Multivariate comonotonicity, stochastic orders and risk measures

Similar documents
On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures

ECOLE POLYTECHNIQUE DUAL THEORY OF CHOICE WITH MULTIVARIATE RISKS. Alfred GALICHON Marc HENRY. Cahier n December 2010

ECOLE POLYTECHNIQUE COMONOTONIC MEASURES OF MULTIVARIATE RISKS. Ivar EKELAND Alfred GALICHON Marc HENRY CENTRE NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE

Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market

ECOLE POLYTECHNIQUE PARETO EFFICIENCY FOR THE CONCAVE ORDER AND MULTIVARIATE COMONOTONICITY G. CARLIER R.-A. DANA A. GALICHON.

Decomposability and time consistency of risk averse multistage programs

Multidimensional inequalities and generalized quantile functions

An axiomatic characterization of capital allocations of coherent risk measures

On Kusuoka representation of law invariant risk measures

Pareto Optimal Allocations for Law Invariant Robust Utilities

Risk Aggregation with Dependence Uncertainty

Coherent Risk Measures. Acceptance Sets. L = {X G : X(ω) < 0, ω Ω}.

Regularly Varying Asymptotics for Tail Risk

VaR vs. Expected Shortfall

Risk Aggregation with Dependence Uncertainty

Inverse Stochastic Dominance Constraints Duality and Methods

Generalized quantiles as risk measures

Aggregate Risk. MFM Practitioner Module: Quantitative Risk Management. John Dodson. February 6, Aggregate Risk. John Dodson.

Comonotonicity and Maximal Stop-Loss Premiums

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games

Abstract Various notions of risk aversion can be distinguished for the class of rank-dependent expected utility (RDEU) preferences.

Multivariate Stress Testing for Solvency

On optimal allocation of risk vectors

The newsvendor problem with convex risk

A Note on Robust Representations of Law-Invariant Quasiconvex Functions

The Canonical Model Space for Law-invariant Convex Risk Measures is L 1

Portfolio optimization with stochastic dominance constraints

Asymptotic Bounds for the Distribution of the Sum of Dependent Random Variables

A Theory for Measures of Tail Risk

Sharp bounds on the VaR for sums of dependent risks

Expected Shortfall is not elicitable so what?

Expected Shortfall is not elicitable so what?

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search

Péter Csóka, P. Jean-Jacques Herings, László Á. Kóczy. Coherent Measures of Risk from a General Equilibrium Perspective RM/06/016

Distortion Risk Measures: Coherence and Stochastic Dominance

Mean-Variance Utility

Stochastic Optimization with Risk Measures

Multivariate Measures of Positive Dependence

On a Class of Multidimensional Optimal Transportation Problems

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Generalized quantiles as risk measures

Risk Measures on P(R) and Value At Risk with Probability/Loss function

Bregman superquantiles. Estimation methods and applications

Arrow-Debreu Equilibria for Rank-Dependent Utilities with Heterogeneous Probability Weighting

Remarks on quantiles and distortion risk measures

Rapporto n Risk Measures on P(R) and Value At Risk with Probability/Loss function. Marco Fritelli, Marco Maggis, Ilaria Peri.

The distribution of a sum of dependent risks: a geometric-combinatorial approach

Efficient portfolios in financial markets with proportional transaction costs

Risk Aggregation and Model Uncertainty

Risk Aversion and Coherent Risk Measures: a Spectral Representation Theorem

Time Consistent Decisions and Temporal Decomposition of Coherent Risk Functionals

Representation theorem for AVaR under a submodular capacity

On convex risk measures on L p -spaces

In the Ramsey model we maximized the utility U = u[c(t)]e nt e t dt. Now

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

Aggregation-Robustness and Model Uncertainty of Regulatory Risk Measures

CVaR and Examples of Deviation Risk Measures

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information

Notes on Recursive Utility. Consider the setting of consumption in infinite time under uncertainty as in

Multivariate comonotonicity

Spectral Measures of Uncertain Risk

Stochastic dominance with respect to a capacity and risk measures

EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS UNDER LAW-INVARIANCE: A UNIFYING APPROACH. Department of Mathematics, University of Munich, Germany

Dual utilities under dependence uncertainty

Four notions of mean preserving increase in risk, risk attitudes and applications to the Rank-Dependent Expected Utility model

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design

On Quasi-convex Risk Measures

Stochastic orders: a brief introduction and Bruno s contributions. Franco Pellerey

Characterization of Upper Comonotonicity via Tail Convex Order

Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets

Sum of Two Standard Uniform Random Variables

Optimal Risk Sharing with Optimistic and Pessimistic Decision Makers

Modeling of Dependence Structures in Risk Management and Solvency

Choice under Uncertainty

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

Lecture Quantitative Finance Spring Term 2015

Multivariate Stress Scenarios and Solvency

VaR bounds in models with partial dependence information on subgroups

OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM IN GAMES

Reward-Risk Portfolio Selection and Stochastic Dominance

A Note on the Swiss Solvency Test Risk Measure

Anti-comonotone random variables and Anti-monotone risk aversion

Extreme Negative Dependence and Risk Aggregation

RISK AND RELIABILITY IN OPTIMIZATION UNDER UNCERTAINTY

3 Integration and Expectation

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

INTENSITY OF THE SENSE OF FAIRNESS: MEASUREMENT AND BEHAVIORAL CHARACTERIZATION. October 2000

Risk Measures in non-dominated Models

The Value of Information Under Unawareness

COHERENT APPROACHES TO RISK IN OPTIMIZATION UNDER UNCERTAINTY

JOINT PROBABILITY DISTRIBUTIONS

Theoretical Foundation of Uncertain Dominance

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 9 Jan 2016

Dual representations of risk measures

Monetary Risk Measures and Generalized Prices Relevant to Set-Valued Risk Measures

Fundamentals in Optimal Investments. Lecture I

Modern Portfolio Theory with Homogeneous Risk Measures

Introduction to Empirical Processes and Semiparametric Inference Lecture 22: Preliminaries for Semiparametric Inference

Transcription:

Multivariate comonotonicity, stochastic orders and risk measures Alfred Galichon (Ecole polytechnique) Brussels, May 25, 2012 Based on collaborations with: A. Charpentier (Rennes) G. Carlier (Dauphine) R.-A. Dana (Dauphine) I. Ekeland (Dauphine) M. Henry (Montréal)

This talk will draw on four papers: [CDG]. Pareto e ciency for the concave order and multivariate comonotonicity. Guillaume Carlier, Alfred Galichon and Rose-Anne Dana. Journal of Economic Theory, 2012. [CGH] "Local Utility and Multivariate Risk Aversion. Arthur Charpentier, Alfred Galichon and Marc Henry. Mimeo. [GH] Dual Theory of Choice under Multivariate Risks. Alfred Galichon and Marc Henry. Journal of Economic Theory, forthcoming. [EGH] Comonotonic measures of multivariate risks. Ivar Ekeland, Alfred Galichon and Marc Henry. Mathematical Finance, 2011.

Introduction Comonotonicity is a central tool in decision theory, insurance and nance. Two random variables are «comonotone» when they are maximally correlated, i.e. when there is a nondecreasing map from one to another. Applications include risk measures, e cient risk-sharing, optimal insurance contracts, etc. Unfortunately, no straightforward extension to the multivariate case (i.e. when there are several numeraires). The goal of this presentation is to investigate what happens in the multivariate case, when there are several dimension of risk. Applications will be given to: Risk measures, and their aggregation E cient risk-sharing Stochastic ordering.

1 Comonotonicity and its generalization 1.1 One-dimensional case Two random variables X and Y are comonotone if there exists a r.v. Z and nondecreasing maps T X and T Y such that X = T X (Z) and Y = T Y (Z) : For example, if X and Y are sampled from empirical distributions, X (! i ) = x i and Y (! i ) = y i, i = 1; :::; n where x 1 ::: x n and y 1 ::: y n then X and Y are comonotonic.

By the rearrangement inequality (Hardy-Littlewood), max permutation nx i=1 x i y (i) = nx i=1 x i y i : More generally, X and Y are comonotonic if and only if max ~Y = d Y E h X ~Y i = E [XY ] :

Example. Consider!! 1! 2 P (!) 1=2 1=2 X (!) +1 1 Y (!) +2 2 ~Y (!) 2 +2 X and Y are comonotone. ~Y has the same distribution as Y but is not comonotone with X. One has E [XY ] = 2 > 2 = E h X ~Y i :

Hardy-Littlewood inequality. The probability space is now [0; 1]. Assume U (t) = (t), where is nondecreasing. Let P a probability distribution, and let X (t) = FP 1 (t): For ~X : [0; 1]! R a r.v. such that ~X P, one has E [XU] = Z 1 0 (t)f 1 P (t)dt E h ~XU i : Thus, letting Z 1 %(X) = (t)f 1 0 X (t)dt = max n E[ ~XU]; = max n E[X ~U]; ~U = d U o : ~X = d X o

A geometric characterization. Let be an absolutely continuous distribution; two random variables X and Y are comonotone if for some random variable U, we have U 2 argmax ~ U U 2 argmax ~ U n E[X ~U]; ~U o, and n E[Y ~U]; ~U o : Geometrically, this means that X and Y have the same projection of the equidistribution class of =set of r.v. with distribution.

1.2 Multivariate generalization Problem: what can be done for risks which are multidimensional, and which are not perfect substitutes? Why? risk usually has several dimension (price/liquidity; multicurrency portfolio; environmental/ nancial risk, etc). Concepts used in the univariate case do not directly extend to the multivariate case.

The variational characterization given above will be the basis for the generalized notion of comonotonicity given in [EGH]. De nition (-comonotonicity). Let be an atomless probability measure on R d. Two random vectors X and Y in L 2 d are called -comonotonic if for some random vector U, we have U 2 argmax ~ U U 2 argmax ~ U n E[X ~U]; ~U o, and n E[Y ~U]; ~U o equivalentely: X and Y are -comonotonic if there exists two convex functions V 1 and V 2 and a random variable U such that X = rv 1 (U) Y = rv 2 (U) : Note that in dimension 1, this de nition is consistent with the previous one.

Monge-Kantorovich problem and Brenier theorem Let and P be two probability measures on R d with second moments, such that is absolutely continuous. Then sup U;XP E [hu; Xi] where the supremum is over all the couplings of and P if attained for a coupling such that one has X = rv (U) almost surely, where V is a convex function R d! R which happens to be the solution of the dual Kantorovich problem inf V (u)+w (x)hx;ui Z V (u) d (u) + Z W (x) dp (x) : Call Q P (u) = rv (u) the -quantile of distribution P.

Comonotonicity and transitivity. Puccetti and Scarsini (2010) propose the following de nition of comonotonicity, called c-comonotonicity: X and Y are c-comonotone if and only if n Y 2 argmax Y ~ E[X ~Y ]; ~Y Y o or, equivalently, i there exists a convex function u such that Y 2 @u (X) that is, whenever u is di erentiabe at X, Y = ru (X) : However, this de nition is not transitive: if X and Y are c-comonotone and Y and Z are c-comonotone, and if the distributions of X, Y and Z are absolutely continuous, then X and Z are not necessarily c-comonotome. This transivity (true in dimension one) may however be seen as desirable.

In the case of -comonotonicity, transitivity holds: if X and Y are -comonotone and Y and Z are -comonotone, and if the distributions of X, Y and Z are absolutely continuous, then X and Z are -comonotome. Indeed, express -comonotonicity of X and Y : for some U, X = rv 1 (U) Y = rv 2 (U) and by -comonotonicity of Y and Z, for some ~U, Y = rv 2 ~ U Z = rv 3 ~ U this implies ~U = U, and therefore X and Z are - comonotone.

Importance of. In dimension one, one recovers the classical notion of comotonicity regardless of the choice of. However, in dimension greater than one, the comonotonicity relation crucially depends on the baseline distribution, unlike in dimension one. The following lemma from [EGH] makes this precise: Lemma. Let and be atomless probability measures on R d. Then: - In dimension d = 1, -comonotonicity always implies -comonotonicity. - In dimension d 2, -comonotonicity implies -comonotonicity if and only if = T # for some location-scale transform T (u) = u + u 0 where > 0 and u 0 2 R d. In other words, comonotonicity is an invariant of the locationscale family classes.

2 Applications to risk measures 2.1 Coherent, regular risk measures (univariate case) Following Artzner, Delbaen, Eber, and Heath, recall the classical risk measures axioms: Recall axioms: De nition. A functional % : L 2 d! R is called a coherent risk measure if it satis es the following properties: - Monotonicity (MON): X Y ) %(X) %(Y ) - Translation invariance (TI): %(X+m) = %(X)+m%(1) - Convexity (CO): %(X + (1 )Y ) %(X) + (1 )%(Y ) for all 2 (0; 1). - Positive homogeneity (PH): %(X) = %(X) for all 0.

De nition. % : L 2! R is called a regular risk measure if it satis es: - Law invariance (LI): %(X) = %( ~X) when X ~X. - Comonotonic additivity (CA): %(X + Y ) = %(X) + %(Y ) when X; Y are comonotonic, i.e. weakly increasing transformation of a third randon variable: X = 1 (U) and Y = 2 (U) a.s. for 1 and 2 nondecreasing. Result (Kusuoka, 2001). A coherent risk measure % is regular if and only if for some increasing and nonnegative function on [0; 1], we have Z 1 %(X) := (t)f 1 0 X (t)dt; where F X denotes the cumulative distribution functions of the random variable X (thus Q X (t) = FX 1 (t) is the associated quantile). % is called a Spectral risk measure. For reasons explained later, also called Maximal correlation risk measure.

Leading example: Expected shortfall (also called Conditional VaR or TailVaR): (t) = 1 1 1 ftg : Then %(X) := 1 1 Z 1 F 1 X (t)dt:

Kusuoka s result, intuition. Law invariance ) %(X) = FX 1 Comonotone additivity+positive homogeneity ) is linear w.r.t. FX 1 : FX 1 R = 10 (t)fx 1 (t)dt. Monotonicity ) is nonnegative Subadditivity ) is increasing Unfortunately, this setting does not extend readily to multivariate risks. We shall need to reformulate our axioms in a way that will lend itself to easier multivariate extension.

2.2 Alternative set of axioms Manager supervising several N business units with risk X 1 ; :::; X N. Eg. investments portfolio of a fund of funds. True economic risk of the fund X 1 + ::: + X N. Business units: portfolio of (contingent) losses X i report a summary of the risk %(X i ) to management. Manager has limited information: 1) does not know what is the correlation of risks - and more broadly, the dependence structure, or copula between X 1 ; :::; X N. Maybe all the hedge funds in the portfolio have the same risky exposure; maybe they have independent risks; or maybe something inbetween. 2) aggregates risk by summation: reports %(X 1 ) + ::: + %(X N ) to shareholders.

Reported risk: %(X 1 )+:::+%(X N ); true risk: %(X 1 + ::: + X N ). Requirement: management does not understate risk to shareholders. Summarized by %(X 1 ) + ::: + %(X N ) %( ~X 1 + ::: + ~X N ) (*) whatever the joint dependence (X 1 ; :::; X N ) 2 (L 1 d )2. But no need to be overconservative: %(X 1 )+:::+%(X N ) = where denotes equality in distribution. sup %(X 1 +:::+X N ) ~X 1 X 1 ;:::; ~X N X N De nition. A functional % : L 2 d! R is called a strongly coherent risk measure if it is convex continuous and for all (X i ) in 2 N, L 2 d %(X 1 )+:::+%(X N ) = sup n %( ~X 1 + ::: + ~X N ) : ~X i X i o :

A representation result. The following result is given in [EGH]. Theorem. The following propositions about the functional % on L 2 d are equivalent: (i) % is a strongly coherent risk measure; (ii) % is a max correlation risk measure, namely there exists U 2 L 2 d, such that for all X 2 L2 d, %(X) = sup n E[U ~X] : ~X X o ; (iii) There exists a convex function V : R d! R such that %(X) = E[U rv (U)]

Idea of the proof. One has %(X)+%(Y ) = sup n %(X + ~Y ) : But %(X + ~Y ) = %(X) + D% X ( ~Y ) + o () By the Riesz theorem (vector case) D% X ( ~Y ) = E h m X : ~Y i, thus %(X)+%(Y ) = sup n %(X) + E h m X : ~Y i + o () : ~Y Y o thus %(Y ) = sup n E h m X : ~Y i : ~Y Y o therefore % is a maximum correlation measure.

3 Application to e cient risk-sharing Consider a risky payo X (for now, univariate) to be shared between 2 agents 1 and 2, so that in each contingent state: X = X 1 + X 2 X 1 and X 2 are said to form an allocation of X. Agents are risk averse in the sense of stochastic dominance: Y is preferred to X if every risk-averse expected utility decision maker prefers Y to X: X cv Y i E[u(X)] E[u(Y )] for all concave u Agents are said to have concave order preferences. These are incomplete preferences: it can be impossible to rank X and Y.

One wonders what is the set of e cient allocations, i.e. allocations that are not dominated w.r.t. the concave order for every agent. Dominated allocations. Consider a random variable X (aggregate risk). An allocation of X among p agents is a set of random variables (Y 1 ; :::; Y p ) such that X i Y i = X: Given two allocations of X, Allocation (Y i ) dominates allocation (X i ) whenever E 2 4 X i 3 u i (Y i ) 5 E 2 4 X i u i (X i ) for every continuous concave functions u 1 ; :::; u p. The domination is strict if the previous inequality is strict whenever the u i s are strictly concave. 3 5 Comonotone allocations. In the single-good case, it is intuitive that e cient sharing rules should be such that in

better states of the world, every agent should be better of than in worse state of the world otherwise there would be some mutually agreeable transfer. This leads to the concept of comonotone allocations. The precise connection with stochastic dominance is due to Landsberger and Meilijson (1994). Comonotonicity has received a lot of attention in recent years in decision theory, insurance, risk management, contract theory, etc. (Landsberger and Meilijson, Ruschendorf, Dana, Jouini and Napp...). Theorem (Landsberger and Meilijson). Any allocation of X is dominated by a comonotone allocation. Moreover, this dominance can be made strict unless X is already comonotone. Hence the set of e cient allocations of X coincides with the set of comonotone allocations. This result generalizes well to the multivariate case. Up to technicalities (see [CDG] for precise statement), ef- cient allocations of a random vector X is the set of

-comonotone allocations of X, hence (X i ) solves X i X i = ru i (U) X i = X for convex functions u i : R d! R, with U. Hence X = ru (U) with u = P i u i. That is U = ru (X) ; hence e cient allocations are such that X i = ru i ru (X) : This result opens the way to the investigation of testable implication of e ciency in risk-sharing in an risky endowment economy.

4 Application to stochastic orders Quiggin (1992) shows that the notion of monotone mean preserving increases in risk (hereafter MMPIR) is the weakest stochastic ordering that achieves a coherent ranking of risk aversion in the rank dependent utility framework. MMPIR is the mean preserving version of Bickel- Lehmann dispersion, which we now de ne. De nition. Let Q X and Q Y be the quantile functions of the random variables X and Y. X is said to be Bickel-Lehmann less dispersed, denoted X % BL Y, if Q Y (u) Q X (u) is a nondecreasing function of u on (0; 1). The mean preserving version is called monotone mean preserving increase in risk (MMPIR) and denoted - MMP IR. MMPIR is a stronger ordering than concave ordering in the sense that X % MMP IR Y implies X % cv Y.

The following result is from Landsberger and Meilijson (1994): Proposition (Landsberger and Meilijson). A random variable X has Bickel-Lehmann less dispersed distribution than a random variable Y if and only i there exists Z comonotonic with X such that Y = d X + Z. The concept of -comonotonicity allows to generalize this notion to the multivariate case as done in [CGH]. De nition. A random vector X is called -Bickel-Lehmann less dispersed than a random vector Y, denoted X % BL Y, if there exists a convex function V : R d! R such that the -quantiles Q X and Q Y of X and Y satisfy Q Y (u) Q X (u) = rv (u) for -almost all u 2 [0; 1] d. As de ned above, -Bickel-Lehmann dispersion de nes a transitive binary relation, and therefore an order. Indeed, if X % BL Y and Y % BL Z, then Q Y (u) Q X (u) =

rv (u) and Q Z (u) Q Y (u) = rw (u). Therefore, Q Z (u) Q X (u) = r(v (u)+w (u)) so that X % BL Z. When d = 1, this de nition simpli es to the classical de nition. [CGH] propose the following generalization of the Landsberger- Meilijson characterization. Theorem. A random vector X is -Bickel-Lehmann less dispersed than a random vector Y if and only if there exists a random vector Z such that: (i) X and Z are -comonotonic, and (ii) Y = d X + Z.

Conclusion We have introduced a new concept to generalize comonotonicity to higher dimension: -comonotonicity. This concept is based on Optimal Transport theory and boils down to classical comonotonicity in the univariate case. We have used this concept to generalize the classical axioms of risk measures to the multivariate case. We have extended existing results on equivalence between e ciency of risk-sharing and -comonotonicity. We have extended existing reults on functions increasing with respect to the Bickel-Lehman order. Interesting questions for future research: behavioural interpretation of mu? computational issues? empirical testability? case of heterogenous beliefs?