A Stirling Encounter with Harmonic Numbers

Similar documents
Binomial transform of products

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 8 and 9 Principle of Inclusion and Exclusion Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 11 and 13, 2009

Math 4707 Spring 2018 (Darij Grinberg): midterm 2 page 1. Math 4707 Spring 2018 (Darij Grinberg): midterm 2 with solutions [preliminary version]

6.4 Binomial Coefficients

Math 475, Problem Set #12: Answers

Automated Proofs for Some Stirling Number Identities

Combinatorially Thinking

42 Dependence and Bases

Bertrand s postulate Chapter 2

CS 70 Second Midterm 7 April NAME (1 pt): SID (1 pt): TA (1 pt): Name of Neighbor to your left (1 pt): Name of Neighbor to your right (1 pt):

Infinite Sequences and Series

#A18 INTEGERS 11 (2011) THE (EXPONENTIAL) BIPARTITIONAL POLYNOMIALS AND POLYNOMIAL SEQUENCES OF TRINOMIAL TYPE: PART I

distinct distinct n k n k n! n n k k n 1 if k n, identical identical p j (k) p 0 if k > n n (k)

Double Derangement Permutations

Chapter 2. Asymptotic Notation

Generating Functions and Their Applications

CIS Spring 2018 (instructor Val Tannen)

Jacobi symbols. p 1. Note: The Jacobi symbol does not necessarily distinguish between quadratic residues and nonresidues. That is, we could have ( a

Lecture Overview. 2 Permutations and Combinations. n(n 1) (n (k 1)) = n(n 1) (n k + 1) =

COMP 2804 Solutions Assignment 1

Math 155 (Lecture 3)

Sequences of Definite Integrals, Factorials and Double Factorials

Combinatorial and Automated Proofs of Certain Identities

x !1! + 1!2!

MATH10040 Chapter 4: Sets, Functions and Counting

19.1 The dictionary problem

Complete Solutions to Supplementary Exercises on Infinite Series

Solutions to Final Exam

Permutations, Combinations, and the Binomial Theorem

NICK DUFRESNE. 1 1 p(x). To determine some formulas for the generating function of the Schröder numbers, r(x) = a(x) =

Math 2784 (or 2794W) University of Connecticut

2. F ; =(,1)F,1; +F,1;,1 is satised by thestirlig ubers of the rst kid ([1], p. 824). 3. F ; = F,1; + F,1;,1 is satised by the Stirlig ubers of the se

GROUPOID CARDINALITY AND EGYPTIAN FRACTIONS

SEQUENCES AND SERIES

A GENERALIZATION OF THE SYMMETRY BETWEEN COMPLETE AND ELEMENTARY SYMMETRIC FUNCTIONS. Mircea Merca

Name Period ALGEBRA II Chapter 1B and 2A Notes Solving Inequalities and Absolute Value / Numbers and Functions

The Hypergeometric Coupon Collection Problem and its Dual

On the Fibonacci-like Sequences of Higher Order

(A sequence also can be thought of as the list of function values attained for a function f :ℵ X, where f (n) = x n for n 1.) x 1 x N +k x N +4 x 3

Bernoulli Polynomials Talks given at LSBU, October and November 2015 Tony Forbes

6.3 Testing Series With Positive Terms

On Random Line Segments in the Unit Square

q-fibonacci polynomials and q-catalan numbers Johann Cigler [ ] (4) I don t know who has observed this well-known fact for the first time.

Generalized Fibonacci-Like Sequence and. Fibonacci Sequence

CHAPTER 10 INFINITE SEQUENCES AND SERIES

Sequences, Mathematical Induction, and Recursion. CSE 2353 Discrete Computational Structures Spring 2018

arxiv: v1 [math.fa] 3 Apr 2016

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 23 Mar 2016

Problem. Consider the sequence a j for j N defined by the recurrence a j+1 = 2a j + j for j > 0

1 (12 points) Red-Black trees and Red-Purple trees

Linear Regression Demystified

Answer Key, Problem Set 1, Written

1.2 AXIOMATIC APPROACH TO PROBABILITY AND PROPERTIES OF PROBABILITY MEASURE 1.2 AXIOMATIC APPROACH TO PROBABILITY AND

(1 x n ) 1, (1 + x n ). (1 + g n x n ) r n

Zeros of Polynomials

Commutativity in Permutation Groups

Some results on the Apostol-Bernoulli and Apostol-Euler polynomials

It is always the case that unions, intersections, complements, and set differences are preserved by the inverse image of a function.

Random Models. Tusheng Zhang. February 14, 2013

Section 5.1 The Basics of Counting

Chapter 7 COMBINATIONS AND PERMUTATIONS. where we have the specific formula for the binomial coefficients:

CERTAIN CONGRUENCES FOR HARMONIC NUMBERS Kotor, Montenegro

Chapter 0. Review of set theory. 0.1 Sets

Recurrence Relations

w (1) ˆx w (1) x (1) /ρ and w (2) ˆx w (2) x (2) /ρ.

JORGE LUIS AROCHA AND BERNARDO LLANO. Average atchig polyoial Cosider a siple graph G =(V E): Let M E a atchig of the graph G: If M is a atchig, the a

MT5821 Advanced Combinatorics

Recursive Algorithms. Recurrences. Recursive Algorithms Analysis

CHAPTER I: Vector Spaces

arxiv: v1 [math.nt] 10 Dec 2014

ECE Spring Prof. David R. Jackson ECE Dept. Notes 20

Randomized Algorithms I, Spring 2018, Department of Computer Science, University of Helsinki Homework 1: Solutions (Discussed January 25, 2018)

An Introduction to Randomized Algorithms

MAT1026 Calculus II Basic Convergence Tests for Series

The Boolean Ring of Intervals

CALCULATION OF FIBONACCI VECTORS

1. n! = n. tion. For example, (n+1)! working with factorials. = (n+1) n (n 1) 2 1

DIVISIBILITY PROPERTIES OF GENERALIZED FIBONACCI POLYNOMIALS

Lecture 10: Bounded Linear Operators and Orthogonality in Hilbert Spaces

A PROBABILITY PROBLEM

MA131 - Analysis 1. Workbook 3 Sequences II

SOME TRIBONACCI IDENTITIES

1 Counting and Stirling Numbers

3. Z Transform. Recall that the Fourier transform (FT) of a DT signal xn [ ] is ( ) [ ] = In order for the FT to exist in the finite magnitude sense,

The Binomial Theorem

P1 Chapter 8 :: Binomial Expansion

You may work in pairs or purely individually for this assignment.

Permutations & Combinations. Dr Patrick Chan. Multiplication / Addition Principle Inclusion-Exclusion Principle Permutation / Combination

(s)h(s) = K( s + 8 ) = 5 and one finite zero is located at z 1

A Pair of Operator Summation Formulas and Their Applications

Sequences A sequence of numbers is a function whose domain is the positive integers. We can see that the sequence

The Riemann Zeta Function

Part A, for both Section 200 and Section 501

X. Perturbation Theory

Observations on Derived K-Fibonacci and Derived K- Lucas Sequences

Theorem: Let A n n. In this case that A does reduce to I, we search for A 1 as the solution matrix X to the matrix equation A X = I i.e.

Some Basic Counting Techniques

If a subset E of R contains no open interval, is it of zero measure? For instance, is the set of irrationals in [0, 1] is of measure zero?

GENERALIZED HARMONIC NUMBER IDENTITIES AND A RELATED MATRIX REPRESENTATION

Legendre-Stirling Permutations

Transcription:

VOL 75, NO, APRIL 00 95 A Stirlig Ecouter with Haroic Nubers ARTHUR T BENJAMIN GREGORY O PRESTON Harvey Mudd College Clareot, CA 91711 bejai@hcedu gpresto@hcedu JENNIFER J QUINN Occidetal College 1600 Capus Road Los Ageles, CA 90041 jqui@oxyedu Haroic ubers are defied to be partial sus of the haroic series For 1, let H 1 + 1 + 1 3 + + 1 The first five haroic ubers are H 1 1, H 3/, H 3 11/6, H 4 5/1, H 5 137/60 For coveiece we defie H 0 0 Sice the haroic series diverges, H ca get arbitrarily large, although it does so quite slowly For istace, H 1,000,000 1439 Haroic ubers eve appear i real life If you stack -ich log playig cards to overhag the edge of a table as far as possible, the axiu distace that cards ca hag off the edge of the table is H [5] For exaple, 4 cards ca be stacked to exted past the table by just over iches, sice H 4 5/1 Haroic ubers satisfy ay iterestig properties For oegative itegers ad, we list soe idetities below: 1 k 1 k ( k 1 H k H (1) ( k ) H k ) 1 k ( )( H 1 ) () + 1 + 1 ( ) (H H ) (3) Although all of these idetities ca be proved by algebraic ethods (see [5]), the presece of bioial coefficiets suggests that these idetities ca also be proved cobiatorially A cobiatorial proof is a coutig questio, which whe aswered two differet ways, yields both sides of the idetity Cobiatorial proofs ofte provide ituitive ad cocrete explaatios where algebraic proofs ay ot For exaple 1 k k! 1 is a stadard exercise i atheatical iductio But to a cobiatorialist this idetity couts perutatios i two differet ways The right side couts the uber of ways

96 MATHEMATICS MAGAZINE to arrage the ubers 1 through, excludig the atural arrageet 1 3 The left side couts the sae quatity by coditioig o the first uber that is ot i its atural positio: for 1 k 1, how ay arrageets have k as the first uber to differ fro its atural positio? Such a arrageet begis as 1 3 k 1 followed by oe of k ubers fro the set { k + 1, k +,,} The reaiig k ubers (ow icludig the uber k) ca be arraged k! ways Thus there are k k! ways for k to be the first isplaced uber Suig over all feasible values of k yields the left side of the idetity Although H is ever a iteger for > 1[5], it ca be expressed as a ratioal uber whose uerator ad deoiator have cobiatorial sigificace Specifically, for 0 we ca always write H p as a (typically oreduced) fractio where p is a oegative iteger Now p 0 H 0 0 For 1, H H 1 + 1/ leads to Hece for 1, p p 1 ( 1)! + 1 p 1 + ( 1)! (4) p p 1 + ( 1)! (5) The cobiatorial iterpretatio of these ubers is the topic of the ext sectio Stirlig ubers For itegers k 1, let [ k] deote the uber of perutatios of eleets with exactly k cycles Equivaletly [ k] couts the uber of ways for distict people to sit aroud k idetical circular tables, where o tables are allowed to be epty [ k] is called the (usiged) Stirlig uber of the first kid As a exaple, [ 3 ] 3sice oe perso ust sit aloe at a table ad the other two have oe way to sit at the other table We deote these perutatios by (1)(3), (13)(),ad(1)(3) We ca copute the ubers [ k] recursively Fro their defiitio, we see that for 1, [ ] ( 1)!, 1 sice the arrageet (a 1 a a 3 a ) is the sae as arrageets (a a 3 a a 1 ) ad (a 3 a 4 a 1 a ) ad so o Now for k, we will see that [ ] [ ] [ + 1 + k k 1 k ] (6) O the left, we are directly coutig the uber of ways to seat + 1 people aroud k circular tables O the right we cout the sae thig while coditioig o what happes to perso + 1 If + 1 is to be aloe at a table, the the reaiig people ca be arraged aroud k 1tablesi [ k 1] ways If + 1 is ot to be aloe, the we first arrage 1 through aroud k tables (there are [ k] ways to do this); for each of these cofiguratios, we isert perso + 1 to the right of ay of the already-seated

VOL 75, NO, APRIL 00 97 people This gives us [ k] differet perutatios where + 1 is ot aloe Suig gives equatio (6) Notice that whe k, equatio (6) becoes [ ] [ ] + 1 + ( 1)!, (7) which is the sae as recurrece (5) with p [ ] +1 Sicep1 1 [ ], it follows that for all 1, p [ ] +1 Cobiig with the defiitio of p i (4) gives THEOREM 1 For 1, H 1 [ ] + 1 Next we show how to cout Theore 1 directly without relyig o a recurrece First we set soe otatioal covetios Let T deote the set of arrageets of the ubers 1 through ito two disjoit, oepty cycles Thus T [ ] We always write our cycles with the sallest eleet first, ad list the cycles i icreasig order accordig to the first eleet For exaple, T 9 icludes the perutatio (18574)(396), but ot (195)(487)(36) or (13)(4567)(8)(9) By our covetio, the cycle cotaiig 1 is always writte first; cosequetly we call it the left cycle The reaiig cycle is called the right cycle All perutatios i T are of the for (a 1 a a j )(a j+1 a ),where1 j 1, a 1 1, ad a j+1 is the sallest eleet of the right cycle For a purely cobiatorial proof of Theore 1 that does ot rely o a recursio, we ask, for 1 k, how ay perutatios of T +1 have exactly k eleets i the right cycle? To create such a perutatio, first choose k eleets fro {,, + 1} ( ( k) ways), arrage these eleets i the right cycle ((k 1)! ways), the arrage the reaiig k eleets i the left cycle followig the uber 1 (( k)! ways) Hece there are ( k) (k 1)! ( k)! /k perutatios of T+1 with k eleets i the right cycle Sice T +1 has [ +1 [ + 1 ] perutatios, it follows that ] k H, as desired Aother way to prove Theore 1 is to show that for r + 1, there are r 1 perutatios i T +1 that have r as the iiu eleet of the right cycle Here, the perutatios beig couted have the for (1 )(r ) where eleets 1 through r 1 all appear i the left cycle, ad eleets r + 1 through + 1 ca go i either cycle To cout this, arrage eleets 1 through r 1 ito the left cycle, listig eleet 1 first; there are (r )! ways to do this Place eleet r ito the right cycle Now we isert eleets r + 1 through + 1, oe at a tie, each iediately to the right of a already placed eleet I this way, eleets 1 ad r reai first (ad sallest) i their cycles Specifically, the eleet r + 1 ca go to the right of ay of the eleets 1 through rnext,r + ca go to the right of ay of the eleets 1 through r + 1 Cotiuig i this way, the uber of ways to isert eleets r + 1 through + 1isr(r + 1)(r + ) /(r 1)! This process creates a perutatio i T +1 with r as the sallest eleet i the right cycle Thus, there are (r )! (r 1)! r 1

98 MATHEMATICS MAGAZINE such perutatios Sice T +1 has [ ] +1 perutatios, ad every perutatio i T+1 ust have soe sallest iteger r i the right cycle, where r + 1, we get [ ] + 1 +1 r 1 1 k H r A alterate way to see that /(r 1) couts perutatios of the for (1 )(r ) is to list the ubers 1 through + 1 i ay order with the provisio that 1 be listed first There are ways to do this We the covert our list 1 a a 3 r a +1 to the perutatio (1 a a 3 )(r a +1 ) by isertig paretheses This perutatio satisfies our coditios if ad oly if the uber r is listed to the right of eleets, 3,,r 1 This has probability 1/(r 1) sice ay of the eleets, 3,,r have the sae chace of beig listed last aog the Hece the uber of perutatios that satisfy our coditios is /(r 1) Algebraic coectio The Stirlig ubers ca also be defied as coefficiets i the expasio of the risig factorial fuctio [3]: [ ] x(x + 1)(x + ) (x + 1) x (8) Usig this defiitio, Theore 1 ca be derived algebraically by coputig the x coefficiet of x(x + 1)(x + ) (x + ) To show that this algebraic defiitio of Stirlig ubers is equivalet to the cobiatorial defiitio, oe typically proves that both satisfy the sae iitial coditios ad recurrece relatio However, a ore direct correspodece exists [1], which we illustrate with a exaple By the algebraic defiitio, the Stirlig uber [ ] 10 3 is the coefficiet of x 3 i the expasio x(x + 1)(x + ) (x + 9) The cobiatorial defiitio says [ ] 10 3 couts the uber of ways that eleets 0, 1,,,9 ca sit aroud 3 idetical circular tables Why are these defiitios the sae? Each ter of the x 3 coefficiet is a product of seve ubers chose fro aog 1 through 9 Surely this ust be coutig soethig What is a ter like 1 3 5 6 8 9 coutig? As illustrated i FIGURE 1, this couts the uber of ways eleets 0 through 9 ca seat theselves aroud 3 idetical tables where the sallest eleets of the tables are the issig ubers 0, 4, ad 7 To see this, we pre-seat ubers 0, 4, 7the seat the reaiig ubers oe at a tie i icreasig order The uber 1 has just oe optio sit ext to 0 The uber the has two optios sit to the right of 0 or sit to the right of 1 The uber 3 ow has three optios sit to the right of 0 or 1 or The uber 4 is already seated Now uber 5 has five optios sit to the right of 0 or 1 or or 3 or 4, ad so o A geeral cobiatorial proof of equatio (8) ca also be doe by the precedig (or should that be pre-seatig?) arguet With this uderstadig of the iteractios betwee haroic ad Stirlig ubers, we ow provide cobiatorial explaatios of other haroic idetities 1 Recoutig haroic idetities I this sectio, we covert idetities (1), (), ad (3) ito stateets about Stirlig ubers ad explai the cobiatorially We view each idetity as a story of a coutig proble waitig to be told Each side of the idetity recouts the story i a differet, but accurate way Both of our cobiatorial proofs of Theore 1 were

VOL 75, NO, APRIL 00 99 Figure 1 How ay ways ca the ubers 1,, 3, 5, 6, 8, 9 seat theselves aroud these tables? obtaied by partitioig the set T+1 accordig to the size of the right cycle or the iiu eleet of the right cycle, respectively I what follows, we shall trasfor haroic equatios (1), () ad (3) ito three Stirlig uber idetities, each with o the left-had side The right-had sides will be cobiatorially explaied by partitioig T accordig to the locatio of eleet, the largest of the last t eleets, or the eighborhood of the eleets 1 through Our first idetity, after applyig Theore 1, ad re-idexig ( : 1) gives us I DENTITY 1 For ( )! k + 1 ( 1)! + k! To prove this cobiatorially, we ote that the left side of the idetity,, couts the uber of perutatios i T O the right, we kow fro our secod cobiatorial proof of Theore 1, that ( 1)! couts the uber of perutatios i T where the uber appears i the right cycle It reais to show that the suatio above couts the uber of perutatios i T where is i the left cycle Ay such perutatio has the for (1 a1 a a k b1 b b j 1 )(b j bk ), for soe 1 k ad 1 j k We assert that the uber of these perutatios with exactly k ters to the right of is give by the kth ter of the su

100 MATHEMATICS MAGAZINE To see this, select a 1, a,,a k fro the set {3,,} i ay of ( )! /k! ways Fro the uchose eleets, there are [ ] k+1 ways to create two oepty cycles of the for ( b 1 b j 1 )(b j b k ) where 1 j k Multiplyig the two couts gives the kth ter of the su as the uber of perutatios i T with exactly k ters to the right of, as was to be show We apply a differet cobiatorial strategy to prove the ore geeral equatio (), which, after applyig Theore 1 ad re-idexig ( : 1, : t 1, ad k : k ), gives us IDENTITY For 1 t 1 [ ] ( 1)! [ ] k 1 ( 1 t)! + t t (k 1 t)! kt+1 The cobiatorial proof of this idetity requires a ew iterpretatio of ( 1)! /t For 1 t 1, we defie the last t eleets of (1a a j )(a j+1 a ) to be the eleets a, a 1,a +1 t, eve if soe of the are i the left cycle For exaple, the last 5 eleets of (18574)(396) are6,9,3,4,ad7 We clai that for 1 t 1, the uber of perutatios i T where the largest of the last t eleets is aloe i the right cycle is ( 1)! /t Here, we are coutig perutatios of the for (1a a 1 )(a ),wherea is the largest of {a +1 t, a + t,,a 1, a } Aog all ( 1)! perutatios of this for, the largest of the last t eleets is equally likely to be aywhere aog the last t positios Hece ( 1)! /t of the have the largest of the last t eleets i the last positio Next we clai that for 1 t 1, the uber of perutatios i T where the largest of the last t eleets is ot aloe i the right cycle is the suatio i Idetity To see this, we cout the uber of such perutatios where the largest of the last t eleets is equal to k Sice the uber 1 is ot listed aog the last t eleets, we have t + 1 k To costruct such a perutatio, we begi by arragig ubers 1 through k 1 ito two cycles The isert the uber k to the right of ay of the last t eleets There are [ ] k 1 t ways to do this The right cycle cotais at least oe eleet less tha k, sok is ot aloe i the right cycle (ad could eve be i the left cycle) So that k reais the largest aog the last t eleets, we isert eleets k + 1 through, oe at a tie, to the right of ay but the last t eleets There are (k t)(k + 1 t) ( 1 t) ( 1 t)! /(k 1 t)! ways to do this Multiplyig the two couts give the kth ter of the su as the uber of perutatios where the largest of the last t eleets equals k, ad it is ot aloe i the right cycle; suig over all possible values of k, we cout all such perutatios Sice for ay perutatio i T, the largest of the last t eleets is either aloe i the last cycle, or it is t, ad this establishes Idetity Notice that whe t 1, Idetity siplifies to Idetity 1 Whe t 1, Idetity essetially siplifies to equatio (7) For our fial idetity, we covert equatio (3) to Stirlig ubers usig Theore 1 ad re-idexig ( : 1, : 1, ad k : t 1) This gives us IDENTITY 3 For 1 [ ] [ ] ( 1)! 1 ( 1)! + t ( t 1 1 ) ( 1)! ( )! ( t) To prove this idetity cobiatorially, we coditio o whether ubers 1 through all appear i the left cycle First we clai that for 1, the first ter o

VOL 75, NO, APRIL 00 101 the right i the idetity couts the uber of perutatios i T that do ot have eleets 1,, all i the left cycle: For these perutatios, the eleets 1 through ca be arraged ito two cycles i ways Isert the reaiig eleets + 1 through, oe at a tie, to the right of ay existig eleet, fidig that there are ( + 1) ( 1) ( 1)! /( 1)! ways to isert these eleets Multiplyig the two couts gives the first ter of the right-had side To coplete the proof, we ust show that the suatio o the right couts the uber of perutatios i T where eleets 1 through are all i the left cycle To see this, we clai that for t 1, the suad couts the perutatios described above with exactly t eleets i the left cycle ad t eleets i the right cycle To create such a perutatio, we first place the uber 1 at the frot of the left cycle Now choose 1 of the reaiig t 1 t 1 spots i the left cycle to be ways to select these 1 spots assiged the eleets {,, } There are 1 ad ( 1)! ways to arrage eleets,, 1 i those spots For exaple, to guaratee that eleets 1,, 3, 4 appear i the left cycle of F IGURE, we select three of the five ope spots i which to arrage, 3, 4 The isertio of 5, 6, 7, 8, 9 reais Now there are ( )! ways to arrage eleets + 1 through i the reaiig spots, but oly oe out of t of the will put the sallest eleet of the right cycle at the frot of the right cycle Hece, eleets + 1 through ca be arraged i ( )!/( t) legal ways Multiplyig gives the uber of ways to satisfy our coditios for a give t, ad the total is give by the desired suatio Figure I T9, a perutatio with 1,, 3, 4 i a left cycle cotaiig exactly six eleets is created by first selectig three of the five ope spots, ad the arragig, 3, 4 i the Subsequetly, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9 will be arraged i the reaiig spots We have already oted that haroic ubers arise i real life A further occurrece arises i calculatig the average uber of cycles i a perutatio of eleets Specifically, T HEOREM O average, a perutatio of eleets has H cycles There are perutatios of eleets, of which k have k cycles Cosequetly, Theore says k k H, or equivaletly, by Theore 1,

10 MATHEMATICS MAGAZINE IDENTITY 4 For 1, [ ] [ ] + 1 k k The left side couts the uber of perutatios of {1,,} with a arbitrary uber of cycles, where oe of the cycles is distiguished i soe way For exaple (184)(365)(79), (184)(365)(79), ad(184)(365)(79) are three differet arrageets with k 3 The right side couts the uber of perutatios of {0, 1,,} with exactly two cycles It reais to describe a oe-to-oe correspodece betwee these two sets of objects Ca you deduce the correspodece betwee the followig three exaples? ito (184)(365)(79) (079365)(184) (184)(365)(79) (079184)(365) (184)(365)(79) (0365184)(79) I geeral, we trasfor the perutatio with eleets (C k )(C k 1 ) (C j+1 )(C j )(C j 1 ) (C )(C 1 ) (0 C 1 C C j 1 C j+1 C k 1 C k )(C j ) The process is easily reversed Give (0 a 1 a j )(b 1 b j ) i T +1, the right cycle becoes the distiguished cycle (b 1 b j ) The distiguished cycle is the iserted aog the cycles C k 1,C, C 1, which are geerated oe at a tie as follows: C 1 (the rightost cycle) begis with a 1 followed by a ad so o util we ecouter a uber a i that is less tha a 1 Assuig such a a i exists (that is, a 1 1), begi cycle C with a i ad repeat the procedure, startig a ew cycle every tie we ecouter a ew sallest eleet The resultig cycles (after isertig the distiguished oe i its proper place) will be a perutatio of eleets writte i our stadard otatio Hece we have a oe-to-oe correspodece betwee the sets couted o both sides of Idetity 4 Notice that by distiguishig exactly of the cycles above, the procedure above ca be easily odified to prove the ore geeral k [ k ]( k ) [ + 1 + 1 Likewise by distiguishig a arbitrary uber of cycles, the sae kid of procedure results i [ ] k ( + 1)! k k0 ] Beyod haroic ubers We have oly scratched the surface of how cobiatorics ca offer ew isights about haroic ubers Other cobiatorial approaches to haroic idetities are preseted by Presto [6] We leave the reader with a challege: A hyperharoic uber

VOL 75, NO, APRIL 00 103 H (k) is defied as follows: Let H (1) H ad for k > 1, defie H (k) i1 H (k 1) i Now cosider the followig geeralizatio of idetity (1) fro The Book of Nubers by Coway ad Guy [4]: ( ) + k 1 H (k) (H +k 1 H k 1 ) k 1 Such a idetity strogly suggests that there ust be a cobiatorial iterpretatio of hyperharoic ubers as well Ad ideed there is oe [] You ca cout o it! Ackowledget We thak Michael Raugh, David Gaebler, Robert Gaebler, ad the referees for helpful coets, ad Greg Levi for the illustratios We are grateful to Jaet Myhre ad the Reed Istitute for Decisio Scieces for supportig this research REFERENCES 1 Robert Beals, persoal correspodece, 1986 Arthur T Bejai, David J Gaebler, ad Robert P Gaebler, A Cobiatorial Approach to Hyperharoic Nubers, preprit 3 Louis Cotet, Advaced Cobiatorics, D Reidel Publishig Copay, Bosto, 1974 4 Joh H Coway ad Richard K Guy, The Book of Nubers, Copericus, 1996 5 Roald L Graha, Doald E Kuth, ad Ore Patashik, Cocrete Matheatics, Addiso Wesley, 1993 6 Greg Presto, A Cobiatorial Approach to Haroic Nubers, Seior Thesis, Harvey Mudd College, Clareot, CA 001 Giraffes o the Iteret RICHARD SAMUELSON