set describing the universe of points, a class of measurable subsets along

More information