Oligopolistic Markets with Sequential Search and Production Cost Uncertainty

Similar documents
Oligopolistic Markets with Sequential Search and Asymmetric Information

Can Learning Cause Shorter Delays in Reaching Agreements?

Product Policy in Markets with Word-of-Mouth Communication. Technical Appendix

On the Licensing of Innovations under Strategic Delegation

On Industry Structure and Firm Conduct in Long Run Equilibrium

Word of Mass: The Relationship between Mass Media and Word-of-Mouth

Common Value Auctions with Costly Entry

Internet Appendix for Proxy Advisory Firms: The Economics of Selling Information to Voters

Taste for variety and optimum product diversity in an open economy

Millennium Relativity Acceleration Composition. The Relativistic Relationship between Acceleration and Uniform Motion

Market Segmentation for Privacy Differentiated Free Services

Public School Choice: An Economic Analysis

Volume 29, Issue 3. On the definition of nonessentiality. Udo Ebert University of Oldenburg

Optimization of Statistical Decisions for Age Replacement Problems via a New Pivotal Quantity Averaging Approach

A Functional Representation of Fuzzy Preferences

The Impact of Information on the Performance of an M/M/1 Queueing System

Appendix A Market-Power Model of Business Groups. Robert C. Feenstra Deng-Shing Huang Gary G. Hamilton Revised, November 2001

Methods of evaluating tests

Designing Dynamic Contests

KRANNERT GRADUATE SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT

The Hanging Chain. John McCuan. January 19, 2006

Complexity of Regularization RBF Networks

Kiel Institute for World Economics. On the Coexistence of National Companies and Multinational Enterprises

Computer Science 786S - Statistical Methods in Natural Language Processing and Data Analysis Page 1

Capacity Pooling and Cost Sharing among Independent Firms in the Presence of Congestion

Normative and descriptive approaches to multiattribute decision making

A Queueing Model for Call Blending in Call Centers

Sensitivity Analysis in Markov Networks

The Dynamics of Bidding Markets with Financial Constraints

Volunteering and the strategic value of ignorance

OPTIMAL CERTIFICATION POLICY, ENTRY, AND INVESTMENT IN THE PRESENCE OF PUBLIC SIGNALS

The Laws of Acceleration

Assessing the Performance of a BCI: A Task-Oriented Approach

2008/5. Efficiency gains and mergers. Giuseppe De Feo

arxiv: v2 [math.pr] 9 Dec 2016

Blind Queues: The Impact of Consumer Beliefs on Revenues and Congestion

A Characterization of Wavelet Convergence in Sobolev Spaces

Toulouse School of Economics, M2 Macroeconomics 1 Professor Franck Portier. Exam Solution

Peer Transparency in Teams: Does it Help or Hinder Incentives?

Average Rate Speed Scaling

Learning about the Neighborhood

Optimal Sales Force Compensation

Socially-Optimal Locations of Duopoly Firms with Non-Uniform Consumer Densities

LECTURE NOTES FOR , FALL 2004

The population dynamics of websites

The Effectiveness of the Linear Hull Effect

Private Label Positioning and Product Line

Singular Event Detection

Manipulative auction design

Hong Chen. and. Murray Frank 1. and. Hong Kong University of Science and Technology. March 30, Abstract

Simplification of Network Dynamics in Large Systems

6 Dynamic Optimization in Continuous Time

Persuasion, Pandering, and Sequential Proposal

Case I: 2 users In case of 2 users, the probability of error for user 1 was earlier derived to be 2 A1

Asymmetric information allocation to avoid coordination failure"

23.1 Tuning controllers, in the large view Quoting from Section 16.7:

Robust Recovery of Signals From a Structured Union of Subspaces

Subject: Introduction to Component Matching and Off-Design Operation % % ( (1) R T % (

Maximum Entropy and Exponential Families

Frugality Ratios And Improved Truthful Mechanisms for Vertex Cover

Persuasion, Pandering, and Sequential Proposal

Microeconomic Theory I Assignment #7 - Answer key

Quality in Supply Chain Encroachment

IMPEDANCE EFFECTS OF LEFT TURNERS FROM THE MAJOR STREET AT A TWSC INTERSECTION

kids (this case is for j = 1; j = 2 case is similar). For the interior solution case, we have 1 = c (x 2 t) + p 2

Chapter 8 Hypothesis Testing

Frequency hopping does not increase anti-jamming resilience of wireless channels

Financial Innovation and the Transactions Demand for Cash

General Equilibrium. What happens to cause a reaction to come to equilibrium?

Tests of fit for symmetric variance gamma distributions

Generalized Dimensional Analysis

Determination of the reaction order

Tight bounds for selfish and greedy load balancing

Designing Social Norm Based Incentive Schemes to Sustain Cooperation in a Large Community

SINCE Zadeh s compositional rule of fuzzy inference

Do Generation Firms in Restructured Electricity Markets Have Incentives to. Support Social-Welfare-Improving Transmission Investments?

max min z i i=1 x j k s.t. j=1 x j j:i T j

A simple expression for radial distribution functions of pure fluids and mixtures

Reliability Guaranteed Energy-Aware Frame-Based Task Set Execution Strategy for Hard Real-Time Systems

Inequality, Redistribution and Optimal Trade Policy: A Public Finance Approach

7 Max-Flow Problems. Business Computing and Operations Research 608

Irreversibility and restoration in natural resource development

Remark 4.1 Unlike Lyapunov theorems, LaSalle s theorem does not require the function V ( x ) to be positive definite.

On Component Order Edge Reliability and the Existence of Uniformly Most Reliable Unicycles

Complementarities in Spectrum Markets

Lightpath routing for maximum reliability in optical mesh networks

Forecasting Conditional Probabilities of Binary Outcomes under Misspecification

Forecasting Conditional Probabilities of Binary Outcomes under Misspecification

Lecture 3 - Lorentz Transformations

Fig Review of Granta-gravel

Likelihood-confidence intervals for quantiles in Extreme Value Distributions

22.54 Neutron Interactions and Applications (Spring 2004) Chapter 6 (2/24/04) Energy Transfer Kernel F(E E')

Coding for Random Projections and Approximate Near Neighbor Search

3 Tidal systems modelling: ASMITA model

Predicting the confirmation time of Bitcoin transactions

A NETWORK SIMPLEX ALGORITHM FOR THE MINIMUM COST-BENEFIT NETWORK FLOW PROBLEM

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES FINANCIAL INNOVATION AND THE TRANSACTIONS DEMAND FOR CASH. Fernando E. Alvarez Francesco Lippi

Ordered fields and the ultrafilter theorem

Capacity Sharing and Cost Allocation among Independent Firms with Congestion

Analysis of discretization in the direct simulation Monte Carlo

Transcription:

Oligopolisti Markets with Sequential Searh and Prodution Cost Unertainty Maarten Janssen Paul Pihler Simon Weidenholzer February 14, 2011 Abstrat This artile analyzes a sequential searh model where firms fae idential but stohasti prodution osts, the realizations of whih are unknown to onsumers. We haraterize a perfet Bayesian equilibrium satisfying a reservation pries property and provide a suffiient ondition for suh an equilibrium to exist. We show that (i) firms set on average higher pries and make larger profits ompared to the senario where onsumers observe prodution osts, (ii) expeted pries and onsumer welfare an be non monotoni in the number of firms, and (iii) the impat of prodution ost unertainty vanishes as the number of firms beomes very large. JEL Classifiation: D40; D83; L13 Keywords: Sequential Searh, Prie Dispersion, Asymmetri Information We are grateful to Mark Armstrong (editor), anonymous referees, Benny Moldovanu, José Luis Moraga- González, Manfred Nermuth, Regis Renault, Sandro Shelegia, and Chris Wilson and to audienes at the EEA- ESEM 2009 in Barelona, the Workshop Searh and Swithing Costs in Groningen, the Theoretisher Ausshuß des Vereins für Soialpolitik, the Vienna University of Eonomis and Business Administration, the University of Vienna, the Institute for Advaned Studies (Vienna), the Meeting of Austrian Competition Authorities, the Norwegian Shool of Management, the 2010 World Congress of the Eonometri Soiety, and at ECARES (Université Libre de Bruxelles) for helpful omments. An earlier version of this artile was irulated under the title Sequential Searh with Inompletely Informed Consumers: Theory and Evidene from Retail Gasoline Markets. Janssen and Weidenholzer thank the Wiener Wissenshafts-, Forshungs- und Tehnologiefonds (WWTF) for finanial support under projet MA 09-017 Department of Eonomis, University of Vienna and Higher Shool of Eonomis (Mosow). E-mail: maarten.janssen@univie.a.at Eonomi Studies Division, Oesterreihishe Nationalbank. E-mail: paul.pihler@oenb.at Department of Eonomis, University of Vienna. E-mail: simon.weidenholzer@univie.a.at 1

1 Introdution Consider a onsumer who observes the prie of gasoline at a gas station. Knowing that pries between different stations may vary onsiderably, the onsumer must deide whether to buy at the observed prie or searh for a better deal elsewhere. When making this deision, she must estimate how muh of the observed prie is due to ommon fators affeting all gasoline stations in a similar way, e.g. the prie of rude oil, and how muh is due to idiosynrati fators affeting the partiular seller being visited. If the onsumer believes that ommon fators are more relevant in determining the prie, she might onsider searhing for a heaper gas station not worthwhile and, hene, buy at the observed prie. Conversely, if she believes that the station harges a partiularly high prie ompared to other stations, she will probably find it optimal to look for a better deal. A key feature of this problem is that the onsumer must take her deision not knowing the gas station s input (prodution) ost. Moreover, information is asymmetri, as gasoline retailers are obviously aware of this ost. In this artile we study how asymmetri information between firms and onsumers affets market outomes in situations like the one desribed above. To this end, we introdue this feature into the standard sequential searh model with homogeneous goods, as developed by Stahl (1989). In our model, finitely many firms sell a homogenous produt on an oligopolisti market, with all firms faing the same stohasti prodution ost and being aware of its realization. Consumers have inelasti demand and engage in sequential searh for low pries. Unlike Stahl s sequential searh model and unlike most searh literature, onsumers do not observe the firms prodution ost realization. Instead, they hold prior beliefs about the distribution of prodution osts and update these beliefs as they observe pries. This environment aptures not only important features of the retail gasoline market, but also of retail markets for mortgages and other finanial servies, where retailers (i) are subjet to important exogenous, ommon shoks in their main ost fator and (ii) are better informed about these shoks than final onsumers. 1 1 This is not to say that there are no ost differenes between individual firms. What seems to be true, however, in most of these markets-and ertainly in the retail gasoline market- is that the idiosynrati omponent of osts -suh as the rental rate of the shop loation- is muh more stable than the variations of the main ost omponent, 2

In this environment we examine the properties of a perfet Bayesian equilibrium satisfying a reservation pries property (PBERP) where onsumers buy if the observed prie is at or below their urrent reservation prie, and searh for a lower prie otherwise. At the relevant reservation prie the onsumer is indifferent between buying and searhing for a better deal. Notie that a onsumer who observes a prie in the first searh round and ontinues to searh will update her beliefs about the firms underlying prodution ost on the basis of her first prie observation, and therefore she will (generially) have a different reservation prie in the seond searh round. Thus, a onsequene of prodution ost unertainty within a sequential searh framework is that, if there exists an equilibrium where optimal searh behavior in eah searh round is haraterized by a reservation prie, the reservation prie must depend on the history of prie observations. This history-dependene renders the analysis onsiderably more ompliated ompared to the ase where onsumers know the prodution ost. This may have lead the literature to restrit attention to other, often less plausible, searh protools when studying information asymmetry in onsumer searh models. 2 Our artile attempts to fill this gap in the literature by examining a sequential searh framework within the ontext of prodution ost unertainty. Within this framework, we fous on three questions. What are the harateristis of a PBERP? Under whih onditions does suh an equilibrium exist? And what is the role of asymmetri information within a sequential searh framework? Conerning the first question, we first show that in a PBERP no firm will set a prie larger than the onsumers first round reservation prie. To gain intuition for this finding, assume a firm would harge the upper bound, and that this upper bound is higher than the onsumers first-round reservation prie. This firm would obviously not have any sales in the first searh round; moreover, in later searh rounds potential ustomers visiting the firm already have lower whether it is the world oil prie or the interest rate in finanial markets. 2 For example, Dana (1994) onsiders a model of asymmetri information with newspaper searh, i.e., uninformed onsumers an learn all pries at one by paying a searh ost. He emphasizes, however, that the... assumption of newspaper searh is learly restritive and is not as realisti as the assumption that searh is sequential (...). However, analyzing sequential searh equilibrium under inomplete information is extremely diffiult beause onsumers ould in priniple searh more than one and hene more than one instane of Bayesian updating ould our. (p. 747). 3

prie observations in their pokets and, thus, the firm would not have any sales in later searh rounds either. This behavior annot be optimal. The entral step in haraterizing equilibrium, thus, turns out to be the haraterization of the onsumers first-round reservation prie. This is not a straightforward task, as onsumers may in priniple searh more than one, leading to multiple instanes of updating of beliefs about the underlying prodution ost. One important theoretial result of this artile is that this annot happen in a PBERP. Importantly, a onsumer who observes the first-round reservation prie in a PBERP and, being indifferent, ontinues to searh has a stritly higher reservation prie in round two than in round one. This implies that the first-round reservation prie is the prie at whih a onsumer is indifferent between buying now and ontinuing to searh exatly one more round, similar to the omplete information model. Conerning our seond researh question, we show that existene of a PBERP is not trivially guaranteed. This finding is losely related to Rothshild (1974), who shows that an optimal onsumer searh strategy does not need to satisfy a reservation pries property if the prie distribution is unknown to the onsumer, and thus obtaining prie observations also has an informational value as onsumers update their beliefs about the true prie distribution from whih pries are sampled. In an environment where the prie distribution is exogenously given, Rothshild shows that the onsumer searh strategy satisfies a reservation prie property if for any two pries the differene between these two pries is smaller than the differene in their informational ontent. Using similar ideas in an environment where the prie distribution is endogenously determined, and using speifi properties the equilibrium prie distribution has to satisfy, we speify a suffiient ondition for the existene of a PBERP. In partiular, we show that a PBERP exists in markets with either (i) a small support of the prodution ost distribution, (ii) relatively large searh osts, (iii) relatively many firms, or (iv) relatively few shoppers. If a PBERP exists, we show that it is neessarily unique. We extend Rothshild s logi in our framework by arguing that our ondition is also "neessary" in the sense that, if the ondition fails to hold, then one an always find distributions of the prodution ost suh that a PBERP does not exist. Moreover, we provide an example showing that even when the prodution ost is uniformly distributed, a reservation prie equilibrium fails 4

to exist if our ondition is not satisfied. Thus, prodution ost unertainty introdues signifiant hanges to the sequential searh model with respet to the existene of reservation prie equilibria. Conerning our third question, we have the following observations. First, in the ost ertainty benhmark 3 (whih is essentially the Stahl model with unit demand), we show that the expeted minimum prie in the market is independent of the number of firms when this number is not too large, whereas the expeted prie is inreasing. Interestingly, when onsumers are unertain about the underlying ost level, the expeted prie and total onsumer surplus over informed and uninformed onsumers an be non-monotoni in the number of firms. Seond, examining equilibrium prie strategies used by firms, we show that the lower bound of the prie distribution is inreasing in the ost level whereas its upper bound is independent of the ost level. 4 Thus, the extent of equilibrium prie dispersion under prodution ost unertainty dereases as the ost level rises. This onstitutes an important and interesting differene to the ase where onsumers are aware of the prodution ost where the extent of prie dispersion is independent of the prodution ost realization. Third, studying the welfare effets of prodution ost unertainty, we show that, from an ex-ante perspetive, onsumer welfare is unambiguously lower under prodution ost unertainty and profits are unambiguously higher as ompared to the environment where onsumers know the prodution ost. Both informed and uninformed onsumers pay in expeted terms higher pries. Finally, when the number of firms in the industry beomes large, the importane of prodution ost unertainty vanishes and the expeted prie and the expeted minimum prie in the two models onverge to eah other. The main reason is that, with many firms, pries lose to the reservation prie do not onvey information to onsumers about the underlying ost of firms. This artile ontributes to a large and growing literature on equilibrium onsumer searh 3 We use the term ost ertainty when we refer to the situation that onsumers and firms all know the relevant prodution ost. Cost unertainty is used when we refer to the situation that onsumers do not know the relevant prodution ost, but firms do. 4 In a PBERP, the upper bound must be equal to the first round reservation prie of onsumers. Beause the latter annot depend of the ost realization whih is unknown to onsumers, this property arries over to the upper bound. 5

models starting from seminal ontributions by Reinganum (1979), Varian (1980), Burdett and Judd (1983), and Stahl (1989). In terms of the researh question being addressed, the artiles most losely related to the present one are Benabou and Gertner (1993) and Dana (1994). 5 Both artiles onsider, however, simplified searh protools. Benabou and Gertner analyze a duopoly market where prodution osts are subjet to orrelated shoks. Half the onsumers observe one prie and the other half observes the other prie at no ost. The only deision onsumers have to make is whether to also observe the prie of the firm they have not yet observed at a searh ost. Their analysis is restrited to the ase where the orrelation between the prodution shoks of individual firms is not too large or the searh osts are not too large. We onsider the ase where prodution osts are perfetly orrelated and where searh osts and the number of firms an take on any value. Dana (1994) onsiders a model with two types of onsumers (informed and uninformed) where the uninformed onsumers are engaged in newspaper searh. These onsumers get a first prie quote for free and, on the basis of this prie, they deide whether or not to beome fully informed about all pries by paying a searh ost. Papers by Fershtman and Fishman (1992) and Fishman (1996), and the reent ontributions by Yang and Ye (2008) and Tappata (2009), use frameworks similar to Dana (1994), but extend them to a dynami setting. In suh environments, these artiles study asymmetri prie adjustment to ost shoks, the so-alled rokets-and-feathers pattern. To the best of our knowledge, our artile is the first to introdue prodution ost unertainty into a sequential onsumer searh model. 6 In a broader sense the urrent artile is related to reent work whih elaborates on the role of information gathering and information proessing in onsumer searh. 7 This literature fouses 5 Earlier work by Diamond (1971) and Rothshild (1974) has analyzed optimal searh behavior in a world where the prie distribution is unknown, but exogenously given. Reently, Gershkov and Moldovanu (2009) unover some formal relations between optimal stopping rules in the onsumer searh literature and the problem of ensuring monotone alloation rules in dynami alloation problems. 6 Stritly speaking, Benabou and Gertner (1993) analyze a ase of sequential searh, but as their analysis is restrited to duopoly markets, onsumers effetively know the pries of all firms one they engage in searh (beyond their first free prie observation). With two firms, the differene between sequential searh and newspaper searh disappears. 7 Baye, Morgan, and Sholten (2006) surveys a wide range of onsumer searh models. 6

on obfusation (Ellison and Wolitzky (2009), Ellison and Ellison (2009)), boundedly rational agents (see, e.g., Spiegler (2006)), or information gatekeepers on the internet (see, e.g., Baye and Morgan (2001)). Another strand of the literature makes progress on the poliy impliations of the onsumer searh literature on onsumer protetion poliies (see, e.g., Armstrong, Vikers, and Zhou (2009a)) or on the empirial implementation of onsumer searh models (see, e.g., Lah (2007), Hortaçsu and Syverson (2004) and Moraga-González and Wildenbeest (2008)). The remainder of this artile is organized in the following way. In Setion 2 we briefly disuss the standard sequential searh model where onsumers observe prodution osts, establishing a theoretial benhmark for omparison of our ost unertainty model. This setion also ontains some new results (on the expeted prie paid by onsumers who know all pries in the market) and some new haraterizations making it easier to work with the model. In Setion 3 we develop our model in whih the prodution ost realization is unertain to onsumers, define a perfet Bayesian equilibrium and haraterize its properties. In Setion 4 we summarize the effets of prodution ost unertainty on onsumer and produer welfare, assess the effets of entry by omparing the models when the number of firms beomes large, and provide some other omparative stati analysis. Setion 5 ontains a disussion and Setion 6 onludes. Proofs are provided in the Appendix. 2 Sequential searh under prodution ost ertainty We start our analysis by desribing a sequential searh model where there is no unertainty regarding the underlying prodution ost along the lines of Stahl (1989). This model will, at a later stage, serve as our benhmark to assess the impliations of prodution ost unertainty within the sequential searh framework. Essentially, we modify Stahl s model along only two dimensions. First, to simplify the analysis we onsider a model of inelasti demand as in Janssen, Moraga-Gonzalez, and Wildenbeest (2005) and, seond, do not normalize marginal osts to zero. Solving the model for positive marginal osts is inevitable for our purposes, beause later we want to analyze and ompare situations with different marginal ost levels. 7

Model. We onsider an oligopolisti market where N 2 firms sell a homogenous good and ompete in pries. Eah firm n {1,...,N} faes the same prodution tehnology and the same marginal prodution ost, denoted by. Without loss of generality, we normalize fixed osts to zero. Eah firm s objetive is to maximize profits, taking the pries harged by other firms and the onsumers behavior as given. On the demand side of the market we have a ontinuum of risk-neutral onsumers with idential preferenes. Eah onsumer j [0, 1] has inelasti demand normalized to one unit, and holds the same onstant valuation v > 0 for the good. Observing a prie below v, onsumers will, thus, either buy one unit of the good or searh for a lower prie. In the latter ase, they have to pay a searh ost s to obtain one additional prie quote, i.e. searh is sequential. A fration λ [0, 1] of onsumers, the shoppers, have zero searh osts. These onsumers sample all pries and buy at the lowest prie. The remaining fration of 1 λ onsumers the non-shoppers have positive searh osts s > 0. These onsumers fae a non-trivial problem when searhing for low pries, as they have to trade off the searh ost with the (expeted) benefit from searh. Consumers an always ome bak to previously visited firms inurring no additional ost, i.e. we are onsidering a model of ostless reall. 8 We assume that v is large relative to and s so that v is not binding. In this setion onsumers are informed about the ost realization. Equilibrium. In this model, there exists a unique symmetri Nash equilibrium where onsumer behavior satisfies a reservation prie property. Kohn and Shavell (1974) and Stahl (1989) argue that the reservation pries are stationary, i.e., the onsumers reservation pries are independent from the history of prie observations and the number of firms left to be sampled (provided there is still at least one firm left) and an therefore simply be denoted by ρ k (). 9 To haraterize this equilibrium it is useful to introdue some further notation: we denote, for a given prodution ost, the distribution of pries harged by firms by F k (p ), its density by f k (p ), and the lower- and upper- bound of its support by p k () and by p k (), respetively. 8 Janssen and Parakhonyak (2007) analyze the ase where this assumption is replaed by ostly reall. 9 We use the supersript k to indiate variables and parameters of the model where onsumers know the prodution ost realization. 8

It is well-known that the presene of both shoppers and non shoppers, λ (0, 1), implies that there does not exist an equilibrium in pure strategies and that there are no mass points in the equilibrium prie distribution. The main reason behind this observation is that firms fae a tradeoff between setting low pries to ater to the shoppers and setting high pries to extrat profits from the non shoppers. Also, the upper bound of the equilibrium prie distribution must satisfy p k () = ρ k (), i.e., in a symmetri equilibrium no firm will set a prie higher than the reservation prie ρ k (). Given these two observations, the equilibrium prie distribution an be haraterized by Proposition 1 For λ (0,1) and ρ k (), the equilibrium prie distribution for the ost realization is given by respetively f k (p ) = 1 N 1 ( 1 λ F k (p ) = 1 λn p k () (p ) 2 with support on [p k (), p k ()] with p k () = ( ) 1 1 λ λn p k ) N 1 () p 1 p N 1 ( p k () p p ) 2 N N 1 λn λn+1 λ + 1 λ λn+1 λ pk () and p k () = ρ k (). (1) (2) The proof follows essentially Stahl (1989) and is therefore omitted. The result mainly follows from the fat that given the mixed strategy distribution hosen by the ompetitors and its own prie p, a firm s profit is given by [ λ(1 F k (p )) N 1 + 1 λ ] (p ) N and that in a mixed strategy equilibrium, this profit has to be equal to the profit the firm gets if sets a prie equal to the upper bound of the prie distribution, whih is equal to 1 λ N ( pk () ). Having haraterized the Nash equilibrium prie distribution onditional on the reservation prie ρ k (), we turn to optimal onsumer behavior. Given a distribution of pries F k (p ) and an observed prie p, it is straightforward to argue that the reservation prie ρ k () is impliitly determined by ρ k v ρ k () () = v s p f k (p )d p. p k () 9

Using the result that the equilibrium prie distribution satisfies p k () = ρ k (), this ondition boils down to ρ k () = s + E k (p ). (3) As the next lemma shows, this relation between reservation prie and expeted prie allows us to derive a simple formula for the expeted prie onditional on the ost realization, E k (p ). Lemma 1 The expeted prie onditional on the ost realization, E k (p ), is given by where α = 1 1 0 dz [0,1). 1+ λn zn 1 1 λ E k (p ) = + α s, (4) 1 α Janssen and Moraga-González (2004) have shown that α is inreasing in N. It follows that the expeted prie is inreasing in N as well. Note that (3) and (4) imply the following simple expression for the reservation prie, ρ k () = p k () = + s 1 α. (5) The reservation prie is, thus, a onstant markup over the ost, with the size of the markup being determined by the model s parameters s and α whih, in turn, depends on N and λ. Note that α approahes one as the number of firms grows without bound, N, or the fration of informed onsumers shrinks, λ 0, and therefore the reservation prie grows without bound. At some point, the willingness to pay v beomes binding. In order not to ompliate notation, we restrit the analysis to the parameter values where v is not binding. Note further that, by Proposition 1, p k () is a weighted average of and ρ k (). Consequently, it immediately follows that, provided s > 0, the lower bound satisfies p k () >. Thus, firms make positive profits when harging pries aording to F k (p ). Furthermore, the following result obtains: Corollary 1 The equilibrium prie spread, i.e. the differene between the upper bound and the lower bound of the prie distribution, is independent of the realized ost level and given by p k () p k λn s () = λn + 1 λ 1 α. (6) 10

The proof follows from (5) and Proposition 2.1. What is interesting about Corollary 1 is that a hange in leads to a one to one shift in the prie distribution, leaving the extent of prie dispersion unaffeted. In Figure 1 we highlight this point by plotting prie distributions for various realizations of ost. PUT FIGURE 1 APPROXIMATELY HERE Note at this stage that, onditional on the ost, the average prie paid by a fration 1 λ of onsumers, i.e. the non-shoppers, is equal to E k (p ) as given in (4). This is, however, not the (average) prie paid by the λ shoppers who observe all pries in the market and buy at the heapest firm. This latter prie is given by E k (p l ), with p l = min{p 1, p 2,..., p N }. As firms hoose pries randomly and independently from eah other, it follows that the distribution of p l is given by F k l (p l ) = 1 [1 F k (p )] N. (7) Stahl (1989), and reently Morgan, Orzen, and Sefton (2006), and Waldek (2008), suggest that in their models the shoppers observing all pries are better off with entry. In our model featuring unit demand and an endogenous reservation prie this is, however, not the ase. In partiular, the expeted minimum prie is independent of N: Proposition 2 The expeted minimum-prie onditional on the ost realization, E k (p l ), is given by and therefore independent on N. E k (p l ) = + 1 λ s, (8) λ In our model, entry has three different effets on the expeted minimum prie. First, the reservation prie is inreasing in the number of firms through its effet on α. As this implies that pries tend to be higher with more firms, this effet unambiguously makes shoppers worse off. A seond effet is that shoppers sample more firms when there are more firms available 11

in the market. This has the unambiguous effet that for a given prie distribution shoppers are better off. Finally, prie dispersion inreases with more firms in the industry, implying that firms onentrate more on lower and higher pries at the expense of moderate pries. In fat, the lower bound of the prie distribution dereases in the number of firms. The Proposition shows that the net result of these three effets is zero. The differene with earlier results an be explained as follows. Stahl s (1989) result that shoppers are better off with entry holds true when there are already suffiiently many firms. In that ase, the willingness to pay v imposes a binding onstraint on the upper bound of the prie distribution and the first effet mentioned above does not apply anymore. For the speial ase of unit demand, our model is idential to Stahl (1989) and our result holds when N is small enough so that the willingness to pay is not binding. Morgan, Orzen, and Sefton (2006) onsider Varian s (1980) model where the onsumer reservation prie is exogenously given by the willingness to pay and onsumers have unit demand. This, again, implies that the first effet mentioned above does not apply. Finally, we ompute the unonditionally expeted pries E k (p) = E k (p )d and E k (p l ) = E k (p l )d. These expeted pries will later on be important to assess onsumer welfare in the eonomy, as v E k (p l ) is the expeted equilibrium onsumer surplus attained by shoppers whereas v E k (p) is expeted equilibrium surplus of the 1 λ non-shoppers. 10 Formally, we obtain: Corollary 2 The unonditionally expeted pries E k (p) and E k (p l ) are given by where E() = g()d. E k (p) = E() + α s, 1 α and (9) E k (p l ) = E() + 1 λ s, λ (10) The proof follows trivially from Lemma 1 and Proposition 2. Note that both ex-ante expeted pries take the form of a markup over the ex-ante expeted ost, with the size of the respetive 10 We will ompute expeted onsumer surplus in the very beginning of the game, i.e. before the ost level is drawn from g(). 12

markup being determined by the model s parameters. It is interesting to note that the mark-up for the expeted minimum prie is independent of N, and the mark-up of the expeted prie is inreasing in N. 3 Sequential searh under prodution ost unertainty We now turn to the analysis of prodution ost unertainty and modify the model presented in Setion 2 by postulating that onsumers are uninformed about the firms prodution ost. Let nature randomly draw from a ontinuous distribution g() with ompat support on [, ]. Consumers do not know the ost realization and they all hold orret prior beliefs about the prodution ost distribution and update their beliefs aording to Bayes rule after observing pries. On out-of-equilibrium beliefs. Under prodution ost unertainty the exat speifiation of out-of-equilibrium beliefs plays an important role in determining reservation pries. To see this point, assume that onsumers hold out-of-equilibrium beliefs that are suh that, if a prie above their reservation prie is observed, they think that the lowest ost level has been realized with probability one and therefore ontinue to searh. In suh a ase, in equilibrium no firm would set a prie above the reservation prie (more details will be given shortly) and therefore suh a prie observation is learly an out-of-equilibrium event. Note that under these partiular beliefs, one an support a (first round) reservation prie with the property that a onsumer who observes it will stritly prefer to buy instead of atually being indifferent between buying and searhing for a lower prie. In a setting where onsumers know the prodution ost, this ould never be a reservation prie as onsumers would then also be willing to buy at a slightly higher prie. However, in the ase of prodution ost unertainty, under these partiular out-ofequilibrium beliefs, a onsumer would prefer to ontinue searhing for lower pries thinking that the lowest ost level has been realized and thus that pries should be low. Consequently, there would be a disontinuity in the willingness of onsumers to buy around this reservation prie. 13

However, we think that suh a disontinuity is diffiult to defend in a onsumer searh model and we ertainly do not want the omparison between the ases where onsumers know and do not know the prodution ost to depend on the arbitrary hoie of out-of-equilibrium beliefs. We therefore insist that, if at a reservation prie onsumers stritly prefer to buy, out-ofequilibrium beliefs should be suh that onsumers also should buy at a slightly higher prie. 11 This effetively defines the first round reservation prie as the prie at whih the onsumer is indifferent between buying and ontinuing to searh, in a way similar to the familiar ase where onsumers know the prodution ost. In the following, we limit attention to equilibria satisfying suh a reservation pries property. Equilibria with reservation pries property. To provide a formal definition of what we mean by equilibria satisfying a reservation pries property requires to introdue some more notation. In partiular, we denote by ρ t (p 1,..., p t 1 ) the reservation prie of a onsumer in searh round t who has observed pries p 1,..., p t 1 in the t 1 previous searh rounds. Note that, unlike the ase were onsumers know the prodution ost, any reservation prie ρ t (p 1,..., p t 1 ) held by onsumers has to be independent of the prodution ost. As the reservation prie ρ 1 in the first round annot be onditioned on any prie observation, we write ρ 1 = ρ. We have: 12 Definition 1 A perfet Bayesian equilibrium satisfying a reservation pries property (PBERP) is haraterized by: 1) eah firm n {1,...,N} uses a prie strategy that maximizes its (expeted) profit, given the ompeting firms prie strategies and the searh behavior of onsumers; 2) given the (possibly degenerate) distribution of firms pries, onsumers searh optimally given their beliefs, and update their beliefs given their prie observations (if possible) and formulate out-of-equilibrium beliefs whenever they observe a non-equilibrium prie; moreover, optimal onsumer searh is of the following form: 11 We do not impose further onstraints on the out-of-equilibrium beliefs. The ontinuity requirement we impose is onsistent with, but not implied by, the Intuitive Criterion as defined by Cho and Kreps (1987). 12 This definition is an adaptation of the reservation prie equilibrium defined by Dana (1994) to the ase of sequential searh. 14

i) after observing p t = ρ t (p 1,..., p t 1 ) in round t and p 1,..., p t 1 in previous rounds, the onsumer is indifferent between buying and ontinuing to searh; ii) after observing any p t < ρ t (p 1,..., p t 1 ) in round t and p 1,..., p t 1 in previous rounds, the onsumer buys. In what follows, we onentrate on the haraterization of this type of equilibrium and determine onditions for existene. Properties of PBERP. We first examine the properties of a PBERP, assuming that suh an equilibrium exists. Later, we onsider the existene question. A first observation is that in a PBERP, the upper bound of the prie distribution has to be equal to the reservation prie of onsumers in the first searh round, i.e. p() = p = ρ for all [, ]. Suppose this was not the ase and that for some, p() > ρ. If a firm harges p(), it will not sell to shoppers in any PBERP, as p() does not have positive probability and therefore shoppers observe lower pries with probability one. Furthermore, a firm setting p() will not sell to non-shoppers either, as these onsumers will ontinue to searh after observing p in the first searh round, and will then find a lower prie in a subsequent searh round with probability one. On the other hand, it an also not be the ase that for some, p() < ρ as firms ould profitably deviate to a prie equal to ρ beause non-shoppers would ontinue to buy. Under prodution ost unertainty firms fae virtually the same maximization problem as in the benhmark ase where onsumers know the prodution ost. The only major differene is that the upper bound of the prie distribution is now onstant at p = ρ for all realizations of the ost. Formally: Proposition 3 In any PBERP the equilibrium prie distribution for the ost realization is given by respetively ( ) 1 1 λ p p N 1 F(p ) = 1 λn p f (p ) = 1 p N 1 (p ) 2 with support on [p(), p] with p() = ( ) 1 1 λ λn N 1 ( p p p ) 2 N N 1 λn λn+1 λ + 1 λ λn+1 λ p and p = ρ. (11) (12) 15

The proof is omitted, as it is a straightforward extension of Proposition 1. Essentially (11) is idential to (1), the main differene being that now the upper bound is independent of as onsumers annot ondition their searh behavior on the unknown ost parameter. Inspetion of (11) reveals that F(p ) first order stohastially dominates (FOSD) F(p ) whenever >. Furthermore, we have that p() is inreasing in, implying that onsumers who observe pries below p() an rule out ertain (high) ost realizations. Employing the tehniques used in lemma 1 we an write E(p ) as E(p ) = (1 α) + α p. (13) Figure 2 visualizes all these observations by plotting the prie distributions F(p ) for different realizations of the prodution ost. PUT FIGURE 2 APPROXIMATELY HERE This figure points to the fat that the prie spread is dereasing in the ost level, as stated in the following orollary: Corollary 3 If onsumers are uninformed about the firms ost realization, the prie spread in a PBERP is equal to p p() = and therefore is dereasing in the ost level. λn ( p ) λn + 1 λ Corollary 3 establishes a sharp ontrast to the ase with prodution ost ertainty where the prie spread is independent of the realized ost level. We next fous on onsumers searh behavior. Assuming onsumers have orret prior beliefs about the prodution ost and use Bayesian updating after observing a prie p, let δ( p) be the (posterior) probability density funtion of the prodution ost onditional on a prie observation p. By Bayes rule, we have that: g() f (p ) δ( p) = g( ) f (p )d. (14) 16

It remains to speify onsumers out-of-equilibrium beliefs, i.e. beliefs on the ost level for prie observations not in the support of the equilibrium prie distribution. As argued above, we want to avoid out-of-equilibrium beliefs that reate a disontinuity in the willingness of onsumers to buy around the reservation prie. To this end, we assume that for a prie observation above the upper bound of the prie distribution onsumers hold the same beliefs on the ost level as if they had observed the upper bound, i.e. δ( p) = δ( p) for p > p. 13 In the following, we derive several lemmas that will prove useful to examine the properties of PBERP. First, we identify an important feature of Bayesian updating in our framework that plays a key role in our main results: a onsumer who has observed a prie p [p(), p] will put more probability mass on higher realization of the prodution ost and less mass on lower realizations of the prodution ost than under the prior distribution g(). Lemma 2 For any p [p(), p], the posterior distribution of ost levels δ( p) first-order stohastially dominates the prior distribution g(). Lemma 2 implies that non-shoppers who have observed any p [p(), p] expet a higher ost level E( p) than if they hadn t observed any prie, i.e. E( p) = δ( p)d > g()d = E(). Moreover, we find that the higher the prie observed in the interval p [p(), p], the more optimisti the onsumer is about the possibility of finding low pries if she ontinues searhing. Formally, Lemma 3 For all p [p(), p), there is a unique ost level ĉ suh that > 0 if < ĉ δ( p) = 0 if = ĉ p < 0 if > ĉ. Consequently, for all p, p [p(), p) with p > p, the posterior distribution of ost levels δ( p) FOSD δ( p ). 13 As at pries below the lower bound of the prie distribution in the lowest ost senario onsumers buy regardless of their beliefs on the realized ost level, beliefs in these states are irrelevant. 17

Lemma 3 appears puzzling at first sight: it asserts that the larger the prie that is observed, the more onsumers believe that the underlying prodution ost is low. However, the lemma an be understood as follows: in the interval [p(), p], the ratio of endogenously hosen densities f (p )/ f (p ) as implied by (12) is inreasing in p when <. This implies that higher pries in [p(), p] are relatively more likely under low osts than under high osts, whih in turn explains why higher prie observations in p [p(), p] lead the onsumer to beome more optimisti that the ost realization is atually low. We now move on to the haraterization of reservation pries under prodution ost unertainty. Reall that if the prodution ost is known to onsumers the reservation prie is defined as the prie at whih the onsumer is indifferent between buying now and ontinuing to searh one more time. In the present ontext, this would translate into defining the (first round) reservation prie ρ by the indifferene ondition v ρ = v s E(p ρ), with E(p ρ) = E(p )δ( ρ)d. The reservation prie ρ would thus be impliitly given by ρ = s + E(p )δ( ρ)d. (15) However, under prodution ost unertainty pries are not stationary and, due to Bayesian updating of beliefs, do depend on the searh history. The arguments used above may hene not be valid, espeially not if the seond round reservation prie ould be lower than the first round reservation prie. In that ase, the onsumer who ontinues to searh after observing the firstround reservation prie may optimally want to searh beyond the seond round and then it is not obvious that the first round reservation prie should satisfy (15). In what follows, we however prove that (15) still provides a proper haraterization of the first round reservation prie as this reservation prie is stritly below the onsumer s round two reservation prie. Lemma 4 establishes this result. Lemma 4 In any PBERP, after observing the upper bound of the prie distribution in the first searh round, a onsumer s reservation prie in the seond searh round satisfies ρ 2 (ρ) > ρ. 18

It follows that there does not exist a PBERP where onsumers follow a stationary reservation prie searh rule. This is an important differene with the model where onsumers know the underlying prodution ost. Using equation (13) and ρ = p gives us p = s + = s + (1 α) ( ) (1 α) + α p δ( p)d δ( p)d + α p δ( p)d. As δ( p)d = 1 and δ( p)d = E( p), we further have that the reservation prie is impliitly defined by ρ = p = E( p) + s 1 α. (16) Substituting (16) into (13), we arrive at the following result onerning the onditional expeted prie. The laim onerning the onditional expeted minimum prie is a little more diffiult to arrive at, but essentially follows from the fat that (1 λ)(e(p ) ) + λ(e(p l ) ) = (1 λ)(ρ ), (17) i.e., the sum of the expeted industry profits over shoppers and non-shoppers has to be equal to N times the expeted individual profit, whih equals (1 λ)(ρ ). Proposition 4 In any PBERP the onditionally expeted pries E(p ) and E(p l ) in a PBERP are given by E(p ) = + α s + α [E( p) ], (18) 1 α (1 λ) E(p l ) = + (s + (1 α)[e( p) ]. (19) λ From Proposition 4 it immediately follows that the unonditionally expeted pries E(p) and E(p l ) are given by E(p) = E() + α s + α [E( p) E()], (20) 1 α (1 λ) E(p l ) = E() + (s + (1 α)[e( p) E()]). (21) λ As α in (21) depends on N, the expeted minimum prie is now no longer independent of N as it was the ase under prodution ost ertainty. 19

Existene of PBERP. Having established some properties any PBERP should satisfy, we now disuss the existene question. Note that, so far, we have impliitly assumed that nonshoppers would like to buy at all pries below ρ. Although this is straightforward to establish when onsumers know the prodution ost, it is not obvious when they do not. For, onsumers update their beliefs about the true ost as they observe pries. In partiular, after observing a prie p < p() a onsumer may suddenly think that the ost is very low and thus may deide to ontinue searhing. Moreover, we need to verify that for all ost realizations firms find it optimal to set the pries impliitly speified above. In partiular, we need that p() > for all values of. Again, under prodution ost unertainty this ondition is not automatially satisfied as the reservation prie (and thereby the upper bound of the prie distribution) is independent of the ost realization. The next Proposition establishes a suffiient ondition for the existene of PBERP with nonstationary reservation pries. Rothshild (1974) already observed that if onsumers sample from an unknown distribution, it may happen that they prefer to buy at high pries, whereas they ontinue to searh (and do not buy) at lower pries. He also provides a suffiient ondition under whih it is optimal for a onsumer to atually follow a reservation prie strategy. The suffiient ondition he states is that the differene between any two pries should be smaller than the differene in informational ontent of these pries. Rothshild fouses, however, on the onsumer searh problem for a given (but unknown) prie distribution. We show that these onsiderations also arise in onsumer searh models where firms are strategially hoosing pries. Importantly, our suffiient ondition is in terms of the exogenous parameters of the model. Proposition 5 If then a unique PBERP exists. ( ) λn s, (22) λn + 1 λ 1 α The proof is based on the following onsiderations. We first show that observing a prie p with p() < p < ρ, an uninformed onsumer prefers to buy instead of ontinuing to searh and buy 20

in a later round. Note that at these pries, onsumers assign positive probability to any ost realization and by Lemma 2 beome more pessimisti about the possibility of finding lower pries when ontinuing to searh after observing suh a prie than before observing any prie. We then examine lower prie observations p < p(), where onsumers an rule out ertain high ost realizations. For a PBERP to exist, onsumers must still find it optimal to buy at suh pries. This, in turn, requires that onsumers do not infer from observing a prie p < p() that the ost is low enough so that ontinued searh pays off. To rule out this ase, we exploit the idea that a onsumer who finds it optimal to buy at a prie p if he knows the ost realization is, i.e. p ρ k (), ertainly has to find it optimal to buy in the unknown ost ase at the same prie. Consequently, by imposing p( ) ρ k () we an guarantee that a onsumer will find it optimal to buy at all prie observations smaller than the reservation prie ρ. This ondition translates into inequality (22) haraterizing the existene of a PBERP. Furthermore, inequality (22) also is suffiient to ensure that firms will set pries as speified above, i.e. p() > holds for all [, ]. Note that the existene ondition we impose bears no relation to the disussion on out-of-equilibrium beliefs. The pries in the middle range of the distributions are in the support of the equilibrium pries of the firms. The main question is whether onsumers prefer really to buy at these pries, or whether using Bayes rule they believe that osts may be quite low and would prefer to ontinue to searh. It is interesting to see when the ondition in Proposition 5 holds. Clearly, this is the ase when the support of the ost distribution is small or s is large. More interestingly, it is also the ase when N is large enough (for any given values of the other parameters). To see this, note that both λn λn+1 λ and α approah one as N approahes infinity; the RHS of inequality (22) therefore approahes infinity as well. Finally, note that when + Ns, a PBERP exists also for small values of λ. To arrive at this observation, we evaluate λn λn + 1 λ 1 1 1 1 0 dz 1+ λn zn 1 1 λ when λ is lose to zero. Applying l Hopital s Rule, we get that in a neighborhood of λ = 0 N (λn+1 λ) 2 10 Nz N 1 /(1 λ) 2 (1+ λn 1 λ zn 1 ) 2 dz = N 10 Nz N 1 dz = 1 10 z N 1 dz = N. 21

For λ lose to 0, the right hand side of our inequality is thus approximately equal to + Ns. We summarize our findings regarding the existene of PBERP in the following orollary: Corollary 4 A PBERP exists in environments with (i) a suffiiently small support of the ost distribution,, and/or (ii) suffiiently large searh osts s, and/or (iii) suffiiently many firms N, and/or (iv) a suffiiently small fration of shoppers λ, provided that + Ns holds. For general funtions g() the ondition established in Proposition 5 is almost neessary in the following sense. If p( ) > ρ k (), then one an onstrut a density funtion of the ost parameter, g(), that is onentrated on values lose to the two extremes and (see Figure 3) suh that, after observing a prie smaller than p( ), onsumers suddenly onsider it extremely likely that the ost is lose to. In partiular, if a prie observation p is in the interval (ρ k (), p( )) onsumers will then prefer to ontinue to searh. PUT FIGURE 3 APPROXIMATELY HERE One may then wonder whether, if we restrit the prior ost distribution, existene of a PBERP may always be guaranteed. Considering a uniform distribution of prodution osts, the next example demonstrates that this is not the ase. Figure 4 displays the net benefits of searh in a duopoly market with searh osts equal to s = 0.00675, a shopper-share equal to λ = 0.025, and prodution osts drawn from the uniform distribution U(0,1). PUT FIGURE 4 APPROXIMATELY HERE As an easily be seen, for this parameter onstellation no PBERP exists: the onsumer does not prefer to buy for all pries below the potential reservation prie defined by equation (16). 22

Whereas for pries between ρ = 1.0260 and p( ) = 1.0248 the onsumer stritly prefers to buy, when observing pries slightly below p( ), the net benefits of searh are inreasing rapidly. Indeed, the net searh benefits beome positive for an interval of pries a bit below p( ). The reason is that when the onsumer observes pries just below p( ), she infers that the expeted prodution ost is relatively low and so is the expeted prie. When she would observe even lower pries, the searh benefits inrease rapidly and it beomes profitable not to buy at the observed prie but to searh for a lower prie, even though the onsumer would have bought had she observed a slightly higher prie. In ase a PBERP does not exist, it is important to know what type of equilibrium does exist. Unfortunately, it turns out this is a very diffiult issue to resolve. For example, it an be shown that allowing for reservation pries whih are more general than the ones in Definition 1 does not overome the non-existene problem. Note that a more general reservation prie strategy is a strategy aording to whih onsumers buy if, and only if, they observe a prie at or below a ertain ut-off prie, but where onsumers are not indifferent between buying and ontinuing searhing at the reservation prie. As explained before, suh reservation pries ould be supported in our framework by speifying out-of-equilibrium beliefs in suh a way that after observing pries higher than the upper bound of the prie support (the reservation prie), onsumers believe that the underlying osts are very low and therefore stritly prefer to ontinue searhing. The next result establishes that there are parameter values for whih equilibria where onsumers follow suh strategies do not exist. Proposition 6 If s is relatively small or is relatively large and g() has a relatively high probability mass lose to, then an equilibrium where onsumers follow a reservation prie strategy does not exist. Together with the obvious fat that there annot be a hole in the prie distribution at whih the non-shoppers deide to buy with probability one, Proposition 6 implies that for some parameter values onsumers have to follow a mixed strategy in equilibrium. We leave it for further researh to fully haraterize these equilibria. 23

4 Welfare impliations and the impat of entry We are now ready to ompare the two models more formally. The most important basis for this omparison is the examination of the split of welfare between uninformed onsumers, informed onsumers and firms generated in the two models, and how this split of welfare depends on the number of firms in the industry. First, we assess the impat of prodution ost unertainty on (i) the ex ante expeted prie, (ii) the ex ante expeted lowest prie, (iii) the ex ante expeted prie spread, and (iv) the ex ante expeted profit of firms by omparing the two information senarios. Proposition 7 In the PBERP of the sequential searh model under prodution ost unertainty, the ex-ante expeted prie paid by non-shoppers, E(p), the ex-ante expeted prie paid by shoppers, E(p l ), the ex-ante expeted prie spread, E( p p), and the ex-ante expeted profit made by firms, are higher than in the known ost model. Consequently, onsumer surplus is lower and produer surplus is higher. Proposition 7 illustrates that onsumer welfare is higher when onsumers are informed about the firms prodution ost, suggesting that poliy interventions induing observability of prodution ost benefit onsumers. Note that this result is in ontrast with one of the findings in Benabou and Gertner (1993) where more unertainty in the market leads to inreased benefit of searh and thereby imposes a downward pressure on pries. The main reason for our result is the following. As uninformed onsumers update their beliefs about the underlying ost level upon observing the reservation prie, their ost expetation E( p) in the unknown ost ase is larger than the unonditional a priori expeted ost E() (whih is relevant in the known ost ase). The expeted pries in equations (20) and (21) are therefore larger than the ones in (9) and (10). By the same argument the ex-ante expeted prie spread under prodution ost unertainty, E( p p()), is larger than the ex-ante expeted prie spread if onsumers know the prodution ost, E( p k () p k ()). Yet, it is important to note that the ex ante variation of pries 24