Presuppositions (introductory comments)

Similar documents
Must... stay... strong!

Introduction to Pragmatics

Spring 2018 Ling 620 Introduction to Semantics of Questions: Questions as Sets of Propositions (Hamblin 1973, Karttunen 1977)

Matthew Mandelkern and Daniel Rothschild January 24, 2018

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Basics of Intensional Semantics, Part 1: The Motivation for Intensions and How to Formalize Them 1

Homogeneity and Plurals: From the Strongest Meaning Hypothesis to Supervaluations

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Indicative conditionals

The Semantics of Questions Introductory remarks

Matthew Mandelkern and Daniel Rothschild May 29, 2018

First-Degree Entailment

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 5)

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

Spring 2017 Ling 620. The Semantics of Modals, Part 3: The Ordering Source 1

Global Approach to Scalar Implicatures in DRT*

Semantics and Generative Grammar. An Introduction to Intensional Semantics 1

The Semantics of Definite DPs 1. b. Argument Position: (i) [ A politician ] arrived from Washington. (ii) Joe likes [ the politician ].

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

To every formula scheme there corresponds a property of R. This relationship helps one to understand the logic being studied.

(1) If Bush had not won the last election, then Nader would have won it.

Introduction to Semantics. The Formalization of Meaning 1

A modal analysis of presupposition and modal subordination

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 1

1 Classical scalar implicature

We have seen that the symbols,,, and can guide the logical

Mathematical Logic Prof. Arindama Singh Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 15 Propositional Calculus (PC)

CS70 is a course about on Discrete Mathematics for Computer Scientists. The purpose of the course is to teach you about:

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2012 Vazirani Note 1

Generalized Quantifiers Logical and Linguistic Aspects

Strengthening Principles and Counterfactual Semantics

Ling 130 Notes: Syntax and Semantics of Propositional Logic

Lecture 7. Logic. Section1: Statement Logic.

Introduction to Semantics. Pronouns and Variable Assignments. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

Berlin, May 16 / 2003

6.080 / Great Ideas in Theoretical Computer Science Spring 2008

The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern AAL/ALC Modal 2011 Logic 1 / 26

Truth-Functional Logic

1 Propositional Logic

Basics of conversational implicatures

cis32-ai lecture # 18 mon-3-apr-2006

Exhaustive interpretations: what to say and what not to say

Intensional semantics: worlds, modals, conditionals

Axiomatic systems. Revisiting the rules of inference. Example: A theorem and its proof in an abstract axiomatic system:

Algebra Exam. Solutions and Grading Guide

Presupposition and Montague Grammar (Krahmer 1998, Ch. 5)

Semantics and Generative Grammar. The Semantics of Adjectival Modification 1. (1) Our Current Assumptions Regarding Adjectives and Common Ns

Philosophy 244: Modal Logic Preliminaries

CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Propositional Logic I. Knowledge-based Agents

Knowledge-based Agents. CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Propositional Logic I. Knowledge-based Agents. Outline. Knowledge-based Agents

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

A Little Deductive Logic

Structural Induction

CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

CS 2800: Logic and Computation Fall 2010 (Lecture 13)

What if Every "If Only" Statement Were True?: The Logic of Counterfactuals

A Little Deductive Logic

Lecture 4: Proposition, Connectives and Truth Tables

Computability Crib Sheet

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Semantics of Modals, Part 1: Basics of the Quantificational Analysis, and the Appearance of Ambiguity 1

Spring 2017 Ling 620. An Introduction to the Semantics of Tense 1

HOW TO CREATE A PROOF. Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating

Singleton Indefinites (re. Schwarzschild 2000)

How to write maths (well)

Guide to Proofs on Discrete Structures

MATH 22 INFERENCE & QUANTIFICATION. Lecture F: 9/18/2003

Paucity, abundance, and the theory of number: Online Appendices

Predicates, Quantifiers and Nested Quantifiers

Hamblin Semantics & Focus

CS280, Spring 2004: Final

Choosing Logical Connectives

Chapter 26: Comparing Counts (Chi Square)

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

8. Reductio ad absurdum

Logic I - Session 10 Thursday, October 15,

Two sets of alternatives for numerals

Bar-Hillel and the Division of Labor in Language

564 Lecture 25 Nov. 23, Continuing note on presuppositional vs. nonpresuppositional dets.

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Pronouns and Variable Assignments 1. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

Natural deduction for truth-functional logic

Intermediate Logic. Natural Deduction for TFL

Alternative Notations and Connectives

Deriving indirectness and questioning entailment for epistemic must 1

A Weakness for Donkeys

173 Logic and Prolog 2013 With Answers and FFQ

Propositional Logic Review

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

First Order Logic: Syntax and Semantics

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models

Solution to Proof Questions from September 1st

Antecedents of counterfactuals violate de Morgan s law

8. Reductio ad absurdum

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities

CS1800: Strong Induction. Professor Kevin Gold

Mathematical Logic Part One

Description Logics. Deduction in Propositional Logic. franconi. Enrico Franconi

Vacuous and Non-Vacuous Behaviors of the Present Tense

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Handout on Logic, Axiomatic Methods, and Proofs MATH Spring David C. Royster UNC Charlotte

base 2 4 The EXPONENT tells you how many times to write the base as a factor. Evaluate the following expressions in standard notation.

Transcription:

1 Presuppositions (introductory comments) Some examples (1) a. The person who broke the typewriter was Sam. b. It was Sam who broke the typewriter. c. John screwed up again. d. John likes Mary, too. e. John realizes that he screwed up. 1. Identifying Presuppositions (2) The person who broke the typewriter was Sam. Sentence (2) seems to entail the following sentences: (3) a. Someone broke the typewriter. b. Only one person broke the typewriter. c. Sam broke the typewriter. However, different feelings are associated with the different entailments. In particular (3)a and (3)b feel somewhat different from (3)c. But, how so? There is a clear feeling (it is said) that in an ideal or proper conversation, (3)a and (3)b would already be taken for granted at the point in which (2) is uttered, and that (3)c would be taken to be the noteworthy piece of the conversation. (4) We say that sentence, S, presupposes p if p is taken for granted in every ideal conversation before S is uttered. Major methodological problem: is it clear that we have reliable intuitions about how things work in an ideal conversation, given that so many of our conversations are far from ideal (i.e., require presupposition accommodation )? (5) I am asked by someone who I have just met, Are you going to lunch? I reply, No, I ve got to pick up my sister. Here I seem to presuppose that I have a sister, even though I do not assume that the addressee knows this. (Stalnaker 1974, for very useful discussion, see von Fintel 2000) How can we justify Stalnaker s intuition about what he seems to presuppose. Two fortunate facts: a. There are a few tests that allow us to identify presuppositions (with no reliance on our theoretical intuitions about the nature of ideal conversations). b. Presuppositions have characteristic projection properties.

2 2. Two Tests (from Kai s class notes) 2.1. Hey, wait a minute! (von Fintel, crediting Shanon for the inspiration) (6) The person who broke the typewriter was Sam. a. Hey wait a minute, I didn t know that someone broke the typewriter. b. #Hey wait a minute, I didn t know that Sam broke anything. (7) At 5 PM, John screwed up again. a. Hey wait a minute, I didn t know that he screwed up before. b. #Hey wait a minute, I didn t know that he messed up at 5 PM. If p is a presupposition of S, HWM, I didn t know that p is a good response to an utterance of S. If p is an entailment of S which is not a presupposition (or entailed by a presupposition), HWM, I didn t know that p is a bad response to an utterance of S. Possible Explanation: Although presupposition accommodation is possible. It is something that we do out of our good nature when the presupposition is not controversial. But sometimes we might want to object and natural language has a construction specialized for this purpose. Problem: As pointed out by Ofra, we can object to aspects of the assertion other than the presupposition with HWM: (8) All of the students were at the party Hey wait a minute, I didn t (even) know that SOME of the students were at the party. So, if there is a test for presuppositions here, it is rather subtle 2.2. What s more! Furthermore ( Percus 1998 lecture notes) (9) A. Sam broke a typewriter. B. #Yes, and furthermore, the person who broke a typewriter is Sam. B. Yes, and furthermore, Only Sam broke a typewriter. If p is a presupposition of S and what we can infer from S is equivalent to p and S', yes, and what s more S (or yes, furthermore S) is a bad response to an utterance of S'. In other words: what s more S is bad if only the presupposed part of S is new in the context. Explanation: The presupposition of every assertion must in principle be satisfied in the context. (In other words, every conversation is not that different from our idealization.)

3 But there is this process of presupposition accommodation. Before we evaluate the sentence we might accommodate the presupposition, and then evaluate the sentence. What goes wrong with the bad what s more sentences is that after accommodation, the sentence provides no new information. And a what s more sentence must provide new information. 3. An Empirical Claim and a Theoretical Challenge (10) We say that a sentence S presupposes p, if a. p is taken for granted in every utterance of S (as diagnosed by HWM, WM ) b. p has special projection properties (to be specified). Empirical Claim: If p is an entailment of S, p satisfied (a) iff p satisfied (b) (Our two tests for presuppositions coincide.) Challenge: To understand why the empirical claim might be right. In other words, to understand: a. What type of grammatical representation for S (together with principles of language use) leads to the pragmatic fact that p is taken for granted. b. To understand how the grammatical representation of S (together with principles of language use) leads to the particular projection properties we will identify. 4. Stalanaker s Strategy (11) We say that a sentence S semantically presupposes p, if the denotation of S is a partial function, which is undefined in a world w, unless p is true in w. Every conversational context could be said to be based on a set of shared presuppositions (Common Ground, CG), which could be characterized (with many idealizations) as a set of possible worlds (Context Set, CS; henceforth, simply C). The reason we utter a sentence S is to add its content to CG. This fails unless the presuppositions of S are true in every world in C. (12) CCP(S p ) = λc:c p.c {w: S'(w)=1} Stalnaker asks us to imagine a procedure that for every world in C, w, needs to decide whether w stays in the updated context or not. If S' is false in w, the answer is no, if S' is true in w, the answer is yes. If S' is undefined in w, the procedure fails. Does this help us in any way in the projection problem? 4.1. Negation, a semantic approach (from Heim and Kratzer, similar to what is assumed in Gazdar)

4 (13) neg' = λp t. p = 0 Which is shorthand for: (14) neg' = λp: p {0,1}. p = 0 which is the same as: 1 if t =0 (15) neg' = λt. 0 if t =1 Undefined, otherwise (16) John doesn t admire the king of France. λw: there is a unique KoF in w. John doesn t admires the KoF Hence negation is a hole (Karttunen s terminology) (17)A function f st, st is: a. a hole if for all X that presupposes p (for all X p ), f(x) presupposes p. b. a filter if for all X p, f(x) presupposes q, and q p. c. a plug if for all X p, f(x) presupposes nothing. Generalizes in the standard way to n place relations that take a proposition in the n th position. 4.2. Conjunction, a pragmatic approach (Stalnaker) (18) and' = λt 1. λt 2. t 1 = t 2 =1 Conjunction should be a hole too, but it s a filter: (19) Moldavia is a monarchy and the King of Moldavia is powerful. λw: there is a unique KoM. Moldavia is a monarchy and the KoM is powerful. Stalnaker, the two sentences are parsed one at a time (a matter of language use): Once a proposition has been asserted in a conversation, then (unless or until it is challenged) the speaker can reasonably take it for granted for the rest of the conversation, In particular, when a speaker says something of the form A and B, he may take it for granted that A (or at least that his audience recognizes that he accepts that A) after he has said it. The proposition that A will be added to the background of common assumptions before the speaker asserts that B. Now suppose that B expresses a proposition that would, for some reason, be inappropriate to assert except in a context where A, or something entailed by A, is presupposed. Even if A is not presupposed initially, one may still assert A and B since by the time one gets to saying that B, the context has shifted, and it is by then

5 presupposed that A. But. How general is this? 1. Problems with other connectives where it is less obvious how a statement about the order of assertion might be useful. (20) Either this house has no bathroom or the bathroom is well hidden. (21) If Moldavia is a Monarchy, the king is not particularly noticeable. 3. Embedding (22) a. I have never met an academic who was an idiot and who knew that he was an idiot. (Schlenker) b. I never heard of a monarchy in which the king was bald. Cf. I never heard of a country in which the king was bald 5. The Heim/Kartunnen Strategy (Heim 1983) Adopt Stalnaker s basic intuition but introduce it into the grammar. More specifically, replace denotations we are accustomed to with CCPs C + S is Heim s notation for CCP(S)(C) For atomic sentences, we assume lexical specification of presuppositions, e.g., by partial functions: (23) C + S{p} is defined iff C p, when defined C + S{p} = C {w: S'(w)=1} For complex sentences: (24) a. C + not A = C [C + A] b. C + [A & B] = [C + A] + B c. C + [If A, then B] = C + [not [A & not B]] = C [C + [A & not B]] = C [[C + A ] + not B] = C ([C + A ] [[C + A] +B]) There s more to which we will probably return. Still need to discuss: a. the CCP of quantifiers, b. accommodation strategies and the way they might relate to CCPs (local vs. global accommodation).

6 6. Still not understood (Soames 1984, Rooth cited in Heim 1990): E.g., why not the following? (25) a. C + not A = C [W + A] b1. C + [A & B] = [C + B] + A b2. C + [A & B] = [C + B] [C + A] c. C + [If A, then B] = [C [C + A]] [C + B], and more So, we have a way of stating the projection properties of various connectives within Heim s framework. But we can t predict the projection properties from the classical meanings of the connectives. Is it reasonable to hope that we would be able to predict projection properties from the basic meanings of the connectives? 7. Peters (1979) Strategy Various people, starting, I think, with van Fraassen, have tried to deal with presupposition projection using tools from tri-valiant logical systems. Karttunen, who is responsible for all of the generalizations we are trying to capture, argued that they can t be captured by the tri-valiant systems. Peters aim was to show that this is false. Basic machinery: add a third member to D t, and revise the truth functional lexical entries appropriately. (26) D t = {1, 0, #} (27) and(p)( q) = 1, if p = q = 1 = 0, if p = 0 or [(p = 1) & (q =0)] = #, if p = # or [(p = 1) & (q =#)] p q q 1 0 # p 1 1 0 # 0 0 0 0 # # # # This, in conjunction with Stalnaker s assertability condition, yields more or less correct results: (28) Stalnaker s Assertability Condition: A sentence S is assertable in a context C only if w C[S(w) #) But aren t the truth tables just as stipulative as Heim s lexical entries?

7 6. Trivalent system in the post Schlenker era: Strong Kleene: (29) and(p)( q) = 1, if p = q = 1 = 0, if p = 0 or [(q =0)] = #, otherwise p q q 1 0 # p 1 1 0 # 0 0 0 0 # # 0 # Intuition: imagine that the system is 2 valued, and that # stands either for 1 or 0, but that you don t know which. If you can figure out the value for the whole sentence, ignoring #, you have it. Otherwise, the value is #. A rule (for a propositional logic): Suppose you encounter a node, X, of type t with semantic value #. Look at the first node of type t above X, Y, If you can figure out the value for Y, ignoring X, you have it. That is to say, if the truth value for Y is the same in a two valued system when you replace the value of X with 0 or 1, the value of node Y is whatever that truth value is. Otherwise, the value of Y is #. Peter s Intuition (hinted at in Beaver and Krahmer): Imagine that the system is 2 valued, and that # stands either for 1 or 0, but that you don t know which. If you can figure out the value for the whole sentence, ignoring # and everything that follows it, you have it. Otherwise, the value is #. A rule (for a propositional logic): Suppose you encounter a node, X, of type t with semantic value #. Look at the first node of type t above X, Y. If you can figure out the value for Y, based on material pronounced before X, you have it. That is to say, if the truth value for Y is the same in a two valued system when you replace the value of X and every node (of type t) in Y pronounced after X with 0 or 1, the value of node is whatever that truth value is. Otherwise, the value of Y is #. Homework: construct lexical entries for or and if then, guided by the Strong Kleene and the Peters intuition as it was stated above.

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.954 Pragmatics in Linguistic Theory Spring 2010 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.