Nonsensitivity, Stability, NIP, and Non-SOP; Model Theoretic Properties of Formulas in Continuous Logic. Karim Khanaki

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Nonsensitivity, Stability, NIP, and Non-SOP; Model Theoretic Properties of Formulas in Continuous Logic. Karim Khanaki"

Transcription

1 Nonsensitivity, Stability, NIP, and Non-SOP; Model Theoretic Properties of Formulas in Continuous Logic Karim Khanaki Faculty of Fundamental Sciences, Arak University of Technology, P.O. Box , Arak, Iran; School of Mathematics, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences (IPM), P.O. Box , Tehran, Iran; Abstract We characterize SOP, NIP, and stability in terms of topological and measure theoretical properties of classes of functions in continuous logic. We show that a formula φ(x, y) has the strict order property if there are a i s such that the sequence φ(x, a i ) is pointwise convergence but its it is not sequentially continuous. We deduce from this a theorem of Shelah: a theory is unstable iff it has the IP or the SOP. We study a measure theoretic property, Talagrand s stability, and explain the relationship between it and the NIP in continuous logic. This makes clear that Talagrand s stability is the correct counterpart of NIP in integral logic. Then we study forking and independence in stable and NIP theories, and their connections to measure theory. We also study sensitive families of functions and chaotic maps and their connections with stability. Keywords: Sensitivity, chaotic function, integral logic, local stability, independence property, strict order property, continuous logic AMS subject classification: 03B48, 03C45, 28C10, 43A07 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Continuous Logic Syntax and semantics Compactness Types Stability 6 4 NIP Talagrand s stability NIP in Continuous Logic Almost definability of types in NIP theories

2 5 Forking and independence relation Non-forking and stability Properties of non-forking Almost non-forking and NIP Properties of almost non-forking The number of coheirs SOP NIP+Non-SOP = Stable Definability of types and Fréchet-Urysohn spaces The Eberlein-Šmulian theorem and NIP/Non-SOP First order logic is angelic Sensitivity and chaotic maps 22 8 Appendix 23 References 25 1 Introduction Shelah s stability theory essentially leads to classifying the special properties of formulas in which the number of types (or models) can be controlled by them. The set-theoretic criteria largely pass over in favor of definitions which mention ranks or combinatorial properties of a particular formula. Up to present time there are a few properties of formulas in which their definitions are in terms of topological (or analysis) concepts. Maybe the discrete nature of formulas in classical model theory is its cause. For example, a formula φ(x, y) has the order property if there exist a i, b j, i, j < ω such that φ(a i, b j ) if and only if i < j. One can assume that φ is a 0-1 valued function, then φ has the order property iff there exist a i, b j such that i j φ(a i, b j ) = 1 0 = j i φ(a i, b j ). Therefore stability is equivalent to the absence of two different double its. The latter is a topological property of a class of functions by Grothendieck s criterion [Gro52]. What happen if we study real valued formulas? One might therefore hope to obtain new classes of functions (formulas) and develop a sharper stability theory by making use of topological properties of Stone spaces instead of only their cardinalities. In Mathematics, more exactly Analysis, the set X R of all real-valued functions on a topological space X can be classified by many classes such as differentiable, continuous, Baire, Borel, measurable and so on. A function belongs to a special class if it satisfies a desirable property. We know that the class of continues function is not closed for pointwise topology; there are sequences of continuous functions such that their poinwise its are not continuous. In classical model theory, we classify not only sets of real-valued functions (or formulas) on a specific space X, but that we study the (first order) properties so that a set A has the property P if (i) the closure A of A is a compact subset of a suitable set A P, (ii) every element of A is a closure of a small subset of A. For example, we study the 2

3 sets of continuous functions such that the pointwise closure of their elements are again continuous, and every point in the closures is a it of a sequence of the elements of those sets. In model theory, the later classes are called stable. Let us explain further. In this paper we work in Continuous Logic which is an extension of classical first order logic, and therefore our results hold for classical case. Let M be an L-structure in this logic. A maximal set of formulas in L(M) which is finitely satisfiable in a model of T h(m) is called a complete type. By Kakutani representation theorem of M-spaces, there is a compact Hausdorff space S(M), is called the space of types, such that every type is realized in S(M). Then for every formula φ, there is a continuous function f φ : S(M) R which is an extension of the interpretation of formula φ(x) in M. By a result of Grothendieck, it is known that a subset A of real-valued functions on on M (or S(M)) is stable if and only if it is relatively compact in C(S(M)) for the topology of poinwise convergence, where C(S(M)) is the space of all continuous functions on S(M). In fact, one can continue this pattern for the NIP. By a result of Bourgain, Fremlin and Talagrand (short BFT), we show that the set A has the NIP if and only if the pointwise closure of A is a set of measurable functions for all Radon measures on S(M). In fact, the role played by the Grothendieck s criterion in stable theories is mirrored in NIP theories by the result of BFT. This is not the end of the story, we give a notation of non-forking extension in NIP theories, we call almost non-forking, such that it satisfy symmetry and transitivity. Moreover, in stable cases, this notation is consistence with the classical notation. We study the strict order property (short SOP) and show that a formula φ(x, y) has the strict order property if there are a i s such that the sequence φ(x, a i ) is pointwise convergence but its it is not sequentially continuous. We deduce from this a theorem of Shelah: a theory is unstable iff it has the IP or the SOP. Then we show that the theorem definability of types in stable theories is equivalent to the Fréchet-Urysohn property, and Shelah s theorem is equivalent to the Eberlein-Šmulian theorem. Finally, we study sensitive families of functions and chaotic maps and their connections with stability. At the end, it is worth stating that many of results in this paper holds in other realvalued logics, such as integral logic, operator logic, and so on. 2 Continuous Logic In this section we give a brief review of continuous logic from [BU10] and [BBHU08]. Results stated without proof can be found there. Readers familiar with continuous logic can go to the next section. 2.1 Syntax and semantics A Language is a set L consisting of constant symbols and function/relation symbols of various arities. To each relation symbol R is assigned a bound R 0 and we assume that its interpretations is bounded by R. It is always assumed that L contains the metric symbol d and d = 1. We use R as value space and its common operations +, and 3

4 scalar products as connectives. Moreover to each relation symbol R (function symbol F ) is assigned a modulus of uniform continuity R ( F ). We also use the symbols sup and inf as quantifiers. Let L be a language. L-terms and their bound are inductively define as follows: Constant symbols and variables are terms If F is a n-ary function symbol and t 1,..., t n are terms, then F (t 1,..., t n ) is a term. All L-terms are constructed in this way. Definition 2.1 L-formulas and their bounds are inductively defined as follows: Every r R is an atomic formula with bound r. If R is a n-ary relation symbol and t 1,..., t n are terms, R(t 1,..., t n ) is an atomic formula with bound R. If φ, ψ are formula and r R then φ + ψ, φ ψ and rφ are formula with bound resp φ + ψ, φ ψ, r φ. If φ is a formula and x is a variable, sup x φ and inf x φ are formulas with the same bound as φ. Definition 2.2 A perstructure in L is pseudo-metric space (M, d) equipped with: for each constant symbol c L, an element c M M for each n-ary function symbol F a function F M : M n M such that d M n ( x, ȳ) F (ɛ) = d M (F M ( x), F M (ȳ)) ɛ for each n-ary relation symbol R a function R M : M n [ R, R ] such that d M n ( x, ȳ) R (ɛ) = R M ( x) R M (ȳ) ɛ. If M is a prestructure, for each formula φ( x) and ā M, φ M (ā) is defined inductively starting from atomic formulas. In particular, (sup y φ) M (ā) = sup b M φ M (ā, b). Similar for inf y φ. Proposition 2.3 Let M be an L-prestructure and φ( x) a formula with x = n. Then φ M ( x) is a real valued function on M n with a modulus of uniform continuity φ and φ M (ā) φ for every ā. Interesting prestructures are those which are complete metric spaces. They are called L-structures. Every prestructure can be easily transformed to a complete L-structure by first taking the quotient metric and then completing the resulting metric space. By uniform continuity, interpretations of function and relation symbols induce well-defined function and relations on the resulting metric space (cf. [BU10]). 4

5 2.2 Compactness Let L be a language. An expression of the form φ ψ, where φ, ψ are formulas, is called a condition. The equality φ = ψ is called a condition again. These conditions are called closed if φ, ψ are sentences. A theory is a set of closed conditions. The notion M T is defined in the obvious way. M is then called a model of T. A theory is satisfiable if has a model. In [BBHU08], a variant of the ultraproduct constructon is defined. The most important application of this construction in logic is to prove the Loś theorem and to deduce the compactness theorem. Theorem 2.4 (Compactness Theorem) Let T be an L-theory and C a class of L- structures. Assume that T is finitely satisfiable in C. Then there exists an ultraproduct of structures from C that is a model of T. 2.3 Types There is a intrinsic connection between some concepts from functional analysis and continuous logic. In fact, types are well-known mathematical objects, Riesz homomorphisms. For showing of this connection, one can use two results in functional analysis, Gelfand representation of C -algebras and Kakutani representation of M-spaces. Here we work in a real-valued logic, therefore we use the later. Suppose that L is an arbitrary language. Let M be an L-structure, A M and T A = T h(m, a) a A. Let p(x) be a set of L(A)-statements in free variable x. We shall say that p(x) is a type over A if p(x) T A is satisfiable. A complete type over A is a maximal type over A. We let S M (A) be the set of all complete types over A. The type of a in M over A, denoted by tp M (a/a), is the set of all L(A)-statements satisfied in M by a. We give a characterization of complete types. First we need some definitions. Let L A be the family of all interpretations φ M in M where φ is an L(A)-formula (not a condition) with a free variable x. L A is an Archimedean Riesz space of measurable functions on M. Let σ A (M) be the set of Riesz homomorphisms I : L A R such that I(1) = 1. The set σ A (M) is called the spectrum of T A. Note that σ A (M) is a weak* compact subset of L A. The next proposition shows that a complete type can be coded by a Riesz homomorphism and gives a characterization of complete types. In fact, by Kakutani representation theorem, the map S M (A) σ A (M), defined by p I p where I p (φ M ) = r if φ(x) = r is in p, is bijection. Proposition 2.5 Assume that M, A and T A are as above. (i) The map S M (A) σ A (M) defined by p I p is bijection. (ii) p S M (A) if and only if there is an elementary extension N of M and a N such that p = tp N (a/a). 5

6 We equip S M (A) = σ A (M) with the related topology induced from L A. Therefore, S M (A) is a compact and Hausdorff space. For a complete type p = tp M (a/a) and a formula φ, we let φ(p) = φ M (a). It is easy to verify that the topology on S M (A) is the weakest topology in which all the functions p φ(p) are continuous. This topology sometimes called the logic topology. 3 Stability Definition 3.1 A formula φ(x, y) is called stable in a structure M if there are no r > s and infinite sequences a n, b n M such that for all i > j: φ(a i, b j ) r and φ(a j, b i ) s. A formula φ is stable in a theory T if it is stable in every model of T. It is easy to verify that φ(x, y) is stable in M if whenever a n, b n M form two sequences we have n m φ(a n, b m ) = m n φ(a n, b m ), provided both its exist. Fact 3.2 (Grothendieck s Criterion, [Gro52]) Let X be an arbitrary topological space, X 0 X a dense subset. Then the following are equivalent for a subset A C b (X): (i) The set A is relatively weakly compact in C b (X). (ii) The set A is bounded, and whenever f n A and x n X 0 form two sequences we have n m f n (x m ) = m n f n (x m ), whenever both its exists. Because we believe that the proof of Grothendieck s criterion in the case of compact spaces which is presented in [KN63, 8.18] is informative and useful we mention it in 8. Fact 3.3 (Fundamental Theorem of Stability) Let φ(x, y) be a formula and T a theory. Then the following are equivalent. (i) The formula φ is stable in T. (ii) For every model M T, every φ-type over M is definable by a φ-predicate over M. (iii) For each cardinal λ = κ ℵ 0 T, and model M T with M λ, S φ (M) λ. (iv) There exists a cardinal λ = κ ℵ 0 then S φ (M) λ. T such that for every model M T, M λ We give some definitions and results that we use later. 6

7 Definition 3.4 (Order property) A bounded family F of real valued functions on a set X has the (strong) order property (or short OP) if there exist real numbers s < r and an (infinite) sequence {f n } n F and {a m } m X such that either min m n f n (a m ) r and max m<n f n (a m ) s, or min m<n f n (a m ) r and max m n f n (a m ) s. F has the weak order property (or short wop) if there exist real numbers s < r and an (infinite) sequence {f n } n F and {a m } m X such that either inf m f n (a m ) r and sup n f n (a m ) s, or inf n f n (a m ) r and sup m f n (a m ) s. A formula φ has the (weak) order property in a model M if the family {φ(x, b), φ(a, y) : a, b M} has the (weak) order property. A formula φ has the (weak) order property in a theory T if it has the (weak) order property in a model of T. We note that if {f n } C(X), f n f pointwise, and {f n } n be ordered, then f is not sequential continuous. For this, we have Definition 3.5 Let X be a topological space. A family F C(X) has sequential continuous property (or short SCP) if for every convergence sequence {f n } n of F, its it is sequential continuous, i.e. if f n f pointwise, then there are not a m, a X such that a m a and m f(a m ) f(a). Later we show that the connection between the SCP and the strict order property. Now we give some simple lemmas that we use later. Lemma 3.6 Let X be compact and A C(X) be bounded. (i) Non-wOP = SCP. (ii) Stable = SCP. (iii) Stable = Non-OP. (iv): The formula φ(x, y) has Non-OP in theory T = φ(x, y) has SCP in T. (v): The formula φ(x, y) has Non-OP in theory T = φ(x, y) is stable in T. Therefore, in a theory T, stable Non-OP. Proof. (i): Assume that Non-SCP. Therefore there are f n A, a m X, such that f n f pointwise, and a m a but m f(a m ) f(a). Note that we can assume m f(a m ) exists, because we can find a subsequence a mk such that mk f(a mk ) exists. Therefore, m n f n (a m ) n m f n (a m ). Therefore, A has wop. (ii) Similar to (i). (iii): Assume that OP. Let f n A and a m X such that min m n f n (a m ) r and max m<n f n (a m ) s where s < r. By a technical result in [Rud64] (Theorem 7.23), since A is bounded and X is compact, we can assume that the its m n f n (a m ) and n m f n (a m ) exist. But they are not equal, and hence A is not stable. (iv): We use the notation f n (y) for φ(b n, y). Assume that φ has Non-SCP. Therefore there are f n A, a m X, such that f n f pointwise, and a m a but m f(a m ) s > r f(a). Then, by a selection argument, one can find subsequences {a mk } and {f nk } such that they are witnesses of the OP. Indeed, by induction, we assume that we find a 1,..., a n and {f k } k N such that max k i n f k (a i ) r and min m n<k f k (a m ) s. First, 7

8 without loss of generality we assume that f k (a) r for all k 0. If f k (a n+1 ) > r for some k n, then we omit a n+1 and take a n+1 := a m for some m > n + 1 such that f k (a m ) r for all k n. If f k (a n+1 ) < s for some k n + 1, then we can find a N > n + 1 such that f k (a n+1 ) s for each k N, and we take f n+1+i := f N+i for all i 0. And we continue in this way. Therefore, for each n, we can find a 1,..., a n and {b k } k N such that max m k φ(b k, a m ) r and min m<k φ(b k, a m ) s. Now, by the compactness theorem of model theory, φ has OP. (v)similar to (iv). Definition 3.7 We say that a (bounded) family F of real valued function on a set X has the convergence subsequence property (or short CSP) if for every sequence in F has a pointwise convergence subsequence in R X. Later we show that the connection between the CSP and the independence property. Lemma 3.8 (i) SCP + CSP = Non-wOP. (ii) Stable = Non-wOP. Proof. (i): Assume that wop and CSP(=every sequence in A has a pointwise convergence subsequence in R X ) hold. Therefore there are f n, a m and s < r such that inf m f n (a m ) r and sup n f n (a m ) s where s < r. We can assume that a m a. By CSP, there is a function f such that f n f pointwise. Therefore, f(a m ) = n f n (a m ) sup n f n (a m ) s. Since f n s are continuous, f n (a) = m f n (a m ) = inf m f n (a m ) r. Since X is compact and f is bounded, we can find a subsequence a mk such that {f(a mk )} mk be convergence, and a mk a. Therefore, mk f(a mk ) f(a). Therefore, A has not SCP. (ii): Similar to (i). 4 NIP In this section, first we study some concepts presented in [GM14] and give a new one that has a meaningful connection to stability, see (1) in below. Then we study Talagrand s stability and its relationship to the NIP in continuous logic. Finally, we give a variant of definability of types in NIP theories. Definition 4.1 ([GM14], Definition 2.1) Let (X, τ) be a topological space and ɛ a positive number. We say that a family of (not necessarily continuous) functions F = {f i : X R} i I is: (1) ɛ-non-sensitive in every point (ɛ-nse in short) if for every x X there exists an open subset O x x in X such that diam(f i (O x )) ɛ for every i I. (2) ɛ-non-sensitive (ɛ-ns in short) if there exists a non-void open subset O in X such that diam(f i (O)) ɛ for every i I. (3) Non-Sensitive (in every point) if F is ɛ-ns (ɛ-nse) for every ɛ > 0. 8

9 (4) ɛ-fragmented if for every nonempty closed subset A of X the restriction F A := {f A : A R} f F is an ɛ-ns family. (5) Fragmented, or Hereditarily Non-Sensitive, if F is ɛ-fr for every ɛ > 0. (6) Eventually Fragmented if for every infinite subfamily L F there exists an infinite fragmented subfamily K L. Lemma 4.2 Assume that X is a compact space, and F = {f i : X R} i I C(X) is bounded. Then (i) (ii). (i) ɛ-non-stability: F is ɛ-non-stable, i.e. there are f m s in F and x n s in X such that m n f n (x m ) n m f n (x m ) > ɛ. (ii) ɛ-sensitivity in a point: F is ɛ-sensitive in a point x X, i.e. for every non-void open subset O x in X, there exist some i I such that diam(f i (O)) > ɛ. Proof. (i)= (ii): Assume that F is ɛ-non-stable, and m n f n (x m ) n m f n (x m ) > ɛ. (By Theorem 2.16 in [GM14], we can assume that I is countable.) Assume that x m x. We claim that F is ɛ-sensitive in x. If not, there exists a non-void open subset O x in X such that diam(f i (O)) ɛ for every n I. Since x m x, we can assume that x m O for all m. Therefore, f n (x m ) f n (x) ɛ for all m, n. This contradicts with the ɛ-non-stability of F. (ii)= (i): See Proposition 3.5 in [Meg03]. We can give an explicit proof. Indeed, assume that F is ɛ-stable but it is ɛ-sensitive in x X. Let O n = {y : d(x, y) > ɛ} for all n. Then there exist some f n F such that diam(f n (O n )) > ɛ. Since O n O n+1, diam(f n (O k )) > ɛ for all k n. (For simplicity, we assume that F is stable.) By NIP, there is a sequential continuous function f such that f n f. Therefore, ɛ < m diam(f m (O n )) = diam(f(o n )) for all n. On that other hand, n diam(f(o n )) = diam(f({x})) = 0. But this is a contradiction. Remark 4.3 In the previous lemma ɛ -stability implies ɛ-non-sensitivity. If not: indeed, by ɛ-sensitivity, ɛ < m diam(f m (O n )) = sup y,z On m d(f m (y), f m (z)). Then by 2 Lemma 5.2 in [BBHU08], there exist y n, z n O n such that n sup y,z On m d(f m (y), f m (z)) = n m d(f m (y n ), f m (z n )). By ɛ -stability, 2 n m f m (y n ) m n f m (y n ) < ɛ 2 and n m f m (z n ) m n f m (z n ) < ɛ. Therefore, 2 n m d(f m (y n ), f m (z n )) = m n d(f m (y n ), f m (z n )) ɛ + ɛ. But this is a contradiction. 2 2 To summarize: ɛ-sensitive in a point ɛ/2-non-stable Definition 4.4 (Independence Property) A family F of real valued functions on a set X is said to be independent or has the independence property if there exist real numbers s < r and a sequence f n F such that for each k 1 and for each I {1,..., k}, there is x X with f i (x) s for i I and f i (x) r for i / I. A formula φ is independent in a model M if the family {φ(x, b), φ(a, y) : a, b M} is independent. A formula φ has the independence property in a theory T if it has dependence property in a model of T. 9

10 Fact 4.5 ([GM14], Theorem 2.11) Let X be a compact space and F C(X) a bounded subset. The following conditions are equivalent: (1) F does not contain an independent subsequence. (2) F does not contain a subsequence equivalent to the unit basis of l 1. (3) Each sequence in F has a pointwise convergent subsequence in R X. (4) F is a Rosenthal family for X. (5) F is an eventually fragmented family. Lemma 4.6 ([GM14], Lemma 7.9) Let {f n } be a bounded sequence of continuous functions on a topological space X. Let Y be a dense subset of X. Then {f n } is an independent sequence on X if and only if the sequence of restrictions {f n Y } is an independent sequence on Y. Proposition 4.7 (i) Non-OP = NIP. (ii) Non-OP = NIP + SCP. Proof. (i): Easy. By (i) and 3.6, the proof is completed. 4.1 Talagrand s stability Historically, Talagrands stability (see 4.8), which we call the almost independence property, arose naturally when Talagrand and Fremlin were studying pointwise compact sets of measurable functions; they found that in many cases a set of functions was relatively pointwise compact because it was stable (Fact 4.9). Later did it appear that the concept was connected with Glivenko-Cantelli classes in the theory of empirical measures, as explained in [Tal87]. In this subsection we study this property and show that it is the correct counterpart of NIP in integral logic (cf. [Kha14]). Then, we give the connection between the NIP in continuous logic and this property. Definition 4.8 (Talagrand stability, [Fre06]) Let A C(X) be a (not necessarily countable) pointwise bounded family of continuous functions from X to R. Suppose that µ is a measure on X. We say that A has the µ-almost non independence property, or short the µ-almost NIP, if A is a stable set of functions in the sense of Definition 465B in [Fre06], that is, whenever E M is measurable, µ(e) > 0 and s < r in R, there is some k 1 such that (µ 2k ) D k (A, E, s, r) < (µe) 2k where D k (A, E, s, r) = f A{w E 2k : f(w 2i ) s, f(w 2i+1 ) r for i < k}. We say that A has the universal almost non independence property, or short the universal almost NIP, if A has the µ-almost NIP for all Radon measure µ on X. Fact 4.9 ([Fre06, Proposition 465D]) Let X be a compact Housdorff space and A C(X) be a (not necessarily countable) pointwise bounded family of continuous functions 10

11 from X to R. Suppose that µ is a Radon measure on X. If A has the µ-almost NIP, then the poinwise closure of A, denoted by cl p (A), has the µ-almost NIP and every element in cl p (A) is µ-measurable. In [Fre75] Fremlin obtained an important result, which we call Fremlin s dichotomy. He proved that sets of measurable functions on perfect measure spaces are either good (relatively countably compact for the pointwise topology and relatively compact for the topology of convergence in measure) or bad (with neither property). (We recall that a subset A of a topological space X is relatively countably compact if every sequence of A has a cluster point in X.) Now, we remember this result: Theorem 4.10 (Fremlin s dichotomy, [Fre75]) Let (X, Σ, µ) be a perfect σ-finite measure space, and {f n } a sequence of real-valued measurable functions on X. Then either {f n } has a subsequence which is convergent almost everywhere or {f n } has a subsequence with no measurable cluster point in R X. Proposition 4.11 Let (X, Σ, µ) be a finite Radon measure on compact a space X, and A L 0 a bounded family of real-valued measurable functions on X. Then (i)= (ii). If A has the property (M) in [Tal87], i.e. for all s < r and all k, the set D k (A, X, r, s) be measurable (particularly A be countable), then (ii)= (i). (i)= (iii), but not(iii)= (i). (i) A has the µ-almost NIP. (ii) The following property, that we call ( ), fails: There exist measurable set E, µ(e) > 0 and s < r in R, such that for each n, and almost all w E n, for each subset I of {1,..., n}, there is f A with f(w i ) < s if i I and f(w i ) > r if i / I. (iii) Every sequence in A has a subsequence which is convergent almost everywhere. Proof. (i)= (ii): Clear. (M) (ii)= (i): Proposition 4 in [Tal87], or part (iii) of case 2 of the proof of 465L in [Fre06]. (i)= (iii): Assume that {f n } A. We take an arbitrary subsequence of it (still denoted by {f n }). Let D be a non-principal ultrafilter on N. Define f(x) = D f i (x) for all x X. (By assumption, there is a real number r such that for each h A, h r. Therefore, f is well defined.) Since A has the µ-almost NIP and f cl p ({f n }), the function f is measurable (cf. 456Db in [Fre06]). Therefore every subsequence of {f n } has a measurable cluster point. Then, by Fremlin s dichotomy, {f n } has a subsequence which is convergent almost everywhere. not(iii)= (i): In [SF93], Shelah and Fremlin find that in a model of set theory there is a separable pointwise compact set of real-valued Lebesgue measurable functions on the unit interval, which it is not stable. Professor Fremlin kindly pointed out to the author that Shelah s model, described in their paper [SF93], in fact deals with the point that there is a countable set of continuous 11

12 functions which is relatively pointwise compact in L 0 but that it is not R-stable. Of course this will not happen if a set be relatively pointwise compact in L 0 (µ) for each Radon measure µ: Proposition 4.12 Let X be compact and Hausdorff, and F C(X) be uniformly bounded. Then the following are equivalent: (i) F is NIP. (ii) Each sequence in F has a subsequence which is pointwise convergence. (iii) Each sequence in F has a subsequence which is µ-almost everywhere convergence for each Radon measure µ on X. (iv) For each Radon measure µ on X, each sequence in F has a subsequence which is µ-almost everywhere convergence. Proof. (i) (ii): This is the equivalence (ii) (vi) in Theorem 2F in [BFT78]. (i) (iii): By either Fremlin s dichotomy and the equivalence (v) (vi) in Theorem 2F in [BFT78], or 465X(a) in [Fre06] and the equivalence (ii) (vi) in Theorem 2F in [BFT78], the proof is completed. (i) (iv): This is the equivalence (v) (vi) in Theorem 2F in [BFT78] and Fremlin s dichotomy. 4.2 NIP in Continuous Logic The following fact shows that why the µ-almost NIP is the correct notation of the NIP for integral logic. First we review a definition in Continuous Logic. Let M be an L-structure in continuous logic, and φ(x; y) a formula. We say φ(x; y) has the non independent property (short the NIP) on M, in the sense of continuous logic, if for each sequence φ(a n, y) in the set A = {φ(a, y) : a M}, and r > s there is some I N such that {y S φ(y) (M) : ( i I φ(a i, y) < s ) ( i/ I φ(a i, y) > r ) } =, where S φ(y) (M) is the space of all complete φ(y)-types on M. Theorem 4.13 (Theorem 2F, [BFT78]) Let M be an L-structure in continuous logic, and φ(x; y) a formula. Let A = {φ(a, y) : a M} and à = {φ(x, b) : b M}. Then the following are equivalent: (i) φ has the NIP on M (in the sense of continuous logic). (ii) à has the µ-almost NIP for all Radon measures on M. Proof. (i)= (ii): By the NIP of φ(x; y) and the compactness theorem of continuous logic, there is some integer n such that no set of size n is shattered by φ(x, y). Therefore if E M, µ(e) > 0, r > s, then for each (a 1,..., a n ) E n there is a set I {1,..., n} such that {y S φ(y) (M) : ( φ(a i, y) < s ) ( φ(a i, y) > r )} =, i I where S φ(y) (M) is the space of all complete φ(y)-types on M. Therefore, the set A = {φ(x, b) : b S φ(y) (M)} (and particularly the set Ã) has the µ-almost NIP for all Radon 12 i/ I

13 measures on X = S φ(y) (M) (equivalently on M). (Note that by Theorem 465T in [Fre06], A has the µ-almost NIP if and only if every countable subset of A has the µ-almost NIP. Therefore, the conditions (i) and (ii) in 4.11 are equivalent.) (ii)= (i): Conversely, assume that à has the µ-almost NIP for all Radon measures on M (or equivalently on X = S φ(x) (M)). Therefore, by Fact 4.9, à is relatively compact in M r ( X) (the space of all µ-measurable functions on X for each Radon measure µ). By the equivalence (iv) (vi) in Theorem 2F in [BFT78], for each sequence φ(x, a n ) in Ã, and r < s, there is some I N such that {x S φ(x) (M) : ( φ(x, a i ) < s ) ( φ(x, a i ) > r )} =. i I Therefore, the set à (and equivalently the dual formula φ(y; x) := φ(x; y)) has the NIP on M (in the sense of continuous logic). So, by applying the direction (i)= (ii) on φ (equivalently on Ã), we conclude that à = A has the µ-almost NIP (for all Radon measures). Then, again by Theorem 2F in [BFT78], we conclude that A has the NIP in the sense of continuous logic. In fact the proof of the previous result says more: Corollary 4.14 (NIP duality) By the above assumptions, φ has the NIP if and only if φ has the NIP. Similarly, A has the µ-almost NIP (for all Radon measures µ) if and only if à has the µ-almost NIP (for all Radon measures µ). Consequently, φ has the NIP if and only if A has the µ-almost NIP (for all Radon measures µ). 4.3 Almost definability of types in NIP theories It is well-known that every type in a stable theories is definable. Here we want to give a counterpart of this fact for NIP theories. In [Kha14] the author showed that if a formula φ (in integral logic) has the µ-almost NIP on a model M, then every type in S φ (M) is µ-almost definable. Here we say a formula ψ is universally measurable on M, if it is µ-measurable for all probability Radon measures on M. We need some definitions from [Kha14]. Let ψ be a measurable function on (S φ (M), µ φ ) where µ φ is the unique Radon measure induced by φ M (x, b) for all b M. Then ψ is called an almost φ-definable relation over M if there is a sequence g n : S φ (M) R, g n φ, of continuous functions such that n g n (b) = ψ(b) for almost all b S φ (M). (We note that by the Stone-Weierstrass theorem every continuous function g n : S φ (M) R can be expressed as a uniform it of algebraic combinations of (at most countably many) functions of the form p φ(p, b), b M.) An almost definable relation ψ(y) over M defines p S φ (M) if φ(p, b) = ψ(b) for almost all b M, and in this case we say that p is almost definable. Assume that every type p in S φ (M) is almost definable by a measurable function ψ p. Then, we say that p is almost equal to q, denoted by p q, if ψ p (b) = ψ q (b) for almost all b M. Define [p] = {q S φ (M) : p q} and [S φ ](M) = {[p] : p S φ (M)}. Now by the above results it is easy to show that: 13 i/ I

14 Theorem 4.15 (Almost definability) Let φ(x, y) be a formula NIP in a structure M (in the sense of continuous logic). Then every p S φ (M) is almost definable by a (unique up to measures) universally measurable and almost φ-definable relation ψ(y) over M, where φ(y, x) = φ(x, y). Proof. See [Kha14]. In fact, by the BFT theorem, the converse of the above theorem holds: Theorem 4.16 Let T be a theory. Then the following are equivalent: (i) T is NIP. (ii) For every formula φ and M T, every type p S φ (M) is almost definable (for all Radon measures on M). 5 Forking and independence relation It is a known fact that in NIP theories, non-forking is not an independence relation, which means in particular that it does not satisfy symmetry and transitivity (see for example [Sim14a]). Historically, H. Jerome Keisler was the first person who discovered the relationship between forking, measures and NIP theories in the frame work of classical model theory. Almost a decade before that, Bourgain, Fremlin and Talagrand (short BFT) were shown the intrinsic connection between measures theory and the dependence property. In fact, the role played by the Grothendieck s criterion in stable theories is mirrored in NIP theories by a result of them. In this section we define non-forking extensions in two levels: stable and NIP theories. Then we show that non-forking is an independence relation in both levels. 5.1 Non-forking and stability A global type, is a type over the monster model U. Let A U and let p S x (U). We say that p is finitely satisfiable (finitely realized) in A if for every formula φ(x, a) = r p there exists c A such that U φ(c, a) = r. Definition 5.1 Let T be stable, A U, and p S x (U). We say that p does not fork over A if p is finitely satisfiable in every model containing A. Construction. Let A = {a i : i < κ} U be a small set and D be an ultrafilter on κ. We define global type p D S(U) by: p D φ(x, b) = r {i : U φ(a i, b) = r} D, for each formula φ(x, b) = r L(U). Then p D is finitely satisfiable in A. Conversely, every global type finitely satisfiable in A is equal to p D for some (not necessarily unique) ultrafilter D. In particular note that if we take D to be a principal ultrafilter, then we obtain a realized type. 14

15 If p 0 S x (M) is a type, then a coheir of p 0 is a global extension p of p 0 which is finitely satisfiable in M, i.e. p 0 p S x (U) and for every formula φ(x; b) = r p, there is a M such that φ(a; b) = r holds. Equivalently, p S x (U) is a coheir of a p 0 S x (M) if there are types p i S x (M) such that i p i = p. Indeed, by the definition of coheir; if φ(x, b) = r p then there is a M such that U φ(a, b) = r. Therefore p [φ(x, b) = r] = {q S x (U) : q φ(x, b) = r} and tp(a) [φ(x, b) = r], i.e. for each neighborhood [φ(x, b) = r] of p, there exists a type tp(a) = tp(a) M S x (M) in [φ(x, b) = r], and this means that p is a cluster point of some elements of S x (M). A type p 0 S x (M) always has at least a coheir: let {a i M : i < M } be an indexed set of elements of M, and D an ultrafilter on M such that if p 0 φ(x, b) = r then {i : U φ(a i, b) = r} D. Then we define p D S x (U) by: p D φ(x, b) = r {i : U φ(a i, b) = r} D, for every formula φ(x, b) = r L(U). Clearly, p D is a coheir of p 0. (Note that the set E = {{i : U φ(a i, b) = r} : p 0 φ(x, b) = r} has the finite intersection property. If D be an ultrafilter on M such that E D. Then p D φ(x, b) = r {i : U φ(a i, b) = r} D.) We remark that (in continuous logic) every type in S x (M) is finitely satisfiable in M. Indeed, if φ(x, a) r p S x (M) then U sup x φ(x, a) r, and hence M sup x φ(x, a) r (because sup x φ(x, a) r T h(m)), i.e. there is a c M such that φ(c, a) r holds. Theorem 5.2 Let T be stable, A U, and p S x (U). Then the following are equivalent: (i) p does not fork over A; (ii) p is definable over every model containing of A. Proof. (i)= (ii): Assume that p S x (U) is a coheir of p M which M is a model containing of A. Then there are p i S x (M), i I such that i,d p i = p which D is an ultrafilter on I. Let φ(x, y) L. Since T is stable, every type in S x (M) is M- definable. Therefore, there is a M-definable function ψ i (=d i φ) such that p i φ(x, b) = r iff ψ i (b) = r, for all b M (and hence for all b U). Again, by stability, the set {ψ i } i is a relatively compact subset of C(S φ (M)). Let ψ := i,d ψ i (pointwise it). Then for all b U p φ(x, b) = r i,d φ(p i, b) = r i,d ψ i (b) = r ψ(b) = r. since φ is continuous (ii)= (i): Clear. Assume that p is definable over every model containing of A and p [φ(x, b) = r] which b is in U. Since A = {φ(a i, y) : a i M} is relatively compact, there are a i M, i I and an ultrafilter D on I such that i,d φ(a i, y) = ψ(y). Now, clearly p φ = i,d tp φ (a i /M). Therefore, i,d tp(a i ) [φ(x, b) = r]. 15

16 Proposition 5.3 Let A U. Every type over A has an extension over U which does not fork over A. proof. See the construction. 5.2 Properties of non-forking In this subsection T is stable. In the next subsection we study forking and its properties in NIP theories. Definition 5.4 Let A B, and p S x (B). We say that p does not fork over A, or that p is a nonforking extension of p A, if p has an extension p over U such that p does not fork over A. Proposition 5.5 (symmetry) tp(a/ab) does not fork over A iff tp(b/aa) does not fork over A. proof. Assume that p S x (U) is a global non-forking extension of tp(a/m) which M is a model containing Ab. For each formula φ(x, y) there is a M-definable formula ψ(y) such that p φ(x, c) = r iff ψ(c) = r for all c U. We can assume that ψ has the following form: ψ(y) = ψ(y, A, b, m) which m M. Now we can define the global type q as the following: q φ(x, c) = r iff ψ(a, A, c, m) = r for all c U. It is easy to verify that q is a definable extension of tp(b/m) and ψ = ψ(a, A, y, m) is its definable framework, where ψ is M -definable which M is a model containing of m, a (or containing of M, a). (We note that if ψ(y) = i ψ(y, A, b, m) which ψ i are M-definable, then ψ(y) = i ψ(a, A, y, m).) ( See Iovino s paper. Also, see Proposition 7.14 in [BU10].) Proposition 5.6 (Transitivity) Let A B C and p S x (C). If p does not fork over B and p B does not fork over A, then p does not fork over A. proof. Assume that p is an extension of p and q is an extension of p B such that p does not fork over B and q does not fork over A. Then p does not fork over B, so, by uniqueness of non-forking extension, p = q. Thus, p does not fork over A. 5.3 Almost non-forking and NIP We give a generalization of the notation of non-forking extension in NIP theories. It is easy to verify that the restriction of the new notation to stable case is consistence with the (first) classical notation. The theory T is NIP if all formulas φ(x; y) L are NIP. Definition 5.7 Let T be NIP, A U, and p S x (U). (i) We say that p almost does not fork over A, or is an almost non-forking over A, if p is almost finitely satisfiable in every model containing A, i.e. there are p i S x (M) such that i p i [p] which [p] is the class of types almost equial to p (cf. [Kha14]). 16

17 (ii) p is almost definable over A if for each formula φ(x, y) and every model M containing A, there is an almost (M-)definable function ψ(y) such that φ(p, b) = ψ(b) for almost all b M (and hence b U) for each Radon measure on U. (see [Kha14].) Similar to the stable case: Definition 5.8 Let A B, and p S x (B). We say that p almost does not fork over A, or that p is an almost nonforking extension of p A, if p has an extension p over U such that p almost does not fork over A. Theorem 5.9 Let T be NIP, A U, and p S x (U). Then the following are equivalent: (i) p almost does not fork over A; (ii) p is almost definable over every model containing of A. Proof. Use The proof is similar to the stable case. 5.4 Properties of almost non-forking Proposition 5.10 Let T be NIP. (i) (symmetry): tp(a/ab) almost does not fork over A iff tp(b/aa) almost does not fork over A. (ii) (Transitivity): Let A B C and p S x (C). If p almost does not fork over B and p B almost does not fork over A, then p almost does not fork over A. proof. The proofs are similar to the stable case. 5.5 The number of coheirs Proposition 5.11 If T has IP, then for each cardinal κ > T there is some model M of cardinality κ and p S(M) having 2 2κ coheirs. Proof. Assume that T has IP. Then there is a set {a i : i < κ}, a formula φ(x; y) and r > s such that for any A κ, we can find some b A such that: φ(a i ; b A ) r if i A, and φ(a i, b A ) s if i / A. Let M be a model of size κ containing all the a i s. For D an ultrafilter over κ, we define p D by p D φ(x, b) = r {i : U φ(a i, b) = r} D. Then we have p D φ(x; b A ) r A D. This shows that for D D, the two types p D and p D are distinct. Furthermore, p D is finitely satisfiable in M. As there are 2 2κ pairwise distinct ultrafilters on κ, we have obtained 2 2κ global types finitely satisfiable in M. Since there are only 2 κ types in variable x over M, there is at least one such type which has 2 2κ global coheirs. 6 SOP In classical model theory a formula φ(x, y) has the strict order property (SOP) if there exists a sequence (a i : i < ω) in the monster model U such that for all i < ω, φ(u, a i ) φ(u, a i+1 ). 17

18 We can assume that φ(x, y) is a 0-1 valued function on U such that φ(a, b) = 1 iff φ(a, b). Then φ(x, y) has the strict order property if there are a i s such that for each b U, the sequence {φ(b, a i )} i is monotone, and therefore the pointwise it {φ(x, a i )} i exists, but its it is not sequentially continuous. Indeed, take b j φ(u, a j+1 ) \ φ(u, a j ). On the other hand, if b i φ(u, a i) then there is a k such that for all i k, b φ(u, a i ), therefore i φ(b, a i ) = 1. Otherwise, b U \ i φ(u, a 1), and therefore i φ(b, a i ) = 0. In the other word, for each b the sequence φ(b, a i ) is monotone and hence the pointwise it ψ(x) := i φ(x, a i ) is well-defined. But j ψ(b j ) = j i φ(b j, a i ) = 1 0 = i j φ(b j, a i ). One can assume that U is equipped with the Stone topology (or the logic topology). Since this topology is compact, there is a subsequence b jk and b U such that b jk b. Therefore, the subsequence b jk converges to b but k ψ(b jk ) ψ(b), i.e. ψ is not sequentially continuous. To summarize, it is natural to conjecture that in the generalized model theory the strict order property is equivalent to the existence of a pointwise convergence sequence of real valued functions such that its it is not sequentially continuous. Our next goal is to convince the reader that this is indeed the case. Definition 6.1 (Strict order property) A bounded family F of real valued functions on a set X has the ɛ-strict order property (or short ɛ-sop) if there exist (i): {a m } m X, and (ii): an (infinite) sequence {f n } n F such that for each x X the sequence {f n (x)} m is monotone, and hence f n is convergence to a function f R X, but m f(a m ) n m f n (a m ) > ɛ. F has strict order property (or short SOP) if for some ɛ > 0 it has ɛ-sop. If X be a compact space and f n s be sequentially continuous then the SOP means that f is not sequentially continuous. A formula φ(x, y) has the (ɛ-)strict order property in a model M if the family {φ(x, a) : a M} has the (ɛ-)strict order property. The formula φ has the (ɛ-)strict order property in a theory T if it has the (ɛ-)strict order property in a model of T. The next result shows that the SCP and the Non-SOP are actually the same. Proposition 6.2 Non-SOP SCP. Proof. = : Assume that f n C(X) and a m X such that f n f but n m f n (a m ) m f(a m ), i.e. T has not SCP. Then, for a countable model M T (or equivalently a separable model) we can find a subsequence f nk such that for each a M the sequence f nk (a) is monotone. (Indeed, let M be a countable model of T such that {a m } M. Let b 1, b 2,... be an enumeration of the elements of M. Then for each b i there is a monotone subsequence of {f n (b i )}, which we shall denote by {f i,n }. By a diagonal argument, we can find a sequence {f n,n } such that it is desirable (cf. Theorem 7.23 in [Rud64]).) Now, by the compactness theorem, since T is complete, this sequence is monotone in every model of T, i.e. if N T then {f nk (b)} is monotone for each b N, and hence T has SOP. =: Clear. 18

19 By the above result, SOP is expresible. Indeed, let ψ n (x) := ( n f i (x) f i+1 (x) ) ( n f i (x) f i+1 (x) ). i=1 Then by the compactness theorem, {ψ n } n expresses that the sequence {f n } n is monotone. Also, for all i < j, f i (b j ) f j (b i ) ɛ expresses the ɛ-non-stability. To summarize, the SOP is expressible. 6.1 NIP+Non-SOP = Stable Now we can give a topological proof of the following classical result. We note that the NIP and the Non-SOP are negative properties but they are equivalent to the CSP and the SCP which are positive. Theorem 6.3 Let X be a compact space and A C(X) be bounded. Then A is stable iff it has CSP and SCP. Proof. We show that cl p (A) C(X) iff every sequence of A has a convergence subsequence in R X and the it of every convergence sequence of A is sequentially continuous. Assume that A has NIP(=CSP) and SCP. Assume that {f n } n A and {a m } m X and the double its m n f n (a m ) and n m f n (a m ) exist. Let a be a closure point of {a m } m. Without loss of generality we can assume that a m a. By NIP, there is a convergence subsequence f nk such that f nk f. Therefore m nk f nk (a m ) = m f(a m ) and nk m f nk (a m ) = nk f nk (a) = f(a). By SCP, f is sequentially continuous and therefore m f(a m ) = f(a). Since the double its exist, it is easy to verify that m n f n (a m ) = m nk f nk (a m ) and n m f n (a m ) = nk m f nk (a m ). Therefore A has the double it property and hence it is stable(=wap). The converse is just 4.7. Corollary 6.4 (Shelah, [She71]) Theory T is unstable iff it has the IP or the SOP. We say a family F C(X) is sequentially close (or has sequentially closeness property), if the pointwise it of each convergence sequence of its elements is in C(X). If X be compact, then it is known that F has SCP iff it is sequentially close (cf. 8.2). To summarize: stable NIP + Non-SOP WAP CSP + SCP Eberlein Rosenthal + Sequentially Closeness i=1 19

20 6.2 Definability of types and Fréchet-Urysohn spaces Almost all the combinatorial content of stability, in classical model theory, is contained in the theorem of definability of types (cf. Lemma 2.2 in [Pil96]). In [Ben1?] Ben Yaacov gave a proof of this theorem using the Grothendieck s criterion. Here we take a closer study of this theorem and show that it is equivalent to that every compact subset of C(X) is a Fréchet-Urysohn space. Proposition 6.5 (i) (ii). (i) Fréchet-Urysohn space: If X is a compact space and A C(X) is relatively compact, then every point of the closure of A is a it of a sequence in A. (ii) Definability of types: If φ is a stable formula in model M, then every type in S φ (M) is definable. Proof. We use the Grothendieck s criterion as a catalyst. (i)= (ii): The set A = {φ(a, y) : a M} is relatively compact in C(S φ (M)) because φ is stable. Let p(x) S φ (M), and let a i M be any net such that i tp φ (a i /M) = p. Since A is relatively pointwise compact, there is a ψ C(X) such that i φ a i (y) = ψ(y). By (i), ψ is the pointwise it of a sequence φ an (y) of the family {φ a i (y)} i. Therefore, there is a subsequence φ an k (y) such that k φ an k (y) = ψ(y). Clearly, ψ(y) is a φ-definable relation over M, and for b M we have φ(p, b) = k φ(a nk, b) = ψ(b). Therefore, p is definable by a φ-definable relation ψ over M. (ii)= (i): Assume that the set A = {φ(a, y) : a M} C(S φ (M)) is relatively compact. Equivalently, φ is stable in M. Let ψ(y) A. Then there are a i M, i I and an ultrafilter D on I such that i,d φ(a i, y) = ψ(y). We define the type p D as the following: p D φ(x, b) = r ɛ > 0 {i I : φ(a i, b) r ɛ} D, for every b M. It is easy to verify that p D is a complete type on M. Indeed, let a := i,d a i, since S φ (M) is compact, a is well-defined. Therefore, if p D φ(x, b) = r then φ(a, b) = i,d φ(a i, b) = r because φ(x, b) is continuous for each b. Thus p D = tp(a) is a complete type in S φ (M). Now, by (ii), p D is definable, i.e. there is a sequence φ an (y) in A such that n φ an = ψ. Therefore every point of the closure of A is a it of a sequence in A. The interested reader can compare the proofs of Theorem 462B in [Fre06] and Lemma 2.2 in [Pil96]. 6.3 The Eberlein-Šmulian theorem and NIP/Non-SOP The well known compactness theorem of Eberlein and Šmulian says that weakly compactness and weakly sequentially compactness are equivalent on a Banach space. By the previous observation (6.5), for the Banach space C(X) which X is compact, this theorem 20

21 is equivalent to the following expression: relatively weakly compactness and relatively weakly sequentially compactness are equivalent on C(X). Now, we show the connection between Shelah s theorem (Stable = NIP+Non-SOP) and the Eberlein-Šmulian theorem for the Banach space C(X) which X is compact. Proposition 6.6 (i) (ii). (i) The Eberlein-Šmulian theorem: If X is a compact space and A C(X), then the following statements are equivalent: (a) The weak closure of A is weakly compact in C(X). (b) Each sequence of elements of A has a subsequence that is weakly convergent in C(X). (ii) NIP+Non-SOP = Stable: If T is a first order theory, then the following statements are equivalent: (a ) T is stable. (b ) T has the NIP and the Non-SOP. Proof. First, we note that by the Grothendieck s criterion, (a) (a ). (i)= (ii): Assume that (a ) holds, then T A is weakly compact and hence by (i), it has the NIP and the Non-SOP. Conversely, assume that (b ) holds, i.e. T has the NIP and the Non-SOP. Then by the NIP, every sequence has a pointwise convergence subsequence. By the Non-SOP, its it is sequentially continuous, and hence it would be continuous (cf. 8.2). (ii)= (i): Assume that (a) holds, i.e. A is relatively weakly compact. By (ii), A has the NIP, and hence each sequence of elements of A has a subsequence that is pointwise convergent in R X. Since A has not the SOP, the pointwise it f of a convergence sequence {f n } A is sequentially continuous and hence it would be continuous. Conversely, if (b) holds, then A has the NIP and the Non-SOP. Therefore, by (ii), A is relatively weakly compact. Of course, the Eberlein-Šmulian theorem is proved for arbitrary Banach spaces, but it follows easily from the case C(X) (cf. Theorem 462D in [Fre06]). On the other hand, we note that for a compact space X, countably compactness and sequentially compactness are equivalent in C(X). 6.4 First order logic is angelic Fremlin s notation of an angelic topological space is as follow: A regular Hausdorff space X is angelic if whenever A is a subset of X which is relatively countably compact in X, then (i) A is relatively compact (ii) every point of A is the it of a sequence in A. Roughly an angelic space is one for which the conclusions of the Eberlein-Šmulian theorem hold. By the previous observations it is easy to show that: 21

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson American Institute of Mathematics Workshop September 2006 Outline Continuous logic 1 Continuous logic 2 The metric on S n (T ) Origins Continuous logic Many classes of (complete)

More information

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY Iranian Journal of Fuzzy Systems Vol. 10, No. 3, (2013) pp. 103-113 103 PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY S. M. BAGHERI AND M. MONIRI Abstract. We present some model theoretic results for

More information

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

ω-stable Theories: Introduction ω-stable Theories: Introduction 1 ω - Stable/Totally Transcendental Theories Throughout let T be a complete theory in a countable language L having infinite models. For an L-structure M and A M let Sn

More information

Tame definable topological dynamics

Tame definable topological dynamics Tame definable topological dynamics Artem Chernikov (Paris 7) Géométrie et Théorie des Modèles, 4 Oct 2013, ENS, Paris Joint work with Pierre Simon, continues previous work with Anand Pillay and Pierre

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. In this paper, we will introduce some of the most basic concepts in geometric stability theory, and attempt to state a dichotomy theorem

More information

Weight and measure in NIP theories

Weight and measure in NIP theories Weight and measure in NIP theories Anand Pillay University of Leeds September 18, 2011 Abstract We initiate an account of Shelah s notion of strong dependence in terms of generically stable measures, proving

More information

Model theory for metric structures

Model theory for metric structures Model theory for metric structures Itaï Ben Yaacov Alexander Berenstein C. Ward Henson Alexander Usvyatsov Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Metric structures and signatures 4 3 Formulas and their interpretations

More information

Measures in model theory

Measures in model theory Measures in model theory Anand Pillay University of Leeds Logic and Set Theory, Chennai, August 2010 Introduction I I will discuss the growing use and role of measures in pure model theory, with an emphasis

More information

CHAPTER I THE RIESZ REPRESENTATION THEOREM

CHAPTER I THE RIESZ REPRESENTATION THEOREM CHAPTER I THE RIESZ REPRESENTATION THEOREM We begin our study by identifying certain special kinds of linear functionals on certain special vector spaces of functions. We describe these linear functionals

More information

More on invariant types in NIP theories

More on invariant types in NIP theories More on invariant types in NIP theories Pierre Simon June 22, 2013 This note is not intended for publication in its present form. I wrote it to be used as a reference for other papers (mainly [CPS13])

More information

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS URI ANDREWS AND H. JEROME KEISLER Abstract. Every complete first order theory has a corresponding complete theory in continuous logic, called the randomization theory.

More information

Definably amenable groups in NIP

Definably amenable groups in NIP Definably amenable groups in NIP Artem Chernikov (Paris 7) Lyon, 21 Nov 2013 Joint work with Pierre Simon. Setting T is a complete first-order theory in a language L, countable for simplicity. M = T a

More information

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0 BENJAMIN LEDEAUX Abstract. This expository paper introduces model theory with a focus on countable models of complete theories. Vaught

More information

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS REAL AND COMPLE ANALYSIS Third Edition Walter Rudin Professor of Mathematics University of Wisconsin, Madison Version 1.1 No rights reserved. Any part of this work can be reproduced or transmitted in any

More information

Stone-Čech compactification of Tychonoff spaces

Stone-Čech compactification of Tychonoff spaces The Stone-Čech compactification of Tychonoff spaces Jordan Bell jordan.bell@gmail.com Department of Mathematics, University of Toronto June 27, 2014 1 Completely regular spaces and Tychonoff spaces A topological

More information

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then MH 7500 THEOREMS Definition. A topological space is an ordered pair (X, T ), where X is a set and T is a collection of subsets of X such that (i) T and X T ; (ii) U V T whenever U, V T ; (iii) U T whenever

More information

INDEPENDENCE RELATIONS IN RANDOMIZATIONS

INDEPENDENCE RELATIONS IN RANDOMIZATIONS INDEPENDENE RELATIONS IN RANDOMIZATIONS URI ANDREWS, ISAA GOLDBRING, AND H. JEROME KEISLER Abstract. The randomization of a complete first order theory T is the complete continuous theory T R with two

More information

D, such that f(u) = f(v) whenever u = v, has a multiplicative refinement g : [λ] <ℵ 0

D, such that f(u) = f(v) whenever u = v, has a multiplicative refinement g : [λ] <ℵ 0 Maryanthe Malliaris and Saharon Shelah. Cofinality spectrum problems in model theory, set theory and general topology. J. Amer. Math. Soc., vol. 29 (2016), pp. 237-297. Maryanthe Malliaris and Saharon

More information

Model Theory and Forking Independence

Model Theory and Forking Independence Model Theory and Forking Independence Gabriel Conant UIC UIC Graduate Student Colloquium April 22, 2013 Gabriel Conant (UIC) Model Theory and Forking Independence April 22, 2013 1 / 24 Types We fix a first

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M.

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M. COMPACTNESS If C R n is closed and bounded, then by B-W it is sequentially compact: any sequence of points in C has a subsequence converging to a point in C Conversely, any sequentially compact C R n is

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

c 2010 Hernando Tellez

c 2010 Hernando Tellez c 2010 Hernando Tellez CONTRIBUTIONS TO MODEL THEORY OF METRIC STRUCTURES BY HERNANDO TELLEZ DISSERTATION Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in

More information

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 Index Page 1 Topology 2 1.1 Definition of a topology 2 1.2 Basis (Base) of a topology 2 1.3 The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 1.4 Basic topology concepts: limit points, closed sets,

More information

General Topology. Summer Term Michael Kunzinger

General Topology. Summer Term Michael Kunzinger General Topology Summer Term 2016 Michael Kunzinger michael.kunzinger@univie.ac.at Universität Wien Fakultät für Mathematik Oskar-Morgenstern-Platz 1 A-1090 Wien Preface These are lecture notes for a

More information

Introduction to Model Theory

Introduction to Model Theory Introduction to Model Theory Charles Steinhorn, Vassar College Katrin Tent, University of Münster CIRM, January 8, 2018 The three lectures Introduction to basic model theory Focus on Definability More

More information

Contents: 1. Minimization. 2. The theorem of Lions-Stampacchia for variational inequalities. 3. Γ -Convergence. 4. Duality mapping.

Contents: 1. Minimization. 2. The theorem of Lions-Stampacchia for variational inequalities. 3. Γ -Convergence. 4. Duality mapping. Minimization Contents: 1. Minimization. 2. The theorem of Lions-Stampacchia for variational inequalities. 3. Γ -Convergence. 4. Duality mapping. 1 Minimization A Topological Result. Let S be a topological

More information

PROBLEMS. (b) (Polarization Identity) Show that in any inner product space

PROBLEMS. (b) (Polarization Identity) Show that in any inner product space 1 Professor Carl Cowen Math 54600 Fall 09 PROBLEMS 1. (Geometry in Inner Product Spaces) (a) (Parallelogram Law) Show that in any inner product space x + y 2 + x y 2 = 2( x 2 + y 2 ). (b) (Polarization

More information

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem Set 2: s Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem 1. (a) Prove that a closed subset of a complete metric space is complete. (b) Prove that a closed subset of a compact metric space is compact. (c) Prove that

More information

A trichotomy of countable, stable, unsuperstable theories

A trichotomy of countable, stable, unsuperstable theories A trichotomy of countable, stable, unsuperstable theories Michael C. Laskowski Department of Mathematics University of Maryland S. Shelah Department of Mathematics Hebrew University of Jerusalem Department

More information

Algebraic closure in continuous logic

Algebraic closure in continuous logic Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas Volumen 41 (2007), páginas 279 285 Algebraic closure in continuous logic C. Ward Henson Hernando Tellez University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign, USA Abstract. We study

More information

16 1 Basic Facts from Functional Analysis and Banach Lattices

16 1 Basic Facts from Functional Analysis and Banach Lattices 16 1 Basic Facts from Functional Analysis and Banach Lattices 1.2.3 Banach Steinhaus Theorem Another fundamental theorem of functional analysis is the Banach Steinhaus theorem, or the Uniform Boundedness

More information

VC-dimension in model theory and other subjects

VC-dimension in model theory and other subjects VC-dimension in model theory and other subjects Artem Chernikov (Paris 7 / MSRI, Berkeley) UCLA, 2 May 2014 VC-dimension Let F be a family of subsets of a set X. VC-dimension Let F be a family of subsets

More information

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University February 7, 2007 2 Contents 1 Metric Spaces 1 1.1 Basic definitions...........................

More information

Measures and Measure Spaces

Measures and Measure Spaces Chapter 2 Measures and Measure Spaces In summarizing the flaws of the Riemann integral we can focus on two main points: 1) Many nice functions are not Riemann integrable. 2) The Riemann integral does not

More information

G δ ideals of compact sets

G δ ideals of compact sets J. Eur. Math. Soc. 13, 853 882 c European Mathematical Society 2011 DOI 10.4171/JEMS/268 Sławomir Solecki G δ ideals of compact sets Received January 1, 2008 and in revised form January 2, 2009 Abstract.

More information

Stable embeddedness and N IP

Stable embeddedness and N IP Stable embeddedness and N IP Anand Pillay University of Leeds January 14, 2010 Abstract We give some sufficient conditions for a predicate P in a complete theory T to be stably embedded. Let P be P with

More information

A SECOND COURSE IN GENERAL TOPOLOGY

A SECOND COURSE IN GENERAL TOPOLOGY Heikki Junnila, 2007-8/2014 A SECOND COURSE IN GENERAL TOPOLOGY CHAPTER I COMPLETE REGULARITY 1. Definitions and basic properties..... 3 2. Some examples..... 7 Exercises....9 CHAPTER II CONVERGENCE AND

More information

Hence C has VC-dimension d iff. π C (d) = 2 d. (4) C has VC-density l if there exists K R such that, for all

Hence C has VC-dimension d iff. π C (d) = 2 d. (4) C has VC-density l if there exists K R such that, for all 1. Computational Learning Abstract. I discuss the basics of computational learning theory, including concept classes, VC-dimension, and VC-density. Next, I touch on the VC-Theorem, ɛ-nets, and the (p,

More information

Chapter 1. Introduction

Chapter 1. Introduction Chapter 1 Introduction Functional analysis can be seen as a natural extension of the real analysis to more general spaces. As an example we can think at the Heine - Borel theorem (closed and bounded is

More information

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller Real Analysis Notes Thomas Goller September 4, 2011 Contents 1 Abstract Measure Spaces 2 1.1 Basic Definitions........................... 2 1.2 Measurable Functions........................ 2 1.3 Integration..............................

More information

Continuous Functions on Metric Spaces

Continuous Functions on Metric Spaces Continuous Functions on Metric Spaces Math 201A, Fall 2016 1 Continuous functions Definition 1. Let (X, d X ) and (Y, d Y ) be metric spaces. A function f : X Y is continuous at a X if for every ɛ > 0

More information

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS DIEGO ANDRES BEJARANO RAYO Abstract. We expand on and further explain the work by Malliaris and Shelah on the cofinality spectrum by doing

More information

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515 THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515 Proposition 1 (=comment on page 17). If A is an algebra, then any finite union or finite intersection of sets in A is also in A. Proposition 2 (=Proposition 1.1). For every

More information

SPACES WHOSE PSEUDOCOMPACT SUBSPACES ARE CLOSED SUBSETS. Alan Dow, Jack R. Porter, R.M. Stephenson, Jr., and R. Grant Woods

SPACES WHOSE PSEUDOCOMPACT SUBSPACES ARE CLOSED SUBSETS. Alan Dow, Jack R. Porter, R.M. Stephenson, Jr., and R. Grant Woods SPACES WHOSE PSEUDOCOMPACT SUBSPACES ARE CLOSED SUBSETS Alan Dow, Jack R. Porter, R.M. Stephenson, Jr., and R. Grant Woods Abstract. Every first countable pseudocompact Tychonoff space X has the property

More information

The Caratheodory Construction of Measures

The Caratheodory Construction of Measures Chapter 5 The Caratheodory Construction of Measures Recall how our construction of Lebesgue measure in Chapter 2 proceeded from an initial notion of the size of a very restricted class of subsets of R,

More information

CHAPTER V DUAL SPACES

CHAPTER V DUAL SPACES CHAPTER V DUAL SPACES DEFINITION Let (X, T ) be a (real) locally convex topological vector space. By the dual space X, or (X, T ), of X we mean the set of all continuous linear functionals on X. By the

More information

REPRESENTABLE BANACH SPACES AND UNIFORMLY GÂTEAUX-SMOOTH NORMS. Julien Frontisi

REPRESENTABLE BANACH SPACES AND UNIFORMLY GÂTEAUX-SMOOTH NORMS. Julien Frontisi Serdica Math. J. 22 (1996), 33-38 REPRESENTABLE BANACH SPACES AND UNIFORMLY GÂTEAUX-SMOOTH NORMS Julien Frontisi Communicated by G. Godefroy Abstract. It is proved that a representable non-separable Banach

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

7 Complete metric spaces and function spaces

7 Complete metric spaces and function spaces 7 Complete metric spaces and function spaces 7.1 Completeness Let (X, d) be a metric space. Definition 7.1. A sequence (x n ) n N in X is a Cauchy sequence if for any ɛ > 0, there is N N such that n, m

More information

Contents. Index... 15

Contents. Index... 15 Contents Filter Bases and Nets................................................................................ 5 Filter Bases and Ultrafilters: A Brief Overview.........................................................

More information

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: COMPACT SETS AND FINITE-DIMENSIONAL SPACES. 1. Compact Sets

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: COMPACT SETS AND FINITE-DIMENSIONAL SPACES. 1. Compact Sets FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: COMPACT SETS AND FINITE-DIMENSIONAL SPACES CHRISTOPHER HEIL 1. Compact Sets Definition 1.1 (Compact and Totally Bounded Sets). Let X be a metric space, and let E X be

More information

Set theory and topology

Set theory and topology arxiv:1306.6926v1 [math.ho] 28 Jun 2013 Set theory and topology An introduction to the foundations of analysis 1 Part II: Topology Fundamental Felix Nagel Abstract We provide a formal introduction into

More information

Functional Analysis. Franck Sueur Metric spaces Definitions Completeness Compactness Separability...

Functional Analysis. Franck Sueur Metric spaces Definitions Completeness Compactness Separability... Functional Analysis Franck Sueur 2018-2019 Contents 1 Metric spaces 1 1.1 Definitions........................................ 1 1.2 Completeness...................................... 3 1.3 Compactness......................................

More information

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler ATHEATCS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATONS Vol. - odel Theory - H. Jerome Keisler ODEL THEORY H. Jerome Keisler Department of athematics, University of Wisconsin, adison Wisconsin U.S.A. Keywords: adapted probability

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order. October 12, 2010 Sacks Dicta... the central notions of model theory are absolute absoluteness, unlike cardinality, is a logical concept. That is why model theory does not founder on that rock of undecidability,

More information

Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces

Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces T. C. Dorlas Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies School of Theoretical Physics 10 Burlington Road, Dublin 4, Ireland. Email: dorlas@stp.dias.ie

More information

1.2 Fundamental Theorems of Functional Analysis

1.2 Fundamental Theorems of Functional Analysis 1.2 Fundamental Theorems of Functional Analysis 15 Indeed, h = ω ψ ωdx is continuous compactly supported with R hdx = 0 R and thus it has a unique compactly supported primitive. Hence fφ dx = f(ω ψ ωdy)dx

More information

Linear Topological Spaces

Linear Topological Spaces Linear Topological Spaces by J. L. KELLEY ISAAC NAMIOKA AND W. F. DONOGHUE, JR. G. BALEY PRICE KENNETH R. LUCAS WENDY ROBERTSON B. J. PETTIS W. R. SCOTT EBBE THUE POULSEN KENNAN T. SMITH D. VAN NOSTRAND

More information

Math 209B Homework 2

Math 209B Homework 2 Math 29B Homework 2 Edward Burkard Note: All vector spaces are over the field F = R or C 4.6. Two Compactness Theorems. 4. Point Set Topology Exercise 6 The product of countably many sequentally compact

More information

3 (Due ). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure?

3 (Due ). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure? MA 645-4A (Real Analysis), Dr. Chernov Homework assignment 1 (Due ). Show that the open disk x 2 + y 2 < 1 is a countable union of planar elementary sets. Show that the closed disk x 2 + y 2 1 is a countable

More information

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France Maharam Algebras Boban Veličković Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France Abstract Maharam algebras are complete Boolean algebras carrying a positive continuous submeasure.

More information

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2010) 944 955 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Types directed by constants

More information

Notions such as convergent sequence and Cauchy sequence make sense for any metric space. Convergent Sequences are Cauchy

Notions such as convergent sequence and Cauchy sequence make sense for any metric space. Convergent Sequences are Cauchy Banach Spaces These notes provide an introduction to Banach spaces, which are complete normed vector spaces. For the purposes of these notes, all vector spaces are assumed to be over the real numbers.

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

Type decompositions in NIP theories

Type decompositions in NIP theories École Normale Supérieure, Paris Logic Colloquium 2012, Manchester Definition A formula φ(x; y) has the independence property if one can find some infinite set B such that for every C B, there is y C such

More information

Locally convex spaces, the hyperplane separation theorem, and the Krein-Milman theorem

Locally convex spaces, the hyperplane separation theorem, and the Krein-Milman theorem 56 Chapter 7 Locally convex spaces, the hyperplane separation theorem, and the Krein-Milman theorem Recall that C(X) is not a normed linear space when X is not compact. On the other hand we could use semi

More information

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 Instructions: Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 If you signed up for Computability Theory, do two E and two C problems. If you signed up for Model Theory, do two E and two M problems. If you signed up

More information

MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction

MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction 1 INTRODUCTION MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, 2014 1 Introduction Definition. If A, B are sets and there exists a bijection A B, they have the same cardinality, which we write as A, #A. If there exists

More information

Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies

Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies BS V c Gabriel Nagy Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies Notes from the Functional Analysis Course (Fall 07 - Spring 08) In this section we discuss two important, but highly non-trivial,

More information

s P = f(ξ n )(x i x i 1 ). i=1

s P = f(ξ n )(x i x i 1 ). i=1 Compactness and total boundedness via nets The aim of this chapter is to define the notion of a net (generalized sequence) and to characterize compactness and total boundedness by this important topological

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets 2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets NOTE: AS OF 2008, SOME OF THIS STUFF IS A BIT OUT- DATED AND HAS A FEW TYPOS. I WILL REVISE THIS MATE- RIAL SOMETIME. In this lecture we discuss two

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

Commutative Banach algebras 79

Commutative Banach algebras 79 8. Commutative Banach algebras In this chapter, we analyze commutative Banach algebras in greater detail. So we always assume that xy = yx for all x, y A here. Definition 8.1. Let A be a (commutative)

More information

Part A. Metric and Topological Spaces

Part A. Metric and Topological Spaces Part A Metric and Topological Spaces 1 Lecture A1 Introduction to the Course This course is an introduction to the basic ideas of topology and metric space theory for first-year graduate students. Topology

More information

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007 Modern Model Theory Begins Theorem (Morley 1965) If a countable first order theory is categorical in one uncountable cardinal it is categorical in all uncountable cardinals. Outline 1 2 3 SELF-CONSCIOUS

More information

A CLASSIFICATION OF SEPARABLE ROSENTHAL COMPACTA AND ITS APPLICATIONS

A CLASSIFICATION OF SEPARABLE ROSENTHAL COMPACTA AND ITS APPLICATIONS A CLASSIFICATION OF SEPARABLE ROSENTHAL COMPACTA AND ITS APPLICATIONS SPIROS ARGYROS, PANDELIS DODOS AND VASSILIS KANELLOPOULOS Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Ramsey properties of perfect sets and of subtrees

More information

MTG 5316/4302 FALL 2018 REVIEW FINAL

MTG 5316/4302 FALL 2018 REVIEW FINAL MTG 5316/4302 FALL 2018 REVIEW FINAL JAMES KEESLING Problem 1. Define open set in a metric space X. Define what it means for a set A X to be connected in a metric space X. Problem 2. Show that if a set

More information

COFINALITY SPECTRUM THEOREMS IN MODEL THEORY, SET THEORY AND GENERAL TOPOLOGY

COFINALITY SPECTRUM THEOREMS IN MODEL THEORY, SET THEORY AND GENERAL TOPOLOGY COFINALITY SPECTRUM THEOREMS IN MODEL THEORY, SET THEORY AND GENERAL TOPOLOGY M. MALLIARIS AND S. SHELAH Abstract. We connect and solve two longstanding open problems in quite different areas: the model-theoretic

More information

Topological properties

Topological properties CHAPTER 4 Topological properties 1. Connectedness Definitions and examples Basic properties Connected components Connected versus path connected, again 2. Compactness Definition and first examples Topological

More information

Logical Connectives and Quantifiers

Logical Connectives and Quantifiers Chapter 1 Logical Connectives and Quantifiers 1.1 Logical Connectives 1.2 Quantifiers 1.3 Techniques of Proof: I 1.4 Techniques of Proof: II Theorem 1. Let f be a continuous function. If 1 f(x)dx 0, then

More information

Eberlein-Šmulian theorem and some of its applications

Eberlein-Šmulian theorem and some of its applications Eberlein-Šmulian theorem and some of its applications Kristina Qarri Supervisors Trond Abrahamsen Associate professor, PhD University of Agder Norway Olav Nygaard Professor, PhD University of Agder Norway

More information

arxiv:math.lo/ v1 28 Nov 2004

arxiv:math.lo/ v1 28 Nov 2004 HILBERT SPACES WITH GENERIC GROUPS OF AUTOMORPHISMS arxiv:math.lo/0411625 v1 28 Nov 2004 ALEXANDER BERENSTEIN Abstract. Let G be a countable group. We proof that there is a model companion for the approximate

More information

The Countable Henkin Principle

The Countable Henkin Principle The Countable Henkin Principle Robert Goldblatt Abstract. This is a revised and extended version of an article which encapsulates a key aspect of the Henkin method in a general result about the existence

More information

ABSTRACT INTEGRATION CHAPTER ONE

ABSTRACT INTEGRATION CHAPTER ONE CHAPTER ONE ABSTRACT INTEGRATION Version 1.1 No rights reserved. Any part of this work can be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means. Suggestions and errors are invited and can be mailed

More information

THE CHARACTERISTIC SEQUENCE OF A FIRST-ORDER FORMULA

THE CHARACTERISTIC SEQUENCE OF A FIRST-ORDER FORMULA THE CHARACTERISTIC SEQUENCE OF A FIRST-ORDER FORMULA M. E. MALLIARIS Abstract. For a first-order formula ϕ(x; y) we introduce and study the characteristic sequence P n : n < ω of hypergraphs defined by

More information

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields Thomas Scanlon University of California, Berkeley 8 June 2010 Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and

More information

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Department of Mathematics Bachelor Thesis (7.5 ECTS) Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Author: Dionijs van Tuijl Supervisor: Dr. Jaap van Oosten June 15, 2016 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminaries

More information

Margulis Superrigidity I & II

Margulis Superrigidity I & II Margulis Superrigidity I & II Alastair Litterick 1,2 and Yuri Santos Rego 1 Universität Bielefeld 1 and Ruhr-Universität Bochum 2 Block seminar on arithmetic groups and rigidity Universität Bielefeld 22nd

More information

DEFINABLE OPERATORS ON HILBERT SPACES

DEFINABLE OPERATORS ON HILBERT SPACES DEFINABLE OPERATORS ON HILBERT SPACES ISAAC GOLDBRING Abstract. Let H be an infinite-dimensional (real or complex) Hilbert space, viewed as a metric structure in its natural signature. We characterize

More information

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3 Analysis Math Notes Study Guide Real Analysis Contents Ordered Fields 2 Ordered sets and fields 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts 2 Metric Spaces 3 Metric Spaces 3 Definitions 4 Separability

More information

Bounded and continuous functions on a locally compact Hausdorff space and dual spaces

Bounded and continuous functions on a locally compact Hausdorff space and dual spaces Chapter 6 Bounded and continuous functions on a locally compact Hausdorff space and dual spaces Recall that the dual space of a normed linear space is a Banach space, and the dual space of L p is L q where

More information

CONTINUOUS MODEL THEORY AND FINITE- REPRESENTABILITY BETWEEN BANACH SPACES

CONTINUOUS MODEL THEORY AND FINITE- REPRESENTABILITY BETWEEN BANACH SPACES CONTINUOUS MODEL THEORY AND FINITE- REPRESENTABILITY BETWEEN BANACH SPACES CONTINUOUS MODEL THEORY AND FINITE- REPRESENTABILITY BETWEEN BANACH SPACES By: SEAN CONLEY, B. ARTS SC. A Thesis Submitted to

More information

Functional Analysis HW #3

Functional Analysis HW #3 Functional Analysis HW #3 Sangchul Lee October 26, 2015 1 Solutions Exercise 2.1. Let D = { f C([0, 1]) : f C([0, 1])} and define f d = f + f. Show that D is a Banach algebra and that the Gelfand transform

More information

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces Chapter 2 Metric Spaces The purpose of this chapter is to present a summary of some basic properties of metric and topological spaces that play an important role in the main body of the book. 2.1 Metrics

More information

Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm

Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm Chapter 13 Radon Measures Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm (13.1) f = sup x X f(x). We want to identify

More information

Metric Spaces and Topology

Metric Spaces and Topology Chapter 2 Metric Spaces and Topology From an engineering perspective, the most important way to construct a topology on a set is to define the topology in terms of a metric on the set. This approach underlies

More information

Properly forking formulas in Urysohn spaces

Properly forking formulas in Urysohn spaces Properly forking formulas in Urysohn spaces Gabriel Conant University of Notre Dame gconant@nd.edu March 4, 2016 Abstract In this informal note, we demonstrate the existence of forking and nondividing

More information