Question 1 Affiliated Private Values

Similar documents
Thus far, we ve made four key assumptions that have greatly simplified our analysis:

Robert Wilson (1977), A Bidding Model of Perfect Competition, Review of Economic

Weak bidders prefer first-price (sealed-bid) auctions. (This holds both ex-ante, and once the bidders have learned their types)

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

A Simple Example to Illustrate the Linkage Principle

Online Appendix for "Auctions in Markets: Common Outside Options and the Continuation Value Effect" Not intended for publication

Monotonicity in Asymmetric First-Price Auctions with Affiliation

The Revenue Equivalence Theorem 1

Lecture 6 Games with Incomplete Information. November 14, 2008

An auction with finite types

First price auctions with general information structures: Implications for bidding and revenue

Auctions. data better than the typical data set in industrial organization. auction game is relatively simple, well-specified rules.

Notes on Auctionsy. ECON 201B - Game Theory. Guillermo Ordoñez UCLA. February 15, 2007

Non-Existence of Equilibrium in Vickrey, Second-Price, and English Auctions

2. If the values for f(x) can be made as close as we like to L by choosing arbitrarily large. lim

Integer-Valued Polynomials

This work is distributed as a Discussion Paper by the STANFORD INSTITUTE FOR ECONOMIC POLICY RESEARCH

MIT Sloan School of Management

1 Functions, Graphs and Limits

First-Price Auctions with General Information Structures: Implications for Bidding and Revenue

Econ Slides from Lecture 10

Lecture 10: Mechanism Design

Uniqueness and Existence of Equilibrium in Auctions with a Reserve Price

Lecture 9 - Increasing and Decreasing Functions, Extrema, and the First Derivative Test

Symmetric Separating Equilibria in English Auctions 1

A Review of Auction Theory: Sequential Auctions and Vickrey Auctions

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours.

Working Paper EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN COMMON-VALUE SECOND-PRICE AUCTIONS. Heng Liu

Math Lecture 23 Notes

Mechanism Design: Bayesian Incentive Compatibility

CS364B: Frontiers in Mechanism Design Lecture #2: Unit-Demand Bidders and Walrasian Equilibria

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design

Differentiation. Table of contents Definition Arithmetics Composite and inverse functions... 5

REPUTATION IN REPEATED SECOND-PRICE AUCTIONS. Sushil Bikhchandani. Abstract

Advanced Microeconomics II

Working Paper EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN COMMON-VALUE SECOND-PRICE AUCTIONS. Heng Liu

Algorithmic Mechanism Design

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

An Invitation to Mathematics Prof. Sankaran Vishwanath Institute of Mathematical Science, Chennai. Unit - I Polynomials Lecture 1B Long Division

Chapter 7 Rational Expressions, Equations, and Functions

North Carolina State University

Solution: Since the prices are decreasing, we consider all the nested options {1,..., i}. Given such a set, the expected revenue is.

Lecture 4. 1 Examples of Mechanism Design Problems

Definition: For nonempty sets X and Y, a function, f, from X to Y is a relation that associates with each element of X exactly one element of Y.

Second Price Auctions with Differentiated Participation Costs

Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

On Random Sampling Auctions for Digital Goods

MATH 408N PRACTICE MIDTERM 1

Lecture Notes on Monotone Comparative Statics and Producer Theory

Examples 2: Composite Functions, Piecewise Functions, Partial Fractions

Systems of Equations. Red Company. Blue Company. cost. 30 minutes. Copyright 2003 Hanlonmath 1

Math 115 Second Midterm March 25, 2010

CPS 173 Mechanism design. Vincent Conitzer

Characterization of equilibrium in pay-as-bid auctions for multiple units

Partial Fractions. June 27, In this section, we will learn to integrate another class of functions: the rational functions.

Math 320-2: Final Exam Practice Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 2015

A. Incorrect! Perform inverse operations to find the solution. B. Correct! Add 1 to both sides of the equation then divide by 2 to get x = 5.

Second-Price Auctions with Different Participation Costs

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

Lecture Note II-3 Static Games of Incomplete Information. Games of incomplete information. Cournot Competition under Asymmetric Information (cont )

Mechanism Design with Correlated Types

CHAPTER 11. SEQUENCES AND SERIES 114. a 2 = 2 p 3 a 3 = 3 p 4 a 4 = 4 p 5 a 5 = 5 p 6. n +1. 2n p 2n +1

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Redistribution Mechanisms for Assignment of Heterogeneous Objects

Information Aggregation in Auctions with an Unknown Number of Bidders

CS 598RM: Algorithmic Game Theory, Spring Practice Exam Solutions

Contents CONTENTS 1. 1 Straight Lines and Linear Equations 1. 2 Systems of Equations 6. 3 Applications to Business Analysis 11.

Homework 6. (x 3) 2 + (y 1) 2 = 25. (x 5) 2 + (y + 2) 2 = 49

Solutions. F x = 2x 3λ = 0 F y = 2y 5λ = 0. λ = 2x 3 = 2y 5 = x = 3y 5. 2y 1/3 z 1/6 x 1/2 = 5x1/2 z 1/6. 3y 2/3 = 10x1/2 y 1/3

Interdependent Value Auctions with an Insider Bidder 1

Chapters 4/5 Class Notes. Intermediate Algebra, MAT1033C. SI Leader Joe Brownlee. Palm Beach State College

Lecture 10: Profit Maximization

means is a subset of. So we say A B for sets A and B if x A we have x B holds. BY CONTRAST, a S means that a is a member of S.

6.1 Polynomial Functions

Linear Algebra, Summer 2011, pt. 2

Math 1320, Section 10 Quiz IV Solutions 20 Points

Math Lecture 4 Limit Laws

Looking smart versus playing dumb in common-value auctions

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

FIRST PRICE AUCTIONS WITH GENERAL INFORMATION STRUCTURES: IMPLICATIONS FOR BIDDING AND REVENUE. Dirk Bergemann, Benjamin Brooks, and Stephen Morris

Algebra 2 CP Semester 1 PRACTICE Exam January 2015

Calculus with Analytic Geometry I Exam 8 Take Home Part.

CS 573: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture date: April 11, 2008

Position Auctions with Interdependent Values

Math 131, Lecture 20: The Chain Rule, continued

Solutions to Math 41 Second Exam November 5, 2013

Math 115 Spring 11 Written Homework 10 Solutions

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions

Some Lecture Notes on Auctions

Expansion of Terms. f (x) = x 2 6x + 9 = (x 3) 2 = 0. x 3 = 0

Sealed-bid first-price auctions with an unknown number of bidders

Two hours UNIVERSITY OF MANCHESTER SCHOOL OF COMPUTER SCIENCE. Date: Thursday 17th May 2018 Time: 09:45-11:45. Please answer all Questions.

CS364B: Frontiers in Mechanism Design Lecture #3: The Crawford-Knoer Auction

Game Theory: Spring 2017

Revenue Guarantee Equivalence

= $ m. Telephone Company B charges $11.50 per month plus five cents per minute. Writing that mathematically, we have c B. = $

Advanced Economic Theory Lecture 9. Bilateral Asymmetric Information. Double Auction (Chatterjee and Samuelson, 1983).

Introduction to linear programming using LEGO.

Chapter 2. Equilibrium. 2.1 Complete Information Games

Transcription:

Econ 85 Fall 7 Problem Set Solutions Professor: Dan Quint Question Affiliated Private alues a - proving the ranking lemma Suppose g(y) < h(y) for some y > x. Let z = max {x : x < y, g(x) h(x)} (Since g and h are continuous, the set of points where g(x) h(x) is closed. Since it excludes y, the intersection of it with [x, y) is still closed. Since the set includes x, it is nonempty, and therefore the maximum exists.) By continuity, g(z) = h(z), and by definition, g(x) < h(x) for all x (z, y]. But then by assumption, g (x) h (x) for all x [z, y], so g(y) g(z) h(y) h(z), or g(y) h(y), a contradiction. b - value function in the first-price auction If bidder j bids according to β F, and bidder i, given type t i, bids β F (t), he wins whenever β F (t) > β F (t j ), which is when t j < t, which occurs with probability F j (t t i ). The object is worth t i to him, and he pays β F (t) when he wins. (If I hadn t told you to assume β F was an equilibrium, you d still have to check separately for deviations outside the range of β F, but by the usual arguments, they wouldn t be profitable.) By the envelope theorem, then, ( ) F P [ i = Fj (t t i ) ( t i β F (t) )] t i since β F (t i ) is i s equilibrium strategy at t i. Calculating the partial derivative gives t=ti [ Fj (t t i ) ( t i β F (t) )] = F j (t t i ) + Fj (t t i ) ( t i β F (t) ) t i where Fj is the partial derivative of F j with respect to its second argument; plugging in t = t i gives ( ) F P i = Fj (t i t i ) + Fj (t i t i ) ( t i β F (t i ) ) c - bid function in the second-price auction In the second-price auction, if I bid t, I win when b j (t j ) < t, in which case I pay b j (t j ). In the dominant-strategy equilibrium, b j (t j ) = t j ; and since types are correlated, its distribution is conditioned on my true type. So if I have a true type s, bid t, and win, my expected payment is E (t j t i = s, t j < t)

d - value function in the second-price auction In the second price auction, if I have a true type t i and bid t, I win whenever t j < t, which happens with probability F j (t t i ). When I win, the object is worth t i to me, and by part c above, I pay on average β S (t i, t). My value function is then the solution to the maximization problem over my possible bids. [ Fj (t t i ) ( t i β S (t i, t) )] = F j (t t i ) F j (t t i )β S (t i, t) + Fj (t t i ) ( t i β S (t i, t) ) t i where β S is the partial of βs with respect to its first argument; plugging in t = t i, the envelope theorem gives us ( ) SP i (ti ) = F j (t i t i ) F j (t i t i )β S (t i, t i ) + Fj (t i t i ) ( t i β S (t i, t i ) ) e - β S increasing in t i This is really the crux of the proof. One of the affiliation results we mentioned in class (without proof) was that if (x,..., x n ) are affiliated random variables and g is any increasing function, E (g(x,..., x n ) x [a, b ], x [a, b ],..., x n [a n, b n ]) is increasing in a, b,..., a n, b n. (This is Theorem 5 in Milgrom and Weber (98); it s proved in the appendix, but using some abstract terms and lattice theory.) Direct application of that result would imply that E (t j t j [, t], t i [s, s]) is increasing in s, since g(t i, t j ) = t j is nondecreasing. To see a clean proof for this case, though, rewrite this expectation as β S (s, t) = wf j(w s)dw F j (t s) Integrating the numerator by parts, with u = w and dv = f j (w s)dw, we find that so wf j (w s)dw = wf j (w s) w=t w= F j (w s)dw = tf j (t s) β S F j (w s) (s, t) = t F j (t s) dw F j (w s)dw Recall one of our earlier affiliation lemmas (one that we did prove in class see the notes from lecture ): if x and x are affiliated, then F (x x ) is log-supermodular. This means that for x > x and x > x, F (x x )F (x x ) F (x x )F (x x )

or F (x x ) F (x x ) F (x x ) F (x x ) that is, for x > x, F (x x ) F (x x ) is decreasing in x. Since t j and t i are affiliated and w t everywhere within the integral, F j(w s) F j (t s) decreasing in s; so is increasing in s as claimed. is decreasing in t i, so its integral, β S F j (w s) (s, t) = t F j (t s) dw F j (w s) F j (t s) dw, is f - value functions and bids Knowing that t = t i solves the maximization problem posed in both value functions, and and so SP i F P i (t i ) = F j (t i t i ) ( t i β F (t i ) ) SP i (t i ) = F j (t i t i ) ( t i β S (t i, t i ) ) (t i ) i F P (t i ) if and only if β S (t i, t i ) β F (t i ) as claimed. g - applying the ranking lemma By symmetry, the lowest types never win, so i SP () = = i F P (). To apply the ranking lemma, we need to show that for t i, i F P (t i ) SP From parts b and d above, ( F P i i (t i ) ( i F P ) (ti ) ( i SP ) (ti ) ) (ti ) ( i SP ) (ti ) = F j (t i t i ) + Fj (t i t i ) ( t i β F (t i ) ) F j (t i t i ) + F j (t i t i )β S(t i, t i ) Fj (t i t i ) ( t i β S (t i, t i ) ) = F j (t i t i )β S (t i, t i ) + F j (t i t i ) ( β S (t i, t i ) β F (t i ) ) We showed in part e that β S is positive, so the first term is always positive. F j is negative, since one of our lemmas in class was that under affiliation, F (x x ) is decreasing in x (the distribution of x increases in a first-order stochastic dominance sense when x rises, so F (x ) decreases). We showed in part f that i F P (t i ) i SP (t i ) implies β F (t i ) β S (t i, t i ), and so both pieces of the second term are negative; so the whole expression is positive. 3

h - revenue dominance By part f, knowing i F P (t i ) i SP (t i ) everywhere implies that β F (t i ) β S (t i, t i ) everywhere. Since both auctions are efficient, the winner is the same in either auction at any signal pair, and pays weakly more in expectation in the second-price auction, so the second-price auction earns weakly higher expected revenue. Question Extra Credit I wasn t kidding when I said I didn t know the answer. When t i and t j are affiliated, the expression for ( i F P ) (ti ) ( i SP ) (ti ) is the same as before, but now β S is negative and Fj is positive. But that means that ( β S (t i, t i ) β F (t i ) ) is related in the wrong direction to ( i F P ) (ti ) ( i SP ) (ti ), so we can t apply the ranking lemma. I m curious to see what you guys come up with. 4

Question 3 Common alues and Information Aggregation 3a Conditional on =, the joint density of (X i, Y ) at (x, x) is 3b Conditional on =, the joint density is 3c ( ) ( ) ( + x (n ) + x x + ) n ( ) ( ) ( 3 3 3 x (n ) x x ) n Note that E( whatever) = Pr( = whatever). Using Bayes Law, letting Z denote the event that X i = Y = x, and abusing notation a little bit by allowing Pr(Z) to refer to the probability density at that event. Pr( = Z) = Pr( =, Z) Pr(Z) = Pr( = ) Pr(Z = ) Pr( = ) Pr(Z = ) + Pr( = ) Pr(Z = ) Since Pr( = ) = Pr( = ) =, this is exactly 3d A A + B = A A + B b i (x) = E( X i = Y = x) is exactly the usual equilibrium we ve been looking at in common-value second-price auctions. (Even if you learned Y and b j (Y ), you don t expect to gain by changing your bid.) The simplest way to disprove information aggregation is to show that when =, the winning bid is bounded above by b i (), which is bounded away from. To see this, note that at x =, and and so A = (n ) B = (n ) b i () = ( ) 3 ( ) A A + B = 9 and does not change as n. So even as n grows arbitrarily large, b i () =.9, and so the winning bid cannot converge to in probability when =. 5

3e To agree with the notation in Pesendorfer and Swinkels, we ll first do this for n bidders and k objects, then plug in n = r + and k = r +. 3f When =, the joint density of (X i, Y k ) at (x, x) is E = ( ) ( ) ( + x (n ) + x n k = (r + ) ( r r ) ( x ) k ( x + ) n k ) ( ) ( + x x ) r ( x + ) r x Similarly, when =, the joint density of (X i, Y k ) at (x, x) is 3g F = ( ) ( ) ( 3 3 x (n ) x n k = (r + ) ( r By the same Bayes -Law logic as before, r ) ( 3 x + ) k ( 3 x ) n k ) (3 ) ( x 3 x + ) r ( 3 x ) r x E( X i = Y k = x) = E E + F Note the (r + ) r C r appears in both E and F, and therefore drops out of both the numerator and denominator. Similarly, to get rid of all the one-halfs everywhere, multiply numerator and denominator by r. This leaves us with b r i (x) = ( + x) [( x x ) ( x + x )] r ( + x) [( x x ) (x + x )] r + ( 3 x) [( 3x + x ) (3x x )] r 3h We can rewrite the last expression as b r i (x) = + Q(r, x) where Q(r, x) = ( 3 x ) [( 3x + x )(3x x ] r ) + x ( x x )(x + x ) = ( 3 x ) [( ] x)( x)(3 x)x r + x = ( + x)( x)( + x)x 6 ( 3 x + x ) [( ] x)(3 x) r ( + x)( + x)

( ) Note that the first term in this expression, 3/ x, /+x is bounded below by 9 by 9; specifically, it never approaches either or. If ( x)(3 x) > ( + x)( + x) and above then the term in square brackets is greater than, and so Q(r, x) grows unboundedly as r, and so b i (r). Conversely, if ( x)(3 x) < ( + x)( + x) then the fraction in square brackets is less than, so Q(r, x) goes to as r, and so b i (r). Let s look at the latter case. Note that ( x)(3 x) < ( + x)( + x) 6 5x + x < + 3x + x 4 8x < < x So for x >, Q and so br i (x) as r. On the other hand, for x <, Q and b r i (x). Now, consider what happens when r. When =, the distribution of the r + nd -highest type (the one whose bid sets the price) becomes a very narrow distribution around the median of the conditional distribution f(x = ), which is around.68; so the probability that it lies within, say, the interval [.55,.65] goes to. But since b r i (x) is increasing in x and b r i (.55), when =, the price converges in probability to. By the same argument, when =, the r + nd -highest type converges in probability to the median of f(x = ), which is around.38; since b r i goes to around there, the price converges in probability to when =. So information aggregates. 7