Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect"

Transcription

1 Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva August 2014 Abstract Many violations of the Independence axiom of Expected Utility can be traced to subjects attraction to risk-free prospects. The key axiom in this paper, Negative Certainty Independence (Dillenberger, 2010), formalizes this tendency. Our main result is a utility representation of all preferences over monetary lotteries that satisfy Negative Certainty Independence together with basic rationality postulates. Such preferences can be represented as if the agent were unsure of how to evaluate a given lottery p; instead, she has in mind a set of possible utility functions over outcomes and displays a cautious behavior: she computes the certainty equivalent of p with respect to each possible function in the set and picks the smallest one. The set of utilities is unique in a well-defined sense. We show that our representation can also be derived from a cautious completion of an incomplete preference relation. JEL: D80, D81 Keywords: Preferences under risk, Allais paradox, Negative Certainty Independence, Incomplete preferences, Cautious Completion, Multi-Utility representation. We thank Faruk Gul, Yoram Halevy, Fabio Maccheroni, Massimo Marinacci, Efe Ok, Wolfgang Pesendorfer, Gil Riella, and Todd Sarver for very useful comments and suggestions. The co-editor and the referees provided valuable comments that improved the paper significantly. We greatly thank Selman Erol for his help in the early stages of the project. Cerreia-Vioglio gratefully acknowledges the financial support of ERC (advanced grant, BRSCDP-TEA). Ortoleva gratefully acknowledges the financial support of NSF grant SES Department of Decision Sciences and IGIER, Università Bocconi. simone.cerreia@unibocconi.it. Department of Economics, University of Pennsylvania. ddill@sas.upenn.edu. Department of Economics, Columbia University. pietro.ortoleva@columbia.edu. 1

2 1 Introduction Despite its ubiquitous presence in economic analysis, the paradigm of Expected Utility is often violated in choices between risky prospects. While such violations have been documented in many different experiments, a specific preference pattern emerges as one of the most prominent: the tendency of people to favor risk-free options the so-called Certainty Effect (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979). This is shown in Allais Common Ratio and Common Consequence paradoxes, as well as in many more recent experimental studies. (Section 6 discusses this evidence at length.) Dillenberger (2010) suggests a way to define the Certainty Effect behaviorally, by introducing an axiom called Negative Certainty Independence (NCI). NCI states that for any two lotteries p and q, any number λ in [0, 1], and any lottery δ x that yields the prize x for sure, if p is preferred to δ x then λp + (1 λ) q is preferred to λδ x + (1 λ) q. That is, if the sure outcome x is not enough to compensate the decision maker (henceforth DM) for the risky prospect p, then mixing it with any other lottery, thus eliminating its certainty appeal, will not result in the mixture of δ x being preferred to the corresponding mixture of p. NCI is weaker than the Independence axiom, and in particular it permits Independence to fail when the Certainty Effect is present allowing the DM to favor certainty, but ruling out the converse behavior. In this paper we characterize the class of continuous, monotone, and complete preference relations, defined on lotteries over some interval of monetary prizes, that satisfy NCI. That is, we characterize a new class of preferences that accommodate the Certainty Effect, together with very basic rationality postulates. We show that any such preference relation admits the following representation: there exists a set W of strictly increasing (Bernoulli) utility functions over monetary outcomes, such that the value of any lottery p is given by V (p) = inf c (p, v), v W where c (p, v) is the certainty equivalent of lottery p calculated using the utility function v. That is, if we denote by E p (v) the expected utility of p with respect to v, then c (p, v) = v 1 (E p (v)). We call this representation a Cautious Expected Utility representation and interpret it as follows. The DM acts as if she were unsure how to evaluate each given lottery: she does not have one, but a set of possible utility functions over monetary 2

3 outcomes. She then reacts to this multiplicity using a form of caution: she evaluates each lottery according to the lowest possible certainty equivalent corresponding to some function in the set. Note that c (δ x, v) = x for all v W, which means that while the DM acts with caution when evaluating general lotteries, such caution does not play a role when evaluating degenerate ones. This captures the Certainty Effect. The Cautious Expected Utility model is also linked with the notion of a completion of incomplete preferences. Consider a DM who has an incomplete preference relation over lotteries, which is well-behaved (that is, a reflexive, transitive, monotone, and continuous binary relation that satisfies Independence). The DM is asked to choose between two options that the original preference relation is unable to compare; she then needs to choose a rule to complete her ranking. Suppose that she follows what we call a Cautious Completion: if the original relation is unable to compare a lottery p with a degenerate lottery δ x, then in the completion the DM opts for the latter when in doubt, go with certainty. We show that there always exists a unique Cautious Completion and that it admits a Cautious Expected Utility representation. 1 We then discuss the relation of our model with the theoretical and empirical literature. We argue that our model suggests a useful way of interpreting existing empirical evidence and derives new theoretical predictions, especially emphasizing the following three points. First, similarly to the most popular alternatives to Expected Utility (the Rank Dependent Utility (RDU) model of Quiggin, 1982 and the Betweenness class of Dekel, 1986 and Chew, 1989), our model accommodates the Certainty Effect by weakening the Independence axiom. In terms of generality, preferences in our class neither nest, nor are nested in, those that satisfy Betweenness, and are distinct from RDU, in the sense that RDU satisfies NCI only in the limiting case of Expected Utility. In terms of the key axiom delineating the departure from Expected Utility, while NCI is yet to be tested in its fullness, it is built on the Certainty Effect, which has solid empirical support. On the other hand, the analogous axioms (Comonotonic/Ordinal Independence and Betweenness) are frequently violated in experiments. Second, our model can accommodate some evidence on the Certainty Effect (e.g., the presence of Allais-type behavior with large stakes but not with small ones), which 1 In fact, we show that it admits a Cautious Expected Utility representation with the same set of utilities that can be used to represent the original incomplete preference relation (in the sense of the Expected Multi-Utility representation of Dubra et al., 2004). 3

4 poses difficulties to many popular alternative models. Third, our model is consistent with the main stylized facts of preferences under risk as surveyed in Camerer (1995) and Starmer (2000). Moreover, some of these facts are predicted by our model without requiring any additional assumptions on the functional form. The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. Section 2 presents the axiomatic structure, the main representation theorem, and the uniqueness properties of the representation. Section 3 characterizes risk attitudes and comparative risk aversion. Section 4 presents the result on the completion of incomplete preference relations. Section 5 surveys related theoretical models. Section 6 discusses the experimental evidence. All proofs appear in the Appendices. 2 The Model 2.1 Framework Consider a compact interval [w, b] R of monetary prizes. Let be the set of lotteries (Borel probability measures) over [w, b], endowed with the topology of weak convergence. We denote by x, y, z generic elements of [w, b] and by p, q, r generic elements of. We denote by δ x the degenerate lottery (Dirac measure at x) that gives the prize x [w, b] with certainty. The primitive of our analysis is a binary relation over. The symmetric and asymmetric parts of are denoted by and, respectively. The certainty equivalent of a lottery p is a prize x p [w, b] such that δ xp p. We start by imposing the following basic axioms on. Axiom 1 (Weak Order). The relation is complete and transitive. Axiom 2 (Continuity). For each q, the sets {p : p q} and {p : q p} are closed. Axiom 3 (Weak Monotonicity). For each x, y [w, b], x y if and only if δ x δ y. The three axioms above are standard postulates. Weak Order is a common assumption of rationality. Continuity is needed to represent through a continuous utility function. Finally, under the interpretation of as monetary lotteries, Weak Monotonicity simply implies that more money is better than less. 4

5 2.2 Negative Certainty Independence (NCI) Consider a version of Allais paradox (called the Common Ratio Effect), in which subjects choose between A = δ 3000 and B = 0.8δ δ 0, and also between C = 0.25δ δ 0 and D = 0.2δ δ 0. The typical finding is that the majority of subjects tend to systematically violate the Independence axiom of Expected Utility by choosing the pair A and D. 2,3 Kahneman and Tversky (1979) called this pattern of behavior the Certainty Effect. The next axiom, introduced in Dillenberger (2010), captures the Certainty Effect with the following relaxation of Independence. Axiom 4 (Negative Certainty Independence). For each p, q, x [w, b], and λ [0, 1], p δ x λp + (1 λ)q λδ x + (1 λ)q. (NCI) NCI states that if the sure outcome x is not enough to compensate the DM for the risky prospect p, then mixing it with any other lottery, thus eliminating its certainty appeal, will not result in the mixture of x being more attractive than the corresponding mixture of p. In particular, x p, the certainty equivalent of p, might not be enough to compensate for p when part of a mixture. 4 the Certainty Effect. In this sense NCI captures When applied to the Common Ratio experiment, NCI only posits that if B is chosen in the first problem, then D must be chosen in the second one. Specifically, it allows the DM to choose the pair A and D, in line with the typical pattern of choice. Coherently with this interpretation, NCI captures the Certainty Effect as defined by Kahneman and Tversky (1979) except that, as opposed to the latter, NCI applies also to lotteries with three or more possible outcomes and can thus apply to broader evidence. 5 For example, the exact same theoretical restrictions can be used to address also Allais Common Consequence Effect. 6 2 Recall that a binary relation satisfies Independence if and only if for each p, q, r and for each λ (0, 1], we have p q if and only if λp + (1 λ) r λq + (1 λ) r. 3 This example is taken from Kahneman and Tversky (1979). Of 95 subjects, 80 percent chose A over B, 65 percent chose C over D, and more than half chose the pair (A, D). Note that prospects C and D are the 0.25:0.75 mixture of prospects A and B, respectively, with δ 0. This means that the only pairs of choices consistent with Expected Utility are (A, C) and (B, D). 4 We show in Appendix A (Proposition 6) that our axioms imply that preserves First Order Stochastic Dominance and thus for each lottery p there exists a unique certainty equivalent x p. 5 Kahneman and Tversky (1979) define the Certainty Effect as the requirement that for x, y [w, b] and α, β (0, 1), if αδ y + (1 α) δ 0 is indifferent to δ x, then αβδ y + (1 αβ) δ 0 is preferred to βδ x + (1 β) δ 0. Note that this immediately follows from NCI. 6 In Allais Common Consequence Effect, subjects choose between A = δ 1M and B = 0.1δ 5M + 5

6 Figure 1: NCI and the Marschak-Machina triangle Besides capturing the Certainty Effect, NCI puts additional structure on preferences over. For example, NCI (in addition to the other basic axioms) implies Convexity: for each p, q, if p q then λp + (1 λ) q q for all λ [0, 1]. 7 NCI thus suggests weak preference for randomization between indifferent lotteries. Similarly, NCI implies that if p δ x then λp + (1 λ) δ x p for all λ [0, 1], which means neutrality towards mixing a lottery with its certainty equivalent. To illustrate these restrictions, we now discuss the pattern of indifference curves in any Marschak-Machina triangle, which represents all lotteries over three fixed outcomes x 3 > x 2 > x 1 (see Figure 1). NCI implies three restrictions on these curves: (i) by Convexity, all curves must be convex; (ii) the bold indifference curve through the origin (which represents the lottery δ x2 ) is linear, due to neutrality towards mixing a lottery with its certainty equivalent; and (iii) this bold indifference curve is also the steepest, that is, its slope relative to the (p 1, p 3 ) coordinates exceeds that of any 0.89δ 1M δ 0, and also between C = 0.11δ 1M δ 0 and D = 0.1δ 5M + 0.9δ 0. The typical pattern of choice is the pair (A, D). It can be shown that when combined with Axioms 1 3, the only way to violate NCI is to choose the pair (B, C), and that any such violation of NCI has a corresponding violation in the Common Ratio Effect (and vice versa). Our focus on the Common Ratio Effect in motivating NCI is made mostly for explanatory purposes. 7 To see this, assume p q and apply NCI twice to obtain that λp+(1 λ) q λδ xp +(1 λ) q λδ xp + (1 λ) δ xq = δ xq q. 6

7 other indifference curve in the triangle. 8 Since, as explained by Machina (1982), the slope of an indifference curve expresses local attitude towards risk (with greater slope corresponds to higher local risk aversion), property (iii) captures the Certainty Effect by, loosely speaking, requiring that local risk aversion is at its peak when it involves a degenerate lottery. In Section 6 we show that this pattern of indifference curves is consistent with a variety of experimental evidence on decision making under risk. 2.3 Representation Theorem Before stating our representation theorem, we introduce some notation. We say that a function V : R represents when p q if and only if V (p) V (q). Denote by U the set of continuous and strictly increasing functions v from [w, b] to R. We endow U with the topology induced by the supnorm. For each lottery p and function v U, E p (v) denotes the expected utility of p with respect to v. The certainty equivalent of lottery p calculated using the utility function v is thus c (p, v) = v 1 (E p (v)) [w, b]. Definition 1. Let be a binary relation on and W a subset of U. The set W is a Cautious Expected Utility representation of if and only if the function V : R, defined by V (p) = inf c (p, v) p, v W represents. We say that W is a Continuous Cautious Expected Utility representation if and only if V is also continuous. Theorem 1. Let be a binary relation on. The following statements are equivalent: (i) The relation satisfies Weak Order, Continuity, Weak Monotonicity, and Negative Certainty Independence; (ii) There exists a Continuous Cautious Expected Utility representation of. According to a Cautious Expected Utility representation, the DM has a set W of possible utility functions over monetary outcomes. While each of these functions is strictly increasing, i.e., agrees that more money is better, these functions may have different curvatures: it is as if the DM is unsure how to evaluate each lottery. The 8 The steepest middle slope property is formally derived in Lemma 3 of Dillenberger (2010). 7

8 DM reacts to this multiplicity with caution: she evaluates each lottery p by using the utility function that returns the lowest certainty equivalent. As an example, suppose the DM needs to evaluate the lottery p that pays either $0 or $10, 000, both equally likely. The DM may find it difficult to give a precise answer, but, instead, finds it conceivable that her certainty equivalent of p falls in the range [$3, 500, $4, 500], and that this interval is tight (that is, the end points are plausible evaluations). This is the first component of the representation: the DM has a set of plausible valuations that she considers. Nevertheless, when asked how much she would be willing to pay in order to obtain p, she is cautious and answers at most $3, 500. This is the second component. Note that if W contains only one element then the model reduces to Expected Utility. Moreover, since each v W is strictly increasing, it preserves monotonicity with respect to First Order Stochastic Dominance. An important feature of the representation in Theorem 1 is that the DM uses the utility function that minimizes the certainty equivalent of a lottery, instead of its expected utility. This leads to the Certainty Effect: while the DM acts with caution when evaluating general lotteries, caution does not play a role when evaluating degenerate ones independently of the utility function being used, the certainty equivalent of receiving the prize x for sure is x. Example 1. Let [w, b] [0, ) and W = {u 1, u 2 }, where u 1 (x) = exp ( βx), β > 0; and u 2 (x) = x α, α (0, 1). Consider the Common Ratio example from Section 2.2. Let α = 0.8 and β = We have V (B) = c (B, u 1 ) 2904 < 3000 = V (A), but V (D) = c (D, u 2 ) 535 > 530 c (C, u 2 ) = V (C). Thus A B but D C. Example 1 shows that one could address experimental evidence related to the Certainty Effect using a set W that includes only two utility functions. The key feature that allows this is that there is no unique v in W which minimizes the certainty equivalents for all lotteries otherwise, only v would matter and behavior would coincide with Expected Utility. 9 9 This implies, for example, that if all utilities in W have constant relative risk aversion (that is, v i W only if v i (x) = x αi for some α i (0, 1)), then preferences will be indistinguishable from Expected Utility with coefficient of relative risk aversion equals 1 min j α j. In Section 2.6 we suggest some convenient parametric class of utility functions that can be used in applications. 8

9 The interpretation of the Cautious Expected Utility representation is different from some of the most prominent existing models of non-expected Utility. For example, the common interpretation of Rank Dependent Utility is that the DM knows her utility function but she distorts probabilities. By contrast, in a Cautious Expected Utility representation the DM takes probabilities at face value, but she is unsure of which utility function to use and applies caution. Rather, the interpretation of our model is reminiscent of the Maxmin Expected Utility of Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989) under ambiguity, in which the DM has a set of probabilities and evaluates acts using the worst probability in the set. Our model can be seen as a corresponding model under risk. This analogy with Maxmin Expected Utility will be strengthened by our analysis in Section 4, where we argue that both models can be derived from extending incomplete preferences using a cautious rule. Before proceeding, we introduce a notion that will play a major role in the subsequent analysis. Let be the largest subrelation of that satisfies the Independence axiom. Formally, define on by p q λp + (1 λ) r λq + (1 λ) r λ (0, 1], r. (1) In the context of choice under risk, this derived relation was proposed and characterized by Cerreia-Vioglio (2009). It parallels a notion introduced in the context of ambiguity by Ghirardato et al. (2004) (see also Cerreia-Vioglio et al., 2011). Since it satisfies Independence, is often interpreted as including the comparisons that the DM is confident in making. We refer to as the Linear Core of. 2.4 Proof Sketch of Theorem 1 In what follows we sketch the proof of Theorem 1; a complete proof appears in Appendix B. We focus here only on the sufficiency of the axioms for the representation. Step 1. Define the Linear Core of. As we have discussed above, we introduce the binary relation on defined in (1). Step 2. Find the set W U that represents. By Cerreia-Vioglio (2009), is reflexive, transitive, continuous, and satisfies Independence. In particular, there exists a set W of continuous functions on [w, b] that constitutes an Expected Multi- Utility representation of, that is, p q if and only if E p (v) E q (v) for all v W (see Dubra et al., 2004). Since satisfies Weak Monotonicity and NCI, also 9

10 satisfies Weak Monotonicity. Thus, W can be chosen to be composed only of strictly increasing functions. Step 3. Representation of. We show that admits a certainty equivalent representation, i.e., there exists V : R such that V represents and V (δ x ) = x for all x [w, b]. Step 4. Relation between and. We note that (i) is a completion of, i.e., p q implies p q; and (ii) for each p and for each x [w, b], p δ x implies δ x p. The latter is an immediate implication of NCI. Step 5. Final step. We conclude the proof by showing that we must have V (p) = inf v W c (p, v) for all p. For each p, find x [w, b] such that p δ x, which means V (p) = V (δ x ) = x. First note that we must have V (p) = x inf v W c (p, v). If not, then we would have that x > c (p, v) for some v W, which means, by Step 2, p δ x. But by Step 4(ii) we would obtain δ x p, contradicting δ x p. Second, we must have V (p) = x inf v W c (p, v): if not, then we would have x < inf v W c (p, v). We could then find y such that x < y < inf v W c (p, v), which, by Step 2, would yield p δ y. By Step 4 (i), we could conclude that p δ y δ x, contradicting p δ x. 2.5 Uniqueness and Properties of the Set of Utilities We now discuss the uniqueness properties of the set W in a Cautious Expected Utility representation. We define the set of normalized utility functions U nor = {v U : v(w) = 0, v(b) = 1} and, without loss of generality, confine our attention to a normalized representation (that is, when W U nor ). We first show that even with this normalization, we are bound to find uniqueness properties only up to the closed convex hull. Denote by co (W) the closed convex hull of a set W U nor. Proposition 1. If W, W U nor are such that co (W) = co (W ) then inf v W c (p, v) = inf c (p, v) p. v W Moreover, W in general will not be unique, even up to the closed convex hull, as we can always add redundant utility functions that will never achieve the infimum. To see this, consider any set W in a Cautious Expected Utility representation and add to it a function v which is a continuous, strictly increasing, and strictly convex transformation of some other function u W. The set W { v} will give a Cautious 10

11 Expected Utility representation of the same preference relation, as the function v will never be used in the representation. 10 Once we remove these redundant utilities, we can identify a unique (up to the closed convex hull) set of utilities. In particular, for each preference relation that admits a Continuous Cautious Expected Utility representation, there exists a set Ŵ such that any other Cautious Expected Utility representation W of these preferences is such that co(ŵ) co(w). In this sense Ŵ is a minimal set of utilities. Moreover, the set Ŵ will have a natural interpretation in our setup: it constitutes a unique (up to the closed convex hull) Expected Multi-Utility representation of the Linear Core, the derived relation defined in (1). Theorem 2. Let be a binary relation on that satisfies Weak Order, Continuity, Weak Monotonicity, and Negative Certainty Independence. Then there exists Ŵ U nor such that (i) The set Ŵ is a Continuous Cautious Expected Utility representation of ; (ii) If W U nor is a Cautious Expected Utility representation of then co(ŵ) co(w); (iii) The set Ŵ is an Expected Multi-Utility representation of, that is, p q E p (v) E q (v) v Ŵ. Moreover, Ŵ is unique up to the closed convex hull Parametric Sets of Utilities and Elicitation In applied work, it is common to focus on parametric classes of utility functions. In this subsection we suggest two examples of parsimonious families of utility functions that are compatible with Cautious Expected Utility representation. We then remark on the issue of how to elicit the set of utilities from a finite data set. 10 Since u W and c (p, u) c (p, v) for all p, there will not be a lottery p such that inf v W { v} c (p, v) = c (p, v) < inf v W c (p, v). 11 Evren (2014) characterizes (possibly incomplete) preference relations that satisfy Independence and a form of continuity which is stronger than ours. He obtains a normalized Expected Multi- Utility representation with a compact set W. To our knowledge, he was the first to study the notion of uniqueness of this representation up to the closed convex hull (see his Theorem 2). 11

12 The first example is the family of Expo-Power utility functions (Saha, 1993), which generalizes both constant absolute and constant relative risk aversion, given by u (x) = 1 exp ( λx θ), with λ 0, θ 0, and λθ > 0. This functional form has been applied in a variety of fields, such as finance, intertemporal choices, and agriculture economics. Holt and Laury (2002) argue that this functional form fits well experimental data that involve both low and high stakes. The second example is the set of Pareto utility functions, given by u (x) = 1 ( 1 + x γ ) κ, with γ > 0 and κ > 0. Ikefuji et al. (2012) show that a Pareto utility function has some desirable properties. 12 We conclude with a remark on the issue of elicitation. If one could observe the certainty equivalents for all lotteries, then the whole preference relation would be recovered and the set W identified (up to its uniqueness properties) but this requires an infinite number of observations. With a finite data set, one can approximate, or partially recover, the set W as follows. Note that if a function v assigns to some lottery p a certainty equivalent smaller than the one observed in the data, then v cannot belong to W. Therefore, by observing the certainty equivalents of a finite number of lotteries, one could exclude a set of possible utility functions and approximate the set W from above. The set thus obtained would necessarily contain the true one, and as the number of observations increases, it will shrink to coincide with W (or, more precisely, with a version of W up to uniqueness). Such elicitation would be significantly faster if, as is often the case in empirical work, one focuses on utility functions that come from a specific parametric class. 3 Cautious Expected Utility and Risk Attitudes In this section we explore the connection between Theorem 1 and standard definitions of risk attitude, and characterize the comparative notion of more risk averse than. 12 If u is Pareto, then the coefficient of absolute risk aversion is u (x) u (x) = κ+1 x+γ, which is increasing in κ and decreasing in γ. Therefore, for a large enough interval [w, b], if κ u > κ v and γ u > γ v then u and v are not ranked in terms of risk aversion. 12

13 Throughout this section, we mainly focus on a minimal representation Ŵ as in Theorem 2. Remark. If W is a Continuous Cautious Expected Utility representation of a preference relation, we denote by Ŵ a set of utilities as identified in Theorem 2 (which is unique up to the closed convex hull). More formally, we can define a correspondence T that maps each set W that is a Continuous Cautious Expected Utility representation of some to a class of subsets of U nor, T (W), each element of which satisfies the properties of points (i)-(iii) of Theorem 2 and is denoted by Ŵ. 3.1 Characterization of Risk Attitudes We adopt the following standard definition of risk aversion/risk seeking. Definition 2. We say that is risk averse (resp., risk seeking) if p q (resp., q p) whenever q is a mean preserving spread of p. Theorem 3. Let be a binary relation that satisfies Weak Order, Continuity, Weak Monotonicity, and Negative Certainty Independence. The following statements are true: (i) The relation is risk averse if and only if each v (ii) The relation is risk seeking if and only if each v Ŵ is concave. Ŵ is convex. Theorem 3 shows that the relationship found under Expected Utility between the concavity/convexity of the utility function and risk attitude holds also for the Continuous Cautious Expected Utility model although it now involves all utilities in the set Ŵ. In turn, this shows that our model is compatible with many types of risk attitudes. For example, despite the presence of the Certainty Effect, when all utilities are convex the DM would be risk seeking. 3.2 Comparative Risk Aversion We now proceed to compare the risk attitudes of two individuals. Definition 3. Let 1 and 2 be two binary relations on. We say that 1 is more risk averse than 2 if and only if for each p and for each x [w, b], p 1 δ x = p 2 δ x. 13

14 Theorem 4. Let 1 and 2 be two binary relations with Continuous Cautious Expected Utility representations, W 1 and W 2, respectively. The following statements are equivalent: (i) 1 is more risk averse than 2 ; (ii) Both W 1 W 2 and W 1 are Continuous Cautious Expected Utility representations of 1 ; (iii) co ( W 1 W 2 ) = co(ŵ1). Theorem 4 states that DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 if and only if all the utilities in W 2 are redundant when added to W 1. 13,14 This result compounds two different channels that lead one DM to be more risk averse than another. The first is related to the curvatures of the functions in each set of utilities. For example, if each v W 2 is a strictly increasing and strictly convex transformation of some ˆv W 1, then DM2 assigns a strictly higher certainty equivalent than DM1 to any nondegenerate lottery p (while the certain outcomes are, by construction, treated similarly in both). In particular, no member of W 2 will be used in the representation corresponding to W 1 W 2. The second channel corresponds to comparing the size of the two sets: if W 2 W 1, then for each p the certainty equivalent under W 2 is weakly greater than that under W 1, implying that 1 is more risk averse than 2. To distinguish between these two different channels and characterize the behavioral underpinning of the second one, we focus on the notion of Linear Core and its representation as in Theorem 2. Definition 4. Let 1 and 2 be two binary relations on with corresponding Linear Cores 1 and 2. We say that 1 is more indecisive than 2 if and only if for each p, q p 1 q = p 2 q. Since we interpret the derived binary relation as capturing the comparisons that the DM is confident in making, Definition 4 implies that DM1 is more indecisive than DM2 if whenever DM1 can confidently declare p weakly better than q, so does 13 We thank Todd Sarver for suggesting point (iii) in Theorem Note that if both 1 and 2 are Expected Utility preferences, then there are v 1 and v 2 such that {v 1 } = W 1 = Ŵ1, {v 2 } = W 2 = Ŵ2, and points (ii) and (iii) in Theorem 4 are equivalent to v 1 being a strictly increasing concave transformation of v 2. 14

15 DM2. The following result characterizes this comparative relation and links it to the comparative notion of risk aversion. Proposition 2. Let 1 and 2 be two binary relations that satisfy Weak Order, Continuity, Weak Monotonicity, and Negative Certainty Independence. The following statements are true: (i) 1 is more indecisive than 2 if and only if co(ŵ2) co(ŵ1); (ii) If 1 is more indecisive than 2 then 1 is more risk averse than 2. 4 Cautious Completions of Incomplete Preferences Our analysis thus far has focused on the characterization of a complete preference relation that satisfies NCI (in addition to the other basic axioms). We now show that it is also related to that of a cautious completion of incomplete preferences. Consider a DM who has an incomplete preference relation over. There might be occasions in which the DM is asked to choose among lotteries she cannot compare, and to do this she has to complete her preferences. Suppose that the DM wants to do so by applying caution: when in doubt between a sure outcome and a lottery, she opts for the sure outcome. Which preferences will she obtain as a completion? This analysis parallels the one of Gilboa et al. (2010), who consider an environment with ambiguity instead of risk. 15,16 Since we study an incomplete preference relation, we require a slightly stronger notion of continuity, called Sequential Continuity (which coincides with our Continuity axiom if the binary relation is complete and transitive). Axiom 5 (Sequential Continuity). Let {p n } n N and {q n } n N be two sequences in. If p n p, q n q, and p n q n for all n N then p q. 15 There is one minor formal difference: while in Gilboa et al. (2010) both the incomplete relation and its completion are primitives of the analysis, in our case the primitive is simply the incomplete preference relation over lotteries, and we study the properties of all possible completions of this kind. 16 Riella (2013) develops a more general treatment that encompasses the result in this section and the one in Gilboa et al. (2010); he shows that a combined model could be obtained starting from a preference relation over acts that admits a Multi-Prior Expected Multi-Utility representation, as in Ok et al. (2012) and Galaabaatar and Karni (2013), and constructing a Cautious Completion. 15

16 In the rest of the section, we assume that is a reflexive and transitive binary relation over, which satisfies Sequential Continuity, Weak Monotonicity, and Independence. We look for a Cautious Completion of, which is defined as follows. Definition 5. Let be a binary relation on. We say that the binary relation ˆ is a Cautious Completion of if and only if the following hold: 1. The relation ˆ satisfies Weak Order, Weak Monotonicity, and for each p there exists x [w, b] such that p ˆ δ x ; 2. For each p, q, if p q then p ˆ q; 3. For each p and x [w, b], if p δ x then δ x ˆ p. Point 1 imposes few minimal requirements of rationality on ˆ and the existence of a certainty equivalent for each lottery p. (Weak Monotonicity will imply that this certainty equivalent is unique.) In point 2, we assume that the relation ˆ extends. Finally, point 3 requires that such a completion of is done with caution. Theorem 5. If is a reflexive and transitive binary relation on that satisfies Sequential Continuity, Weak Monotonicity, and Independence, then admits a unique Cautious Completion ˆ and there exists a set W U nor such that for all p, q p q E p (v) E q (v) v W and p ˆ q inf c (p, v) inf c (q, v). v W v W Moreover, W is unique up to the closed convex hull. Theorem 5 shows that, given a binary relation which satisfies all the tenets of Expected Utility except completeness, there always exists a unique Cautious Completion ˆ. Most importantly, such completion admits a Cautious Expected Utility representation, using the same set of utilities as in the Expected Multi-Utility representation of the original preference. This shows that the Cautious Expected Utility model could also represent the behavior of a subject who might be unable to compare some of the available options and, when asked to extend her ranking, does 16

17 so by being cautious. Together with Theorem 1, Theorem 5 shows that this behavior is indistinguishable from that of a subject who starts with a complete preference relation and satisfies Axioms 1 4. Theorem 5 strengthens the link between our model and the Maxmin Expected Utility model of Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989). Gilboa et al. (2010) show that the latter could be derived as a completion of an incomplete preference relation over Anscombe-Aumann acts that satisfies the same assumptions as (adapted to their domain), by applying a form of caution according to which, when in doubt, the DM chooses a constant act. Similarly, here we derive the Cautious Expected Utility model by extending an incomplete preference over lotteries using a form of caution according to which, when in doubt, the DM chooses a risk-free lottery Related Literature Dillenberger (2010) introduces the NCI axiom and studies its implications in dynamic settings. Under specific assumptions on preferences over two-stage lotteries, he shows that NCI is a necessary and sufficient condition to a property called preference for one-shot resolution of uncertainty. Dillenberger, however, does not provide a utility representation for preferences that satisfy NCI, as in Theorem 1. Cerreia-Vioglio (2009) characterizes the class of continuous and complete preference relations that satisfy Convexity. Loosely speaking, Cerreia-Vioglio shows that there exists a set W of normalized Bernoulli utility functions, and a real function U on R W, such that preferences are represented by V (p) = inf v W U (E p (v), v). Using this representation, Cerreia-Vioglio interprets Convexity as a behavioral property that captures a preference for hedging that may arise in the face of uncertainty about the value of outcomes, future tastes, and/or the degree of risk aversion. He suggests the choice of the minimal certainty equivalent as a criterion to resolve uncertainty about risk attitudes and as a completion procedure. Since NCI implies Convexity (see Section 2.2), our model is a special case of his (from the representation, this can be seen by setting U (E p (v), v) = v 1 (E p (v)) = c (p, v)). A popular generalization of Expected Utility is the Rank Dependent Utility (RDU) model of Quiggin (1982), also used within Cumulative Prospect Theory (Tversky and 17 The condition in Gilboa et al. (2010) is termed Default to Certainty; Point 3 of Definition 5 is the translation of this condition to the context of choice under risk. 17

18 Kahneman, 1992). In this model, individuals weight probability in a nonlinear way using a distortion function f : [0, 1] [0, 1], which is strictly increasing and onto. 18 If f (p) = p then RDU reduces to Expected Utility. If f is convex, then larger weight is given to inferior outcomes, leading to a pessimistic probability distortion suitable to explain the Allais paradoxes. Apart from the different interpretation of RDU compared to our Cautious Expected Utility representation, as discussed in Section 2.3, the two models are behaviorally distinct: Dillenberger (2010) shows that RDU satisfies NCI only in the limiting case of Expected Utility. 19 Another popular class of continuous and monotone preferences is the one introduced by Dekel (1986) and Chew (1989) based on the Betweenness axiom. 20 Under this postulate, indifference curves in the Marschak-Machina triangle are linear, but they are not necessarily parallel as in Expected Utility. One prominent example of such preferences is Gul (1991) s model of Disappointment Aversion (denoted DA in Figure 2), which adds one parameter, β ( 1, ) to Expected Utility. Artstein- Avidan and Dillenberger (2011) show that Gul s preferences satisfy NCI if and only if β 0; and Dillenberger and Erol (2013) provide an example of a continuous, monotone, and complete preference relation that satisfies NCI but not Betweenness. Thus, preferences in our class neither nest, nor are nested in, those that satisfy Betweenness. Figure 2 summarizes our discussion thus far. 21 Maccheroni (2002) (see also Chatterjee and Krishna, 2011) studies the following model: there exists a set T of utilities over outcomes, such that preferences are rep- 18 If we order the prizes in the support of a finite lottery p, with x 1 < x 2 <... < x n, then the functional form for RDU is: n 1 V (p) = u(x n )f(p (x n ) ) + u(x i )[f( i=1 n p (x j )) f( j=i n j=i+1 p (x j ))], where f : [0, 1] [0, 1] is strictly increasing and onto, and u : [w, b] R is increasing. 19 Bell and Fishburn (2003) show that Expected Utility is the only RDU with the property that for each binary lottery p and x [w, b], p δ x implies αp+(1 α) δ x δ x. This property is implied by NCI (see Section 2.2). Geometrically, it corresponds to the linear indifference curve through the origin in any Marschak-Machina triangle (Figure 1 in Section 2.2). 20 The Betweenness axiom states that for each p, q and λ (0, 1), p q (resp., p q) implies p λp + (1 λ) q q (resp., p λp + (1 λ) q q). 21 Chew and Epstein (1989) show that there is no intersection between RDU and Betweenness other than Expected Utility (see also Bell and Fishburn, 2003). Whether or not RDU satisfies Convexity depends on the curvature of the distortion function f; in particular, concave f implies Convexity. In addition to Disappointment Aversion with negative β, an example of preferences that satisfy Betweenness but do not satisfy NCI is Chew (1983) s model of Weighted Utility. 18

19 Expected Utility Cautious EU DA with >0 Rank Dependent Utility Convex preferences DA with <0 Betweenness Figure 2: Cautious Expected Utility and other models resented by V (p) = min E p (v). Maccheroni s interpretation that the most pessimist v T of [the DM] selves gets the upper hand over the others, is closely related to the interpretation of our functional form. In addition, both models satisfy Convexity. There are, however, two main differences between the two models. First, Maccheroni s model cannot (and was not meant to) address the Certainty Effect: since certainty equivalents are not used, also degenerate lotteries have multiple evaluations. Second, besides Convexity, Maccheroni s other key axiom, which requires Independence when mixing lotteries with the best possible outcome (b), is distinct from NCI. Schmidt (1998) develops a model in which the value of any nondegenerate lottery p is E p (u), whereas the value of the degenerate lottery δ x is v(x). The Certainty Effect is captured by requiring v(x) > u(x) for all x. Schmidt s model violates both Continuity and Monotonicity, while we confine our attention to preferences that satisfy both of these basic properties. In addition, his model also violates NCI. 22 Other discontinuous 22 For example, take u (x) = x and v (x) = 2x, and note that V (δ 3 ) = 6 > 4 = V (δ 2 ), but V (δ 2 ) = 4 > 2.5 = V (0.5δ δ 2 ). (The statement in Dillenberger and Erol (2013) that Schmidt s model satisfies NCI is incorrect.) 19

20 specifications of the Certainty Effect include, for example, Gilboa (1988) and Jaffray (1988), which are models of expected utility with security level. Dean and Ortoleva (2014) present a model that, when restricted to preferences over lotteries, generalizes pessimistic RDU. In their model, the DM has one utility function and a set of convex probability distortion functions; she then evaluates each lottery using the most pessimistic of these distortions. The exact relation between their model and ours remains an open question. Machina (1982) studies a model with minimal restrictions imposed on preferences apart from requiring them to be smooth (Fréchet differentiable). One of the main behavioral assumptions proposed by Machina is Hypothesis II, which implies that indifference curves in the Marschak-Machina triangle Fan Out, that is, they become steeper as one moves in the north-west direction. The steepest middle slope property (Section 2.2) implies that our model can accommodate Fanning Out in the lower-right part of the triangle (from where most evidence on Allais-type behavior had come), while global Fanning Out is ruled out. 6 Experimental Evidence In this section we discuss the experimental evidence pertaining to the two Allais paradoxes the Common Ratio and Common Consequence effects and more broadly the empirical regularities of preferences under risk. In light of this evidence, we evaluate the fit of our model and that of the two most popular alternatives to Expected Utility, RDU and Betweenness, which are also consistent with Allais-type behavior. 23 Our discussion relies on the surveys in Camerer (1995) and Starmer (2000), and on more recent findings. The presence of Allais-type behavior when one alternative in the choice set is riskfree is extensively documented (see Camerer, 1995, Section C1). A natural question is whether violations of Expected Utility in these experiments depend on the special nature of certainty, or whether they would be exhibited also when certainty is not 23 In reviewing the evidence related to the Common Ratio and Common Consequence effects, we find it useful to discuss them together. For the purpose of our paper this is inconsequential, since our model puts the exact same restrictions on behavior in both problems. Moreover, the two phenomena are often discussed either interchangeably or jointly to emphasize specific issues; for example, even though the term Certainty Effect was first referred to as a special case of the Common Ratio Effect, in more recent literature it is typically understood as any violation of Expected Utility resulting from experiments that include one lottery that is risk-free. 20

21 involved. Some early evidence initially suggested the latter (e.g., Kahneman and Tversky, 1979 and MacCrimmon and Larsson, 1979; see Machina, 1987 for a survey). 24 A second wave of empirical studies, however, provide evidence that certainty does matter. The results in Cohen and Jaffray (1988), Conlisk (1989), Camerer (1992), Sopher and Gigliotti (1993), Harless and Camerer (1994), and Humphrey (2000), all indicate that Allais-type violations of Expected Utility are much less frequent when the safe option is moved away from certainty and, more generally, when only non-degenerate lotteries over common outcomes are involved. 25 This pattern is documented as one of the key stylized facts of preferences under risk. Some recent evidence even argues that non-expected Utility behavior completely disappears unless certainty is involved (see Andreoni and Harbaugh, 2010, and Andreoni and Sprenger, 2010, 2012). 26 The Cautious Expected Utility model is compatible with more violations of Expected Utility as we approach the boundaries of the Marschak-Machina triangle. Moreover, it implies that Allais-type violations cannot be more prominent when a risk-free prospect is not involved than when it is. This is formalized in the following proposition (the proof is an immediate implication of NCI and is omitted). Proposition 3. Let be a binary relation on that satisfies Weak Order, Continuity, Weak Monotonicity, and Negative Certainty Independence. Fix x 3 > x 2 > x 1, and for α, β, γ [0, 1] consider the lotteries A = δ x2 ; B = αδ x3 + (1 α) δ x1 ; C = βa + (1 β) δ x1 ; D = βb + (1 β) δ x1 ; E = γc + (1 γ) δ x1 ; and F = γd + (1 γ) δ x1. Then C D and E F A B In words, if we observe a Common-Ratio violation for the pairs CD and EF, then we must also observe such violation for AB and EF, when A is a risk-free lottery. Note that without further assumptions, our model does not rule out the opposite of the Common Ratio Effect away from certainty, as long as Continuity is preserved 24 For example, Kahneman and Tversky found that 86 percent of their subjects chose 0.9δ δ 0 over 0.45δ δ 0, while 73 percent chose 0.01δ δ 0 over 0.02δ δ 0. This is an instance of the Common Ratio Effect since the ratio of the probabilities to receive 3000 and 6000 is the same in both problems (equals = ). 25 For example, in Conlisk (1989) the fraction of Expected Utility violations drops from about 50 percent in the basic version that includes one degenerate lottery to about 32 percent in the displaced Allais version, where each of the new prospects puts strictly positive probability on all prizes. 26 On the other hand, some studies found a reverse Certainty Effect, which is clearly incompatible with our model. See Wu et al. (2005) and Blavatskyy (2010). 21

22 (e.g., it permits D C and F E, at least for small enough values of β ). This is also allowed by both RDU and Betweenness; in their most general forms, these models put no restrictions on the behaviors just discussed (for example, they are compatible with fewer violations of Expected Utility away from certainty and with the absence of reverse Common Ratio Effect, but are consistent with the opposite patterns as well). Many studies investigated whether Allais results, and the pattern of indifference curves they suggest, persist when constructed using different kind of mixtures, e.g., when computed in the upper part of the Marschak-Machina triangle as opposed to the lower part (from where most early evidence had come). A robust finding is that indifference curves in the triangle exhibit Mixed Fanning: they become first steeper (Fanning Out) and then flatter (Fanning In) as we move in the north-west direction. In particular, global Fanning Out is inconsistent with the available data. 27 As we noted in Section 5, our model is compatible with Mixed Fanning and rules out global Fanning Out. Betweenness is compatible with both Mixed Fanning and Fanning Out. RDU rules out global Fanning Out (see Röell, 1987). 28 Another robust finding is that Allais-type behavior is significantly less frequent when stakes are small rather than large. 29 Our model is compatible with this evidence: for instance, this would be the case if, as in Example 1, one of the utility functions in W is the most risk averse for a range of outcomes below a threshold. 30 Models based on Betweenness are also consistent with it. However, this is not the case for RDU. As its name suggests, in that model only the ranks of outcomes within the support of a lottery matter for the probability distortion, not their sizes. Thus, the presence of Allais-type behavior should be independent of the stakes. 31 The behavioral patterns we have mentioned so far are documented for lotteries 27 Chew and Waller (1986); Camerer (1989); Conlisk (1989); Battalio et al. (1990); Prelec (1990); Sopher and Gigliotti (1993); Wu (1994). 28 RDU is compatible with many fanning patterns of indifference curves, but is inconsistent with Mixed Fanning in the strict sense (see Wu and Gonzalez, 1998). 29 Conlisk (1989); Camerer (1989); Burke et al. (1996); Fan (2002); Huck and Müller (2012); Agranov and Ortoleva (2014). Some of these studies also found that Expected Utility violations are less prominent in experiments that include real rather than hypothetical payoffs. 30 In Example 1, u 2 has a higher Arrow-Pratt coefficient of (absolute) risk aversion [ than ] u 1 for all outcomes below 1 α β. Therefore, when restricted to lotteries with support in w, 1 α β, preferences are Expected Utility with Bernoulli index u 2, but they violate Expected Utility for larger stakes. 31 RDU implies that if we detect an Allais-type violation of Expected Utility in some range of prizes, e.g., with x 1 < x 2 < x 3, then similar violations of Expected Utility can be produced in any range of prizes. That is, for any y 1 < y 3 there exists y 2 (y 1, y 3 ) and a, b (0, 1) such that δ y2 aδ y3 + (1 a) δ y1 but bδ y2 + (1 b) δ y1 abδ y3 + (1 ab) δ y1. 22

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva February 2014 Abstract Many violations of the Independence axiom of Expected Utility can be

More information

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva May 2013 Abstract One of the most prominently observed behavioral patterns in decision making

More information

Cautious and Globally Ambiguity Averse

Cautious and Globally Ambiguity Averse Ozgur Evren New Economic School August, 2016 Introduction Subject: Segal s (1987) theory of recursive preferences. Ambiguity aversion: Tendency to prefer risk to ambiguity. (Ellsberg paradox) risk objective,

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal January 9, 204 Abstract Machina (2009, 202) lists a number of situations where Choquet expected utility, as well as other known models

More information

An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences

An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences Simone Cerreia-Vioglio a, David Dillenberger b, Pietro Ortoleva c a Università Bocconi and Igier, b University of

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal May 0, 0 Abstract Machina (009, 0) lists a number of situations where standard models of ambiguity aversion are unable to capture

More information

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 56, No., February 05 RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES BY DAVID DILLENBERGER AND UZI SEGAL University of Pennsylvania, U.S.A.; Boston College, U.S.A., and Warwick

More information

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging Mark Dean and Pietro Ortoleva Abstract Two of the most well-known regularities observed in preferences under risk and uncertainty are ambiguity aversion and

More information

Deliberately Stochastic

Deliberately Stochastic Deliberately Stochastic Simone Cerreia-Vioglio, David Dillenberger, Pietro Ortoleva, Gil Riella First version: February 2012 This version: May 5, 2018 Abstract We study stochastic choice as the outcome

More information

Deliberately Stochastic

Deliberately Stochastic Deliberately Stochastic Simone Cerreia-Vioglio, David Dillenberger, Pietro Ortoleva, Gil Riella First version: February 2012 This version: May 5, 2018 Abstract We study stochastic choice as the outcome

More information

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty Yosuke Hashidate Abstract This paper presents a behavioral characteization of a reference-dependent choice under uncertainty in the Anscombe-Aumann

More information

Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation

Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation Yosuke Hashidate Abstract In decision theory, it is not generally postulated that decision makers randomize their choices. In contrast, in real life, even

More information

A New Look at Local Expected Utility

A New Look at Local Expected Utility A New Look at Local Expected Utility S. Cerreia-Vioglio, F. Maccheroni, M. Marinacci Department of Decision Sciences and GER, Università Bocconi February 22, 2014 Abstract We revisit the classical local

More information

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Adam Dominiak 1 and Gerelt Tserenjigmid 2 1,2 Department of Economics, Virginia Tech September 10, 2018 Abstract In this paper, we study choice under growing awareness

More information

Second-Order Expected Utility

Second-Order Expected Utility Second-Order Expected Utility Simon Grant Ben Polak Tomasz Strzalecki Preliminary version: November 2009 Abstract We present two axiomatizations of the Second-Order Expected Utility model in the context

More information

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009 Measurable Ambiguity with Wolfgang Pesendorfer August 2009 A Few Definitions A Lottery is a (cumulative) probability distribution over monetary prizes. It is a probabilistic description of the DMs uncertain

More information

Mathematical Social Sciences

Mathematical Social Sciences Mathematical Social Sciences 74 (2015) 68 72 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Mathematical Social Sciences journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase Continuity, completeness, betweenness

More information

Confidence Models of Incomplete Preferences

Confidence Models of Incomplete Preferences Confidence Models of Incomplete Preferences Morgan McClellon May 26, 2015 Abstract This paper introduces and axiomatizes a new class of representations for incomplete preferences called confidence models.

More information

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger 1 Uzi Segal 2. 1 University of Pennsylvania 2 Boston College and WBS

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger 1 Uzi Segal 2. 1 University of Pennsylvania 2 Boston College and WBS Skewed Noise David Dillenberger 1 Uzi Segal 2 1 University of Pennsylvania 2 Boston College and WBS Introduction Compound lotteries (lotteries over lotteries over outcomes): 1 1 4 3 4 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1

More information

The Rational Core of Preference Relations

The Rational Core of Preference Relations The Rational Core of Preference Relations Simone Cerreia-Vioglio Efe A. Ok July 11, 2018 Abstract We consider revealed preference relations over risky (or uncertain) prospects, and allow them to be nontransitive

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect

More information

Stochastic Utility Theorem

Stochastic Utility Theorem Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich Working Paper Series ISSN 44-0459 Working Paper No. Stochastic Utility Theorem Pavlo R. Blavatskyy Januar 007 Stochastic Utility Theorem

More information

Choice under uncertainty

Choice under uncertainty Choice under uncertainty Expected utility theory The agent chooses among a set of risky alternatives (lotteries) Description of risky alternatives (lotteries) a lottery L = a random variable on a set of

More information

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory Review of Economic Analysis 4 (01) 67-75 1973-3909/01067 Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory TAPAN BISWAS University of Hull 1 Introduction The axiomatic foundation of the expected

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 6: Choice under Uncertainty

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu Econ 701A Fall 2018 University of Pennsylvania Recitation 7: Uncertainty Xincheng Qiu (qiux@sas.upenn.edu 1 Expected Utility Remark 1. Primitives: in the basic consumer theory, a preference relation is

More information

PIER Working Paper

PIER Working Paper Penn Institute for Economic Research Department of Economics University of Pennsylvania 3718 Locust Walk Philadelphia, PA 19104-6297 pier@econ.upenn.edu http://economics.sas.upenn.edu/pier PIER Working

More information

Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders

Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders David McCarthy and Kalle Mikkola Dept. of Philosophy, University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong, Dept. of Mathematics

More information

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1 Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1 Suguru Ito June 5 th, 2015 Abstract In this paper, we study an individual who faces a three-period decision problem when she accepts the partitional

More information

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus. Testing Revealed Preference Theory, I: Methodology The revealed preference theory developed last time applied to a single agent. This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Absolute and relative ambiguity aversion

Absolute and relative ambiguity aversion Absolute and relative ambiguity aversion A preferential approach Simone Cerreia-Vioglio, Fabio Maccheroni, Massimo Marinacci Università Bocconi Oxford September 2018 CMM (Università Bocconi) Absolute and

More information

Multiple Weighted Expected Utility Theory

Multiple Weighted Expected Utility Theory Multiple Weighted Expected Utility Theory by Zhou, Nan A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland

More information

Ambiguity and Nonexpected Utility

Ambiguity and Nonexpected Utility Ambiguity and Nonexpected Utility Edi Karni, Fabio Maccheroni, Massimo Marinacci October 24, 2013 We gratefully thank Pierpaolo Battigalli, Veronica R. Cappelli, Simone Cerreia-Vioglio, and Sujoy Mukerji

More information

Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting

Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting Traeger, CES ifo 10 p. 1 Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting Christian Traeger Department of Agricultural & Resource Economics, UC Berkeley Introduce a more general preference representation

More information

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts Review of Economics & Finance Submitted on 28/Nov./2011 Article ID: 1923-7529-2012-02-65-11 Yutaka Matsushita Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure

More information

arxiv: v1 [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 2015

arxiv: v1 [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 2015 Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large under Rank-Dependent Utility arxiv:52.08037v [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 205 Louis R. Eeckhoudt IESEG School of Management Catholic University of Lille and CORE Louis.Eeckhoudt@fucam.ac.be

More information

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Tsun-Feng Chiang* *School of Economics, Henan University, Kaifeng, China November 2, 2014 1 / 28 Primitive Notions 1.1 Primitive Notions Consumer

More information

Cognitive Anchor in Other-Regarding Preferences: An Axiomatic Approach

Cognitive Anchor in Other-Regarding Preferences: An Axiomatic Approach Cognitive Anchor in Other-Regarding Preferences: An Axiomatic Approach Yosuke Hashidate Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo First Draft: October 30, 2016 This Draft: January 30, 2017

More information

Common ratio using delay

Common ratio using delay Theory Dec. (2010) 68:149 158 DOI 10.1007/s18-008-9130-2 Common ratio using delay Manel Baucells Franz H. Heukamp Published online: 4 January 2009 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC. 2009 Abstract We

More information

Expected Utility Framework

Expected Utility Framework Expected Utility Framework Preferences We want to examine the behavior of an individual, called a player, who must choose from among a set of outcomes. Let X be the (finite) set of outcomes with common

More information

Range-Dependent Utility

Range-Dependent Utility Range-Dependent Utility Micha l Lewandowski joint work with Krzysztof Kontek March 23, 207 Outline. Inspired by Parducci (964) we propose range-dependent utility (RDU) as a general framework for decisions

More information

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger Uzi Segal. November 25, 2013

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger Uzi Segal. November 25, 2013 Skewed Noise David Dillenberger Uzi Segal November 5, 013 Experimental evidence suggests that individuals who face an asymmetric distribution over the likelihood of a specific event might actually prefer

More information

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

Homework #6 (10/18/2017) Homework #6 (0/8/207). Let G be the set of compound gambles over a finite set of deterministic payoffs {a, a 2,...a n } R +. A decision maker s preference relation over compound gambles can be represented

More information

A MODEL OF PROCEDURAL DECISION MAKING IN THE PRESENCE OF RISK 1. INTRODUCTION

A MODEL OF PROCEDURAL DECISION MAKING IN THE PRESENCE OF RISK 1. INTRODUCTION INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 43, No. 4, November 2002 A MODEL OF PROCEDURAL DECISION MAKING IN THE PRESENCE OF RISK BY JUAN DUBRA AND EFE A. OK 1 Department of Economics, New York University, Universidad

More information

Indecisiveness, preference for flexibility, and a unique subjective state space

Indecisiveness, preference for flexibility, and a unique subjective state space Indecisiveness, preference for flexibility, and a unique subjective state space Nobuo Koida This version: April 12, 2018 Abstract The objective of this study is to unify two major approaches for addressing

More information

A Relationship between Risk and Time Preferences

A Relationship between Risk and Time Preferences A Relationship between Risk and Time Preferences Kota SAITO Department of Economics, Northwestern University kotasaito@northwestern.edu June 12, 2009 Abstract This paper investigates a general relationship

More information

Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries

Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries April 2, 2012 Abstract Preferences may arise from regret, i.e., from comparisons with alternatives forgone by the decision maker. We show that

More information

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013 Uncertainty Michael Peters December 27, 20 Lotteries In many problems in economics, people are forced to make decisions without knowing exactly what the consequences will be. For example, when you buy

More information

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences in Expected Utility Alejandro Francetich Department of Decision Sciences and IGIER Bocconi University, Italy March 7, 204 Abstract Many choice-theoretic

More information

We consider choice over uncertain, monetary payoffs and study a general class of preferences. These preferences

We consider choice over uncertain, monetary payoffs and study a general class of preferences. These preferences Published online ahead of print June 15, 212 MANAGEMENT SCIENCE Articles in Advance, pp. 1 19 ISSN 25-199 (print) ISSN 1526-551 (online) http://dx.doi.org/1.1287/mnsc.112.1537 212 INFORMS Aspirational

More information

Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn

Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn Econ Theory (2011) 48:425 436 DOI 10.1007/s00199-011-0652-4 SYMPOSIUM Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn Mark J. Machina Received: 5 April 2011 / Accepted: 9 June 2011 / Published online: 16 July 2011

More information

WORKING PAPER SERIES

WORKING PAPER SERIES INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR ECONOMIC RESEARCH WORKING PAPER SERIES Paolo Ghirardato and Massimo Marinacci RISK, AMBIGUITY, AND THE SEPARATION OF UTILITY AND BELIEFS Working Paper no. 21/2001 September 2001

More information

Status Quo Bias, Multiple Priors and Uncertainty Aversion

Status Quo Bias, Multiple Priors and Uncertainty Aversion MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Status Quo Bias, Multiple Priors and Uncertainty Aversion Pietro Ortoleva New York University September 2008 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/12243/ MPRA Paper

More information

Bayesian Updating for General Maxmin Expected Utility Preferences

Bayesian Updating for General Maxmin Expected Utility Preferences Bayesian Updating for General Maxmin xpected Utility Preferences Marciano Siniscalchi September 14, 2001 First draft Comments welcome! Abstract A characterization of generalized Bayesian updating in a

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences

Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences Yosuke Hashidate Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo First Draft: January 2015 This Draft: February

More information

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World heoretical Economics Letters, 013, 3, 17-1 http://dxdoiorg/10436/tel01335a004 Published Online September 013 (http://wwwscirporg/journal/tel) Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States

More information

OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM WITH EXPECTED UTILITY

OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM WITH EXPECTED UTILITY OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM WITH EXPECTED UTILITY David Dillenberger University of Pennsylvania Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania Kareen Rozen Brown University Abstract Maximizing subjective expected

More information

CER-ETH Center of Economic Research at ETH Zurich

CER-ETH Center of Economic Research at ETH Zurich CER-ETH Center of Economic Research at ETH Zurich A Dual Approach to Ambiguity Aversion A. Bommier Working Paper 14/207 December 2014 Economics Working Paper Series A Dual Approach to Ambiguity Aversion

More information

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank No. 1611 March 2010 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working Paper No. 1611

More information

Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes

Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes Efe A. Ok Pietro Ortoleva Gil Riella April 7, 2011 Abstract We investigate the classical Anscombe-Aumann model of decision-making

More information

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Alexander Zimper Working Paper Number 97 Department of Economics and Econometrics, University of Johannesburg Revisiting independence

More information

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities William S. Neilson Department of Economics University of Tennessee Knoxville, TN 37996-0550 wneilson@utk.edu April 1993 Abstract

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

Transitive Regret. Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal. October 24, Abstract

Transitive Regret. Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal. October 24, Abstract Transitive Regret Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal October 24, 2009 Abstract Preferences may arise from regret, i.e., from comparisons with alternatives forgone by the decision maker. We ask whether regret-based

More information

Asymmetric gain loss reference dependence and attitudes toward uncertainty

Asymmetric gain loss reference dependence and attitudes toward uncertainty Economic Theory https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-018-1138-4 RESEARCH ARTICLE Asymmetric gain loss reference dependence and attitudes toward uncertainty Juan Sebastián Lleras 1 Evan Piermont 2 Richard Svoboda

More information

A powerful Tool for Analyzing Concave/Convex Utility and Weighting Functions

A powerful Tool for Analyzing Concave/Convex Utility and Weighting Functions A powerful Tool for Analyzing Concave/Convex Utility and Weighting Functions Jingni Yang & Peter P. Wakker* Erasmus School of Economics, Erasmus University Rotterdam, Rotterdam, the Netherlands; * corresponding

More information

A note on comparative ambiguity aversion and justi ability

A note on comparative ambiguity aversion and justi ability A note on comparative ambiguity aversion and justi ability P. Battigalli, S. Cerreia-Vioglio, F. Maccheroni, M. Marinacci Department of Decision Sciences and IGIER Università Bocconi Draft of April 2016

More information

Partial Ambiguity. CHEW Soo Hong, MIAO Bin, and ZHONG Songfa. November 2016

Partial Ambiguity. CHEW Soo Hong, MIAO Bin, and ZHONG Songfa. November 2016 Partial Ambiguity CHEW Soo Hong, MIAO Bin, and ZHONG Songfa November 2016 Abstract We extend Ellsberg s two-urn paradox and propose three symmetric forms of partial ambiguity by limiting the possible compositions

More information

Northwestern University

Northwestern University Northwestern University 00 Sheridan Road 580 Leverone Hall Evanston, IL 6008-04 USA Discussion Paper #54 April 0, 0 Preference for Randomization and Ambiguity Aversion Key words: Ambiguity; randomization,

More information

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY August 18, 2003 Aanund Hylland: # DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY Standard theory and alternatives 1. Introduction Individual decision making under uncertainty can be characterized as follows: The decision

More information

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture I Choice under risk. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture I Choice under risk. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011 Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa Lecture I Choice under risk The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011 Preferences Let X be some set of alternatives (consumption set). Formally,

More information

Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective. Probabilities

Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective. Probabilities Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective Probabilities Edi Karni Johns Hopkins University September 7, 2005 Abstract This paper presents two axiomatic models of decision making under uncertainty

More information

Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals

Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals Zvi Safra and Uzi Segal May 18, 2008 Abstract A reasonable level of risk aversion with respect to small gambles leads to a high, and absurd, level of risk

More information

Quantum Decision Theory

Quantum Decision Theory Quantum Decision Theory V.I. Yukalov and D. Sornette Department of Management, Technology and Economics\ ETH Zürich Plan 1. Classical Decision Theory 1.1. Notations and definitions 1.2. Typical paradoxes

More information

Choice Theory when Agents can Randomize

Choice Theory when Agents can Randomize Choice Theory when Agents can Randomize Jörg Stoye Cornell University August 25, 2013 Abstract This paper takes choice theory to risk or uncertainty. Well-known decision models are axiomatized under the

More information

Parametric weighting functions

Parametric weighting functions Journal of Economic Theory 144 (2009) 1102 1118 www.elsevier.com/locate/jet Parametric weighting functions Enrico Diecidue a, Ulrich Schmidt b,c, Horst Zank d, a Decision Sciences Area, INSEAD, Fontainebleau,

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

Endogenous Status Quo

Endogenous Status Quo ISSN 2279-9362 Endogenous Status Quo Daniele Pennesi No. 314 December 2013 www.carloalberto.org/research/working-papers 2013 by Daniele Pennesi. Any opinions expressed here are those of the authors and

More information

Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility. Pavlo R. Blavatskyy

Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility. Pavlo R. Blavatskyy Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility Pavlo R. Blavatskyy Institute of Public Finance University of Innsbruck Universitaetsstrasse 15 A-6020 Innsbruck Austria Phone: +43 (0) 512 507 71 56 Fax: +43

More information

SUBJECTIVE INDEPENDENCE AND CONCAVE EXPECTED UTILITY. February 12, 2014

SUBJECTIVE INDEPENDENCE AND CONCAVE EXPECTED UTILITY. February 12, 2014 SUBJECTIVE INDEPENDENCE AND CONCAVE EXPECTED UTILITY EHUD LEHRER AND ROEE TEPER February 12, 2014 Abstract. When a potential hedge between alternatives does not reduce the exposure to uncertainty, we say

More information

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences Conditional and Dynamic Preferences How can we Understand Risk in a Dynamic Setting? Samuel Drapeau Joint work with Hans Föllmer Humboldt University Berlin Jena - March 17th 2009 Samuel Drapeau Joint work

More information

Explaining the harmonic sequence paradox. by Ulrich Schmidt, and Alexander Zimper

Explaining the harmonic sequence paradox. by Ulrich Schmidt, and Alexander Zimper Explaining the harmonic sequence paradox by Ulrich Schmidt, and Alexander Zimper No. 1724 August 2011 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working Paper No.

More information

UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of Psychology and Economics (219A) Module I: Choice under Uncertainty

UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of Psychology and Economics (219A) Module I: Choice under Uncertainty UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of Psychology and Economics (219A) Module I: Choice under Uncertainty Reading list 1. Camerer, C. (1995) Individual Decision Making, in Handbook of Experimental

More information

Modelling Choice and Valuation in Decision Experiments. Graham Loomes, University of East Anglia, UK. May 2008.

Modelling Choice and Valuation in Decision Experiments. Graham Loomes, University of East Anglia, UK.  May 2008. Modelling Choice and Valuation in Decision Experiments Graham Loomes, University of East Anglia, UK. E-mail g.loomes@uea.ac.uk May 2008 Abstract This paper develops a parsimonious descriptive model of

More information

Journal of Mathematical Economics

Journal of Mathematical Economics Journal of Mathematical Economics 63 (2016) 164 173 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Mathematical Economics journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jmateco A theory of stochastic

More information

Persuading a Pessimist

Persuading a Pessimist Persuading a Pessimist Afshin Nikzad PRELIMINARY DRAFT Abstract While in practice most persuasion mechanisms have a simple structure, optimal signals in the Bayesian persuasion framework may not be so.

More information

Modelling Choice and Valuation in Decision Experiments. Graham Loomes, University of Warwick, UK.

Modelling Choice and Valuation in Decision Experiments. Graham Loomes, University of Warwick, UK. Modelling Choice and Valuation in Decision Experiments Graham Loomes, University of Warwick, UK. E-mail g.loomes@warwick.ac.uk December 2009 Abstract This paper develops a parsimonious descriptive model

More information

Anchored Preference Relations

Anchored Preference Relations Anchored Preference Relations Jacob S. Sagi October 2002 Abstract This paper axiomatically explores minimal conditions under which reference dependent preferences over risky prospects are normatively admissible.

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

When does aggregation reduce risk aversion?

When does aggregation reduce risk aversion? When does aggregation reduce risk aversion? Christopher P. Chambers and Federico Echenique April 22, 2009 Abstract We study the problem of risk sharing within a household facing subjective uncertainty.

More information

Numerical representation of convex preferences over Anscombe Aumann acts

Numerical representation of convex preferences over Anscombe Aumann acts Numerical representation of convex preferences over Anscombe Aumann acts Patrick Cheridito, Freddy Delbaen, Samuel Drapeau, Michael Kupper January 2015 Abstract In this paper we derive a numerical representation

More information

A Behavioral Characterization of Plausible Priors

A Behavioral Characterization of Plausible Priors A Behavioral Characterization of Plausible Priors Marciano Siniscalchi Economics Department, Northwestern University, and Economics Department, Princeton University. May 2003 Abstract Recent theories of

More information

What Are Asset Demand Tests of Expected Utility Really Testing?

What Are Asset Demand Tests of Expected Utility Really Testing? What Are Asset Demand Tests of Expected Utility Really Testing? Felix Kubler, Larry Selden and Xiao Wei August 25, 2016 Abstract Assuming the classic contingent claim setting, a number of nancial asset

More information

Comments on prospect theory

Comments on prospect theory Comments on prospect theory Abstract Ioanid Roşu This note presents a critique of prospect theory, and develops a model for comparison of two simple lotteries, i.e. of the form ( x 1, p1; x 2, p 2 ;...;

More information

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Journal of Economic Theory 105, 531539 (2002) doi:10.1006jeth.2001.2824 Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Emre Ozdenoren Department of Economics, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan

More information

Decision-Making under Subjective Risk: Toward a General Theory of Pessimism

Decision-Making under Subjective Risk: Toward a General Theory of Pessimism Decision-Making under Subjective Risk: Toward a General Theory of Pessimism Anna Gumen y Efe A. Ok z Andrei Savochkin x November 4, 2013 Abstract The primary objective of this paper is to develop a framework

More information