Cognitive Anchor in Other-Regarding Preferences: An Axiomatic Approach

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Cognitive Anchor in Other-Regarding Preferences: An Axiomatic Approach"

Transcription

1 Cognitive Anchor in Other-Regarding Preferences: An Axiomatic Approach Yosuke Hashidate Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo First Draft: October 30, 2016 This Draft: January 30, 2017 Abstract This paper extends the theory of other-regarding preferences to the decision maker whose choice behaviors are reference-dependent. We investigate a decision maker who chooses an allocation between herself and other passive recipients from a menu. The resulting behavior can be related to a criterion for a subjective fairness, which is determined from choice opportunities. Even though, in most studies on reference-dependent preferences, reference points are given exogenously, decision analysts cannot observe reference points directly in general. To overcome this difficulty, by enriching the domain of preference relations, this paper presents a utility representation that identifies a reference point endogenously. The contribution of this paper is that we provide an axiomatic foundation for reference-dependent inequality aversion. The axiomatic foundation accommodates the existence of a subjective reference point, which is called a cognitive anchor, a criterion for social decision-making. This captures pro-social behaviors with menu-dependence. Moreover, in the model, it is shown that the attitude toward pure altruism, menu-dependent inequality aversion, and reference points, are uniquely identified, respectively. Keywords: Axiomatic Foundation for Behavioral Economics; Cognitive Anchor; Inequality Aversion; Other-Regarding Preferences; Reference-Dependent Preferences; Pro-Social Behaviors. JEL Classification Numbers: D01, D03, D63, D64, D81. I am indebted to my adviser Akihiko Matsui for his unique guidance, constant support, and encouragement. I thank Tatsuya Kameda and Daniel Marszalec for their invaluable discussions. I gratefully acknowledge financial support from the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science (Grant-in-Aid for JSPS Fellows ( )). All remaining errors are mine. yosukehashidate@gmail.com

2 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Preliminaries: An Extended Domain Endogenous Reference Points: An Axiomatic Approach A Foundation for Revealed Reference Axioms Axioms Standard Preferences Reference-Dependent Preferences Other-Regarding Preferences Results Representation Theorem Uniqueness Result Characterization of No Menu Effects Characterization of Pure Altruism Some Properties of Cognitive Anchor Literature Review: Comparison with Other Models Inequality Aversion Social Image Rawlsian Maximin Principles Warm Glow Concluding Remarks 19 A Proof of Theorem 1 20 A.1 Sufficiency Part B Proofs of Propositions 26 B.1 Proof of Proposition B.2 Proof of Proposition B.3 Proof of Proposition C Other Proofs 29 C.1 Proof of Lemma C.2 Proof of Lemma i

3 1 Introduction It is widely recognized that people often evaluate alternatives relative to a reference point. The notion of reference points reflects on the idea that people react to changes. Even in social contexts such as dictator games, reference points might affect decision-making. Suppose that there are two agents. One is a dictator, and another is a recipient. The dictator is given $10, and asked to divide the $10 between herself and the recipient. Even though game theory predicts that the dictator takes the whole amount for her own, various experimental results show that there is a fraction to give a sum between $0 and $5 to the recipient (Camerer (2003)). In terms of reference-dependent preferences, if the dictator makes a choice to get $6 for herself, and give the recipient $4, then the dictator may have a subjective reference point as a fifty-fifty choice in mind, i.e., the Egalitarian choice ($5, $5). 1 Other-regarding preferences in mind can lead to pro-social behaviors, which intend to benefit and help others. In fact, many experimental results in dictator games are related to pro-social behaviors. In many cases, the study of reference-dependent choices, ranging from status-quo bias (Masatlioglu and Ok (2005)), initial endowments (Masatlioglu and Ok (2014)), aspiration levels (Diecidue and Van De Ven (2008)), to loss aversion (Tversky and Kahneman (1991)), has been studied given a reference point exogenously. As behavioral economics shows, status-quo options, initial endowments, or default options may have the role as reference points for decision makers, which affects their decision-making. However, the fact is that it is not easy for decision analysts (observers) to identify reference points in decision-making. However, in general, the reference point itself is not directly observable. In addition, reference points should be subjective. If reference points are given exogenously, then we cannot study how the decision maker can form a reference point subjectively. The goal of this paper is to provide an axiomatic foundation for preferences for menudependent inequality aversion. The axiomatic foundation accommodates the existence of a subjective cognitive anchor, i.e., a reference point, which is endogenously determined. The menu-dependent cognitive anchor can lead to violations from the postulate of rationality, namely, the Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference (WARP). As the menu-dependent cognitive anchor shows, we only allow for those violations from reference-dependence. To do so, we extend the analysis to provide a foundation for revealed reference-dependence (Section 2). Based on revealed references, we present the postulates for the axiomatization, which are categorized by (i) standard preferences, (ii) reference-dependent preferences, and (iii) other-regarding preferences (Section 3). The main result is stated in Theorem 1 (Section 1 To explain such altruistic behaviors, experimentally, empirically, and axiomatically, various models have been developed. For example, see the following literature: (i) Inequality Aversion (Fehr and Schmidt (1999)), (ii) Rawlsian maximin rule (Charness and Rabin (2002)), (iii) Shame (Neilson (2009), Dillenberger and Sadowski (2012)), (iv) Social Image (Saito (2015)), (v) Ex-Ante and Ex-Post Fairness (Fudenberg and Levine (2012), Saito (2013)), and (vi) Reciprocity (Dufwenberg et al. (2011)). 1

4 4). Moreover, we show that this menu-dependent utility representation is uniquely identified (Proposition 1). The novelty of this paper is that, to incorporate a subjective reference point into otherregarding preferences, i.e., a cognitive anchor, we enrich the domain of binary relations (see Section 2 in detail). 2 Briefly speaking, it is postulated that decision analysts directly observe binary relations of choices from menus, which are primitives of the model in this paper. In this framework, the decision maker such as a dictator, has a taste of choosing an allocation p from a menu A. The decision maker has the rankings of choices from menus. For example, assume that p = ($5, $5) is a fair allocation, q = ($10, $0) is a selfish allocation, r = ($7, $3) is an intermediate allocation between them. In this framework, the decision maker might prefer a choice of an allocation p from a menu {p, q} to a choice of an allocation p from a menu {p, q, r}. In revealed preference theory, choosing an allocation p from a menu is the same as that of another menu. However, we explore some cases such that the decision maker might prefer a choice of an allocation p from a menu {p, q} to a choice of an allocation p from a menu {p, q, r}. Such a binary relation may arise in social contexts from other-regarding preferences including inequality aversion and preferences for fairness. In Section 2, we present an axiomatic foundation for revealed reference-dependence. From choice data, it is hard to justify the difference between choosing p from A and choosing p from B. To provide an axiomatic analysis for reference-dependent preferences, Ok, Ortoleva, and Riella (2015) develop a revealed preference theory of reference-dependent choices. They relax WARP to obtain the existence of reference points endogenously. We follow the choice-theoretic foundation for the primitive of this paper. First, we require that for any pairwise menus such as {p, q}, no cycle condition, which does not allow for preference reversals under pairwise choice problems, holds (Lemma 2). This condition is valid since, in general, we observe some preference reversals when a third alternative is added into the pairwise choice problem. 3 Next, we require that an acyclic condition holds under reference-dependence (Lemma 1). These behavioral foundations from choices make it possible to explore a utility representation of reference-dependent preferences. In Section 3, we present the axioms for the main theorem (Theorem 1). First, we describe the basic axioms that is well-known in decision theory. The basic axioms are related to foundation for revealed references explained in Section 2. Next, we introduce the two key axioms to obtain a reference point (cognitive anchor) endogenously: (i) Separability, and (ii) Comparative Valuations in Menus. The axiom of Separability requires that preferences for allocations and reference-dependent preferences are separable. This axiom guarantees that the reference-dependent preferences happen when the sizes of menus are more than three, i.e., 2 Suzumura and Xu (2001, 2003) study this type of binary relation in social choice theory. 3 See Huber, Payne, and Puto (1982) (Attraction Effects) and Simonson (1989) (Compromise Effects). 2

5 A 3. In addition, the property reflects the existence of reference points. On the other hand, the axiom of Comparative Valuations in Menus captures the property of reference points. This axiom requires that if for any alternatives in a menu, a dominant alternative is added into the menu, then the evaluations of the alternatives in the original menu decrease. Adding the dominant alternative into the menu changes the criterion of decision-making. The criterion, i.e., the cognitive anchor in social contexts increases in comparative valuations. Finally, we provide the axioms for inequality aversion (other-regarding preferences). The two axioms ( (i) Comonotonic Independence, and (ii) Fair Allocations ) are not new. We apply uncertain-averse preferences (Schmeidler (1989), Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989)) into other-regarding preferences. 4 In Section 4, we state the main result: the representation theorem (Theorem 1) and the uniqueness result (Proposition 1). Moreover, we characterize reference-dependent preferences, preferences for allocations, and reference points, respectively. First, we consider the case that there is no menu effects. In this case, the decision maker does not have any reference-dependent preferences, which reduces to the standard utility representation. Next, we characterize the attitude toward pure altruism. By Separability stated above, preferences for allocations and reference-dependent preferences are separable. From preferences for allocations, we can identify the attitude toward pure altruism. In this sense, our model separates pure altruism from reference-dependent preferences. Finally, we characterize the menu-dependent cognitive anchor. We study the attitude toward pro-social behaviors in a positive way or in a negative way with the parameter of the menu-dependent cognitive anchor. In Section 5, we provide a literature review. We compare our model with other models such as (i) inequality aversion, (ii) pride, shame, and temptation, (iii) Rawlsian maximin rules, and (iv) warm glow. In Section 6, we conclude. 2 Preliminaries: An Extended Domain We introduce notation. Let X be a finite set of all alternatives. The elements of X, i.e., alternatives are denoted by x, y, z X. Assume that (X, d) is a separable metric space with the Euclidean distance d. Let A be the set of all non-empty compact subsets of X, endowed with the Hausdorff metric. The Hausdorff metric is defined by { d h (A, B) = max max d(x, y), max min x A y B min x B y A } d(x, y). The elements of A are denoted by A, B, C A. We call the elements of A menus. Menus are opportunity sets. 4 See also Rohde (2010), which is an axiomatic foundation for the Fehr and Schmidt (1999) s inequalityaverse representation. The axiomatic foundation is similar to that in Schmeidler (1989). 3

6 Let us denote a choice correspondence. A set-valued map c : A X is a choice correspondence if c(a) and c(a) A for each A A. We consider the product X A, endowed with the product metric d of the Euclidean metric d and the Hausdorff metric d h. We consider a space: (X A) {(x, A) X A x A}. An element (x, A) (X A) means that a decision maker chooses an alternative x from a menu A. The primitive of the model is a binary relation over (X A). The asymmetric and symmetric parts of are denoted by and, respectively. 2.1 Endogenous Reference Points: An Axiomatic Approach We investigate a binary relation on (X A) as the primitive of the present paper. Take an arbitrary option (x, A) (X A). This option means that a decision maker chooses an alternative x from a menu A. We try to capture the ranking of choices from menus by observing this binary relation. We explicitly analyze menu effects like how sizes of menus or contents in menus affects decision-making. Let us remark that, in general, decision analysts cannot observe the difference between (x, A) and (y, B) from choice data only. If an alternative x is chosen over a menu A, we interpret that alternative as a preferred alternative for that decision maker. Thus, behaviorally, we cannot distinguish the difference between a choice from a menu A and a choice from another menu B. In this sense, our approach is based on non-consequentialism. There is an advantage of considering this binary relation on (X A) directly. This approach makes it possible to characterize reference-dependent preferences directly. We are able to justify which type of axioms the decision maker with reference-dependent preferences do satisfy. In addition, we are able to characterize the decision maker who has no menu effects, i.e., the decision maker who has reference-independent preferences in the standard manner. In addition, we present an axiomatic foundation for reference-dependent choices based on Ok, Ortoleva, and Riella (2015). To derive reference points endogenously, recently, there has been new literature: Ok, Ortoleva, and Riella (2015) and Tserenjigmid (2016), who study a revealed preference theory of reference-dependent choices by analyzing choice correspondences as primitives. The two papers relax the Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference (WARP) suitably. The common feature of the two literature induces the two binary relations from the weaker axioms of WARP. One is a binary relation which represents a standard preference maximization (Debreu (1959), Kreps (1988)), another is related to reference-dependent preferences. Their models are based on, in principle, observed choice data. 4

7 2.2 A Foundation for Revealed Reference We explore an axiomatic analysis of reference-dependent choices. Ok, Ortoleva, and Riella (2015) provide two important notions to identify revealed reference: (i) revealed c-reference and (ii) potential c-reference. We explain about the two notions in the following, one by one. First, we explain about the notion of revealed c-references. Consider an arbitrary pairwise choice problem {x, y}. Suppose that x is not chosen over y in the pairwise choice problem, i.e., {y} = c({x, y}). However, we sometimes observe that when an alternative z X is added into the pairwise choice problem {x, y}, x is chosen, i.e., x c({x, y, z}). In other words, the existence of the third alternative z affects the resulting choice behavior, and then x is chosen. Formally, this notion is stated as follows. Definition 1. (Revealed c-reference): We say that an alternative z is a revealed c-reference for x if there is an alternative y X such that (i) x c({x, y, z}) \ c({x, y}); or (ii) y c({x, y}) and {x, y} c({x, y, z}) = {x}. Second, we consider a related notion for a third alternative z with a pairwise choice problem {x, y}. That is, it is the case that the addition of the alternative z does not change the choice behavior in a choice problem {x, y, z} from the original pairwise choice problem {x, y}. Concretely, if the alternative x is chosen over the alternative y, then x is still chosen when the third alternative z is added. Conversely speaking, if the alternative y is not chosen over x, then y is not chosen even if the third alternative z is added. Definition 2. (Potential c-reference): We say that an alternative z is a potential c-reference for x if, for every y X such that {z} = c({x, y, z}), (i) x c({x, y}) x c({x, y, z}); and (ii) y / c({x, y}) y / c({x, y, z}). The key point is that two definitions focus on pairwise choice problems. We pay attention to observable choice behaviors when a new alternative is added into a pairwise choice problem. The added third alternative is categorized into the two roles: (i) reference-dependence or (ii) reference-independence. We need to observe carefully whether a third alternative for a pairwise choice problem affects the taste on the pairwise choice problem or not. 2.3 Axioms We present some basic axioms for the binary relation on (X A). Plus, we provide a behavioral foundation for the properties of. 5

8 First, we provide a basic postulate on the study of subjective reference-dependence: (i) completeness and (ii) transitivity. Axiom(Weak Order): is complete and transitive: (i) (Completenessr): For any (x, A), (y, B) (X A), (x, A) (y, B) or (x, A) (y, B). (ii) (Transitivity):For any (x, A), (y, B), (z, C) (X A), if (x, A) (y, B) and (y, B) (z, C), then (x, A) (z, C). The axiom of completeness requires that any options are comparable. 5 Also, the property of transitivity is required. The following axiom for choice correspondences is related to the axiom of Reference Acyclicity in Ok, Ortoleva, and Riella (2015). Axiom(Reference Acyclicity): For any integer m 2 and x 1,, x m X, if x i is a revealed c-reference for x i+1 for each i = 1,, m 1, then x 1 is a potential c-reference for x m. The axiom is an acyclic condition under reference-dependence. Without loss of generality, suppose that there exist finitely some alternatives x 1, x 2,, x m X. Then, as the axiom says, x 1 is a revealed c-reference for x 2, x 2 is a revealed c-reference for x 3, and so on. x m 1 is a revealed c-reference for x m. This axiom requires that for any sequences of alternatives, x 1 is a potential c-reference for x m. If x 1 is a revealed c-reference for x m, it immediately leads to a violation of WARP. Lemma 1. Suppose that satisfies Completeness. Then, satisfies Transitivity if and only if c satisfies Reference Acyclicity. Next, we introduce a consistency condition for reference-dependent preferences. To do so, for simplicity, we define on X as follows. Definition 3. For any x, y X, x y if (x, {x}) (y, {y}). The asymmetric and symmetric part of are described by > and, respectively. Axiom(Pairwise Consistency): For any x, y X, if (x, {x, y}) (y, {x, y}), then x y. This axiom says that the ranking of choices from singleton menus should be justified by the ranking of choices from pairwise menus. We provide the following condition for choice correspondences in Ok, Ortoleva, and Riella (2015). 5 See Evren and Ok (2011) for the generalization of incomplete preference relations. 6

9 Axiom(No-Cycle Condition): For any x, y, z X, if x c({x, y}) and y c({y, z}), then x c({x, z}). This condition says that the consistent condition for choice behaviors holds under any pairwise choice problems. Even though pairwise choice problems are extreme, there is no possibility such that a third alternative affects the alternatives in pairwise choice problems. In this case, any preference reversals like cycles do not happen. Lemma 2. Suppose that satisfies Pairwise Consistency. Then, satisfies Weak Order if and only if c satisfies No-Cycle Condition. In addition, we provide a weaker version of continuity. Axiom (Continuity): The sets {(p, A) (X A) (p, A) (q, B)} and {(p, A) (X A) (q, B) (p, A)} are closed (in the product metric d ). Finally, we postulate a basic axiom: Non-Degeneracy. exists an option that is strictly preferred. This axiom requires that there Axiom(Non-Degeneracy): There exists (x, A), (y, B) (X A) such that (x, A) (y, B). 3 Axioms We introduce notation briefly. Let 1 denote the decision maker, and S be the finite set of other agents. Let I = {1} S be the set of all agents. Let Z be a finite set of outcomes. (Z) is the set of all lotteries with finite support. Since Z is finite, the topology generated by the Euclidean metric d is equivalent to the weak topology on (Z). Let ( (Z)) I be the set of all allocations. The elements of ( (Z)) I are denoted by p = (p 1,, p n ) = (p 1, p S ) where S = {2, n}. The lottery p i is an allocation for an agent i. Let A be the set of all non-empty compact subsets of ( (Z)) I endowed with the Hausdorff metric d h. Menus are denoted by A, B, C A. Let us consider a space (Z) I A, endowed with the product metric d by the Euclidean metric d and the Hausdorff metric d h. Consider a space (( (Z) I ) A) {(p, A) (Z) I A p A}. The primitive of the model is a binary relation over (( (Z) I ) A). The asymmetric and symmetric parts of are denoted by and, respectively. 7

10 3.1 Standard Preferences First, we postulate a basic axiom, stated in Section 2: (i) Weak Order, (ii) Pairwise Consistency, (iii) Continuity, and (iv) Non-Degeneracy. Axiom (Standard Preferences): satisfies (i) Weak Order, (ii) Pairwise Consistency, (iii) Continuity, and (iv) Non-Degeneracy. Next, we induce the two preference relations of the decision maker 1: (i) the individual preference, 1 and (ii) the social preference S. For simplicity, for any singleton menus, we write down a binary relation on singleton menus in the following way. We say that p q if (p, {p}) (q, {q}). We define 1 and S as follows. Definition 4. 1 and S are defined as follows: (i) p 1 1 q 1 if (p 1, r S ) (q 1, r S ) for some r S (Z) S. (ii) p S S q S if (r 1, p S ) (r 1, q S ) for some r 1 (Z). In addition, we provide the following axioms: Consistency, Pareto, and Singleton Independence. The first axiom, Consistency, provides a consistency condition between the decision maker 1 s own preference 1 and the social preference S. This axiom follows from the Saito (2015) s consistency axiom (p.344). Remember that the decision maker 1 is not a social planner. The decision maker 1 may not know other agents preference relations directly. This setting is actually valid under dictator games. 6 Axiom (Consistency): For any p S, q S ( (Z)) S, if p i 1 q i for any i S, then p S S q S. The next axiom, Pareto, is standard in economic theory. Axiom (Pareto): For any p, q ( (Z)) I, if p 1 1 q 1 and p S S q S, then (p, A) (q, A) for any A A. Moreover, we introduce another condition for singleton menus. We use convex combinations in the standard manner. For any menus A, B A and λ [0, 1], the convex combination of the two menus is defined by λa + (1 λ)b = {λp + (1 λ)q p A, q A }. The following axiom requires that Independence holds under singleton menus. 6 Axiomatically, this axiom makes it possible to obtain a unique non-constant cardinal utility function u : (Z) R. 8

11 Axiom (Singleton Independence): For any p, q, r ( (Z)) I and λ [0, 1], (p, {p}) (q, {q}) (λp + (1 λ)r, {λp + (1 λ)r}) (λq + (1 λ)r, {λq + (1 λ)r}). 3.2 Reference-Dependent Preferences To obtain a subjective reference point (a cognitive anchor in social decision-making) endogenously, we provide a key axiom: Separability. The axiom, Separability, is a minimal requirement in the framework of this paper to study menu effects. This axiom is a separable condition, which requires that the evaluation of allocations that stems from preferences for allocations and menus preferences including reference-dependent preferences are separable. As the axiom shows, the sizes of menus are more than three, i.e., A, B 3. This axiom captures a type of menu effects of the decision maker. Axiom (Separability): For any p, q A B, (p, A) (p, B) (q, A) (q, B). In the framework of this paper, this axiom captures reference-dependent preferences. The ranking between (p, A) and (p, B) means that if (p, A) is preferred to (p, B), then an allocation p in the menu A is relatively more preferred to a choice of p from the menu B. This type of tastes reflects menu effects. In addition to Separability, we provide another axiom for reference-dependent preferences. Axiom (Comparative Valuations in Menus): Suppose that, for any p A, there exists q ( (Z)) I such that q j j p j for any j {1, S}. Then, (i) (p, A) (p, A {q}); and (ii) (q, A {q}) (q, {q}). Suppose that for any allocations p A, there exists an allocation q (Z) I such that q j j p j for any j {1, S}. That is, q dominates p. The first condition requires that if such an attractive allocation q is added into a menu A, then the comparative valuation of p A decreases due to the existence of q A {q}. This axiom can be interpreted as the notion of satisfaction in Simon (1957). In other words, adding q into A changes the criterion of decision-making. As a result, the criterion in comparative valuations increases. Then, the evaluation of allocations p in the menu A decreases. On the other hand, the second condition requires that the added allocation q is relatively preferred in the menu A {q} more than that in {q} due to the allocations in the original menu A. 9

12 3.3 Other-Regarding Preferences We provide the following two axioms that are related to other-regarding preferences including inequality aversion. In our framework, other-regarding preferences in social contexts can happen when sizes of menus are more than two, i.e., A 2 since the decision maker 1 has to care about acting pro-socially or not. By relaxing the Independence axiom, we provide two axioms: Comonotonic Independence and Fair Allocations. First, we introduce Comonotonic Independence. 7 Let us introduce the notion of comonotonicty of allocations. We say that two allocations p, q are comonotonic if there exists no i S such that p i 1 p 1 and q i 1 q 1. The following axiom requires that, for any menus whose number of alternatives is more than two, Independence only holds when menus are comonotonic each other. Axiom (Comonotonic Independence): For any comonotonic allocations p, q, r, for any menus A, B, C A with A, B, C 2, and for any λ [0, 1], (p, A) (q, B) (λp + (1 λ)r, λa + (1 λ)c) (λq + (1 λ)r, λa + (1 λ)c). Next, we provide a consistency condition for fair allocations. 8 We say that an allocation r (Z) I is a fair allocation if r i = r j for any i, j I. The following axiom says that the mixture with fair allocations does not change the ranking. Axiom (Fair Allocations): For any A, B A and λ [0, 1], (p, A) (q, B) (λp + (1 λ)r, λa + (1 λ)c) (λq + (1 λ)r, λa + (1 λ)c) where r (Z) I such that r i = r j for all i, j I. 4 Results 4.1 Representation Theorem We state the main result. Theorem 1. The following statements are equivalent: (a) satisfies Standard Preferences, Singleton Independence, Separability, Comparative Valuations in Menus, Comonotonic Independence, and Fair Allocations. (b) There exists a tuple (u, α, β( ), γ, θ) where u is a non-constant function u : (Z) R, α 7 This axiom follows from the axiom of comonotonic independence in Schmeidler (1989) in the Anscombe and Aumann framework. 8 See also the axiom of Certainty Independence in Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989), which is a generalization of subjective expected utility theory. 10

13 is a vector such that α 1 > 0, and α i 0 for each i S with i S α i = 1, β( ) is a capacity on {1, S}, γ is the vector such that γ j [0, 1] for any j {1, S}, and θ [0, 1] is a parameter such that is represented by a function V : (( (Z) I ) A) R defined by V (p, A) = [ ] α i u(p i ) + θ β j (A)(u(p j ) u j (A)), i I j {1,S} where u j (A) = γ j max q A u(q j ) + (1 γ j ) min r A u(r j ) for any j {1, S}, and u(p S ) = i S α iu(p i ). We briefly explain about the interpretation of the model in the main theorem. The utility function represents a binary relation on (( (Z) I ) A). The first term, i I α iu(p i ), represents 1 and S, which is a utility representation of a generalized weighted utilitarian. By Consistency, since the decision maker 1 does not know about other agents true preferences, the allocations for other agents are evaluated by the decision maker 1 s utility function. By definition, α 1 > 0 captures the level of (pure) selfishness. To see the interpretation of the first term, take an arbitrary menu A A. For simplicity, assume that θ = 0. Let A = {(u 1 (p 1 ), u S (p S )) R 2 p = (p 1, p S ) A }. In Figure 1, for example, the allocation p A is put as u(p) = (u 1 (p 1 ), u S (p S )). As Figure 1 shows, α 1 captures the level of pure selfishness. If α 1 decreases, then the attitude toward pure altruism increases. us A* u(p) = ( u1(p1), us(ps) ) α1 u1(p1) + us(ps) u1 Figure 1: Attitude toward Pure Altruism Next, let us move on to the explanation about the second term. The parameter θ [0, 1] captures that how much the decision maker reacts to menu effects, especially, a menudependent cognitive anchor. The utility difference u(p j ) u j (A) is a comparative valuation of an allocation in the menu A. (u j (A)) j {1,S} is a cognitive anchor (reference point) of the menu A. The non-additive measure, i.e., the capacity β(a) = (β 1 (A), β S (A)) on {1, S} captures the attitude toward inequality aversion with menu-dependence. 11

14 We explain about the reason why we introduce the non-additive measure on {1, S} to capture inequality aversion. A set-valued function β is called to be a capacity if it is monotonic and normalized. That is, for each j {1, S}, β(j) β({1, S}) holds, and both β({1, S}) = 1 and β( ) = 0 hold. Before stating the interpretation of the second term, let us explain about the Choquet expected utility representation in Schmeidler (1989). Suppose that a finite state space Ω is given (ω Ω). Let Z be a set of outcomes. Also, let (Z) be the set of all probability distributions on Z with finite support. Anscombe=Aumann acts are defined by f : S (Z). Let H be the set of Anscombe=Aumann acts. The primitive is a binary relation on H. The preference relation is represented by a pair (u, v) where (i) u : Z R is a vnm function, and (ii) v is a capacity. 9 Suppose that u(f(ω j )) u(f(ω j+i )) for each j = 1,, n. Let u(f(ω j )) = u j R. Then, the utility of an act f is represented by U(f) = u 1 v(s 1 ) + n j=2 [ ] u j v( j i=1 S i) v( j 1 i=1 S i). To get the intuition of the Choquet integral, consider the following case. Suppose that a finite state space is given by Ω = {E 1, E 2, E 3 }, and that u 1 u 2 u 3. Then, the Choquet expected utility is calculated by u 1 v(e 1 ) + (u 2 u 3 )v(e 1 E 2 ) + (u 3 0)v(E 1 E 2 E 3 ) = u 1 v(e 1 ) + u 2 [ v(e1 E 2 ) v(e 1 ) ] + u 3 [ v(e1 E 2 E 3 ) v(e 1 E 2 ) ]. By arranging the order like u 1 u 2 u 3, we can write down the Choquet expected utility representation (Figure 2). u u1 u2 u3 v (E1 UE2 U E3) v (E1 U E2) v (E1) E3 E1 E2 u3 u2 u1 u Figure 2: Choquet Expected Utility Now, we can move on to explain about the interpretation of the second term. The second term, i.e., the expected utility with the Choquet integral, is written as follows. Given a menu A A, the menu-dependent cognitive anchor of the decision maker is obtained and written by (u 1 (A), u S (A)). For each allocation, the utility with menu-dependence is written by u j (p j ) u j (A) for each j {1, S}. Let û j (p j ) = u j (p j ) u j (A). Then, we have û 1 β 1 (A) + û S (1 β 1 (A)). 9 v(ω) = 1, v( ) = 0, and v is monotonic. 12

15 The menu-dependent capacity β( ) stems from the cognitive anchor u( ) = (u 1 ( ), u S ( )). Since the cognitive anchor in our model depends on menus, the attitude toward inequality aversion also depends on menus. In this sense, pro-social behaviors are determined by the decision maker s subjective reference point, i.e., cognitive anchor in social contexts. The menu-dependent cognitive anchor is formed by menus. For each j {1, S}, the criterion is defined by u j (A) = γ j max q A u(q j ) + (1 γ j ) min r A u(r j ). us us B* A* us(a) B us(a) u1(a) u1 u1(a) B u1 Figure 3: Cognitive Anchor 4.2 Uniqueness Result We state the uniqueness result. Proposition 1. Suppose that the two representations (u, α, β( ), γ, θ) and (u, α, β ( ), γ, θ ) represent the same binary relation. Then, the following statements hold: (i) u = au + b for some a > 0 and b R; (ii) α = α ; (iii) β( ) = β ( ); (iv) γ = γ ; (v) θ = θ. In the uniqueness result (Proposition 1), the axiom of Consistency has an important role for this identification result. Since the decision maker 1 is not a social planner, the decision maker evaluates other agents allocations by using her own preference relations 1. This implies that the allocations for others are also evaluated by her own utility function u : (Z) R. Mathematically speaking, in (i), by the von Neumann Morgenstein Expected Utility Theorem, u is unique up to positive affine transformations. In (ii), since u is unique up to a positive affine transformation, and u satisfies Singleton Independence, α is uniquely 13

16 identified. In (iii), the non-additive measure β( ) is also uniquely identified due to the cardinal utility function u. in (iv), the parameter γ for cognitive anchor is also uniquely identified. Finally, in (v), the parameter θ [0, 1] is uniquely identified. 4.3 Characterization of No Menu Effects We characterize the parameter θ [0, 1]. Especially, we consider an extreme case θ = 0. To characterize this case, we introduce the following axiom. Axiom(No Menu Effects): For any A, B A with p A B, (p, A) (p, B). This axiom says that the decision maker 1 has no menu effects. Choosing an allocation p from any menus produces the same utility for the decision maker 1. Axiomatically speaking, this axiom is a stronger version of Separability. Proposition 2. Suppose that is represented by a tuple (u, α, β( ), γ, θ). Then, exhibits No Menu Effects if and only if θ = 0. In the utility representation, we can write down as follows. For any (p, A) (( (Z) I ) A), V ((p, A)) = U(p) = i I α iu(p i ). The representation reduces to a generalized weighted utilitarian. 4.4 Characterization of Pure Altruism We provide comparative statics on α. α 1 is the level of selfishness for the decision maker 1. In the same way in Saito (2015), we study a comparative attitude toward pure altruism. The attitude toward pure altruism is captured by singleton menus. We investigate a binary relation on (Z) I. Let X be the binary relation of the decision maker X, and Y be the binary relation of the decision maker Y, respectively. Definition 5. For any X and Y on (Z)I such that X j = Y j for each j {1, S}, X is more altruistic than Y if, for any p, q (Z)I with p S h S q S for each h {X, Y }, p Y q p X q. We consider the case that an allocation p is better than q in the social preference: p S h S q S for each h {X, Y }. Under the assumption that X j = Y j for each j {1, S}, if a decision maker Y prefers p to q with p S Y S q S, then another decision maker X also prefers p to q with p S X S q S. Proposition 3. Suppose that is represented by a tuple (u, α, β, γ, θ). Plus, suppose that X and Y are represented by two utility representation (u, αx ) and (u, α Y ), respectively. Then, X is more altruistic than Y if and only if α1 X αy 1. 14

17 us us A* α1 X u1(p1) + us(ps) A* α1 Y u1(p1) + us(ps) u1 u1 Figure 4: Comparative Statics on Pure Altruism 4.5 Some Properties of Cognitive Anchor We examine a menu-dependent cognitive anchor (subjective reference point). We characterize a relationship between γ 1 and γ S. We study pro-social behaviors with reference-dependence (menu-dependence). The key point in our model is that pro-social behaviors can be captured by not only inequality aversion (β( )) but also menu-dependent cognitive anchor (γ). The non-additive measure (capacity) β( ) is put on {1, S} based on the menu-dependent cognitive anchor u( ). As a result, the attitude toward inequality aversion is menu-dependent. We provide an axiomatic characterization for the parameter of the menu-dependent cognitive anchor, since the decision maker privately determines a cognitive anchor, and the cognitive anchor affects resulting choice behaviors. Axiom(Negative Pro-Social Preference): For any p, q (Z) I, if (i) (p, {p}) (q, {q}); and (ii) p 1 1 q 1, then (p, {p, q}) (q, {p, q}). The interpretation of the above axiom is as follows. From the condition (i), the allocations p and q are indifferent. The condition (ii) says that the decision maker 1 prefers p to q in the sense that her own individual preference 1 says that p 1 is strictly preferred to q 1. As a result, the decision maker 1 prefers choosing p from {p, q} to choosing q from {p, q}. Proposition 4. Suppose that is represented by a tuple (u, α, β( ), γ, θ). Then, exhibits Negative Pro-Social Preference if and only if γ 1 γ S. The above result in Proposition 4 says that the decision maker makes use of her advantage of choosing an allocation (γ 1 γ S ). We call such a pro-social behavior a negatively pro-social behavior. To form a cognitive anchor given a menu, the parameter γ = (γ 1, γ S ) is a subjective 15

18 criterion for the decision maker. Suppose γ 1 > γ S > 0. Even though the decision maker feels in making a choice in a selfish way, the decision maker cares about social image deliberately. Next, conversely, we also present the following axiom: Positive Pro-Social Preference. Axiom(Positive Pro-Social Preference): For any p, q (Z) I, if (i) (p, {p}) (q, {q}); and (ii) p S S q S, then (p, {p, q}) (q, {p, q}). In the similar way with Negative Pro-Social Preference, the axiom of Positive Pro-Social Preference is interpreted. By the condition (i), the allocations p and q are indifferent. Contrary to Negative Pro-Social Preference, the condition (ii) says that the decision maker 1 s social preference S means that p S q S. As a result, the decision maker 1 prefers choosing p from {p, q} to choosing q from {p, q}. Proposition 5. Suppose that is represented by a tuple (u, α, β, γ, θ). Then, exhibits Positive Pro-Social Preference if and only if γ 1 γ S. The result of the above Proposition 5 states that the decision maker chooses an altruistic allocation positively (γ S γ 1 ). We call such a pro-social behavior a positively pro-social behavior. The parameter γ S γ 1 implies that a concern for others is subjectively large. Then, decision-making leads to take pro-social behaviors positively. 5 Literature Review: Comparison with Other Models 5.1 Inequality Aversion There are various models for other-regarding preferences. Fehr and Schmidt (1999) present a seminal theory of inequality aversion, which captures a preference for (ex-post) fairness, which only concerns for fair outcomes (allocations). 10 In the model, the decision maker pays attention the difference of payoffs between her own payoff and other agents payoffs. The difference of payoffs can produce a feeling of envy or guilt. Formally, the model is stated as follows. Consider the case that there are two agents: I = 1 S where S = {2}, i.e., I = {1, 2}. In the model, monetary payoffs are considered. The utility of an allocation is defined by U F =S (x) = u(x 1 ) a 1 max{u(x 2 ) u(x 1 ), 0} b 1 max{u(x 1 ) u(x 2 ), 0}, 10 Fudenberg and Levine (2012) argues that the difference between ex-ante fairness and ex-post fairness should be analyzed. Saito (2013) characterizes an axiomatic foundation for social preferences with ex-ante and ex-post fairness. Rohde (2010) provides an axiomatic foundation for the Fehr and Schmidt (1999) s inequality-averse utility model. 16

19 where a i b i, b i [0, 1) for each i {1, 2}. Suppose u(x 2 ) > u(x 1 ). Then, we have U(x) = u(x 1 ) a 1 (u(x 2 ) u(x 1 )). In this case, the decision maker feels dissatisfied with the inequality due to u(x 2 ) u(x 1 ) > 0, which exhibits feeling envy. On the other hand, suppose u(x 2 ) < u(x 1 ). Then, we have U(x) = u(x 1 ) b 1 (u(x 1 ) u(x 2 )). In this case, the decision maker feels guilty with the inequality due to u(x 1 ) u(x 2 ) > 0, which exhibits guilt. Thus, this model captures preferences for (ex-post) fairness. In this paper, the attitude toward inequality aversion is captured by a unique capacity β( ) = (β 1 ( ), β S ( )) with menu-dependence. Because of menu-dependent cognitive anchor and inequality aversion, we allow for preference reversals, deviations from WARP. On the other hand, Fehr and Schmidt (1999) do not allow for any preference reversals. 5.2 Social Image Dillenberger and Sadowski (2012) and Saito (2015) apply the framework of subjective state spaces (Kreps (1979), Dekel et al. (2001)) into social contexts. The two literature investigates two stages in decision-making: first, the decision maker chooses a set of allocations at the ex-ante stage, and then, next, she chooses an allocation at the ex-post stage from the set chosen at the ex-ante stage. Dillenberger and Sadowski (2012) develop the theory of shame of acting selfishly. 11 Saito (2015) develops a theory which uniquely identifies three emotions in social decision-making: (i) pride in acting altruistically, (ii) shame of acting selfishly, and (iii) temptation to act selfishly. First, the model in Dillenberger and Sadowski (2012) is stated as follows. In their model, monetary payoffs are considered. The utility of a menu is given by [ ] V D=S (A) = max α i u(x i ) g(φ(x), max φ(y)), x A y A i I where g : R 2 R captures the disutility of shame of acting selfishly. The function φ : Z I R is a social utility, which captures the decision maker s subjective norm. Then, max y A φ(y) is the optimal social utility in the menu A. Because of the form of g, WARP can be violated. In their model, however, g and φ are not uniquely identified. On the other hand, this paper uniquely identify the parameters for other-regarding preferences β( ) and γ with menu-dependence. Next, the model in Saito (2015) is stated as follows. The utility of a menu is given by [ V Saito (A) = max α i u(x i )+β 1 max α 1(u(q 1 ) u(p 1 )) β S max ( α i u(r i ) ] α i u(p i )), p A q A r A i I i S i S where α 1 > 0, { i 0 and i S α i = 1, β 1 < 1, and β S 0. The first term is the same as that in our model. The difference between Saito (2015) and this paper appears in the second and 11 See also Neilson (2009), which presents a non-axiomatic model of shame. 17

20 third term. The second term captures the utility arising from the pride in acting altruistically if β 1 0, or the disutility arising from temptation of acting selfishly if β 1 0. In the similar way, the third term captures the disutility due to the shame of acting selfishly. The key point in that model is a linear structure, which makes the prediction more restrictive. That is, the Saito (2015) s model satisfies WARP in ex-post choices unlike this paper. 5.3 Rawlsian Maximin Principles Charness and Rabin (2002) shed light on the procedure in other-regarding behaviors, not outcomes. In the model of Rawlsian quasi-maximin principles, the decision maker cares about her own payoffs, the minimum payoff among all agents, and total payoffs. 12 Formally, the model is stated as follows. In their model, monetary payoffs are considered. The utility of an allocation is defined by [ U C=R (x) = δu(x 1 ) + (1 δ) λ i I where δ [0, 1] and λ [0, 1]. ] α i u(x i ) + (1 λ) min u(x i), i I This model does not have an axiomatic foundation, but the Rawlsian maximin principle is similar to the menu-dependent cognitive anchor in other-regarding preferences. 5.4 Warm Glow Evren and Minardi (2015) develop a theory of Warm Glow, which refers to other-serving behavior that is valuable for the decision maker, apart from its social implications. 13 Evren and Minardi (2015) provide an axiomatic foundation for Warm Glow by viewing it as a form of preferences for larger choice sets driven by the decision maker s desire to have freedom to act selfishly. Specifically, the model is based on the idea of Warm Glow to the freedom to be selfish. Formally, the model is stated as follows. In their model, monetary payoffs are considered. The utility of a menu is given by ( ) V E=M (A) = max U α i u(x i ), max u(y 1) u(x 1 ), x A y A i I where U : R 2 R is a weakly increasing function. The key part in their model is the second argument in U. To interpret this part, consider two allocations x and y with y 1 > x 1. Then, V E=M ({x}) = U( i I α iu(x i ), 0). And, consider a menu {x, y}. The interpretation of U( i I α iu(x i ), u(y 1 ) u(x 1 )) U( i I α iu(x i ), 0) is an intrinsic payoff of the decision 12 See also Dufwenberg and Kirchsteiger (2004), which develop a theory of reciprocity for extensive games in which the sequential structure of a strategic situation is made explicit, and propose a new solution concept: sequential reciprocity equilibrium. 13 See also Andreoni (1989, 1990), which are seminal literature of warm glow. 18

21 maker associated with the pro-social behavior to choose the allocation x instead of a selfish allocation y. Compared with our model, in their model, the function U is not uniquely identified even though their model also allows for preference reversals. On the other hand, we uniquely identify the parameters related to other-regarding preferences. 6 Concluding Remarks We have developed a reference-dependent model in other-regarding preferences, which captures an subjective and endogenous reference point as a cognitive anchor, which can be a criterion for decision-making. This reference-dependent model has a foundation for revealed reference-dependence in Ok, Ortoleva, and Riella (2015). The model captures pro-social behaviors arising from reference-dependent preferences. That is, the attitude toward otherregarding preferences depends on menus. The building blocks of the model have a distinction between pure altruism and pro-social behaviors. The pure altruism is captured by α. On the other hand, menu-dependent pro-social behaviors are captured by a pair (β( ), γ) where β( ) captures the menu-dependent inequality aversion, and γ is a paramter for the menu-dependent cognitive anchor. One remark is that the objective of this paper is to identify unique parameters for pure altruism (α) and menu-dependent pro-social behaviors (γ). We do not consider any assumptions for a specific correlation between them. For example, some people may think that if a decision maker has the attitude toward pure altruism is relatively high, i.e., α 1 is low, then her attitude toward pro-social behaviors is also high, i.e., γ S is high. Such a correlation should be studied in empirical studies as a future task. 19

22 A Proof of Theorem 1 A.1 Sufficiency Part We show the sufficiency part. (Theorem 1). Suppose that satisfies the axioms in the main theorem STEP 1: In Step 1, we induce the binary relation on (Z) I to represent the first term. By using 1 and S, we show that any singleton menus are represented by a non-constant function u : (Z) R. That is, for any p (Z) I, an allocation p is represented by U(p) = i I u(p i). First, we show that the primitive of the model, that is, the binary relation is represented by V : (( (Z) I ) A). As Debreu (1959) shows, it suffices to show that (( (Z) I ) A) is separable and connected. Next, remember that we define on (Z) I as follows. Definition 6. For any p, q (Z) I, p q if (p, {p}) (q, {q}). Again, remember the definitions of 1 and S. We can write down the two definitions by using. We say that p 1 1 q 1 if (p 1, r S ) (q 1, r S ) for some r S (Z) S. In the similar way, we say that p S S q S if (r 1, p S ) (r 1, q S ) for some r 1 (Z). The asymmetric and symmetric part of are described by > and, respectively. First, we show that 1 and S are well-defined. Consider 1. We show that p 1 1 q 1 if (p 1, r S ) (q 1, r S ) for any r S (Z) S. Suppose (p 1, r S ) (q 1, r S ) and (p 1, r S ) < (q 1, r S ). Consider 1 2 r S r S (Z)S. Then, by Singleton Independence, (p 1, 1 2 r S r S ) ( 1 2 q p 1, 1 2 r S r S ) and (p 1, r S ) < ( 1 2 q p 1, 1 2 r S r S ). This is a contradiction. Thus, we have p 1 1 q 1 if (p 1, r S ) (q 1, r S ) for any r S (Z) S. In the similar way, we can easily show that S is well-defined. Next, we show that 1 is represented by u : (Z) R. By definition, satisfies Completeness, Transitivity, and Continuity, so it is easily shown that 1 satisfies Completeness, Transitivity, and (Mixture) Continuity. We show that 1 satisfies Independence: For any p 1, q 1, r 1 and λ [0, 1], p 1 1 q 1 if and only if λp 1 + (1 λ)r 1 1 λq 1 + (1 λ)r 1. We show it by using the induced preference relation. Fix p 1, q 1, r 1 (Z) and λ [0, 1]. Then, for any p S, q S (Z) S, p 1 1 q 1 (p 1, p S ) (q 1, p S ) λ(p 1, p S ) + (1 λ)(r 1, q 1 ) λ(q 1, p S ) + (1 λ)(r 1, q S ) λp 1 + (1 λ)r 1 1 λq 1 + (1 λ)r 1. In the similar way, it is shown that S satisfies Independence. Hence, by von Neumann-Morgenstern s Expected Utility Theorem (See Kreps (1988)), there exists a mixture linear utility function u : (Z) R which represents 1. u is unique up to a positive affine transformation. is a binary relation on (Z) I. By Pareto, if p 1 1 q 1, and p S S q S, then p q. By 20

A Cognitive Foundation for Social Image Concerns

A Cognitive Foundation for Social Image Concerns CIRJE-F-1085 A Cognitive Foundation for Social Image Concerns Yosuke Hashidate CIRJE, Faculty of Economics, The University of Tokyo May 2018 CIRJE Discussion Papers can be downloaded without charge from:

More information

Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences

Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences Yosuke Hashidate Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo First Draft: January 2015 This Draft: February

More information

Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation

Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation Yosuke Hashidate Abstract In decision theory, it is not generally postulated that decision makers randomize their choices. In contrast, in real life, even

More information

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty Yosuke Hashidate Abstract This paper presents a behavioral characteization of a reference-dependent choice under uncertainty in the Anscombe-Aumann

More information

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1 Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1 Suguru Ito June 5 th, 2015 Abstract In this paper, we study an individual who faces a three-period decision problem when she accepts the partitional

More information

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Journal of Economic Theory 105, 531539 (2002) doi:10.1006jeth.2001.2824 Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Emre Ozdenoren Department of Economics, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan

More information

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva May 2013 Abstract One of the most prominently observed behavioral patterns in decision making

More information

Impure Altruism and Impure Selfishness

Impure Altruism and Impure Selfishness Impure Altruism and Impure Selfishness Kota SAITO California Institute of Technology September 5, 2013 Abstract Altruism refers to a willingness to benefit others, even at one s own expense. In contrast,

More information

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences in Expected Utility Alejandro Francetich Department of Decision Sciences and IGIER Bocconi University, Italy March 7, 204 Abstract Many choice-theoretic

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus. Testing Revealed Preference Theory, I: Methodology The revealed preference theory developed last time applied to a single agent. This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices

More information

Preference for Commitment

Preference for Commitment Preference for Commitment Mark Dean Behavioral Economics G6943 Fall 2016 Introduction In order to discuss preference for commitment we need to be able to discuss preferences over menus Interpretation:

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Axiomatic Decision Theory

Axiomatic Decision Theory Decision Theory Decision theory is about making choices It has a normative aspect what rational people should do... and a descriptive aspect what people do do Not surprisingly, it s been studied by economists,

More information

Social Preferences under Uncertainty

Social Preferences under Uncertainty Social Preferences under Uncertainty Equality of Opportunity vs. Equality of Outcome Kota SAITO Assistant Professor of Economics California Institute of Technology March 9, 0 Abstract This paper introduces

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence

Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence June 9, 2009 GENERAL OUTLINE Economic Rationality is Individual Optimization and Group Equilibrium Narrow version: Restrictive Assumptions about Objective

More information

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu Econ 701A Fall 2018 University of Pennsylvania Recitation 7: Uncertainty Xincheng Qiu (qiux@sas.upenn.edu 1 Expected Utility Remark 1. Primitives: in the basic consumer theory, a preference relation is

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

Expected Utility Framework

Expected Utility Framework Expected Utility Framework Preferences We want to examine the behavior of an individual, called a player, who must choose from among a set of outcomes. Let X be the (finite) set of outcomes with common

More information

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva February 2014 Abstract Many violations of the Independence axiom of Expected Utility can be

More information

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Susumu Cato January 17, 2006 Abstract In actual life, we face the opportunity of many choices, from that opportunity set, we have to choose from different alternatives.

More information

Static Decision Theory Under Certainty

Static Decision Theory Under Certainty Static Decision Theory Under Certainty Larry Blume September 22, 2010 1 basics A set of objects X An individual is asked to express preferences among the objects, or to make choices from subsets of X.

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

Homework #6 (10/18/2017) Homework #6 (0/8/207). Let G be the set of compound gambles over a finite set of deterministic payoffs {a, a 2,...a n } R +. A decision maker s preference relation over compound gambles can be represented

More information

Lexicographic Expected Utility with a Subjective State Space

Lexicographic Expected Utility with a Subjective State Space Lexicographic Expected Utility with a Subjective State Space Youichiro Higashi Kazuya Hyogo August 25, 2008 Abstract This paper provides a model that allows for a criterion of admissibility based on a

More information

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank No. 1611 March 2010 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working Paper No. 1611

More information

Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting

Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting Traeger, CES ifo 10 p. 1 Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting Christian Traeger Department of Agricultural & Resource Economics, UC Berkeley Introduce a more general preference representation

More information

Subjective Utilitarianism: Decisions in a social context

Subjective Utilitarianism: Decisions in a social context Subjective Utilitarianism: Decisions in a social context Shiri Alon and Ehud Lehrer March 19, 2017 Abstract Individual decisions are often subjectively affected by other-regarding preferences. We present

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal May 0, 0 Abstract Machina (009, 0) lists a number of situations where standard models of ambiguity aversion are unable to capture

More information

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect

More information

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts Review of Economics & Finance Submitted on 28/Nov./2011 Article ID: 1923-7529-2012-02-65-11 Yutaka Matsushita Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure

More information

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities NUPRI Working Paper 2016-03 Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities Takuya Iimura, Toshimasa Maruta, and Takahiro Watanabe October, 2016 Nihon University Population Research Institute http://www.nihon-u.ac.jp/research/institute/population/nupri/en/publications.html

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal January 9, 204 Abstract Machina (2009, 202) lists a number of situations where Choquet expected utility, as well as other known models

More information

Rationality and Uncertainty

Rationality and Uncertainty Rationality and Uncertainty Based on papers by Itzhak Gilboa, Massimo Marinacci, Andy Postlewaite, and David Schmeidler Warwick Aug 23, 2013 Risk and Uncertainty Dual use of probability: empirical frequencies

More information

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging Mark Dean and Pietro Ortoleva Abstract Two of the most well-known regularities observed in preferences under risk and uncertainty are ambiguity aversion and

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

Journal of Mathematical Economics

Journal of Mathematical Economics Journal of Mathematical Economics 63 (2016) 164 173 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Mathematical Economics journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jmateco A theory of stochastic

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

Coalitional Strategic Games

Coalitional Strategic Games Coalitional Strategic Games Kazuhiro Hara New York University November 28, 2016 Job Market Paper The latest version is available here. Abstract In pursuit of games played by groups of individuals (each

More information

Extrapolated Social Preferences

Extrapolated Social Preferences Extrapolated Social Preferences Maya Eden World Bank July 17, 2017 Abstract This paper proposes a simpler interpretation of Harsanyi s impartial observer idea. It postulates an impartiality axiom with

More information

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World heoretical Economics Letters, 013, 3, 17-1 http://dxdoiorg/10436/tel01335a004 Published Online September 013 (http://wwwscirporg/journal/tel) Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States

More information

Preferences and Utility

Preferences and Utility Preferences and Utility How can we formally describe an individual s preference for different amounts of a good? How can we represent his preference for a particular list of goods (a bundle) over another?

More information

THE EMPIRICAL IMPLICATIONS OF PRIVACY-AWARE CHOICE

THE EMPIRICAL IMPLICATIONS OF PRIVACY-AWARE CHOICE THE EMPIRICAL IMPLICATIONS OF PRIVACY-AWARE CHOICE RACHEL CUMMINGS, FEDERICO ECHENIQUE, AND ADAM WIERMAN Abstract. This paper initiates the study of the testable implications of choice data in settings

More information

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice Susumu Cato Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo, Japan Society for the Promotion of Science Research Fellow First Version: January 10, 2007

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY August 18, 2003 Aanund Hylland: # DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY Standard theory and alternatives 1. Introduction Individual decision making under uncertainty can be characterized as follows: The decision

More information

Northwestern University

Northwestern University Northwestern University 2001 Sheridan Road 580 Leverone Hall Evanston, IL 60208-2014 USA Discussion Paper #1489 August 1, 2010 Preference for Randomization Ambiguity Aversion and Inequality Aversion Key

More information

Quantum Decision Theory

Quantum Decision Theory Quantum Decision Theory V.I. Yukalov and D. Sornette Department of Management, Technology and Economics\ ETH Zürich Plan 1. Classical Decision Theory 1.1. Notations and definitions 1.2. Typical paradoxes

More information

Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility. Pavlo R. Blavatskyy

Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility. Pavlo R. Blavatskyy Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility Pavlo R. Blavatskyy Institute of Public Finance University of Innsbruck Universitaetsstrasse 15 A-6020 Innsbruck Austria Phone: +43 (0) 512 507 71 56 Fax: +43

More information

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva August 2014 Abstract Many violations of the Independence axiom of Expected Utility can be traced

More information

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice http://selod.ensae.net/m1 Paris School of Economics (selod@ens.fr) September 27, 2007 Notations Consider an individual (agent) facing a choice set X. Definition (Choice set, "Consumption set") X is a set

More information

Mathematical Social Sciences

Mathematical Social Sciences Mathematical Social Sciences 74 (2015) 68 72 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Mathematical Social Sciences journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase Continuity, completeness, betweenness

More information

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries Chapter 2 Decision Making under Risk In the previous lecture I considered abstract choice problems. In this section, I will focus on a special class of choice problems and impose more structure on the

More information

A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts

A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts Joseph Y. Halpern Cornell University Computer Science Department Ithaca, NY 14853 halpern@cs.cornell.edu http://www.cs.cornell.edu/home/halpern August 15, 2018

More information

Deliberately Stochastic

Deliberately Stochastic Deliberately Stochastic Simone Cerreia-Vioglio, David Dillenberger, Pietro Ortoleva, Gil Riella First version: February 2012 This version: May 5, 2018 Abstract We study stochastic choice as the outcome

More information

Moral Costs and Rational Choice: Theory and Experimental Evidence. James C. Cox, John A. List, Michael Price, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Anya Samek

Moral Costs and Rational Choice: Theory and Experimental Evidence. James C. Cox, John A. List, Michael Price, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Anya Samek Moral Costs and Rational Choice: Theory and Experimental Evidence James C. Cox, John A. List, Michael Price, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Anya Samek Dictator Games Hundreds of dictator games in the past 30 years

More information

Efficiency and Incentives in Randomized Social Choice

Efficiency and Incentives in Randomized Social Choice Technische Universität München Department of Mathematics Master s Thesis Efficiency and Incentives in Randomized Social Choice Florian Brandl Supervisor: Prof. Felix Brandt Submission Date: September 28,

More information

Deliberately Stochastic

Deliberately Stochastic Deliberately Stochastic Simone Cerreia-Vioglio, David Dillenberger, Pietro Ortoleva, Gil Riella First version: February 2012 This version: May 5, 2018 Abstract We study stochastic choice as the outcome

More information

A Unique Costly Contemplation Representation

A Unique Costly Contemplation Representation A Unique Costly Contemplation Representation Haluk Ergin Todd Sarver Current Draft: December 2005 PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE Abstract We extend the costly contemplation model to preferences over sets of

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 6: Choice under Uncertainty

More information

Transitive Regret. Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal. October 24, Abstract

Transitive Regret. Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal. October 24, Abstract Transitive Regret Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal October 24, 2009 Abstract Preferences may arise from regret, i.e., from comparisons with alternatives forgone by the decision maker. We ask whether regret-based

More information

WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS

WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS Implementation in Mixed Nash Equilibrium Claudio Mezzetti & Ludovic Renou No 902 WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Implementation in Mixed Nash Equilibrium Claudio Mezzetti & Ludovic

More information

LIMITED ATTENTION AND STATUS QUO BIAS

LIMITED ATTENTION AND STATUS QUO BIAS LIMITED ATTENTION AND STATUS QUO BIAS Mark Dean Özgür Kıbrıs Yusufcan Masatlioglu January 16, 2016 Abstract We introduce and axiomatically characterize a model of status quo bias in which the status quo

More information

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 11, October 3 Outline 1 Subjective Expected Utility 2 Qualitative Probabilities 3 Allais and Ellsebrg Paradoxes 4 Utility

More information

Individual decision-making under certainty

Individual decision-making under certainty Individual decision-making under certainty Objects of inquiry Our study begins with individual decision-making under certainty Items of interest include: Feasible set Objective function (Feasible set R)

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Regret aversion and opportunity dependence

Regret aversion and opportunity dependence Regret aversion and opportunity dependence Takashi Hayashi Department of Economics, University of Texas at Austin Austin, TX 78712 USA e-mail: th925@eco.utexas.edu First version, June 2005. This version,

More information

No-envy in Queueing Problems

No-envy in Queueing Problems No-envy in Queueing Problems Youngsub Chun School of Economics Seoul National University Seoul 151-742, Korea and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627, USA E-mail: ychun@plaza.snu.ac.kr

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012 Chapter 7: Von Neumann - Morgenstern Utilities Note: This

More information

An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences

An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences Simone Cerreia-Vioglio a, David Dillenberger b, Pietro Ortoleva c a Università Bocconi and Igier, b University of

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Mantas Radzvilas July 2017 Abstract In 1986 David Gauthier proposed an arbitration scheme

More information

Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries

Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries April 2, 2012 Abstract Preferences may arise from regret, i.e., from comparisons with alternatives forgone by the decision maker. We show that

More information

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Econ Theory Bull DOI 10.1007/s40505-016-0100-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Wei He 1 Nicholas C. Yannelis 1 Received: 7 February 2016 / Accepted:

More information

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization Edi Karni Johns Hopkins University and Warwick Business School Quitzé Valenzuela-Stookey Northwestern University Marie-Louise Vierø Queen s University December 10,

More information

Second-Order Expected Utility

Second-Order Expected Utility Second-Order Expected Utility Simon Grant Ben Polak Tomasz Strzalecki Preliminary version: November 2009 Abstract We present two axiomatizations of the Second-Order Expected Utility model in the context

More information

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 56, No., February 05 RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES BY DAVID DILLENBERGER AND UZI SEGAL University of Pennsylvania, U.S.A.; Boston College, U.S.A., and Warwick

More information

Ashamed to be Selfish

Ashamed to be Selfish Ashamed to be Selfish David Dillenberger University of Pennsylvania Philipp Sadowski Duke University September 20, 2010 ERID Working Paper Number 84 This paper can be downloaded without charge from The

More information

Choice with Menu-Dependent Rankings (Presentation Slides)

Choice with Menu-Dependent Rankings (Presentation Slides) Choice with Menu-Dependent Rankings (Presentation Slides) Paulo Natenzon October 22nd, 2008 1 References that appear on the slides are [1], [2], [3], [4], [5], [6], [7]. References [1] Markus K. Brunnermeier

More information

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information by Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics, Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA 30303

More information

Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260

Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260 1 Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260 Problem 1 a) What is a public good game? See, for example, Camerer (2003), Fehr and Schmidt (1999) p.836, and/or lecture notes, lecture 1 of Topic 3.

More information

Status Quo Bias, Multiple Priors and Uncertainty Aversion

Status Quo Bias, Multiple Priors and Uncertainty Aversion MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Status Quo Bias, Multiple Priors and Uncertainty Aversion Pietro Ortoleva New York University September 2008 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/12243/ MPRA Paper

More information

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

Can everyone benefit from innovation? Can everyone benefit from innovation? Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi June 16, 2017 Abstract We study a resource allocation problem with variable technologies, and ask if there is an allocation

More information

Costly Contemplation

Costly Contemplation Costly Contemplation Haluk Ergin MIT December 2003 Abstract We study preferences over opportunity sets. Such preferences are monotone if every opportunity set is at least as good as its subsets. We prove

More information

Preference for Commitment

Preference for Commitment Preference for Commitment Mark Dean Behavioral Economics Spring 2017 Introduction In order to discuss preference for commitment we need to be able to discuss people s preferences over menus Interpretation:

More information

Axiomatic bargaining. theory

Axiomatic bargaining. theory Axiomatic bargaining theory Objective: To formulate and analyse reasonable criteria for dividing the gains or losses from a cooperative endeavour among several agents. We begin with a non-empty set of

More information

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 1

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 1 Introduction to game theory LECTURE 1 Jörgen Weibull January 27, 2010 1 What is game theory? A mathematically formalized theory of strategic interaction between countries at war and peace, in federations

More information

Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes

Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes Efe A. Ok Pietro Ortoleva Gil Riella April 7, 2011 Abstract We investigate the classical Anscombe-Aumann model of decision-making

More information

A Theory of Subjective Learning

A Theory of Subjective Learning A Theory of Subjective Learning David Dillenberger Juan Sebastián Lleras Philipp Sadowski Norio Takeoka July 2014 Abstract We study an individual who faces a dynamic decision problem in which the process

More information

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Adam Dominiak 1 and Gerelt Tserenjigmid 2 1,2 Department of Economics, Virginia Tech September 10, 2018 Abstract In this paper, we study choice under growing awareness

More information

Hypothetical Bargaining and Equilibrium Refinement in Non-Cooperative Games

Hypothetical Bargaining and Equilibrium Refinement in Non-Cooperative Games Hypothetical Bargaining and Equilibrium Refinement in Non-Cooperative Games Mantas Radzvilas December 2016 Abstract Virtual bargaining theory suggests that social agents aim to resolve non-cooperative

More information

Partially Dominant Choice

Partially Dominant Choice Partially Dominant Choice Georgios Gerasimou February 19, 2015 Abstract This paper proposes and analyzes a model of context-dependent choice with stable but incomplete preferences that is based on the

More information

Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness

Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness T.C.A. Madhav Raghavan 31 July, 2014 Abstract In this note we study group-strategy-proofness, which is the extension of strategy-proofness to groups

More information

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences Conditional and Dynamic Preferences How can we Understand Risk in a Dynamic Setting? Samuel Drapeau Joint work with Hans Föllmer Humboldt University Berlin Jena - March 17th 2009 Samuel Drapeau Joint work

More information

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS IMPLEMENTATION IN MIXED NASH EQUILIBRIUM

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS IMPLEMENTATION IN MIXED NASH EQUILIBRIUM DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS IMPLEMENTATION IN MIXED NASH EQUILIBRIUM Claudio Mezzetti, University of Warwick, UK Ludovic Renou, University of Leicester, UK Working Paper No. 09/10 April 2009 Updated January

More information

Behavioral Mechanism Design

Behavioral Mechanism Design Behavioral Mechanism Design Serkan Kucuksenel January 2010 Abstract This paper studies the mechanism design problem for the class of Bayesian environments where agents do care for the well-being of others.

More information

A Theory of Local Menu Preferences

A Theory of Local Menu Preferences A Theory of Local Menu Preferences Madhav Chandrasekher Current Draft: June 12, 2014 Abstract: Choice models which satisfy Arrow s WARP cannot represent preferences that arise from settings in which the

More information