Degree equatives: The same as comparatives?

Similar documents
Degree pluralities : distributive, cumulative and collective readings of comparatives

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 5)

Quantifiers in than-clauses

Homogeneity and Plurals: From the Strongest Meaning Hypothesis to Supervaluations

Boolean AND and the Semantic Correlates of Gradable Adjectives

Focus in complex noun phrases

Basics of conversational implicatures

An Alternative Semantics for English Aspectual Particles

Two Reconstruction Puzzles Yael Sharvit University of Connecticut

a. Rachel is {taller / more intelligent} than Stephanie (is). a. Rachel is the {tallest / most intelligent} (student in my class).

Quantifiers in Than-Clauses *

A New Account for too and either 1

Seminar in Semantics: Gradation & Modality Winter 2014

At most at last. Doris Penka Universität Konstanz

TOPICS IN DEGREE SEMANTICS: 4 LECTURES HANDOUT 1: DEGREES

UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Indefinites in Comparatives Aloni, M.D.; Roelofsen, F.

The Semantics of Questions Introductory remarks

Exhaustive interpretations: what to say and what not to say

FREE CHOICE IN MODAL CONTEXTS

list readings of conjoined singular which -phrases

Less. the set of degrees that satisfy y the set of degrees that satisfy f

Two Reconstruction Puzzles Yael Sharvit University of Connecticut

Gradable Adjectives, Compounded Scales, Conjunction and Structured Meanings

Predicative superlatives. 1 Superlatives can have a purely predicative construal

Plural Superlatives and Distributivity

PLURAL PREDICATION AND QUANTIFIED THAN -CLAUSES *

Economy and Embedded Exhaustification Danny Fox and Benjamin Spector

Comparative superlatives in relative clauses

Semantics I, Rutgers University Week 3-1 Yimei Xiang September 17, Predicate logic

Internal and Interval Semantics for CP-Comparatives

Spring 2018 Ling 620 Introduction to Semantics of Questions: Questions as Sets of Propositions (Hamblin 1973, Karttunen 1977)

Vacuous and Non-Vacuous Behaviors of the Present Tense

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

Two sets of alternatives for numerals

Introduction to Semantics. The Formalization of Meaning 1

Peter Hallman, University of Vienna

Introduction to Semantics. Pronouns and Variable Assignments. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

Spring 2017 Ling 620. An Introduction to the Semantics of Tense 1

Scalar additives and their interaction with focus

How to determine if a statement is true or false. Fuzzy logic deal with statements that are somewhat vague, such as: this paint is grey.

Comparatives and quantifiers

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 2: Quantificational DPs in Non-Subject Position and Pronominal Binding 1

Wh-islands in degree questions: A semantic approach

Antonymy and Evaluativity

DEGREE QUANTIFIERS, POSITION OF MERGER EFFECTS WITH THEIR RESTRICTORS, AND CONSERVATIVITY

Methodology and Statistics Laura Handojo. applied to Negative Polarity Items

FREE CHOICE AND EXHAUSTIFICATION: AN ACCOUNT OF

Model-theoretic Vagueness vs. Epistemic Vagueness

Global Approach to Scalar Implicatures in DRT*

ONLY: An NPI-licenser and NPI-unlicenser Yimei Xiang, Harvard University Accepted for publication in Journal of Semantics. (DOI: 10.

564 Lecture 25 Nov. 23, Continuing note on presuppositional vs. nonpresuppositional dets.

Pragmatic effects in processing superlative and comparative quantifiers: epistemic-algorithmic approach

Counterfactuals, Correlatives, and Disjunction.

Parasitic Scope (Barker 2007) Semantics Seminar 11/10/08

(6) Some students who drank beer or wine were allowed to drive.

Propositional Logic: Review

Two kinds of long-distance indefinites Bernhard Schwarz The University of Texas at Austin

1 Classical scalar implicature

Scalar Implicatures: Are There Any?

Presuppositions (introductory comments)

Bar-Hillel and the Division of Labor in Language

Cross-Polar Nomalies

Introduction to Pragmatics

Semantics 2 Part 1: Relative Clauses and Variables

Semantics and Generative Grammar. The Semantics of Adjectival Modification 1. (1) Our Current Assumptions Regarding Adjectives and Common Ns

An Alternatives-based Semantics for Dependent Plurals

QUANTIFICATIONAL READINGS OF INDEFINITES

Scales and comparison classes

The Blindness Hypothesis and Individual Level Predicates

Hamblin semantics for Japanese and German (Kratzer and Shimoyama) *

Continuations for Comparatives

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2010 Ling 720. The Basics of Plurals: Part 2 Distributivity and Indefinite Plurals

Exhaustively as Cell Identification

A Universal Scale of Comparison

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Pronouns and Variable Assignments 1. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

Focus Marking, Focus Interpretation & Focus Sensitivity. Malte Zimmermann & Daniel Hole ESSLI 2009, Bordeaux

Don t panic: The inverse reading of most conditionals

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Spring 2017 Ling 620 Eliminating Res-Movement : An Introduction to Concept Generators

Breaking de Morgan s law in counterfactual antecedents

Singleton Indefinites (re. Schwarzschild 2000)

Adjectives and Negation: deriving Contrariety from Contradiction

LIN1032 Formal Foundations for Linguistics

Little * Irene Heim Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Approaching the Logic of Conversational Implicatures

Solving the dilemma between uniqueness and mention some * Yimei Xiang. Harvard University

Other types of Movement

Spring 2017 Ling 620. The Semantics of Modals, Part 3: The Ordering Source 1

Karttunen Semantics. Last week. LING 147. Semantics of Questions Week 4 Yimei Xiang September 22, I. Intensionality

Punctual Until as a Scalar NPI

E-type interpretation without E-type pronoun: How Peirce s Graphs. capture the uniqueness implication of donkey sentences

Ellipsis, Parallelism, and Polarity

Negative Adjectives and Transformation Values

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2015 Ling 720 Adnominal Tenses Redux: Thomas (2014) Nominal Tense and Temporal Implicatures

Spring 2017 Ling 620. The Semantics of Modals, Part 2: The Modal Base 1

The Scalarity of Dou in Focus Structure 1. Liping Chen University of Pittsburgh

Grundlagenmodul Semantik All Exercises

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Basics of Intensional Semantics, Part 1: The Motivation for Intensions and How to Formalize Them 1

A compositional semantics for wh-ever free relatives 1 Aron Hirsch Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Berlin, May 16 / 2003

Transcription:

Degree equatives: The same as comparatives? Zukunftskolleg & Department of Linguistics Workshop Equative Constructions Unversität zu Köln 15 December 2016

Equatives in degree semantics Degree semantic accounts treat equatives in passing (von Stechow, 1984; Rullmann, 1995; Beck, 2011) Standard assumptions: The semantic composition (LF) of degree equatives is the same as for comparatives. The semantics (TC) of degree equatives differs only minimally from that of comparatives. (1) a. John is older than Mary. COMPARATIVE b. [ DegP -er [ than 1 Mary is t 1 -old ]] 2 John is t 2 -old ] LF c. John s age > Mary s age TC (2) a. John is as old as Mary. EQUATIVE b. [ DegP as [ as 1 Mary is t 1 -old ]] 2 John is t 2 -old ] LF c. John s age Mary s age TC

Plot of this talk The standard semantic analysis makes certain predictions that are adequate for degree equatives in English, but not for equatives in German (and many other European languages). This necessitates a different semantic analysis of equatives (at least) in German. Two different strategies cross-linguistically to express degree equatives

Overview 1 Introduction 2 Standard Analysis Syntax and semantics of degree equatives Prediction 1: Licensing of NPIs in the standard Prediction 2: Negative expressions in the standard 3 Towards an analysis Two different strategies cross-linguistically for equatives Equatives in German as correlative constructions 4 Explaining German equatives Non-licensing of NPIs in the standard Occurrence of negative expressions in the standard 5 Conclusion

Terminology I adopt the following terminology from Haspelmath and Buchholz (1998): (3) Mary is as old as comparee parameter marker standard marker Peter. standard

Ingredients of the standard analysis Semantics of gradable adjectives Gradable adjectives denote relations between individuals and degrees: (4) [[ old ]] = λx e.λd e. AGE(x) d This semantics makes gradable adjectives downward scalar predicates, i.e. they allow inferences from larger degrees to smaller ones. (5) Peter is 20 years old. Peter is 19 years old, Peter is 18 years old...

Ingredients of the standard analysis Syntax and LF of equatives The standard (+ standard marker) is analysed as elliptical clause with the standard marker being semantically vacuous. (6) Mary is as old [ as 1 Peter is t 1 old] The parameter marker is an operator that takes the standard clause as its first argument. (7) [as [as 1 Peter is t 1 old]] 2 [ Mary is t 2 old] LF

Ingredients of the standard analysis Semantics and pragmatics of equatives Semantically, the parameter marker is an operator (generalized quantifier over degrees) relating two sets of degrees. (8) [[ as ]] = λd 1<d,t>.λD 2<d,t>.max(D 2 ) max(d 1 ) (9) a. Mary is as old as Peter. b. [as [as 1 Peter is t 1 old]] 2 [ Mary is t 2 old] LF c. max{d: Mary is d-old} max{d: Peter is d-old} TC Mary s age Peter s age This at least-interpretation can be pragmatically strengthened to an exactly-reading by usual scalar implicatures (Horn, 1972).

Prediction 1 of the standard analysis Licensing of NPIs This semantics makes the standard of equatives a downward entailing context (just as the standard of comparatives). (10) D D [[ as ]](D)(P) = 1 (i.e. max(p) max(d)) [[ as ]](D )(P) = 1 (i.e. max(p) max(d )) Thus NPIs are predicted to be licensed in the standard of equatives (just as in comparatives). This prediction is borne out for equatives in English: (11) a. Paris is as quiet as ever. (from Seuren, 1984, 114) b. Two glasses was as much as I cared to drink. c. That was as much as he was willing to lift a finger to do. d. Jim is as competent as anybody here could possibly be.

Prediction 1 of the standard analysis Licensing of NPIs But in German, NPIs in are not licensed in the standard of equatives: (12) *Der Jemen ist so schön, wie ich jemals gedacht habe. the Yemen is so beautiful how I ever thought have (from Krifka, 1991, 155) (13) *Der Palast the palace kann. can ist is so gross wie sich irgendjemand vorstellen so big how REFL anybody imagine

Prediction 1 of the standard analysis Licensing of NPIs This contrasts with comparatives, in which NPIs are licensed in German: (14) Der Jemen ist schöner, als ich jemals gedacht habe. The Yemen is more beautiful than I have ever thought. (15) Der Palast ist grösser als sich irgendjemand vorstellen kann. The palace is bigger than anybody can imagine.

Prediction 2 of the standard analysis Negation in the standard Negation and negative expressions create upward scalar predicates, such that they allow inferences from smaller degrees to larger ones. (16) Nobody is 20 years old. Nobody is 19 years old, nobody is 18 years old... Nobody is 21 years old, nobody is 22 years old... Upward scalar predicates do not have a maximum. E.g.: max{d: nobody is d-old} is undefined The semantics of the equative operator thus predicts that negative expressions cannot occur in the standard (just as in the standard of comparatives).

Prediction 2 of the standard analysis Negation in the standard This prediction is borne out for equatives in English: (17) a. *John is as happy as never before. b. *Mary is as beautiful as no other girl I know. In German equatives, however, negative expressions can occur in the standard: (18) Helena ist so schön wie keine andere (Frau). Helena is so beautiful how no other (woman) Helena is more beautiful than any other woman. This contrasts again with comparatives: (19) *Helena ist schöner als keine andere (Frau). Helena is more-beautiful than no other (woman)

Prediction 2 of the standard analysis Negation in the standard Under the standard analysis it is not possible to derive the correct interpretation of equatives with negative expressions in the standard. (20) Peter ist so alt wie kein anderer (in seiner Klasse). Peter is so old how no other (in his class) Peter is older than anyone else (in his class). (21) a. [as [as 1 nobody is t 1 old]] 2 [ Peter is t 2 old] LF1 b. max{d: nobody is d-old} is undefined! (22) a. nobody 3 [as [as 1 t 3 is t 1 old]] 2 [ Peter is t 2 old] LF2 b. x[max{d : Peter is d-old} max{d : x is d-old}] x[age(peter) AGE(x)] Peter is the youngest.

Cross-linguistic picture The operator analysis of degree equatives makes adequate predictions for English regarding the licensing of NPIs and the non-occurrence of negative expressions in the standard. These predictions are, however, not adequate for German, where negative expressions can occur in the standard and NPIs are not licensed. German equatives are by no means exceptional in exhibiting these properties. Many other European languages pattern with German in allowing negative expressions in the standard of equatives and disallowing NPIs (Krasikova and Penka, 2012).

Cross-linguistic picture These languages use a degree demonstrative as parameter marker and a degree interrogative pronoun as standard marker. (23) Mary ist so gross wie Peter. Mary is so tall how Peter (24) Peter ist so gross. Peter is that tall. (25) Wie gross ist Peter? How tall is Peter? (26) Gianni è alto (così) tanto quanto Maria. Gianni is tall so so-much how-much Maria (27) Helen jest tak wysoka jak Maria. Helen is so tall how Maria EQUATIVE DEGREE DEMONSTRATIVE DEGREE INTERROGATIVE Italian Polish

Equatives as correlative constructions In these constructions, the parameter marker is an adverbial demonstrative pronoun and the standard marker is an adverbial relative pronoun that is generally based on an interrogative pronoun. [... ] Such correlative equative constructions are clearly based on correlative free relative clauses. (Haspelmath and Buchholz, 1998, 288)

Equatives as correlative constructions Idea: Take this parallel between equatives and correlatives at face value and analyse correlative equative constructions in analogy to other correlative constructions (Dayal, 1995; Brasoveanu, 2012). The correlative clause corresponds to a free relative clause and is interpreted as a definite description. This definite description is cataphorically picked up by the demonstrative pronoun in argument position.

Semantics of free relative clauses Free relative clauses are interpreted as definite descriptions (Rullmann, 1995; Dayal, 1995; Jacobson, 1995). Definites are interpreted as denoting the maximally informative object that falls under the relevant predicate (von Fintel et al., 2014). The maximally informative object is the one that creates the most informative true proposition. The most informative proposition is defined as the proposition that entails all other relevant propositions. With downward scalar predicates, the maximally informative degree corresponds to the maximal degree of which the predicate holds. (28) MAX inf (λd. Peter is d-old) = AGE(Peter)

Semantics of correlative equatives German so is a degree demonstrative that refers to a contextually given degree (Beck, 2012). (29) Paul ist 20 Jahre alt. Peter ist auch so alt. Paul is 20 years old. Peter is also that old. In correlative equative constructions, so picks up the referent of the definite description denoted by the free relative clause. This serves as the degree argument of the adjective. (30) Peter ist so 2 alt [MAX inf [ wie 1 Paul t 1 alt ist ]] 2 [ λd. Paul is d-old ] AGE(Paul ) [[ old ]](Peter)(AGE(Paul)) AGE(Peter) AGE(Paul)

Explaining the non-licensing of NPIs NPIs are not licensed in free relatives (Jacobson, 1995). (31) *I can read whatever Bill ever read. Thus, if the standards of an equative is a free relative clause, we do not expect NPIs to be licensed there.

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Restrictions on negative expressions in the standard In itself, the correlative analysis does not explain the occurrence of negative expressions in the standard. In particular, we cannot assume that MAX inf applied to an upward scalar predicate yields the minimal degree of which the predicate holds. Not all kinds of negative expressions can occur in the standard. (32) *Peter ist so alt wie Paul nicht. Peter is so old how Paul not (33) Peter ist so gross wie Paul klein ist. Peter is so tall how Paul short is * Peter is taller than Paul. Peter is as tall as Paul is short. (deviation from standard)

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Restrictions on negative expressions in the standard The presence (or implicit understanding) of certain modifiers is crucial for the acceptability of negative expressions in the standard. (34) *Diesen this Winter winter (35) Diesen Winter this winter nicht mehr. not anymore. gab es so viel Schnee wie letztes Jahr nicht. gave it so much snow how last year not. gab es so viel Schnee wie seit 20 Jahren gave it so much snow how since 20 years The amount of snow this winter equals the amount of snow we last had 20 years ago.

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Restrictions on negative expressions in the standard (36)?? Peter ist so alt wie keiner. Peter is so old how none (37) Peter ist so alt wie kein anderer (in seiner Klasse). Peter is so old how no other (in his class) Peter is older than anyone else (in his class).

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Contribution of mehr anymore The aspectual particle mehr anymore adds the presupposition that the predicate was true at a previous time. (38) a. Chiara wohnt nicht mehr in Köln. Chiara doesn t live in Cologne anymore. b. Wohnt Chiara nicht mehr in Köln? Does Chiara not live in Cologne anymore? c. Es ist möglich, dass Chiara nicht mehr in Köln wohnt. It is possible that Chiara doesn t live in Cologne anymore. (39) Pressupposition: There is a time preceding the speech time at which Chiara lived in Cologne.

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Contribution of mehr anymore (40) [[ wie 1 es seit 20 Jahren nicht mehr t 1 viel Schnee gab ]]= the set of degrees d such that: (i) there is a time preceding the speech time by 20 years at which there was d-much snow; PRESUPPOSITION (ii) there is no time preceding the speech time by less than 20 years at which there was d-much snow TC MAX inf [[ wie 1 es seit 20 Jahren nicht mehr t 1 viel Schnee gab ]] is only defined if there is a degree fulfilling conditions (40-i) and (40-ii). If defined, MAX inf [[ wie 1 es seit 20 Jahren nicht mehr t 1 viel Schnee gab ]] yields the amount of snow 20 years ago.

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Contribution of mehr anymore (41) Diesen Winter this winter nicht mehr. not anymore. gab es so viel Schnee wie seit 20 Jahren gave it so much snow how since 20 years The amount of snow this winter equals the amount of snow we last had 20 years ago. Sentence (41) is true if The amount of snow during the last 19 years does not meet or exceed the amount 20 years ago. PRESUPPOSITION The amount of snow this year is greater or equal to the amount of snow 20 years ago. TC

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Contribution of the exceptive phrase Exceptive phrases such as except for x, but x, other than x trigger the implicature that x is the only exception (von Fintel, 1993; Gajewski, 2008). (42) No student other than Fred attended the talk. Fred is the only student who attended the talk. Fred attended the talk. (43) [[ wie 1 kein anderer als Peter t 1 alt ist ]]= the set of degrees d such that: (i) nobody different from Peter is d-old; (ii) Peter is d-old TC IMPLICATURE

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Contribution of the exceptive phrase (44) Peter ist so alt wie kein anderer (in seiner Klasse). Peter is so old how no other (in his class) Peter is older than anyone else (in his class). MAX inf [[ wie 1 kein anderer als Peter t 1 alt ist ]] is only defined if there is a degree such that (i) nobody different from Peter is d-old; (ii) Peter is d-old TC IMPLICATURE If defined, MAX inf [[ wie 1 kein anderer als Peter t 1 alt ist ]] yields Peter s age. Sentence (44) is true if Nobody meets or exceeds Peter in terms of age. PRESUP. Peter s age is greater or equal to Peter s age. TC

Explaining the occurrence of negative expressions Difference between correlative and operator analysis In general, the modifier phrases have the effect of making the degree predicate doubly bound, i.e. the corresponding set of degrees has a minimum as well as a maximum. This raises the question why the presence of mehr anymore and exceptive phrases rescues negative expressions under the correlative analysis, but not under the operator analysis. Tentative answer: MAX inf takes into account non-truth conditional restrictions (presuppositions, implicatures), while the max-operator does not.

Conclusion Cross-linguistically, there seem to be two different strategies to form degree equatives. The first strategy, represented by English, employs an equative operator parallel to the comparative operator. According to the second strategy, represented by German, equatives are correlative constructions. The standard clause denotes a definite degree, which is picked up by a degree demonstrative in the matrix clause. The strategy employed by a language has consequences for the possibility of NPIs and negative expressions in the standard.

References I Beck, Sigrid (2011), Comparison constructions, in K.von Heusinger, C.Maienborn and P.Portner, eds, Semantics (HSK 33.2), de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, pp. 1341 1390. Beck, Sigrid (2012), DegP scope revisited, Natural Language Semantics 20, 227 272. Brasoveanu, Adrian (2012), Correlatives, Language and Linguistics Compass 6(1), 1 20. Dayal, Veneeta (1995), Quantification in correlatives, in E.Bach, E.Jelinek, A.Kratzer and B.Partee, eds, Quantification in Natural Languages, Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 179 205. Gajewski, Jon (2008), NPI any and connected exceptive phrases, Natural Language Semantics. Haspelmath, Martin and Oda Buchholz (1998), Equative and similative constructions in the languages of Europe, in J.van der Auwera, ed., Adverbial constructions in the languages of Europe, Mouton De Gruyter, pp. 277 334. Horn, Laurence R. (1972), On the Semantic Properties of Logical Operators in English, PhD thesis, UCLA. Jacobson, Pauline (1995), On the quantificational force of free relatives, in E.Bach, E.Jelinek, A.Kratzer and B.Partee, eds, Quantification in Natural Languages, Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 451 486. Krasikova, Sveta and (2012), A cross-linguistic perspective on the semantics of equatives. Talk presented in the SemPrag Forschungskolloquium, Universität Konstanz. Krifka, Manfred (1991), Some remarks on polarity items, in D.Zaefferer, ed., Semantic universals and universal semantics, de Gruyter, pp. 150 189.

References II Rullmann, Hotze (1995), Maximality in the Semantics of wh-constructions, PhD thesis, University of Massachusetts at Amherst. Seuren, Pieter A. M. (1984), The comparative revisited, Journal of Semantics 3, 109 141. von Fintel, Kai (1993), Exceptive constructions, Natural Language Semantics 1, 123 148. von Fintel, Kai, Danny Fox and Sabine Iatridou (2014), Definiteness as maximal informativeness, in L.Crnic and U.Sauerland, eds, The Art and Craft of Semantics: A Festschrift for Irene Heim, Vol. 1, MITWPL 70, pp. 165 174. von Stechow, Arnim (1984), Comparing semantic theories of comparison, Journal of Semantics 3, 1 77.