Dynamics of Stable Sets of Constitutions

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Dynamics of Stable Sets of Constitutions"

Transcription

1 Dynamics of Stable Sets of Constitutions HOUY Nicolas February 26, 2007 Abstract A Self-Designating social choice correspondence designates itself when it is implemented as a constitution and when the society has to choose a constitution from the set it is a member of. A set of constitutions is Stable if it has at least one self-designating correspondence for any preference profile of the society. A set of constitutions is Dynamically Stable if, implementing any constitution of the set, it is always possible to indirectly reach a self-designating one. We give necessary and sufficient sets of conditions for a set of constitutions to be stable and, more generally, dynamically stable. A subset of self-designating constitutions is Strongly Self-Designating if all the other self-designating constitutions indirectly designate one of its member whereas its members do not designate any other selfdesignating constitution. We identify Strongly Stable sets of constitutions, i.e. sets that always show a strongly self-designating subset. We also prove that strong stability and dynamic stability is equivalent to the the strongly self-designating subset being a singleton. Key Words: Social Choice Correspondence, Stability, Self-Selectivity, Dynamics. JEL Classification: D71. Hitotsubashi University and THEMA, Université de Cergy-Pontoise. nhouy@free.fr. M. Cohen, J.-F. Laslier, J.-M. Tallon and J.-C. Vergnaud are gratefully acknowledged. Participants of the CID work group in Paris and the Social Choice seminar in Caen are also thanked.

2 1 Introduction Ideally, what has been or should be the first collective decision ever made? It seems natural to state that it should answer the following question: "How should political decisions be made?". Said differently, the first political decision should be the choice of a constitution. To answer this first question, Rousseau 1 suggests that unanimity is necessary. The obvious problem raised by this requirement, as noticed by Locke 2 is the following: a priori, we don t know what each individual s preferences are, and following, there could well never be unanimity on the choice of a constitution. The possibility of the unanimity is an assumption on preferences rather than a way to choose. As a consequence, to answer this first question, we will have to suggest a condition different from unanimity. We propose that the constitution be Self-Designating. 3 A constitution is self-designating if, when implemented, it is accepted as a constitution. Let us already notice that a constitution is not self-designating by nature. Its self-designation feature depends on the different constitutions proposed and on the preferences of individuals among those constitutions. Let us look at an example to illustrate this and go a little bit further. Let the society be composed of three individuals {1; 2; 3}. Assume that there are four possible constitutions, i.e. processes to make a collective decision: the dictatorship of individual 1, dict 1, the dictatorship of individual 2, dict 2, 1 "Indeed, if there were no prior convention, where, unless the election were unanimous, would be the obligation on the minority to submit to the choice of the majority? How have a hundred men who wish for a master the right to vote on behalf of ten who do not? The law of majority voting is itself something established by convention, and presupposes unanimity, on one occasion at least." [Rousseau, 1762]. 2 "For if the consent of the majority shall not in reason, be received, as the act of the whole, and conclude every individual; nothing but the consent of every individual can make any thing to be the act of the whole: But such a consent is next impossible ever to be had." [Locke, 1690]. 3 To be formally precise, this condition would be a weakening of the unanimity if all the constitutions considered were satisfying the Pareto axiom. We will not impose such a requirement. 1

3 the dictatorship of individual 3, dict 3 and the Borda rule, borda, where each individual awards n points to her favorite option among n, n 1 points to her next favorite option,..., 1 point to her least favorite option; the option with the greatest number of points is selected by the society. We consider that individuals have preferences over this set of constitutions and we denote i the preferences of individual i over the set {dict 1 ;dict 2 ;dict 3 ;borda}. For instance, let the preferences be given by Preferences 1. Preferences 1 dict 1 1 borda 1 dict 3 1 dict 2, dict 3 2 borda 2 dict 2 2 dict 1, dict 2 3 dict 1 3 borda 3 dict 3. In this example, implementing dict 1 leads to a stable political life. Indeed, what if the society decides to choose from the possible constitutions by implementing the current constitution, dict 1? The society (in fact, only individual 1 here) chooses dict 1 since dict 1 is the favorite option of individual 1, and there is no need for a change. dict 1 is self-designating and can positively be implemented. For the same reason, borda is also self-designating. Indeed, it counts 8 points, which is the greatest number of points obtained (7 points are obtained by dict 2 and dict 3, 8 points are obtained by dict 4 1 ). Nevertheless, for the opposite reason dict 2 and dict 3 do not lead to a stable political life. Indeed, implementing dict 2 induces the change for dict 3 and implementing dict 3 induces the change for dict 2. dict 2 and dict 3 are not self-designating. Whatever their normative features, they cannot be used as constitutions almost by definition with the given preferences. In this sense they are positively not implementable. As already noticed, the self-designation feature is a feature of one constitution but it is fully dependent on the set it is considered with and the preferences of the individuals. 4 The equal numbers of points between dict 1 and borda will be discussed further in the introduction. 2

4 A set of constitutions that has at least one self-designating element, whatever the preferences of individuals, will be called stable and it satisfies the Stability axiom. We emphasize the fact that in this entire study, stability must be understood as a political notion. It is not related to the usual notion of mathematical stability. Preferences of the individuals are given (even though not necessarily known) and we do not study how constitutions respond to some shock on preferences. As an illustration of stability, let us show that the set {dict 1 ;dict 2 ;dict 3 ;borda} is not stable. Indeed, if the preferences of individuals were given by Preferences 2, there would be no self-designating constitution. Preferences 2 dict 2 1 dict 1 1 dict 3 1 borda, dict 3 2 dict 2 2 dict 1 2 borda, dict 1 3 dict 3 3 dict 2 3 borda. We argue that for positive reasons a constitutionalist cannot propose a set that is not stable to some individuals for them to choose a constitution if he does not know a priori the preferences of the individuals. If he proposed such a set, the possibility would exist that the society never reach political stability and hence, could never make any "legitimate" decision. This requirement of stability of sets of constitutions is, in our sense, a necessary condition. Then, if, as suggested above, we want to build a set of constitutions that allows the people to choose how to choose, it seems minimal that it should be stable. For the same purpose, it also seems natural that all its elements should be neutral. A constitution is neutral if, and only if, its outcome always depends only on the preferences of the individuals. If a constitutionalist wants to let the people choose how to choose he does not want to influence the society by any means, and in particular by introducing his own preferences as an argument for any choice. So he considers only neutral constitutions. 3

5 We will therefore restrict our study to neutral constitutions. In the first section, we will prove that a set of c neutral constitutions is stable if, and only if, whatever the preferences of the individuals, n constitutions of this set designate the same c+1 n constitutions of this same set. If there is unanimity (one constitution is designated by all the others and itself (n = c)), or universality (one constitution designates all the others and itself (n = 1)), the set is stable. Between those two extremes there is a trade-off. The constitutions of a "large enough" subset must be "similar enough". The larger the subset, the smaller the similarity needs to be. For instance, a set of four constitutions is stable if, and only if, for any preference profile one of the following is true: 1 constitution designates 4 constitutions, 2 constitutions designate the same 3 constitutions, 3 constitutions designate the same 2 constitutions, all the 4 constitutions designate the same constitution. We will show that this trade-off implies that a constitutionalist who wants to build a stable set of constitutions can not have them very precise and very different. As a generalization, we will say that a subset of constitutions of size n densely designates a (possibly different) subset of constitutions of size n if, and only if, l constitutions of the first subset all designate n + 1 l constitutions of the second one. For instance, a subset of four constitutions densely designates another subset of four constitutions if, and only if, one of the following is true: 1 constitution of the first subset designates 4 constitutions of the second subset, 4

6 2 constitutions of the first subset designate the same 3 constitutions of the second subset, 3 constitutions of the first subset designate the same 2 constitutions of the second subset, all the 4 constitutions of the first subset designate the same constitution of the second subset. As above, the interpretation is the following: a subset X densely designates another subset X if, and only if, a "large enough" subset of constitutions of X is "similar enough" when X is considered. As a consequence, our first result can be restated as follows: a set of constitutions is stable if, and only if, it densely designates itself. While the first section deals with the existence of self-designating constitutions, the second and third sections deal with the dynamics of the sets of neutral constitutions. Two dynamic features are considered. The first one deals with the relationship between self-designating constitutions on the one hand, and those that are not on the other hand. In our previous example with Preferences 1, there exists a cycle between dict 2 and dict 3, which are not self-designating. If, for any reason, the initial constitution is dict 2, the political life of the given society will never be stable. Using the idealistic framework stated by Rousseau, reaching one of the self-designating constitutions in a stable set can require the test of all of them. Here, dict 1 or borda that are legitimate constitutions because of their self-designating feature will never be reached unless dict 1 or borda themselves are implemented. We will rule out such situations with the Dynamic Stability axiom. This axiom states that from any constitution, there exists a path that leads to a self-designating one, and this is true for any preference profile. 5

7 Let us imagine the following justifications. The first one relies on the fact that once a constitution is used, the people could not accept to change it without its consent, illegitimately. Then, if the constitutionalist does not know what are the preferences of the individuals a priori, he needs to know that whatever the first constitution implemented, we will legitimately reach a political stable life. The second justification can be said as follows. Assume the preferences of the individuals are allowed to change within any scope. Our dynamic stability condition imposes that, wherever it comes from, the society can reach a new (possibly the same but not necessarily) self-designating constitution. 5 We will show that a set of neutral constitutions is dynamically stable if, and only if, for any preference profile of the individuals, for any subset of constitutions X, if all the constitutions of X only designates constitutions of a subset (possibly different) X, then X must densely designate X. Said differently, there must not exist two subsets (necessarily of same size) such that all the elements of the first exclusively designate elements of the second and nevertheless the first subset does not densely designate the second one. It is then obvious that the dynamic stability condition is a generalization of the stability condition to any pair of subsets. The second relevant dynamic feature deals with the relationships between self-designating constitutions. As shown in [Houy, 2004], for any stable set of neutral and different constitutions, there exists at least one preference profile for which there are several self-designating constitutions. We will see that, besides its purely dynamic meaning, this section can alternatively be seen as a justification for discriminating between self-designating constitutions on dynamic grounds. 5 Once again, since our notion of stability is political and not mathematical, we do not mean by this interpretation that a change in preferences leads to not changing the constitution, we mean that a change in preferences leads to a new implementable (because politically stable) constitution. 6

8 In our example with Preferences 1, dict 1 and borda are self-designating. But borda designates dict 1 whereas the opposite is not true. Then, dynamically, borda can lead to or accept the implementation of dict 1 but once dict 1 is designated, there is no way to go back to borda. dict 1 could be said to be "more self-designating" than borda and we will say that such constitutions are strongly self-designating. Following, our condition of Strong Stability that requires that at least one strongly self-designating constitution exists for each preference profile, is a dynamic condition as well as a way of discriminating between self-designating constitutions in cases of multiple equilibria. We will show that strong stability is rather restrictive and we will be able to exhaustively identify sets of neutral constitutions that satisfy it. We will also show that these two dynamic features, i.e. relationships between self-designating and non self-designating constitutions on the one hand, and between self-designating constitutions themselves on the other hand, are linked. Indeed, imposing the strong stability and dynamic stability axioms is equivalent to imposing the existence and uniqueness of the strongly self-designating constitution. Thus, this paper can also be read as suggesting a solution to the multiple equilibria problem using dynamic arguments. The paper proceeds as follows. In Section 2, we briefly review the literature. In Section 3, we set the formal framework. In Section 4, we give an example to illustrate all the notions used. In Section 5, we deal with the condition of stability for sets of neutral constitutions. In Section 6, we deal with the dynamic relationships between self-designating and non self-designating constitutions. In Section 7, we deal with the dynamic relationships between self-designating constitutions themselves. In Section 8, we prove the link between those two relationships. 7

9 2 Related Literature In this part, we will briefly discuss a few recent studies that deal with the notion of political stability in social choice theory. As far as we know, the dynamic aspects of the stability problem has never been studied. [Koray, 2000] is the first to study a notion which is close to what is called self-designation here. In his study, the timing is divided into two periods. In the second one, the society has to make a choice from some fundamentals. In the first period, the society chooses how the choice will be made in the second period. Individuals build their preferences over social choice functions in the first period anticipating and considering what the outcome will be in the second period. In this framework, Universally Self-Selective social choice functions are searched for. A universally self-selective social choice function is a social choice function that is self-designating whatever the set to which it belongs. The main result is the following: "a unanimous and neutral social choice function is universally self-selective if, and only if, it is dictatorial". Intuitively, if individual i wants to make sure that her most valued alternative will be chosen in the second period, she designates herself as a dictator in the first period. Our study considers a different meaning of "stability". According to [Koray, 2000], since self-selectivity must be universal, stability is the feature of a social choice function. For us, self-designation of a social choice correspondence depends on the set it is considered with. And stability is the feature of a set of constitutions, namely that this set always contains a self-designating social choice correspondence. In this sense, and as already noticed in [Houy, 2004], we just generalize the methodology of social choice theory. Indeed, as noticed by [Sen, 1999], the usual methodology consists in trying to find social choice functions (or correspondences) "more legitimate" than others on normative grounds. We look for "more legitimate" sets of constitutions on dynamic or positive grounds here. In this sense, our frame- 8

10 work allows us to broaden the usual scope of social choice theory by dealing with new objects, namely sets of constitutions. A generalization of this idea is given in [Houy, 2004] where sets of sets of... of sets of constitutions are studied. Since we do not impose the universality of the self-selection feature, we do not need to impose the consequentialism of individuals, and this is the most important difference between [Koray, 2000] s approach and ours. We consider that the choice of a constitution is possibly made on ethical grounds. As an illustration the reader is invited to wonder if he would agree to be a dictator. I do not think the answer is obvious. In reality, it is certainly the case that preferences are built with a consequentialist dimension but not only. Such an idea has been recently studied in [Segal, 2000], for instance. As a consequence, we do not restrict individual preferences. Actually, we do not even need to deal with any fundamental. We deal only with preferences over constitutions themselves. In this sense, our study should be seen as the study of a minimal positive requirement. More recently, [Barbera and Jackson, 2004] have studied the stability of quota rules only. People are still consequentialist but in the first period they do not know their second period preferences. This work has been extended more recently by [Sosnowska, 2002] for weighted voting rules, [Wakayama, 2002] who introduces abstention and [Polborn and Messner, 2002] in overlapping generations models. As in ours, in all these studies, the "self-designation" notion is the feature of a social choice function but it is dependent on other elements of the set to which it belongs, namely, quota rules. The most important difference is that we do not restrict our attention to quota rules or any other specific rules. Moreover, all these studies need to deal with fundamentals. We will be more abstract. The same differences (consequentialism and restriction) exist between our study and the ones from the constitutional design literature such as 9

11 [Rae, 1969], [Romer and Rosenthal, 1983] and more recently [Aghion and Bolton, 2003]. 3 Formal Framework Let N be the set of individuals in the society. 2 N < is the cardinality of this set, the finite number of individuals. For any set A, we will denote R i (A) the preference relation of individual i over A. R i (A) is the set of all possible preference relations of i over A. With a natural notation, R N (A) is a preference profile for all the individuals over A. R N (A), product on i of the R i (A)s, is the set of all possible preference profiles of the society over A. We will consider that the preferences of the individuals are independent. A very important assumption for the sequel is the Universal Domain one. As already noticed, setting this assumption implies that we refuse any consequentialist justification for the preferences of the individuals. Assumption 1 (Universal Domain) The preferences of the individuals can take any form. The society must make a choice from a set of alternatives, C 0. C 0 = 2 C0 is the set of non-empty subsets of C 0. For the sake of simplicity, a first level social choice correspondence (SCC 1 ) is defined a bit differently from what is usually done in the literature. Definition 1 (SCC 1 ) f is a first-level social choice correspondence (SCC 1 ) if, and only if, c 0 C 0, R N (c 0 ) R N (c 0 ), f(c 0,R N (c 0 )) f(r N (c 0 )), f(r N (c 0 )) c 0. Notice that the choice of the society can be made from any subset of C 0. Defining SCC 1 s uniquely on C 0 would not set any problem. We will denote 10

12 C 1 the set of all SCC 1 s. We will denote C 1 the set of all non empty subsets of SCC 1 s. Then, we assume that individuals have preferences over the set of SCC 1 s. Assumption 1 implies that preferences over the set of SCC 1 s do not depend on preferences between the elements of C 0. We define a second level social choice correspondence (SCC 2 ) as a mapping, from any subset of SCC 1 s and from any profile of preferences over this subset onto the set of all non empty subsets of this subset. Definition 2 (SCC 2 ) f is a second level social choice correspondence (SCC 2 ) if, and only if, c 1 C 1, R N (c 1 ) R N (c 1 ), f(c 1,R N (c 1 )) f(r N (c 1 )), f(r N (c 1 )) c 1. We denote C 2 the set of all SCC 2 s and C 2 = 2 C2. Now, we can define a constitution as a pair of one SCC 1 and one SCC 2. Definition 3 (Constitution) f = (f 1,f 2 ) is a constitution if, and only if, f 1 C 1 and f 2 C 2. We will note Z 2, the set of all constitutions and Z 2 = 2 Z2. Finally, for any set of constitutions C = {(fi 1,fi 2 )} i 1,I Z 2, we will note Γ k (C) = {fi k } i 1,I. In this article, we will study only neutral constitutions. Before defining this notion, we will need a definition. Definition 4 (Rσ N (X)) Let X,X C 0 C 1 be such that X = X. Let σ be a one-to-one function between X and X. Rσ N (X) is defined as i N, (a,b) X,σ(a)Rσ(X)σ(b) i ar i (X)b. 11

13 Then, R N σ (X) is the preference profile obtained when each individual has changed, in his preferences, each alternative a of X by its image σ(a) of X = σ(x). For instance, if there are two alternatives, a and b, two individuals, 1 and 2, and that preferences are given by ar 1 ({a,b})b and br 2 ({a,b})a, if we define σ as σ(a) = b and σ(b) = a, we have br 1 σ({a,b})a and ar 2 σ({a,b})b. Besides, notice that if c and d are other alternatives (not necessarily of the same level as a and b), by defining σ as σ(a) = c and σ(b) = d, we can also have cr 1 σ({a,b})d and dr 2 σ({a,b})c. With this definition, the neutrality axiom can be stated as follows. Axiom 1 (Neutrality) A constitution f = (f 1,f 2 ) is neutral if and only if, i,i {0, 1}, (X,X ) C i C i with X = X, R N (X) R N (X), σ one-to-one function between X and X, x f i+1 (R N (X)) σ(x) f i +1 (R N σ (X)). As a consequence of the neutrality axiom, if two constitutions are different with respect to their SCC 1 s, then, they are also different with respect to their SCC 2 s. 6 For the sake of simplicity, we will only consider sets of constitutions such that all the SCC 1 s are mutually different. Using this remark, we will now introduce a new formalism 7. In the sequel, we will deal with a generic set of constitutions noted C Z 2. We will say that a constitution f = (f 1,f 2 ) C designates a constitution g = (g 1,g 2 ) C, and we will write g f(r N (C)) if, an only if, g 1 f 2 (R N (Γ 1 (C))). For the sake of simplicity, we will also not be fully rigorous with the notation of preferences and we will write, R N (C) instead 6 Notice that the converse is not necessarily true. Notice also that, two SCC 2 s can be identical on a given set of SCC 1 s. 7 Notice that formally, it would be sufficient that all the SCC 1 s considered be different and that all the constitutions be neutral only with respect to their SCC 2 in the following sense (see [Barbera and Jackson, 2004] for a discussion of the difference of neutralities). Axiom 2 (Weak Neutrality) A constitution (f 1,f 2 ) is weakly neutral if, and only if, X C 1, R N (X) R N (X), σ permutation of X, x f 2 (R N (X)) σ(x) f 2 (R N σ (X)). 12

14 of R N (Γ 1 (C)). We will also say "constitution" for "social choice correspondence" since a SCC 1 uniquely defines a SCC 2 and hence a constitution. Mathematically, the neutrality axiom has some importance since it allows us to deal with orbites of preferences independently. Indeed, we did not impose any consistency condition between preferences of different orbites. The orbite of a preferences profile R N (C), written < R N (C) >, is obtained by considering all the possible permutations of the alternatives. Definition 5 (Orbite) < R N (C) >= {R N (C) R N (C)/ σ,r N (C) = Rσ N (C)}. Obviously, memberships of orbites describe equivalence classes. Then, any proposition concerning C is true for all preference profiles if, and only if, it is true for all preference profiles of each orbite. In the sequel, with no loss of generality, we will concentrate on a given orbite, say < R N (C) >. By definition, it is possible that a constitution designates all the others and itself. Such a constitution will be called universal and we will say that a set of constitutions always having a universal element satisfies the Universality condition. Definition 6 (Universality) The set of constitutions C satisfies the universality condition if, and only if, R N (C) < R N (C) >, f C, g C,g f(r N (C)). It is also possible that a constitution be designated by all the others and by itself. Such a constitution will be called unanimous and we will say that a set of constitutions always having an unanimous element satisfies the Unanimity condition. Definition 7 (Unanimity) The set of constitutions C satisfies the unanimity condition if, and only if, R N (C) < R N (C) >, f C, g C,f g(r N (C)). 13

15 Finally, for practical reasons, we need a few more definitions. Definition 8 (Self-Designating (SD)) f C,f SD(R N (C)) if, and only if, f f(r N (C)). Definition 9 (Indirectly Designated (ID)) i n ID(i 0 ;R N (C)) if, and only if, there exist r N and a sequence {i k } r k=1 with k,i k C, such that k 0;r 1,i k+1 i k (R N (C)) and i n = i r. Then, SD(R N (C)) is the set of self-designating constitutions, i.e. those that, when implemented by the society, designate themselves when the preference profile is R N (C). ID(i 0 ;R N (C)) is the set of constitutions that can be reached from i 0 by iterating the choice procedure. Obviously, by definition, f SD(R N (C)) implies f ID(f;R N (C)). Definition 10 (Densely Designated (DD)) X C densely designates X C ( X = X ) if, and only if, x X, x X such that: 1. x + x = X +1 = X +1, 2. f x, g x, g f(r N (C)). We will write DD(X,X,R N (C)) for "X densely designates X ". Then, X densely designates X (X and X being of same size) if, and only of, there exist two subsets x and x of X and X respectively such that each constitution of x designates all the constitutions of x and x = X +1 x. Let us give an illustration. If X = X = 4, X densely designates X if, and only if, all the constitutions of X designate the same constitution of X, 3 constitutions in X designate 2 constitutions of X, 2 constitutions of X designate 3 constitutions of X or one constitution of X designates all the constitutions of X. Generally, the intuition behind this definition is the following: X densely designates X if, and only if, a large enough number of constitutions in X designate a large enough number of constitutions in X. 14

16 Said differently, X densely designates X if and only if, when, restricted to the constitutions of X, the constitutions of X are not too precise and too different. 4 Example To introduce the intuitions behind all the dynamics features used in this article and to make the definition clear, we will give an example. Assume a society composed of 7 individuals, N = {1,..., 7}. Assume that, f 1 is the plurality rule, f 2 is the Borda rule, f 3 is the anti-dictatorship of individual 1, f 4 is the dictatorship of individual 2, f 5 is the dictatorship of individual 3 8. Let us consider the following preferences for individuals, R N ({f 1,f 2,f 3,f 4,f 5 }): f 1 1 f 2 1 f 3 1 f 5 1 f 4, f 4 2 f 3 2 f 2 2 f 1 2 f 5, f 3 3 f 5 3 f 2 3 f 1 3 f 4, f 1 4 f 3 4 f 2 4 f 5 4 f 4, f 2 5 f 1 5 f 3 5 f 5 5 f 4, f 2 6 f 1 6 f 5 6 f 3 6 f 4, f 3 7 f 1 7 f 2 7 f 5 7 f 4.. For the sake of simplicity, and even if it not necessary in this article, we will collectively rationalize those choices and set the following weak social ordering for the considered preference profile. fi is the weak social ordering obtained when the constitution f i is implemented. f 1 f1 f 2 f1 f 3 f1 f 4 f1 f 5, 8 Notice that all these constitutions are neutral. 15

17 f 1 f2 f 2 f2 f 3 f2 f 5 f2 f 4, f 4 f3 f 5 f3 f 3 f3 f 2 f3 f 1, f 4 f4 f 3 f4 f 2 f4 f 1 f4 f 5, f 3 f5 f 5 f5 f 2 f5 f 1 f5 f 4. Then, by definition of collective rationalization, we have f i (R N (X)) = {f j X/ f k X, f j fi f k }. f 1 (R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }; f 1 (R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = {f 1 ;f 3 }; f 1 (R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 })) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }. f 2 (R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }; f 2 (R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 })) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }. f 3 (R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = {f 4 }; f 3 (R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = {f 4 }; f 3 (R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 })) = {f 5 }. f 4 (R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = {f 4 }; f 4 (R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = {f 4 }. f 5 (R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 })) = {f 3 }. In a first step, let us assume that this society must choose its constitution in the set {f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 }. If the preference profile is given by R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 }), then, f 1 and f 4 are self-designating since f 1 f 1 (R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) and f 4 f 4 (R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) whereas f 3 is not, f 3 / f 3 (R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })). If we impose only the self-designation feature as a minimal requirement (i.e. that there exist at least one self-designating constitution), this set is valid, for the preference profile R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 }). But one can wonder what would happen if we did not know the preference profile a priori. Then, it is possible that the preference profile be given by Rσ N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 }) with σ(f 1 ) = f 4, σ(f 3 ) = f 3 16

18 and σ(f 4 ) = f 1. In this case, by neutrality, we have f 1 (Rσ N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = σ({f 1 ;f 3 }) = {f 3 ;f 4 } and f 3 (Rσ N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = f 4 (Rσ N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 })) = {f 1 }. No constitution is self-designating, the set of constitutions {f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 } does not always display (i.e. for R N ({f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 }) and all the preference profiles of its orbite) a self-designating element. The condition imposing that there always exist a self-designating constitution, not satisfied by {f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 }, is the Stability condition. The reader can check that the set of constitutions {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 } satisfies the stability condition. The second condition has the following meaning: departing from any initial constitution and for any preference profile, the society can reach a self-designating constitution. Said differently, any constitution indirectly designates a self-designating constitution. This condition is the Dynamic Stability condition. In this example, {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 } does not satisfy the dynamic stability condition. Indeed, if the preferences of the individuals are given by R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 }) and if the initial constitution is f 3, the first political decision will change the constitution for f 5. Then, implementing f 5, the constitution will be changed for f 3 and there is no way out of this cycle. We can check that the set of constitutions {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 } satisfies the dynamic stability condition. Let us still consider the set of constitutions {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 }. When the preference profile is given by R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 }), f 1, f 2 and f 4 are selfdesignating. We can also see that f 4 is indirectly designated by f 1 and f 2 whereas those two constitutions are not indirectly designated by f 4. Then, if initially, f 1 or f 2 (or even f 3 ) are implemented, f 4 can be reached whereas the converse is not true. In some sense, f 4 leads to the most stable political life. We will say that f 4 is strongly self-designating (whereas f 1 and f 2 are only self-designating). The condition imposing that there always exist at least one strongly self-designating constitution is the Strong Stability condition. We will see that this condition is almost as restrictive as the the condition 17

19 of Unique Strong Stability that requires that there always exist exactly one strongly self-designating constitution. We could check that {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 } satisfies the unique strong stability condition whereas {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 } does not. In the sequel, we will give relationships between all those different stability conditions. 5 Stability The first condition on C imposes that there always exist at least one self-designating constitution. Axiom 3 (Stability) The set of constitutions C satisfies the stability axiom if, and only if, R N (C) < R N (C) >, f C such that f SD(R N (C)). We are able to display necessary and sufficient conditions for a set of neutral constitutions to be stable. Theorem 1 9 The set C of c neutral constitutions, satisfies the stability axiom if, and only if, ( )R N (C) < R N (C) >, X C and X C such that: 1. X + X = c + 1, 2. f X, g X, g f(r N (C)). Then, a set of c neutral constitutions is stable if and only if there (always) exist two subsets of constitutions X and X such that the sum of the sizes of X and X equals c + 1 and all the constitutions of X designate all the constitutions of X. There are two special cases. If X = 1, one of the 9 For the sake of simplicity, we did not use all the definitions introduced so far. The same theorem could have been written as follows: The set C of c neutral constitutions, satisfies the stability axiom if, and only if, ( ) 10 R N (C) < R N (C) >, DD(C; C;R N (C)). 18

20 constitutions has to designate all the others and itself: it is universal. If X = c, one of the constitutions is designated by all, it is unanimous. Corollary 1 For a set of neutral constitutions C, Unanimity or Universality imply Stability. Between those two extreme cases, we can have intermediate situations. The smaller X, i.e. the number of constitutions that must have positive agreement on X, the greater this agreement, i.e. the size of X. Said differently, if one wants stability to be satisfied by C, there is a trade-off between the number of constitutions that have to positively resemble each other and the minimal degree to which they resemble each other. In other words, we cannot have very precise (small X ) and very different constitutions (small X). Let us illustrate this theorem by an example. We have seen in Section 4 that the set C = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 } with f 1 (R N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }, f 2 (R N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }, f 3 (R N (C)) = {f 5 } and f 5 (R N (C)) = {f 3 }, satisfies the stability condition. Indeed, we can consider X = {f 1 ;f 2 } and X = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 } so that the conditions given in Theorem 1 are satisfied. On the contrary, if we have C = {f 1;f 2;f 3;f 5} with f 1(R N (C )) = {f 2;f 3}, f 2(R N (C )) = {f 1;f 2;f 3}, f 3(R N (C )) = {f 5} and f 5(R N (C )) = {f 3}, then it is not possible to find two sets X and X that satisfy the conditions given in Theorem 1. And indeed, we can check that if the preferences were given by R N ({f 1;f 5;f 3;f 2}), then one would have f 1(R N ({f 1;f 5;f 3;f 2})) = {f 5;f 3}, f 2(R N ({f 1;f 5;f 3;f 2})) = {f 1;f 5;f 3}, f 3(R N ({f 1;f 5;f 3;f 2})) = {f 2} and f 5(R N ({f 1;f 5;f 3;f 2})) = {f 3} and then, there would be no self-designating constitution. The set {f 1;f 2} of constitutions that are the most similar agree only on the set {f 2;f 3}. To have stability, we would need to have either a one-element broader agreement or the same agreement shared by one more constitution. In {f 1;f 2;f 3;f 5}, constitutions are too different (or equivalently 19

21 too precise) for having stability. Summing up, if, as we interpreted above, the purpose of the constitutionalist is to build a set of constitutions from which a society could choose its constitution, and if this constitutionalist does not know anything about the preferences of the individuals a priori, then, on a given orbit, he cannot design very different and very precise constitutions. There is necessarily a trade-off between, on the one hand the differences between the constitutions of the set, and on the other hand the preciseness of all the constitutions of the set. Indeed, the more precise the constitutions, the less broad the agreement between (possibly partially) similar constitutions can be. 6 Dynamic Stability As shown in Section 4, stability does not imply dynamic stability. Stability imposes that there always be at least one self-designating constitution. However, it does not imply that, implementing any constitution of C, one should reach one of them. It is possible to be in a cycle with no selfdesignating constitution and no way out. The dynamic stability axiom copes with this problem: Axiom 4 (Dynamic Stability) The set C of constitutions satisfies the Dynamic Stability axiom if, and only if, R N (C) < R N (C) >, f C, g SD(R N (C)),g ID(f,R N (C)). This axiom requires that, not only, should there always be at least one self-designating constitution, but that also, departing from any constitution, one can reach one of the self-designating one. The following proposition is then obvious: Proposition 1 For a set C of constitutions, Unanimity implies Dynamic Stability. 20

22 We can prove the following theorem as well. Theorem 2 A set C of neutral constitutions satisfies the Dynamic Stability axiom if, and only if, ( )R N (C) R N (C), X,X C such that X = X, one of the following is true: 1. DD(X,X,R N (C)), 2. f X, g C \ X, g f(r N (C)). First, let us notice that this theorem is a generalization of Theorem 1. Indeed, Theorem 1 corresponds to the case X = X = C. Then, it is obvious that dynamic stability implies stability. Proposition 2 For a set C of constitutions, Dynamic Stability implies Stability. Theorem 2 states that dynamic stability is satisfied if, and only if, the following statement is true: if all constitutions of the subset X designate exclusively constitutions from the subset X (with X = X ), then X must densely designate X. Above, we interpreted Theorem 1 as a condition to satisfy if a constitutionalist wants to build a "good" set of constitutions. How could Theorem 2 be interpreted in the same framework? Let us consider a subset X of constitutions. There are three possibilities. I. the outcomes of the constitutions of X are numerous enough, i.e. the union of the outcomes of X has a strictly greater size than X, II. the outcomes of the constitutions of X are not numerous enough, i.e. the union of the outcomes of X has a smaller size than X, but the constitutions of X satisfy the unanimity/universality trade-off explained in Section 5, 21

23 III. the outcomes of the constitutions of X are not numerous enough, i.e. the union of the outcomes of X has a smaller size than X, and the constitutions of X do not satisfy the unanimity/universality trade-off explained in Section 5. If, for any X, conditions I or II are satisfied, then the dynamic stability condition is also satisfied. On the contrary, if there exists a subset of constitutions that has a "small" range of outcomes and those outcomes are not identical or universal enough (with respect of its size), then, dynamic stability is not satisfied. Then, simplifying a bit, Theorem 2 expresses a stronger preciseness/difference trade-off than Theorem 1 in the sense that this trade-off should be satisfied for any two subsets of constitutions. Finally, let us illustrate Theorem 2 by two examples. First, let us define the following constitutions for a given preference profile, R N ({f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 ;f 5 ;f 6 ;f 7 }) = R N (C). f 1 (R N (C)) = f 2 (R N (C)) = f 3 (R N (C)) = f 4 (R N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 3 ;f 4 ;f 7 }, f 5 (R N (C)) = {f 2 ;f 6 }, f 6 (R N (C)) = {f 5 ;f 6 }, f 7 (R N (C)) = {f 2 ;f 5 }. It is easy to check that for the given preference profile, any constitution can lead to a self-designating one. However, this set of constitutions does not satisfy the dynamic stability axiom. Indeed, if one considers X = {f 5 ;f 6 ;f 7 } and X = {f 2 ;f 5 ;f 6 }, each element of X only designates elements in X and X does not densely designates X, DD(X,X,R N (C)). Let us check that C is not dynamically stable. Let us have σ defined by σ(f i ) = f i for i {1, 3, 4, 5}, σ(f 2 ) = f 6, σ(f 6 ) = f 7 and σ(f 7 ) = f 2. Then f 1 (Rσ N (C)) = f 2 (Rσ N (C)) = f 3 (Rσ N (C)) = f 4 (Rσ N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 }, 22

24 f 5 (Rσ N (C)) = {f 6 ;f 7 }, f 6 (Rσ N (C)) = {f 5 ;f 7 }, f 7 (Rσ N (C)) = {f 5 ;f 6 }. As one can see, from f 5, f 6 or f 7 it is not possible to reach any self-designating constitution (which are f 1, f 2, f 3 and f 4 here). As a second illustration, consider the case given in Section 4. We already noticed that the set of constitutions {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 } is not dynamically stable whereas the set {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 } is. Indeed, one can remark that, in the set {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 5 }, if one considers the subsets X = X = {f 3 ;f 5 }, the elements of X exclusively designate those of X, but X does not densely designates X. Notice that in the set {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 } there is no such pair of subsets of same size. For instance the constitutions of the subset X = {f 3 ;f 4 } exclusively designate the constitutions of X = {f 3 ;f 4 } but X densely designates X. Alternatively, if X = X = {f 2 ;f 3 ;f 4 }, X does not densely designate X but each element of X does not exclusively designate those of X. Another way to express Theorem 2 is as follows. Proposition 3 A set C of neutral constitutions satisfies the dynamic stability axiom if, and only if, R N (C) R N (C), X C, [ f X, g C \ X, such that g f(r N (C))] DD(X,X,R N (C)). Then, a set of neutral constitutions satisfies the dynamic stability axiom if, and only if, for any subset of constitutions X, for any preference profile, if all the designated constitutions by elements of X are in X, then X densely designates itself. This proposition, closer to the initial definition of dynamic stability, means the following. Assume that implementing any constitution from the subset X of C necessarily keeps the society within X. Then, if restricting the 23

25 designation system to X does not satisfy the stability condition, it is obvious that C does not satisfy dynamic stability. If this case never happens, the set C satisfies dynamic stability. 7 Strong Stability In the previous section, we have dealt with the relationship between selfdesignating constitutions and those that are not self-designating. We will now deal with the relationship between self-designating constitutions themselves. So far, we have not addressed the problem of multiple equilibria. As shown in the examples, a set can satisfy dynamic stability and simultaneously there can be several self-designating constitutions in it for some preference profiles. Further, [Houy, 2004] proved that it is not possible to achieve uniqueness of the self-designating constitution for all preference profiles. So the question we raise in this section is the following: when there are several self-designating constitutions, are some of them more "legitimate" as constitutions to be used by the society? And, if the answer is positive, is it possible to impose the uniqueness of it on all preference profiles? Let us assume the following case. C = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }, the preference profile is given by R N (C) and: f 1 (R N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 2 }, f 2 (R N (C)) = {f 2 ;f 3 }, f 3 (R N (C)) = {f 3 }. In this example, all the constitutions are self-designating. However, implementing f 1 and f 2 can lead to f 3 whereas f 3 cannot lead to any other self-designating constitution. We claim that f 3 is more "legitimate", in the sense that it is more "stable" than f 1 and f 2. This idea is formalized in the 24

26 following definition. We denote the set of constitutions such as f 3, Strongly Self-Designating: Definition 11 (SSD) Let C be a set of constitutions. SSD(R N (C)) SD(R N (C)) is defined by: f SSD(R N (C)), g SD(R N (C)) f, g / ID(f,R N (C)), g SD(R N (C)) SSD(R N (C)), f SSD(R N (C)) s.t. f ID(g,R N (C)). If it exists 11, SSD(R N (C)) is the set of self-designating constitutions that does not indirectly (or directly) designate any other self-designating constitution. Moreover, all self-designating constitutions not in SSD(R N (C)) must indirectly (or directly) designate one constitution of SSD(R N (C)). So this definition considers SSD(R N (C)) as the maximal subset of SD(R N (C)) of constitutions that do not designate any other self-designating one, and if there is a subset of SD(R N (C)) of constitutions designating exclusively each other, then SSD(R N (C)) does not exist. 12 For instance, if C = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 } and f 1 (R N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 2 }, f 2 (R N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 2 }, f 3 (R N (C)) = {f 3 }, then SSD(R N (C)) does not exist even though SD(R N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }. Viewed in this way, the constitutions of SSD(R N (C)) have interesting features. Indeed, if this set exists, then once the society implements a constitution of SSD(R N (C)), it cannot reach another self-designating constitution, whereas if it implements a self-designating constitution that is not an element 11 Saying that SSD(R N (C)) does not exist is different from saying that it is an empty set. Clearly, by definition, if SD(R N (C)), then SSD(R N (C)) (but still it can not exist). If SD(R N (C)) =, then SSD(R N (C)) = (and then, it exists). Moreover, it is easy to see that if SSD(R N (C)) exists, it is unique. 12 In particular, SD(R N (C)) = 1 SD(R N (C)) = SSD(R N (C)). 25

27 of SSD(R N (C)), then it can reach one that is an element of SSD(R N (C)). However, if SSD(R N (C)) does not exist, there is the possibility that the society never be in such a comfortable situation. This is why, we impose that SSD(R N (C)) exists for any preference profile. Axiom 5 (Strong Stability) The set C of constitutions satisfies the Strong Stability axiom if, and only if, R N (C) < R N (C) >, SSD(R N (C)) exists. Clearly, this axiom is stronger than the stability axiom. Actually, it is much stronger since we are able to fully identify the sets of neutral constitutions that satisfy the Strong Stability axiom: Theorem 3 Let C = {(f i ) i 1;c } be a set of neutral constitutions. C satisfies strong stability if, and only if, it is one of: c 4 and (i,j,k) 1;c (i j) such that: l 1;c,l / {i;j} {f k } = f l (R N (C)) and, {(f r ) r 1;c {k} } = f i (R N (C)) = f j (R N (C)), f C unanimous and g C f, {f /g f (R N (C))} 1, f C universal and h C f, h(r N (C)) = 1. An immediate corollary is that C, to satisfy Strong Stability, must necessarily satisfy the stability axiom with X {1; 2;c} in Theorem 1. To ease the understanding, a matrix representation of sets of neutral constitutions satisfying the strong stability axiom is given in the end of the next section. 8 Unique Strong Stability In the previous section, we have discriminated between self-designating constitutions. But it is still possible that there are several legitimate potential 26

28 constitutions and then we still did not fully tackle the multiple solutions problem. For instance, if C = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 } and f 1 (R N (C)) = {f 1 ;f 2 ;f 3 }, f 2 (R N (C)) = {f 2 }, f 3 (R N (C)) = {f 3 }, then the strong stability axiom is satisfied and here SSD(R N (C)) = {f 2 ;f 3 } = 2. Could we go further and now impose the uniqueness of the Strongly Self- Designating constitution? This way, we would definitely solve the multiple equilibria problem using dynamic requirements. Axiom 6 (Unique Strong Stability) The set C of constitutions satisfies the Unique Strong Stability axiom if, and only if, R N (C) < R N (C) >, SSD(R N (C)) exists, and SSD(R N (C)) = 1. This axiom is obviously stronger than the strong stability one. How restrictive it is for C is shown in the following theorem: Theorem 4 Let C = {(f i ) i 1;c } be a set of neutral constitutions. C satisfies unique strong stability if, and only if, it is one of the following: c 4 and (i,j,k) 1;c (i j) such that: l 1;c,l / {i;j} {f k } = f l (R N (C)) and, {(f r ) r 1;c {k} } = f i (R N (C)) = f j (R N (C)), f C unanimous and g C f, {f /g f (R N (C))} 1. As can be clearly seen, if one rules out the cases of universality, there is no difference between strong stability and unique strong stability. But, more importantly, a consequence of this last theorem is that there is a link 27

29 between our two parts: there is a dependence between, on the one hand, the relationship between the self-designating constitutions and the others, and on the other hand, the relationship between the self-designating constitutions themselves. This is what is expressed in Theorem 5: Theorem 5 For a set C of neutral constitutions, Unique Strong Stability Strong Stability and Dynamic Stability. In this case, the sets of constitutions given in Theorem 4 have very interesting features. Indeed, in those cases and only in those, SSD(R N (C)) is a singleton for each preference profile and this constitution is reachable from any other, self-designating or not self-designating. Finally, to ease the understanding, we give a matrix representation of the sets of constitutions displayed in Theorems 3 and 4. To do so, let us have the set of neutral constitutions, C = {f i } i 1;n. Since all the SCC 1 are different, we will represent it in n n boolean matrix {x ij }. 13 Let us consider a preference profile R N (C). We will set that x ij = 1 if, and only if, f i designates f j, f j f i (R N (C)). Following, since the constitutions are neutral, a permutation σ of the preferences can be represented simply by a permutation σ of the columns of the initial matrix. Hence, a matrix represents the designation scheme for one preference profile only, but all the designation schemes for the whole orbite of preference profiles can be obtained by permuting the columns of the matrix. With this representation, the following sets of neutral constitutions, C = {f i } i 1;n, are the only ones to satisfy the Unique Strong Stability axiom. Indeed, they are representations of the sets of constitutions displayed in Theorem x ij will be the element in the i th row, j th column. 28

Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra

Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra Wonki Jo Cho Biung-Ghi Ju June 27, 2018 Abstract We study the problem of determining memberships to the groups in a Boolean algebra. The Boolean algebra is composed

More information

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies Iian B. Smythe October 20, 2015 Abstract Does there exist a reasonable method of voting that when presented with three or more alternatives avoids the undue

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011 Complete Characterization of Functions Satisfying the Conditions of Arrow s Theorem Elchanan Mossel and Omer Tamuz arxiv:0910.2465v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011 April 15, 2011 Abstract Arrow s theorem implies

More information

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice Susumu Cato Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo, Japan Society for the Promotion of Science Research Fellow First Version: January 10, 2007

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 0/06 CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY by Indraneel Dasgupta July 00 DP 0/06 ISSN 1360-438 UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France Thema Working Paper n 2010-02 Université de Cergy Pontoise, France Sincere Scoring Rules Nunez Matias May, 2010 Sincere Scoring Rules Matías Núñez May 2010 Abstract Approval Voting is shown to be the unique

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 Rational Choice The central gure of economics theory is the individual decision-maker (DM). The typical example of a DM is the consumer. We shall assume

More information

Computational Tasks and Models

Computational Tasks and Models 1 Computational Tasks and Models Overview: We assume that the reader is familiar with computing devices but may associate the notion of computation with specific incarnations of it. Our first goal is to

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. H. Reiju Mihara reiju@ec.kagawa-u.ac.jp Economics, Kagawa University, Takamatsu, 760-8523, Japan April, 1999 [Social

More information

A Class of Partially Ordered Sets: III

A Class of Partially Ordered Sets: III A Class of Partially Ordered Sets: III by Geoffrey Hemion 1 Definitions To begin with, let us fix a certain notation. Let the pair (X, ) be a given poset. For a X, let a = {x X : x < a} and a = {x X :

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

Regular Choice and the Weak Axiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference

Regular Choice and the Weak Axiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference Regular Choice and the Weak xiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference Indraneel Dasgupta School of Economics, University of Nottingham, UK. and Prasanta K. Pattanaik Department of Economics, University of

More information

Implementation in undominated strategies by bounded mechanisms: The Pareto Correspondence

Implementation in undominated strategies by bounded mechanisms: The Pareto Correspondence Implementation in undominated strategies by bounded mechanisms: The Pareto Correspondence Saptarshi Mukherjee Eve Ramaekers Arunava Sen September 5, 2016 Preliminary and Incomplete Abstract We show that

More information

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010 Arrow s Paradox Prerna Nadathur January 1, 2010 Abstract In this paper, we examine the problem of a ranked voting system and introduce Kenneth Arrow s impossibility theorem (1951). We provide a proof sketch

More information

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY August 18, 2003 Aanund Hylland: # DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY Standard theory and alternatives 1. Introduction Individual decision making under uncertainty can be characterized as follows: The decision

More information

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 18 To recap Tuesday: We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Two finite populations, call them Men and Women, who want to

More information

Iterated Strict Dominance in Pure Strategies

Iterated Strict Dominance in Pure Strategies Iterated Strict Dominance in Pure Strategies We know that no rational player ever plays strictly dominated strategies. As each player knows that each player is rational, each player knows that his opponents

More information

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets 1 Rational and Real Numbers Recall that a number is rational if it can be written in the form a/b where a, b Z and b 0, and a number

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Todd Davies Symbolic Systems Program Stanford University joint work with Raja Shah, Renee Trochet, and Katarina Ling Decision

More information

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games MATHIEU MARTIN THEMA, Departments of Economics Université de Cergy Pontoise, 33 Boulevard du Port, 95011 Cergy Pontoise cedex, France. e-mail: mathieu.martin@eco.u-cergy.fr

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

On the scope of diagonal argument and on contradictory equivalence.

On the scope of diagonal argument and on contradictory equivalence. Daniil Teplitskiy, Russia, Saint Petersburg PSI Co. Ltd. 24JUN2011 To my teachers and good people Isaak Perchenok and Rustem Valeyev. To my friend Aleksey Kiselev whose intellectual paradigm underlies

More information

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information by Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics, Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA 30303

More information

Real Analysis Prof. S.H. Kulkarni Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 13 Conditional Convergence

Real Analysis Prof. S.H. Kulkarni Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 13 Conditional Convergence Real Analysis Prof. S.H. Kulkarni Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Lecture - 13 Conditional Convergence Now, there are a few things that are remaining in the discussion

More information

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives 3.- Social Choice and Welfare Economics 3.1 Arrow s Theorem We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives Let R denote the set of all preference relations

More information

The matrix approach for abstract argumentation frameworks

The matrix approach for abstract argumentation frameworks The matrix approach for abstract argumentation frameworks Claudette CAYROL, Yuming XU IRIT Report RR- -2015-01- -FR February 2015 Abstract The matrices and the operation of dual interchange are introduced

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

Turing Machines, diagonalization, the halting problem, reducibility

Turing Machines, diagonalization, the halting problem, reducibility Notes on Computer Theory Last updated: September, 015 Turing Machines, diagonalization, the halting problem, reducibility 1 Turing Machines A Turing machine is a state machine, similar to the ones we have

More information

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Chapter One. The Real Number System Chapter One. The Real Number System We shall give a quick introduction to the real number system. It is imperative that we know how the set of real numbers behaves in the way that its completeness and

More information

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object.

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object. 1.10. BASICS CONCEPTS OF SET THEORY 193 1.10 Basics Concepts of Set Theory Having learned some fundamental notions of logic, it is now a good place before proceeding to more interesting things, such as

More information

Nontransitive Dice and Arrow s Theorem

Nontransitive Dice and Arrow s Theorem Nontransitive Dice and Arrow s Theorem Undergraduates: Arthur Vartanyan, Jueyi Liu, Satvik Agarwal, Dorothy Truong Graduate Mentor: Lucas Van Meter Project Mentor: Jonah Ostroff 3 Chapter 1 Dice proofs

More information

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116 THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM BY JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116 COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE UNIVERSITY Box 208281 New Haven, Connecticut 06520-8281

More information

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Pingzhong Tang and Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University {kenshin,sandholm}@cscmuedu Abstract The Muller-Satterthwaite

More information

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy.

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy. Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy. Amrita Dhillon and Ben Lockwood This version: March 2001 Abstract De Sinopoli and Turrini (1999) present an example to show

More information

Revealed Reversals of Preferences

Revealed Reversals of Preferences Revealed Reversals of Preferences Houy Nicolas October 5, 2009 Abstract We weaken the implicit assumption of rational choice theory that imposes that preferences do not depend on the choice set. We concentrate

More information

"Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach", by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001),

Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach, by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001), February 25, 2015 "Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach", by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001), 99-105. Also recommended: M. A. Satterthwaite, "Strategy-Proof

More information

Background on Coherent Systems

Background on Coherent Systems 2 Background on Coherent Systems 2.1 Basic Ideas We will use the term system quite freely and regularly, even though it will remain an undefined term throughout this monograph. As we all have some experience

More information

CMU Social choice 2: Manipulation. Teacher: Ariel Procaccia

CMU Social choice 2: Manipulation. Teacher: Ariel Procaccia CMU 15-896 Social choice 2: Manipulation Teacher: Ariel Procaccia Reminder: Voting Set of voters Set of alternatives Each voter has a ranking over the alternatives means that voter prefers to Preference

More information

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: Preference Aggregation, Judgment Aggregation, Graph Aggregation Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss

More information

Existence of Nash Networks in One-Way Flow Models

Existence of Nash Networks in One-Way Flow Models Existence of Nash Networks in One-Way Flow Models pascal billand a, christophe bravard a, sudipta sarangi b a CREUSET, Jean Monnet University, Saint-Etienne, France. email: pascal.billand@univ-st-etienne.fr

More information

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields 1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields Very informally speaking, a commutative ring is a set in which we can add, subtract and multiply elements so that the usual laws hold. A field is a commutative

More information

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting Countability 1 Motivation In topology as well as other areas of mathematics, we deal with a lot of infinite sets. However, as we will gradually discover, some infinite sets are bigger than others. Countably

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Sean Horan, Martin J. Osborne, and M. Remzi Sanver December 24, 2018 Abstract May

More information

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions Shurojit Chatterji, Remzi Sanver and Arunava Sen May 2010 Paper No. 07-2010 ANY OPINIONS EXPRESSED ARE THOSE OF THE AUTHOR(S) AND

More information

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Ryo-Ichi Nagahisa y Kansai University Koichi Suga z Waseda University November 14, 2017 Abstract A social state is assumed to be chracterized by welfare

More information

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013 Uncertainty Michael Peters December 27, 20 Lotteries In many problems in economics, people are forced to make decisions without knowing exactly what the consequences will be. For example, when you buy

More information

Measure and integration

Measure and integration Chapter 5 Measure and integration In calculus you have learned how to calculate the size of different kinds of sets: the length of a curve, the area of a region or a surface, the volume or mass of a solid.

More information

Basic counting techniques. Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School

Basic counting techniques. Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School Basic counting techniques Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School i LECTURE NOTES IN Elementary counting methods Periklis A. Papakonstantinou MSIS, Rutgers Business School ALL RIGHTS RESERVED

More information

Probability (Devore Chapter Two)

Probability (Devore Chapter Two) Probability (Devore Chapter Two) 1016-345-01: Probability and Statistics for Engineers Fall 2012 Contents 0 Administrata 2 0.1 Outline....................................... 3 1 Axiomatic Probability 3

More information

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. IAN KIMING 1. Motivation. It will not come as a big surprise to anyone when I say that we need the real numbers in mathematics. More to the point, we need to be able to

More information

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields 1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields Very informally speaking, a commutative ring is a set in which we can add, subtract and multiply elements so that the usual laws hold. A field is a commutative

More information

Recap Social Choice Fun Game Voting Paradoxes Properties. Social Choice. Lecture 11. Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1

Recap Social Choice Fun Game Voting Paradoxes Properties. Social Choice. Lecture 11. Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1 Social Choice Lecture 11 Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Recap 2 Social Choice 3 Fun Game 4 Voting Paradoxes 5 Properties Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 2 Formal Definition Definition

More information

Isomorphisms between pattern classes

Isomorphisms between pattern classes Journal of Combinatorics olume 0, Number 0, 1 8, 0000 Isomorphisms between pattern classes M. H. Albert, M. D. Atkinson and Anders Claesson Isomorphisms φ : A B between pattern classes are considered.

More information

6 Cosets & Factor Groups

6 Cosets & Factor Groups 6 Cosets & Factor Groups The course becomes markedly more abstract at this point. Our primary goal is to break apart a group into subsets such that the set of subsets inherits a natural group structure.

More information

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer Last time, when discussing the surprise exam paradox, we discussed the possibility that some claims could be true, but not knowable by certain individuals

More information

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design Makis Arsenis National Technical University of Athens April 216 Makis Arsenis (NTUA) AGT April 216 1 / 41 Outline 1 Social Choice Social Choice

More information

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction Tutorial on Mathematical Induction Roy Overbeek VU University Amsterdam Department of Computer Science r.overbeek@student.vu.nl April 22, 2014 1 Dominoes: from case-by-case to induction Suppose that you

More information

Section 2.5 : The Completeness Axiom in R

Section 2.5 : The Completeness Axiom in R Section 2.5 : The Completeness Axiom in R The rational numbers and real numbers are closely related. The set Q of rational numbers is countable and the set R of real numbers is not, and in this sense there

More information

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Social Choice Theory Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Social choice theory MWG, Chapter 21. JR, Chapter 6.2-6.5. Additional

More information

Game Theory and Rationality

Game Theory and Rationality April 6, 2015 Notation for Strategic Form Games Definition A strategic form game (or normal form game) is defined by 1 The set of players i = {1,..., N} 2 The (usually finite) set of actions A i for each

More information

Equivalent Forms of the Axiom of Infinity

Equivalent Forms of the Axiom of Infinity Equivalent Forms of the Axiom of Infinity Axiom of Infinity 1. There is a set that contains each finite ordinal as an element. The Axiom of Infinity is the axiom of Set Theory that explicitly asserts that

More information

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72 Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056 JEL code: D71, D72 Maastricht research school of Economics of TEchnology and ORganizations Universiteit Maastricht

More information

Study skills for mathematicians

Study skills for mathematicians PART I Study skills for mathematicians CHAPTER 1 Sets and functions Everything starts somewhere, although many physicists disagree. Terry Pratchett, Hogfather, 1996 To think like a mathematician requires

More information

Motion Fundamentals. 1 Postulates. 2 Natural Progression. Thomas Kirk

Motion Fundamentals. 1 Postulates. 2 Natural Progression. Thomas Kirk Motion Fundamentals Thomas Kirk I was asked by the Editor to respond to comments by the editorial referee on my article, Derivation of Reciprocal System Mathematics", and also to comment on K.V.K. Nehru

More information

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers Chapter 1 The Real Numbers 1.1. Some Preliminaries Discussion: The Irrationality of 2. We begin with the natural numbers N = {1, 2, 3, }. In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need

More information

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Susumu Cato January 17, 2006 Abstract In actual life, we face the opportunity of many choices, from that opportunity set, we have to choose from different alternatives.

More information

Notes 1 Autumn Sample space, events. S is the number of elements in the set S.)

Notes 1 Autumn Sample space, events. S is the number of elements in the set S.) MAS 108 Probability I Notes 1 Autumn 2005 Sample space, events The general setting is: We perform an experiment which can have a number of different outcomes. The sample space is the set of all possible

More information

Network Topology, Higher Orders of Stability and Efficiency

Network Topology, Higher Orders of Stability and Efficiency MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Network Topology, Higher Orders of Stability and Efficiency Subhadip Chakrabarti and Supanit Tangsangasaksri Queen s University Management School, Queen s University

More information

A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions

A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions Shurojit Chatterji, Arunava Sen and Huaxia Zeng September 2014 Paper No. 13-2014 ANY OPINIONS EXPRESSED ARE THOSE OF THE

More information

DIMACS Technical Report March Game Seki 1

DIMACS Technical Report March Game Seki 1 DIMACS Technical Report 2007-05 March 2007 Game Seki 1 by Diogo V. Andrade RUTCOR, Rutgers University 640 Bartholomew Road Piscataway, NJ 08854-8003 dandrade@rutcor.rutgers.edu Vladimir A. Gurvich RUTCOR,

More information

On the Triangle Test with Replications

On the Triangle Test with Replications On the Triangle Test with Replications Joachim Kunert and Michael Meyners Fachbereich Statistik, University of Dortmund, D-44221 Dortmund, Germany E-mail: kunert@statistik.uni-dortmund.de E-mail: meyners@statistik.uni-dortmund.de

More information

2) There should be uncertainty as to which outcome will occur before the procedure takes place.

2) There should be uncertainty as to which outcome will occur before the procedure takes place. robability Numbers For many statisticians the concept of the probability that an event occurs is ultimately rooted in the interpretation of an event as an outcome of an experiment, others would interpret

More information

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees Francesc Rosselló 1, Gabriel Valiente 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Research Institute

More information

3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS

3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS 3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS January 19, 2010 BOHUSLAV BALCAR, balcar@math.cas.cz 1 TOMÁŠ PAZÁK, pazak@math.cas.cz 1 JONATHAN VERNER, jonathan.verner@matfyz.cz 2 We now come to the important definition.

More information

CONSTRUCTION OF sequence of rational approximations to sets of rational approximating sequences, all with the same tail behaviour Definition 1.

CONSTRUCTION OF sequence of rational approximations to sets of rational approximating sequences, all with the same tail behaviour Definition 1. CONSTRUCTION OF R 1. MOTIVATION We are used to thinking of real numbers as successive approximations. For example, we write π = 3.14159... to mean that π is a real number which, accurate to 5 decimal places,

More information

CS 486: Applied Logic Lecture 7, February 11, Compactness. 7.1 Compactness why?

CS 486: Applied Logic Lecture 7, February 11, Compactness. 7.1 Compactness why? CS 486: Applied Logic Lecture 7, February 11, 2003 7 Compactness 7.1 Compactness why? So far, we have applied the tableau method to propositional formulas and proved that this method is sufficient and

More information

The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice:

The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice: The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice: General Characterization and Possibility Results on Median Spaces * Klaus Nehring Department of Economics, UC Davis, Davis, CA 95616, U.S.A. and Institute

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory COMP323 Introduction to Computational Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Paul G. Spirakis Department of Computer Science University of Liverpool Paul G. Spirakis (U. Liverpool) Introduction to Game

More information

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

Universalism Entails Extensionalism Universalism Entails Extensionalism Achille C. Varzi Department of Philosophy, Columbia University, New York [Final version published in Analysis, 69 (2009), 599 604] 1. Universalism (also known as Conjunctivism,

More information

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 1 Real Numbers In these lectures, we are going to study a branch of mathematics called

More information

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist CS103 Winter 2019 Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist Cynthia Lee Keith Schwarz Now that we re transitioning to writing proofs about discrete structures like binary relations, functions, and graphs,

More information

MATH 243E Test #3 Solutions

MATH 243E Test #3 Solutions MATH 4E Test # Solutions () Find a recurrence relation for the number of bit strings of length n that contain a pair of consecutive 0s. You do not need to solve this recurrence relation. (Hint: Consider

More information

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain College of William and Mary W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2008 Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain Lauren Nicole Merrill College of William

More information

Measures and Measure Spaces

Measures and Measure Spaces Chapter 2 Measures and Measure Spaces In summarizing the flaws of the Riemann integral we can focus on two main points: 1) Many nice functions are not Riemann integrable. 2) The Riemann integral does not

More information

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009 Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009 Our main goal is here is to do counting using functions. For that, we

More information

P (E) = P (A 1 )P (A 2 )... P (A n ).

P (E) = P (A 1 )P (A 2 )... P (A n ). Lecture 9: Conditional probability II: breaking complex events into smaller events, methods to solve probability problems, Bayes rule, law of total probability, Bayes theorem Discrete Structures II (Summer

More information

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH ) Contents 1 Sets 1 2 The Real Numbers 9 3 Sequences 29 4 Series 59 5 Functions 81 6 Power Series 105 7 The elementary functions 111 Chapter 1 Sets It is very convenient to introduce some notation and terminology

More information

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract)

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract) Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract) Conal Duddy, Nicolas Houy, Jérôme Lang, Ashley Piggins, and William S. Zwicker February 22, 2014 1 What is a Social Dichotomy Function? A dichotomy A = (A

More information

SYSU Lectures on the Theory of Aggregation Lecture 2: Binary Aggregation with Integrity Constraints

SYSU Lectures on the Theory of Aggregation Lecture 2: Binary Aggregation with Integrity Constraints SYSU Lectures on the Theory of Aggregation Lecture 2: Binary Aggregation with Integrity Constraints Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam [ http://www.illc.uva.nl/~ulle/sysu-2014/

More information

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED DOV SAMET Abstract. An informal argument shows that common knowledge of rationality implies the iterative elimination of strongly dominated strategies. Rationality

More information

Chapter 3. Introducing Groups

Chapter 3. Introducing Groups Chapter 3 Introducing Groups We need a super-mathematics in which the operations are as unknown as the quantities they operate on, and a super-mathematician who does not know what he is doing when he performs

More information

CS632 Notes on Relational Query Languages I

CS632 Notes on Relational Query Languages I CS632 Notes on Relational Query Languages I A. Demers 6 Feb 2003 1 Introduction Here we define relations, and introduce our notational conventions, which are taken almost directly from [AD93]. We begin

More information

Abstract & Applied Linear Algebra (Chapters 1-2) James A. Bernhard University of Puget Sound

Abstract & Applied Linear Algebra (Chapters 1-2) James A. Bernhard University of Puget Sound Abstract & Applied Linear Algebra (Chapters 1-2) James A. Bernhard University of Puget Sound Copyright 2018 by James A. Bernhard Contents 1 Vector spaces 3 1.1 Definitions and basic properties.................

More information

Expected Utility Framework

Expected Utility Framework Expected Utility Framework Preferences We want to examine the behavior of an individual, called a player, who must choose from among a set of outcomes. Let X be the (finite) set of outcomes with common

More information

Clans, parent sets, litters, atoms, and allowable permutations

Clans, parent sets, litters, atoms, and allowable permutations Clans, parent sets, litters, atoms, and allowable permutations M. Randall Holmes January 26, 2016 Version of 1/25/2015, 12 AM Boise time corrected a misstatement. Introductory remarks: In this note I am

More information

2.1 Convergence of Sequences

2.1 Convergence of Sequences Chapter 2 Sequences 2. Convergence of Sequences A sequence is a function f : N R. We write f) = a, f2) = a 2, and in general fn) = a n. We usually identify the sequence with the range of f, which is written

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018 Individual and Group Stability in Neutral Restrictions of Hedonic Games Warut Suksompong Department of Computer Science, Stanford University 353 Serra Mall, Stanford, CA 94305, USA warut@cs.stanford.edu

More information