Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Similar documents
Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Choice under uncertainty

Preference, Choice and Utility

Choice under Uncertainty

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

Expected Utility Framework

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World

Rationality and Uncertainty

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009

Uncertainty & Decision

Preference and Utility

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1

Second-Order Expected Utility

Allais Paradox. The set of prizes is X = {$0, $1, 000, 000, $5, 000, 000}.

Quantum Decision Theory

Week of May 5, lecture 1: Expected utility theory

Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility. Pavlo R. Blavatskyy

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness

14.12 Game Theory Lecture Notes Theory of Choice

A Theory of Subjective Compound Lotteries

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Maxmin expected utility as resulting from information on others preferences

September 2007, France

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization

The Expected Utility Model

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

MATH 446/546 Homework 2: Due October 8th, 2014

Axiomatic Decision Theory

Coherent Choice Functions Under Uncertainty* OUTLINE

Expressive Rationality

Professors Blume, Halpern and Easley Econ 476/ December 2004 CIS 576. Final Exam

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Perceived Ambiguity and Relevant Measures

Cautious and Globally Ambiguity Averse

Almost essential: Consumption and Uncertainty Probability Distributions MICROECONOMICS

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 3. Risk Aversion

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Univariate Versus Bivariate Strong Independence

Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger 1 Uzi Segal 2. 1 University of Pennsylvania 2 Boston College and WBS

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility. I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications. Decision Theory Spring 2014

Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective. Probabilities

Numerical representation of convex preferences over Anscombe Aumann acts

Axiomatic Foundations of Multiplier Preferences

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Questions in Decision Theory

Choice Under Uncertainty

A Bayesian Approach to Uncertainty Aversion

QED. Queen s Economics Department Working Paper No Marie-Louise Vierø Department of Economics, Queen

We consider choice over uncertain, monetary payoffs and study a general class of preferences. These preferences

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Projective Expected Utility

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1

Mathematical Social Sciences

Indifference Pricing with. Uncertainty Averse Preferences

Extensions of Expected Utility Theory and some Limitations of Pairwise Comparisons

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

Msc Micro I exam. Lecturer: Todd Kaplan.

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Subjective multi-prior probability: a representation of a partial l

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Journal of Mathematical Economics

Problem Set 4 - Solution Hints

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries

Small Worlds: Modeling Attitudes towards Sources of Uncertainty. October Abstract

SUBJECTIVE INDEPENDENCE AND CONCAVE EXPECTED UTILITY. February 12, 2014

Advanced Microeconomics II

Game Theory. Georg Moser. Institute of Computer UIBK. Winter GM (Institute of Computer UIBK) Game Theory 1/19 Organisation

WORKING PAPER SERIES

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Are Universal Preferences Possible? Calibration Results for Non-Expected Utility Theories

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Game theory lecture 4. September 24, 2012

An additively separable representation in the Savage framework

Midterm Exam, Econ 210A, Fall 2008

Uniform Sources of Uncertainty for Subjective Probabilities and

Basic notions of probability theory

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

Bayesian Updating for General Maxmin Expected Utility Preferences

Choice Under Risk. Mark Dean. Lecture Notes for Fall 2015 PhD Class ECON Brown University

Numerical representation of convex preferences over Anscombe Aumann acts

Mean-Variance Utility

Preference for Commitment

Transcription:

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 11, October 3 Outline 1 Subjective Expected Utility 2 Qualitative Probabilities 3 Allais and Ellsebrg Paradoxes 4 Utility Of Wealth 5 Insurance and Betting

Anscombe and Aumann Structure Ω = {1, 2,..., S} is a finite set of states, with generic element s Ω. X is a finite set of size n of consequences with a generic element x X. X is the set of all probability distributions over X. Elements of Ω reprent subjectively perceived randomness, while elements of X represent objectively perceived randomness. Preferences are on H = ( X ) Ω, the space of all functions from Ω to X. An act is a function h : Ω X that assigns a lottery in X to each s Ω. Let h s = h(s) X, and denote h s (x) = [h(s)](x) [0, 1]. This is the probability of x conditional on s, given the act h: (Pr(x s, h)) The set of constant acts is H c = {f H : f (s) = f (s ) for all s Ω} If f, g H, then the function αf + βg : Ω X is defined by [αf + βg](s) = αf (s) + βg(s). Draw a picture to make sure you see how this works.

Subjective Expected Utility (SEU): Idea Starting from preferences, identify a probability distribution µ Ω and a utility index v : X R such that a utility representation of these preferences is U(h) = [ ] µ(s) v(x)h s (x) s Ω equivalently: f g [ ] µ(s) v(x)f s (x) [ ] µ(s) v(x)g s (x) s Ω s Ω Some Accounting Details x X x X x X U(h) is the (subjective) expected value of v given act h since [ ] µ(s) v(x)h s (x) = v(x) Pr(s) {}}{ µ(s) s x x s }{{} E h(s) [v (x)] Pr(x s,h) {}}{ h s (x). } {{ } Pr(x) s µ(s)hs(x) is the total or unconditional subjective probability of x under the function h, denoted Pr(x). Therefore Pr(x) = s Pr(s)Pr(x s, h), since µ(s)hs (x) = Pr(s)Pr(x s, h).

Last Class: State Dependent Expected Utility Theorem The preference relation on H is complete, transitive, independent and Archimedean if and only if there exists a set of vnm indices v 1,..., v S : X R such that. the utility representation is U(h) = v s (x)h s (x) s Ω x X This theorem does not define a unique probability distribution over Ω (see today s homework). To pin down a probability distribution one needs one more assumption: The binary relation on H is state-independent if, for all non-null states s, t Ω, for all acts h, g H, and for all lotteries π, ρ X, (h s, π) (h s, ρ) (g t, π) (g t, ρ).

Subjective Expected Utility Theorem Theorem (Expected Utility Theorem, Anscombe and Aumann) A preference relation on H is complete, transitive, independent, Archimedean, and state-independent if and only if there exists a vnm index v : X R and a probability µ Ω such that U(h) = [ ] µ(s) v(x)h s (x) s Ω is a utility representation of. Moreover, this representation is unique up to affi ne transformations provided at least two acts can be ranked strictly. Remark Therefore: h g [ ] µ(s) v(x)h s (x) [ ] µ(s) v(x)g s (x) s Ω s Ω x X x X The second part says: if there exist h, g H such that h g and U(h) defined above represents, then U (h) = s µ (s) [ x v (x)h s (x)] also represents if and only if µ = µ and v = av + b for some a > 0 and b R. The probability distribution µ is unique. x X

Subjective Expected Utility Theorem Theorem (Expected Utility Theorem, Anscombe and Aumann) A preference relation on H is independent, Archimedean, and state-independent if and only if there exists a vnm index v : X R and a probability µ Ω such that U(h) = [ ] µ(s) v(x)h s (x) = v(x) Pr(s) Pr(x s) {}}{{}}{ µ(s) h s (x) s Ω x X x X s Ω } {{ } Pr(x) is a utility representation of. This representation is unique up to affi ne transformations. Preferences identify two things: the utility index over consequences v : X R and the probability distribution over states µ Ω. Different preferences may imply different beliefs µ on Ω. von Neumann Morgenstern s Theorem only identifies the utility index v. For this reason, this is called Subjective Expected Utility.

Anscombe & Aumann Proof Proof. We will not do it in detail, but here is a breakdown of what would happen. First, convert each act h to a vector x [0, 1] S, by assigning each dimension s {1,..., S} a vnm expected utility for h s this gives [ x v(x)hs(x)] in each state s; monotonicity, a consequence of state-independence, is essential for this step. Then, construct an independent and Archimedean preference relation on [0, 1] S and the measure µ is the dual of the affi ne utility on [0, 1] S. The necessity and uniqueness parts are as usual. Notice that this argument involves using the mixture space theorem (or vnm theorem) twice. the first time to find [ x v(x)hs(x)] in each state s (this is E h(s) [v(x)]); the second to find the measure µ as the dual of the affi ne utility on [0, 1] S.

Savage Subjective Expected Utility Anscombe & Aumann assume the existence of an objective randomizing device (preferences are defined over functions from states to objective lotteries). X is a convex space and one can apply the mixture space theorem. Savage s theory instead considers all uncertainty as subjective: no probabilities are assumed a priori; all probabilities are identified by preferences over basic objects. This comes at the cost of higher mathematical complexity (see Kreps Theory of Choice). Ω is the state space, and X is a finite set of (sure) consequences. Savage acts are elements of X Ω, the space of all functions from Ω to X. The decision maker has preferences over these acts. The expected utility representation is something like U(f ) = v(x)µ(f 1 (x)) = v fdµ = E µ [v f ], x X Ω where f is any act, v : X R is a vnm utility index on consequences, and µ is a probability measure on Ω. Utility and probability are fully endogenous.

Probability Distributions Economists think of preference as primitive, and derive subjective probability as a piece of a subject s utility function. Some statisticians think about probabilities the same way economists think about utility functions. Definition A (finitely additive) probability measure on Ω is a function µ : 2 Ω [0, 1] such that: 1 µ(x ) = 1; 2 If A B =, then µ(a B) = µ(a) + µ(b). They usually assume that µ is also countably additive, which is very useful technically.

Qualitative Probabilities Definition A binary relation on 2 Ω is a qualitative probability if: 1 is complete and transitive; 2 A, for all A Ω; 3 Ω ; a 4 A B if and only if A C B C, for all A, B, C Ω such that A C = B C =. a By A B, we mean A B and not B A, i.e. is the asymmetric component of. Think of this as a binary relation expressing the idea of more likely than. This is a personal characteristic; it varies from individual to individual and can be use to infer the existence of personal probabilities.

Qualitative Probabilities and Probability Measures The relationship between qualitative probability relations and probability measures is similar to the one between preference orders and utility functions. Definition The probability measure µ represents the binary relation on 2 Ω if: µ(a) µ(b) if and only if A B. Result All binary relations that are represented by a probability measure are qualitative probabilities. The converse is false: not all qualitative probabilities can be represented by a probability measure. A stronger version of additivity is required to guarantee representation by a probability measure (see Fishburn 1986 in Statistical Science). Our theorems about preferences infer the existence of probabilities. Their theorem about probabilities infer the existence of a preference relation.

Allais Paradox The decision maker must choose between the following objective lotteries. and between One reasonable prefrence may rank A B and D C. Any such preferences violates independence: Consider the following lotteries E and F : 0.11A +.89A = A B = 0.11E +.89A 0.11A +.89F = C D = 0.11E + 0.89F But independence says for all f, g, h H and α (0, 1), f g αf + (1 α)h αg + (1 α)h.

Ellseberg Paradox An urn contains 90 balls. 30 balls are red (r) and 60 are either blue (b) or yellow (y). One ball will be drawn at random. Consider the following bets. and Many prefer A to B and C over D. Is this consistent with expected utility? By expected utility, there exists a (subjective) probability distribution µ over {r, y, b}. From A B and C D we conclude: µ(r)u($100) + (1 µ(r)) U($0) }{{} > µ(b)u($100) + (1 µ(b)) U($0) }{{} µ(b)+µ(y ) µ(r )+µ(y ) µ(r) > µ(b) and (µ(b) + µ(y))u($100) + µ(r)u($0) > (µ(r) + µ(y))u($100) + µ(b)u($0) µ(r) < µ(b) This contradicts the hypothesis of consistent subjective beliefs.

Risk (Knightian) Uncertainty vs. Risk Knightian Uncertainty (Ambiguity) B R B R B = 30 R = 70 B+R=100 P(B) = 3 10 P(R) = 7 10 20 B 50 50 R 80 B+R=100 P(B) =? P(R) =? Some theories that can account for Knightian Uncertainty. Gilboa & Schmeidler (weaken independence): Maxmin Expected Utility x y min µ(s)u(x s ) min µ(s)u(y s ) µ C µ C s Truman Bewley (drop completeness): Expected Utility with Sets x y s µ(s)u(x s ) s µ(s)u(y s ) s for all µ C

Probability Distribution On Wealth Many applications of expected utility consider preferences over probability distribution on wealth (a continuous variable). A probability distribution is characterziedd by its cumulative distribution function. Definition A cumulative distribution function (cdf) F : R [0, 1] satisfies: x y implies F (x) F (y) (nondecreasing); lim y x F (y) = F (x) (right continuous); a lim x F (x) = 0 and lim x F (x) = 1. a Recall that, if it exists, lim y x f (y ) = lim n f (x + 1 n ). Notation µ F denotes the mean (expected value) of F, i.e. µ F = x df (x). δ x is the degenerate distribution function at x; i.e. δ x yields x with certainty: { 0 if z < x δ x (z) = 1 if z x.

Expected Utility Of Wealth As usual, the space of all distribution functions is convex and one can define preferences over it. The utility index v : R R is defined over wealth (can be negative). The expected utility is the integral of v with respect to F v(x)df (x) = vdf If F is differentiable, the expectation is computed using the density f = F : v df = v(x)f (x) dx. von Neumann and Morgenstern Expected Utility Under some axioms, there exists a utility function U on distributions defined as U(F ) = v df, for some continuous index v : R R over wealth, such that F G v df v dg Axioms not important from now on (need a stronger continuity assumption). We always think of v as a weakly increasing function (more wealth cannot be bad).

Simple Probability A simple probability distribution π on X R is specified by a finite subset of X called the support and denoted supp(π), and for each x X, π(x) > 0 with x supp(π) π(x) = 1 If we restrict attention to simple probability distributions, then even if X is infinite, only elements with strictly positive probability count. The utility index v : X R is defined over wealth (can be negative). The expected utility is the expected value of v with respect to π π(x)v(x) x supp(π) One can write more money is better as: for each x,y X such that x > y then δ x δ y. We can use this setting to think about many applied choice under uncertainty problems like betting and insurance.

A Gamble Betting Suppose an individual is offered the following bet: win ax with probability p lose x with probability 1 p The expected value of this bet is pax + (1 p) ( x) = [pa + (1 p) ( 1)] x Definition A bet is actuarially fair if it has expected value equal to zero (i.e. a = 1 p p ); it is better than fair if the expected value is positive and worse than fair if it is negative. How does she evaluate this bet? Use the expected utility model to find out If vnm index is v( ) and initial wealth is w, expected utility is: probability of winning p v (w + ax) utility of wealh if win probability of losing + (1 p) v (w x) utility of wealth if lose How much does she want of this bet? Answer by finding the optimal x.

Betting and Expected Utility win ax with probability p lose x with probability 1 p The consumer solves The FOC is max pv (w + ax) + (1 p) v (w x) x pav (w + ax) = (1 p) v (w x) rearranging pa (1 p) = v (w x) v (w + ax) If the bet is fair, the left hand side is 1. Therefore, at an optimum, the right hand side must also be 1. If the vnm utility function is strictly increasing and strictly concave (v > 0 and v < 0), the only way a fair bet can satisfy this FOC is to solve which implies x = 0. She will take no part of a fair bet. w + ax = w x What happens with a better than fair bet?

An Insurance Problem Insurance An individual faces a potential accident : the loss is L with probability π nothing happens with probability 1 π Definition An insurance contract establishes an initial premium P and then reimburses an amount Z if and only if the loss occurs. Definition Insurance is actuarially fair when its expected cost is zero; it is less than fair when its expected cost is positive. The expected cost (to the individual) of an insurance contract is [ ] P π( Z) + (1 π) (0) = P πz loss no loss Fair insurance means P = πz

Insurance and Expected Utility An Insurance Problem An individual with current wealth W and utility function v( ) faces a potential accident: lose L with probability π or lose zero with probability 1 π If she buys insurance, her expected utility is πv(w L P + Z }{{} ) wealth if loss + (1 π) v( W P ) }{{} wealth if no loss For example, if the loss is fully reimbursed (Z = L), this becomes πv (W P) + (1 π) v (W P) = v (W P) Will she buy any insurance? Yes if πv (W L P + Z) + (1 π) v (W P) }{{} expected utility with insurance πv (W L) + (1 π) v (W ) }{{} expected utility without insurance How much coverage will she want if she buys any coverage? Find the optimal Z. The answer depends on the premium set by the insurance company P (which could depend on Z) as well as the curvature of the utility function v.

Problem Set 6 (Incomplete) Due Tuesday 9 October 1 Suppose Ω = {s 1, s 2, s 3 } and X = {x 1, x 2, x 3 }. The preference relation is independent, Archimedean, and state-independent. The following are known: δ x1 δ x2 δ x3 and (δ x1, δ x2, δ x3 ) (δ x1, (0, 1 2, 1 2 ), (0, 1 2, 1 2 )) (( 2 3, 1 3, 0), ( 2 3, 1 3, 0), δ x3). Find the decision maker s subjective belief µ. 2 Suppose Ω = {s 1, s 2, s 3 } and X = {x 1, x 2 }. Assume is a preference relation on ( X ) Ω which admits an Anscombe-Aumann expected utility representation. Denote acts as h = (h s1(x 1 ), h s1 (x 2 )) (h s2 (x 1 ), h s2 (x 2 )). The following are (h s3 (x 1 ), h s3 (x 2 )) known: (1, 0) (0, 1) (1, 0) (0, 1) (1, 0) (0, 1) (1, 0) (1, 0) (0, 1) (0, 1) ; (0, 1) (0, 1) (1, 0) (0, 1) ; (0, 1) (0, 1) (0, 1) (1, 0) What is the set of beliefs in Ω that is consistent with these data (if the decision maker follows Anscombe Aumann expected utility)? Is a unique belief identified, i.e. is the identified set a singleton? What if the middle weak preference were an indifference relation? 3 An individual has expected utility preferences with utility over money given by some twice differentiable function v with v > 0 and v < 0. She can choose the value of t in the following bet : receive tx s dollars with probability π s with s = 1,..., S (note that some of the x s are negative). Her initial wealth is w for all s. 1 Show that S s=1 πsxs = 0 if and only if the optimal t is equal to zero. 2 What (if anything) can you say about the optimal t when S s=1 πsxs > 0? How about S s=1 πsxs < 0? 3 Interpret these results in terms of better than fair gambles. What would happen if v = 0? 4 An individual whose wealth is W > 0 could have an accident in which she loses L with probability π. Let u denote the individual utility for money, and assume this function is differentiable at least twice with u > 0 and u < 0. An insurance policy specifies the premium the consumer has to pay regardless of the accident (P ), and the amount the insurance company reimburses if the accident occurs (Z). The latter is chosen by the consumer. 1 Show that if insurance is actuarilly fair, the consumer will insure the entire loss. 2 Characterize the relation between the optimal insurance coverage and the premium P. Interpret this result. (HINT: draw a picture).