Are Universal Preferences Possible? Calibration Results for Non-Expected Utility Theories

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Are Universal Preferences Possible? Calibration Results for Non-Expected Utility Theories"

Transcription

1 Are Universal Preferences Possible? Calibration Results for Non-Expected Utility Theories Zvi Safra and Uzi Segal December 5, 2005 Abstract Rabin [37] proved that a low level of risk aversion with respect to small gambles leads to a high, and absurd, level of risk aversion with respect to large gambles. Rabin s arguments strongly depend on expected utility theory, but we show that similar arguments apply to almost all non-expected utility theories and even to theories dealing with uncertainty. The set of restrictions needed in order to avoid such absurd behavior may suggest that the assumption of universality of preferences over final wealth is too strong. 1 Introduction One of the fundamental hypotheses about decision makers behavior in risky environments is that they evaluate actions by considering possible final wealth levels. Throughout the last fifty years the final-wealth hypothesis has been widely used in the classical theory of expected utility as well as in its We thank Eddie Dekel, Larry Epstein, Simon Grant, Eran Hanany, Edi Karni, Mark Machina, Matthew Rabin, Ariel Rubinstein, and Shunming Zhang for their suggestions. Zvi Safra thanks the Israel Institute of Business research for its financial support. Faculty of Management, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv 69978, Israel and the Academic College of Tel Aviv Yaffo (safraz@post.tau.ac.il). Dept. of Economics, Boston College, Chestnut Hill MA 02467, USA (segalu@bc.edu).

2 applications. Moreover, many of the new alternatives to expected utility, alternatives that were developed during the last twenty five years in order to overcome the limited descriptive power of expected utility, are also based on the hypothesis that only final wealth levels matter. The final-wealth hypothesis is analytically tractable as it requires decision makers to behave according to a unique, universal preference relation over final-wealth distributions. Suggested deviations from this hypothesis require much more elaborate and complex analysis. For example, postulating that decision makers ignore final wealth levels and, instead, care about possible gains and losses, may require using many preference relations and necessitates the need for a mechanism that defines the appropriate reference points. However, the lack of descriptiveness of some of the final-wealth models and, in particular, of the final-wealth expected utility models, have increased the popularity of gain-losses model (such as prospect theory and its offsprings). Recently, Rabin [37] offered a strong theoretical argument against finalwealth expected utility theory: Seemingly innocuous levels of risk aversion with respect to small gambles lead to enormous levels of risk aversion with respect to large gambles. For example, decision makers who at all wealth levels reject an even chance of winning $110 or losing $100 will also reject an even chance of losing $1000, regardless of the potential gain. This latter rejection is obviously absurd. Rabin offered even more stunning versions of this result: Even if the decision maker only rejects the small gamble at all wealth levels in a bounded range between 0 and 300,000, then at a wealth level of $290,000 he rejects an even chance of loosing $2000 and gaining $12,000, A possible response to Rabin s argument is that its basic assumption is actually wrong: No reasonable expected utility decision maker will reject the small gamble at all wealth levels (see Palacios-Huerta and Serrano [35] and LeRoy [26]). Palacios-Huerta and Serrano claim that even if expected utility decision makers are risk averse, moderate observed levels of relative risk aversion imply that their levels of absolute risk aversion go down to zero as wealth increases. Hence, at sufficiently large wealth levels, decision makers will accept the small gamble. This claim also applies to the bounded version of Rabin s result, as the size of the interval [0, 300,000] is quite large. 1 For an earlier claim that a low level of risk aversion in the small implies huge risk aversion at the large, although without detailed numerical estimates, see Hansson [21] and Epstein [13]. 2

3 Our analysis rejects this defence of expected utility theory. As we show in section 2, Rabin s calibration results can be strengthened by restricting the length of the intervals to less than forty thousands. Over such intervals, the claim of Palacios-Huerta and Serrano is less compelling. 2 A natural conclusion from Rabin s argument and from the results of section 2 is that final-wealth expected utility should be replaced with more general final-wealth theories. 3 Several alternatives to expected utility theory were introduced into the literature in the last twenty five years. These include rank-dependent utility (Weymark [48] and Quiggin [36]), betweenness (Chew [4, 5], Fishburn [16], and Dekel [11]), quadratic utility (Machina [27] and Chew, Epstein, and Segal [7]), disappointment aversion (Gul [19]), the more general differentiable non-expected utility model (Machina [27]), and the general class of theories satisfying first order risk aversion (Segal and Spivak [45] and Epstein and Zin [15]). These theories seem to be immune to Rabin s argument since their local behavior (evaluating small gambles) is usually separable from their global behavior (evaluating large gambles). Indeed, it can easily be seen that rank-dependent with linear utility (Yaari [50]) is capable of exhibiting both a relatively strong aversion to small gambles and a sensible degree of risk aversion with respect to large gambles. Nevertheless, if we extend the variety of small lotteries rejected by the decision maker, for example, by assuming that they are rejected even when added to an existing risk, then Rabin s fatal conclusions are not limited to final-wealth expected utility theory only. Our main result is that simple extensions of Rabin s argument apply to many known models of final-wealth non-expected utility theories (sections 4 and 5. All proofs appear in the appendix). Moreover, the analysis of the case of objective probabilities (i.e., under risk) is carried over to the case of subjective probabilities and uncertainty (section 6) and to some theories that are based on gain and losses, 2 Palacios-Huerta and Serrano [35] show that assuming constant relative risk aversion, that is, vnm utilities of the form u(x) = x1 γ 1 γ, rejections of ( 100, 1 2 ; 110, 1 2 ) over a range of 300,000 imply extremely high values of γ, the measure of relative risk aversion (see Table II in [35]). It turns out, however, that when the range of the wealth levels goes down to 30,000, the values of γ, although still high, become a lot more reasonable. In other words, one cannot reject Rabin s arguments by claiming that the if part of his analysis (the rejection of small lotteries) is empirically invalid. 3 Rabin [37, p. 1288] speculates that a possible solution may be to use theories of first order risk aversion [45], where for small risks the risk premium is of the same order of magnitude as the risk itself. Sections and extend (variants of) Rabin s results to functionals satisfying first order risk aversion. 3

4 rather than final wealth (section 7.1). To sum, during the last twenty five years, and especially since the works of Machina [27] and Schmeidler [42], a large part of modern decision theory has been based on the assumption that expected utility theory can be replaced by theories of non-linear preferences that are still complete, transitive, and universal. Our results cast doubt on the possibility of this approach. We do not prove its impossibility and we cannot offer one theorem that covers all non-expected utility preferences. However, we show that almost all known models are vulnerable to arguments very similar to the stronger calibration results of section 2. The set of restrictions our paper imposes on such preferences may suggest that either transitivity, or more likely, universality, of preferences should be dropped. 2 New Calibration Results for Expected Utility Theory Rabin s results were directed at showing that rejections of small, favorable, even bets must lead to the rejection of enormously favorable even bets. In this section we first show that Rabin s results hold even if the range at which the small lotteries are rejected is significantly smaller than the one suggested by Rabin. We then show that rejections of small even bets must also lead to the rejection of extremely profitable low risk investment opportunities. Following Rabin [37], consider a risk averse expected utility maximizer with a concave vnm utility function u, who, for l < g, is rejecting the lottery ( l, 1; g, 1 ) at all wealth levels x in a given interval [a, b] (a and b can take infinite values; when they are finite we assume, for simplicity, that b a = k(l + g) for some integer k). Rejecting the lottery ( l, 1; g, 1 ) at a + l implies u(a + l) > 1u(a) + 1 u(a + l + g) Assume, without loss of generality, u(a) = 0 and u(a + l) = l, and obtain By concavity, u (a) 1 and u(a + l + g) < 2l u (a + l + g) < l g l g u (a) (1) 4

5 Similarly, we get u (b) < u (a) ( ) b a l l+g g (2) Concavity implies that for every c, u(c + l + g) u(c) + (l + g)u (c), hence b a l+g u(b) u(a) + (l + g)u (a) Likewise, for every c, u(c l g) u(c) (l + g)u (c), hence i=1 b a l+g ( ) i 1 l (3) g ( g ) i 1 u(a) u(b) (l + g)u (b) (4) l i=1 Normalizing u(a) = 0 and u (a) = 1 we obtain from eqs. (2) and (3) u (b) ( ) b a l l+g g 1 and u(b) (l + g) ( ) b a l l+g g 1 l g For concave u we now obtain that for every x [a, b] (a x) x < a u(x) ( ) b a l+g u(b) + (x b) x > b l g (5) (6) Alternatively, a normalization with u(b) = 0 and u (b) = 1 gives (by eqs. (2) and (4)) u (a) ( g l ) b a l+g and u(a) (l + g) 1 ( ) b a g l+g l 1 g l (7) and hence, for every x [a, b] u(a) (a x) ( ) b a g l+g l u(x) x b 5 x < a x > b (8)

6 Inequalities (5) and (6) imply that if for all wealth levels x between a and b the decision maker rejects the lottery ( l, 1; g, 1 ), then when his wealth level is a, he will also reject any lottery of the form ( L, p; G, 1 p), G > b a, provided that L > 1 (l + g) ( ) b a l l+g g 1 l g + (G + a b) ( l g ) b a l+g 1 p p (9) For l = 100, g = 110, a = 100,000, and b = 142,000, we obtain that the decision maker prefers the wealth level 100,000 to the lottery that with even chance leaves him with wealth level 97,690 or with wealth level 10,000,000. The following table offers the value of L for different levels of G, b a, and g when l = 100 and p = 1 2. G b a g = 101 g = 105 g = 110 g = , ,740 21,491 4,316 1, ,000 20,000 79,637 5,810 2,330 1,125 40,000 39,586 4,316 2,310 1,125 10, ,376 95,531 12,867 1,174 1,000,000 20, ,873 12,66,421 1,125 40, ,023 4,375 2,310 1,125 10,000 6,097, , ,064 1,617 10,000,000 20,000 3,720,787 89,752 3,450 1,125 40,000 1,392,440 5,035 2,310 1,125 Table 1: If the decision maker rejects ( 100, 1 2 ; g, 1 2 ) at all wealth levels between a and b, then at a he also rejects ( L, 1 2 ; G, 1 2 ), values of L entered in the table. If p 1 1 p, the values of Table 1 should be multiplied by (see eq. (9)). 2 p For example, if the decision maker rejects ( 100, 1; 110, 1 ) on a range of 20,000, then he also rejects the lotteries ( 383, 9 ; 10,000,000, 1 ) and ( 3.45, ; 10,000,000, 1 ). This decision maker will even refuse to pay four cents for a 1:100,000 chance of winning 10 million dollars! Inequalities (7) and (8) imply that if for all wealth levels x between a and b the decision maker rejects the lottery ( l, 1; g, 1 ), then he will also reject, 6

7 at b, any lottery of the form ( (b a), p; G, 1 p), provided that ) b a l+g 1 p(l + g)( g l g 1 > (1 p)g (10) l For l = 100, g = 110, b = 100,000, a = 68,500, and G = 900,000, we obtain that the decision maker will prefer the wealth level 100,000 to the lottery that with probability leaves him with wealth level 68,500 and with probability leaves him with wealth level 1,000,000. In Table 2 below l = 100 and the wealth level is b. The table presents, for different combinations of L = b a, G, and g, values of p such that a rejection of ( 100, 1; g, 1 ) at all x [b L, b] leads to a rejection of ( L, p; G, 1 p) at b. L G g = 101 g = 105 g = 110 g = , ,000 1,000, ,000, , ,000 1,000, ,000, , ,000 1,000, ,000, , ,000 1,000, ,000, , ,000 1,000, ,000, Table 2: If the decision maker rejects ( 100, 1 2 ; g, 1 2 ) at all wealth levels in [b L, b], then at b he also rejects ( L, p; G, 1 p), values of p entered in the Table. We believe that the values of Table 2 are even more disturbing than those of Rabin [37], as many of the entries represent an almost sure gain of huge amounts of money, where with a very small probability less than 100,000 may be lost. In the next section we show that similar tables can be constructed for many non-expected utility models. The numbers may be less stunning than those of Tables 1 and 2, but usually not by much. 7

8 3 Definitions and Assumptions Having Tables 1 and 2 in mind, we begin with the following definition Definition 1 The vector (l, g, L, G, c) is an upper calibration quintuple if a risk averse expected utility decision maker who is rejecting ( l, 1; g, 1) at all wealth levels in [w, w + c] will also reject ( L, 1; G, 1 ) at the wealth level w. The vector (l, g, L, G, ε) is a lower calibration quintuple if a risk averse expected utility decision maker who is rejecting ( l, 1; g, 1 ) at all wealth levels in [w L, w] will also reject ( L, ε; G, 1 ε) at the wealth level w. For example, (100, 101, 123,740, 200,000, 10,000) is an upper calibration quintuple (see Table 1) and (100, 101, 10,000, 100,000, ) is a lower calibration quintuple (see Table 2). Observe that upper and lower quintuples do not depend on the values of w. We assume throughout that preference relations over distributions are risk averse, monotonically increasing, continuous, and that they display a modest degree of smoothness: Definition 2 The functional V belongs to the set V if 1. V is monotonically increasing with respect to first order stochastic dominance; 2. V is continuous with respect to the topology of weak convergence; 3. V exhibits aversion to mean preserving spreads; 4. At every distribution F, the indifference set of V through F has a unique tangent hyperplane. Observe that the hyperplane of part (4) is an indifference set of an expected utility functional with a unique (up to positive affine transformations) vnm utility function u( ; F ), which is called the local utility at F (see Machina [27]). 4 According to the context, utility functionals are defined over lotteries (of the form X = (x 1, p 1 ;... ; x n, p n )) or over cumulative distribution functions (denoted F, H). Degenerate cumulative distribution functions are denoted δ x. Machina [27] introduced the following assumptions. 4 The existence of such hyperplanes does not require Fréchet differentiability (as in Machina [27]) or even Gâteaux differentiability (as in Chew, Karni, and Safra [8] see Dekel [11]). We use these notions of differentiability in section 5 below. 8

9 Definition 3 The functional V V satisfies Hypothesis 1 (H1) if for any distribution F, u (x;f ) is a nonincreasing function of x. u (x;f ) The functional V V satisfies Hypothesis 2 (H2) if for all F and H such that F dominates H by first order stochastic dominance and for all x u (x; F ) u (x; F ) (x; H) u u (x; H) In the sequel, we will also use the opposite of these assumptions, denoted H1 and H2. H1 says that for any distribution F, u (x;f ) is a nondecreasing function of x while H2 says that if F dominates H by first order u (x;f ) stochastic dominance, then for all x u (x; F ) u (x; F ) (x; H) u u (x; H) Also, we will say that H1 (or H1) is satisfied in S if it satisfied at all F S. Similarly, H2 (or H2) is satisfied in S if it applies to all F, H S. 5 Machina [27, 28] shows that H1 and H2 conform with many violations of expected utility, like the Allais paradox, the common ratio effect [1] and the mutual purchase of both insurance policies and public lottery tickets. Hypothesis H2 implies that indifference curves in the set {(x, p; y, 1 p q; z, q) : p + q 1} (where x > y > z are fixed) become steeper as one moves from δ z to δ x. That is, indifference curves in the (q, p) triangle fan out. The experimental evidence concerning H2 is inconclusive. Battalio, Kagel, and Jiranyakul [2] and Conlisk [9] suggest that indifference curves become less steep as one moves closer to either δ x or δ z. However, Conlisk s experiment does not prove a violation of H2 near δ x. 6 Battalio et al. did find some violations of this assumption, but as most of their subjects were consistent with expected utility theory, only a small minority of them violated this hypothesis. For further citations of violations of H2, see Starmer [46, Sec ]. 5 Preferences may satisfy neither H2 nor H2, see section below. 6 In this part of the experiment, subjects were asked to rank B = (5, 0.88; 1, 0.11; 0, 0.01) and B = (5, 0.98; 0, 0.02). Most ranked B higher than B. But this pair does not dominate the pair (1, 1) and (5, 0.1; 1, 0.89; 0, 0.01) of the Allais paradox, and therefore the fact that most decision makers prefer (1, 1) to (5, 0.1; 1, 0.89; 0, 0.01) does not prove a violation of H2. Moreover, we suspect that most decision makers would prefer (5, 0.89; 1, 0.11) to (5, 0.99; 0, 0.01), which is consistent with H2. 9

10 The next definition relates to decision makers who reject the noise ( l, 1; 2 g, 1 ) which is added to all outcomes of a lottery. Some of our results will 2 refer to such decision makers. for a lottery X = (x 1, p 1 ;... ; x n, p n ), define (X l, 1; X + g, 1) = (x 1 l, p 1 ; x g, p 1 ;... ; x 2 n l, pn ; x 2 n + g, pn ). 2 Definition 4 Let x 1,..., x n [a, b]. The functional V satisfies (l, g) random risk aversion in [a, b] if for all X, V (X) > V (X l, 1 2 ; X + g, 1 2 ). The lottery X in the above definition serves as background risk risk to which the binary lottery ( l, 1; g, 1 ) is added. Paiella and Guiso [34] provide some data showing that decision makers are more likely to reject a given lottery in the presence of background risk. 7 Accordingly, if rejection of ( l, 1; g, 1 ) is likely when added to non-stochastic wealth, it is even more likely when added to a lottery. In other words, (l, g) random risk aversion is more behaviorally acceptable than the behavioral assumption that decision makers reject the lottery ( l, 1; g, 1 ) used by Rabin. 4 Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals We start by analyzing the set of betweenness functionals (Chew [4, 5], Fishburn [16], and Dekel [11]). Indifference sets of such preferences are hyperplanes: If F and H are in the indifference set I, then for all α (0, 1), so is αf + (1 α)h. Formally: Definition 5 V satisfies betweenness if for all F and H satisfying V (F ) V (H) and for all α (0, 1), V (F ) V (αf + (1 α)h) V (H). The fact that indifference sets of the betweenness functional are hyperplanes implies that for all F, the indifference set through F can also be viewed as an indifference set of an expected utility functional with vnm utility u( ; F ). 7 Rabin and Thaler [38], on the other hand, seem to claim that a rejection of a small lottery is likely only when the decision maker is unaware of the fact that he is exposed to many other risks. See section 7 for a further discussion. 10

11 4.1 Betweenness and Hypotheses 1 & 2 Our first result implies that betweenness functionals are susceptible to Rabintype criticism whenever they satisfy Hypotheses 1 or 2, or their opposites, H1 or H2. Theorem 1 Let V V be a betweenness functional and let (l, g, L, G, ε) and (l, g, L, Ḡ, c) be lower and upper calibration quintuples, respectively. Define S 1 = {δ x : x [a, b]} for some a and b satisfying b a = max{l, c} and assume that, for all x [a, b], V (x, 1) > V (x l, 1; x + g, 1). 1. If V satisfies H1 or H2 on S 1, then V (b, 1) > V (b L, ε; b + G, 1 ε). 2. If V satisfies H1 or H2 on S 1, then V (a, 1) > V (a L, 1 2 ; a + Ḡ, 1 2 ). In other words, Tables 1 and 2 apply not only to expected utility theory, but also to betweenness functions satisfying Hypotheses 1, 2, or their opposites. Remark 1 If V is expected utility and if preferences satisfy H1, then a rejection of ( l, 1; g, 1 ) at one point implies the rejection of big lotteries as in Table Betweenness and Random Risk Aversion The second result related to betweenness functionals is similar to the first, except that Hypotheses 1 and 2 and their opposites are replaced by the property of random risk aversion with respect to binary lotteries (that is, lotteries with two outcomes at most). Theorem 2 Let V V be a betweenness functional satisfying (l, g) random risk aversion with respect to binary lotteries in [w L, w + c] and let (l, g, L, G, ε) and (l, g, L, Ḡ, c) be lower and upper calibration quintuples, respectively. Then either 1. V (w, 1) > V (w L, ε; w + G, 1 ε); or 2. V (w, 1) > V (w L, 1 2 ; w + c + Ḡ, 1 2 ). 11

12 In other words, a betweenness functional satisfying (l, g) random risk aversion is bound to reject lotteries from at least one of the two tables of section 2. The fact that these results are weaker than those of expected utility (where lotteries from both tables are rejected) is besides the point. Theorems 1 and 2 mimic Rabin s claim against expected utility for betweenness functionals: Seemingly reasonable behavior in the small leads to absurd behavior in the large. 4.3 Some Betweenness Functionals In this section we analyze two specific betweenness functionals: Chew s [4] weighted utility and Gul s [19] disappointment aversion theories. Both are supported by simple sets of axioms Weighted Utility We show first that the expected utility analysis of section 2 can be extended to the case of weighted utility without the need to assume either H1, H2, H1, H2, or random risk aversion. This functional, suggested by Chew [4], is given by vdf V (F ) = (11) hdf for some functions v, h : R R. The local utility of V at δ w is a function for which the indifference set through δ w coincides with the corresponding indifference set of V, that is u(x; δ w )df (x) = u(w; δ w ) v(x)df (x) = v(w) h(x)df (x) h(w) [ v(x) v(w) ] h(w) h(x) df (x) = 0 As vnm functions are unique up to positive linear transformations, we can assume, without loss of generality, that u(x; δ w ) = v(x) v(w) h(x) (12) h(w) Suppose that for every x [a, b], δ x (x l, 1; x + g, 1 ) and that h(x) 1 h(x l) + 1h(x + g). As (x l, 1; x + g, 1 ) is below the indifference curve of 12

13 through δ x, and as this is also an indifference curve of the expected utility preferences with the vnm function u( ; δ x ), it follows that u(x; δ x ) [ 1 2 u(x l; δ x ) u(x + g; δ x)] > 0. Replacing u by the expression on the right hand side of Eq. (12) implies that at w = x v(x) 1 [v(x l) + v(x + g)] 2 v(w) [h(x) 12 ] h(w) [h(x l) + h(x + g)] > 0 Differentiating the left hand side with respect to w we obtain v (w)h(w) v(w)h (w) [h(x) 12 ] h 2 (w) [h(x l) + h(x + g)] (13) Monotonicity with respect to first order stochastic dominance implies that v(w)h (w) v (w)h(w) does not change sign [4, Corollary 5]. 8 The sign of the derivative of the expression in (13) with respect to w thus depends on the sign of h(x) 1 [h(x l) + h(x + g)], which was assumed to be 2 different from zero. In other words, for a given x, the inequality u(x; δ w ) > 1 [u(x l; δ 2 w) + u(x + g; δ w )] is satisfied either for all w [x, b] (denote the set of x having this property K 1 ) or for all w [a, x] (likewise, denote the set of x having this property K 2 ). For every x [a, b], either x K 1, or x K 2. At least half of the points a,..., a + i(l + g),..., b therefore belong to the same set, K 1 or K 2. In order to obtain calibration results, we need enough wealth levels at which ( l, 1; g, 1 ) is rejected, and moreover, the distance between any two such points should be at least l + g. In section 2 we just divided the segment [a, b] into b a segments to obtain Tables 1 and 2. Here we can get only b a l+g 2(l+g) such points, hence we need to observe rejections of ( l, 1; g, 1 ) on twice the ranges needed for Tables 1 and 2. If K 1 contains these points, take w = b and apply Table 2. If K 2 contains these points, take w = a and apply Table In Chew s [4] notation, V (F ) = αφdf/ αdf. To obtain the representation (11), let h = α and φ = v/h. Monotonicity in x of α(x)(φ(x) φ(s)) for all s is equivalent to monotonicity of v(x) h(x)v(s)/h(s), that is, to v (x) h (x)v(s)/h(s) 0. 9 Risk aversion implies the concavity of u( ; δ w ); see the proof of Theorem 1. 13

14 4.3.2 Disappointment Aversion Gul s [19] disappointment aversion is a special case of betweenness, according to which the value of the lottery p = (x 1, p 1 ;... ; x n, p n ) is given by V (p) = γ(α) x q(x)u(x) + [1 γ(α)] x r(x)u(x) where p = αq+(1 α)r for a lottery q with positive probabilities on outcomes that are better than p and a lottery r with positive probabilities on outcomes that are worse than p, and where γ(α) = α/[1 + (1 α)β] for some β ( 1, ). Risk aversion behavior is obtained whenever u is concave and β 0 [19, Th. 3]. We show that this functional satisfies (l, g) random risk aversion with respect to binary lotteries in [r, s] if, and only if, an expected utility maximizer with the vnm utility function u rejects the lotteries ( l, 1; g, 1). Claim 1 Let V V be a disappointment aversion functional with the associated utility function u. Then V satisfies (l, g) random risk aversion with respect to binary random lotteries in [r, s] if, and only if, for every x [r, s], u(x) > 1u(x l) + 1 u(x + g). By claim 1, disappointment aversion theory is compatible with (l, g) random risk aversion. Moreover, to a certain extent, the requirements for this form of risk aversion are similar to Rabin s requirement under expected utility theory. By Theorem 2, disappointment aversion is vulnerable to both Tables 1 and Chew & Epstein on Samuelson Samuelson [41] proved that if a lottery X is rejected by an expected utility maximizer at all wealth levels, then the decision maker also rejects an offer to play the lottery n times, for all values of n. This result has similar flavor to Rabin s calibration analysis, as positive expected value of X implies that the probability of losing money after playing the lottery many times goes to zero. Chew and Epstein [6] showed, by means of an example, that this result does not necessarily hold for non-expected utility preferences. They suggested a special form of a betweenness functional V, given implicitly by ϕ(x V (F ))df = 0 14

15 and proved that under some conditions, a lottery with a positive expected payoff may be rejected when played once, but many repetitions of it may still be attractive. They similarly identified rank dependent functionals with the same property. We don t find these results to contradict ours. We do not claim that all large lotteries with high expected return will be rejected. Tables 1 and 2 identify some very attractive large lotteries that under some conditions are rejected. In the same way in which one cannot dismiss the Allais paradox by claiming that there are many other decision problems that are consistent with expected utility theory, one cannot claim here that the fact that nonexpected utility theories are not vulnerable to Samuelson s criticism implies that they are also immune to Rabin s. Moreover, if the number of times one needs to play a lottery before it becomes attractive is absurdly high (say, one million), Samuelson s identification of unreasonable behavior is still valid, as is Rabin s. 5 General Functionals In this section we analyze preferences that do not satisfy the betweenness axiom, hence we need to make sure that the functionals are sufficiently smooth. This is achieved by requiring them to be Gâteaux differentiable (see below). This differentiability is weaker than Fréchet differentiability, used by Machina [27], and it is consistent with the family of rank dependent utility functionals (see Chew, Karni and Safra [8]). Definition 6 (Zeidler [51, p. 191]) The functional V is Gâteaux differentiable at F if for every H, δv (F, H F ) := t V ((1 t)f + th) t=0 exists and is a continuous linear function of H F. V is Gâteaux differentiable if it is Gâteaux differentiable at all F. If the functional V is Gâteaux differentiable at F, then there exists a function u( ; F ) such that for every H and t, V ((1 t)f + th) V (F ) = t u(x; F )d(h F )(x) + o(t) (14) 15

16 (see [51]). Note that although all indifference sets of betweenness functionals are hyperplanes, these functionals are not necessarily Gâteaux differentiable (see Dekel [11]). The following lemma is needed since the calibration results for expected utility rely on the concavity of the vnm utility function. The relation between risk aversion and concavity of local utilities is known to hold for Fréchet differentiable functionals (Machina [27]), for rank dependent functionals (Chew, Karni and Safra [8]), and for betweenness functionals (Chew [4]) but (as far as we know) not for the class of all Gâteaux differentiable functionals. Lemma 1 If V V is Gâteaux differentiable then all its local utilities are concave. 5.1 Quasi-concave Functionals Definition 7 The functional V is quasi concave if for all F and H satisfying V (F ) V (H) and for all α (0, 1), V (αf + (1 α)h) V (H). V is quasi convex if for all such F, H, and α, V (αf + (1 α)h) V (F ). The next result is similar to Theorem 1. Like betweenness functionals, quasi concave functionals which satisfy the H1 or H2 assumptions (or their inverse see below) on slightly bigger sets are susceptible to Rabin-type criticism. Unlike Theorem 1, we need to assume Gâteaux differentiability. Theorem 3 Let V V be a quasi concave, Gâteaux differentiable functional and let (l, g, L, G, ε) and (l, g, L, Ḡ, c) be lower and upper calibration quintuples, respectively. Define S 3 = {X : supp(x) [a, b]} for some a and b satisfying b a = max{l + g, c + l} and assume that, for all x [a, b], V (x, 1) > V (x l, 1; x + g, 1). 1. If V satisfies H1 or H2 on S 3 then V (b, 1) > V (b g L, ε; b g + G, 1 ε). 2. If V satisfies H1 or H2 on S 3 then V (a, 1) > V (a L, 3 4 ; a + Ḡ, 1 4 ). 16

17 In other words, adjustments that are not larger than g are made in the outcomes of the large lotteries of Table 2 and the probabilities of Table 1 are changed to 3 and 1. Obviously, the rejection of the new big lotteries is still 4 4 absurd General Functionals Proving a calibration result for general non-expected utility functionals requires slightly stronger assumptions than that of Theorem 3. Definition 8 The functional V satisfies approximate risk aversion with respect to (l, g, ε, a, b) if for all x [a, b] and for all ε ε, V (a, ε; x, 1 ε) > V (a, ε; x l, 1 ε 1 ε ; x + g, ) In other words, when some small probability ε is set aside for the outcome a, the decision maker prefers the rest of the probability to yield x rather than an even (residual) chance for x l and x + g. Note that approximate risk aversion implies the rejection of the lottery ( l, 1; g, 1 ) at all x [a, b]. Theorem 4 Let V V be a Gâteaux differentiable functional and let (l, g, L, G, ε) be a lower calibration quintuple. Define S 4 = {X : supp(x) [b g L, b]} for some b and assume that V is approximately risk averse with respect to (l, g, ε, b g L, b). If V satisfies H2 on S 4 then V (b, 1) > V (b g L, ε; b g + G, 1 ε) Here too, the decision maker rejects small variations of the very attractive lotteries of Table Some Functional Forms In this section we analyze two families of non-betweenness functional, the rank dependent and the quadratic utilities. 10 Assuming H2 we actually prove that V (a, 1) > V (a L, l L; a + Ḡ, 1 2 l L). See line (29) at the end of the proof of Theorem Similar results hold if hypothesis H1 is assumed, provided that the relevant interval is increased to a length of L + G and that quasi convexity is assumed. 17

18 5.3.1 Rank Dependent Functionals Rank dependent theory was first suggested by Weymark [48] and Quiggin [36]. Its general form is given by V (F ) = v(x)df(f (x)) For X = (x 1, p 1 ;... ; x n, p n ) with x 1... x n, the finite version of this functional is given by [ ( n i ) ( i 1 )] V (X) = v(x 1 )f(p 1 ) + v(x i ) f p j f p j i=2 This functional is Gâteaux differentiable iff f is differentiable. We assume throughout that v and f are strictly increasing, that v is differentiable, that f is continuously differentiable, and that f is bounded, and bounded away from zero. The local utility of the rank dependent functional is given by j=1 j=1 u(x; F ) = x v (y)df(f (y)) (15) Assuming risk aversion, both v and f are concave. The concavity of f implies that the functional is quasi convex. (For these results, see Chew, Karni, and Safra [8]). Moreover, if f is not linear, the rank dependent functional satisfies neither H1 nor H2. Assumption H1 is not satisfied since, at every F, the local utility function u( ; F ) is not differentiable at points at which F is discontinuous. Therefore, at such points, the local utility displays an extreme level of risk aversion. As for H2, consider lotteries of the form (a, q; b, 1 p q; c, p) where a < b < c and assume u(b) = 0. Then V (a, q; b, 1 p q; c, p) = u(a)f(q)+u(c)(1 f(1 p)). The slope of the indifference curve (in the probability triangle) through (q, p) is u(a)f (q) hence it is constant u(c)f (1 p) whenever p + q = 1. Each such lottery where p + q < 1 therefore both dominates, and is dominated by, lotteries of the form (a, 1 p; c, p), and the slopes of indifference curves must be constant, hence expected utility. We cannot therefore utilize theorem 4 as it stands and will need to modify it. Let X = (x 1, p 1 ;... ; x n, p n ) with the cumulative distribution function F. By eq. (15), at x {x 1,..., x n }, u (x; F ) u (x; F ) = (x) v v (x) 18

19 We therefore replace H1 ( H1) with the assumption H1 ( H1 ), that v (x) v (x) is weakly decreasing (increasing). Clearly, these assumptions are equivalent to the assumptions that for w > w (w < w), if a lottery X is accepted at w, then it is also accepted at w. The next theorem extends the calibration results to the class of rank dependent functionals. Theorem 5 Let V V be a rank dependent functional. 1. Suppose V satisfies H1 and let (l, g, L, G, ε) be a lower calibration quintuple. There exist d = d(η) and G(η) η 0 G such that if V is (l, g) random risk averse on [a, a+d] then V (a, 1) > V (a L, ε; a+g(η), 1 ε). 2. Suppose V satisfies H1 and let (l, g, L, G, c) be an upper calibration quintuple. There exist d = d(η), L(η) η 0 L, and G(η) η 0 G such that if V is (l, g) random risk averse on [a d, a] then V (a, 1) > V (a L(η), 1 2 ; a + G(η), 1 2 ). Risk aversion implies that both u and f are concave. Yaari [49, 50] discussed two kinds of risk aversion: Rejection of mean preserving spreads, and preferences for the expected value of a lottery over the lottery itself. In expected utility theory both notions are equivalent to each other (Rothschild and Stiglitz [39]). But under the rank dependent analysis, the former requires concave u and f, while the latter requires concave u but only f(p) p for all p. The proof of theorem 5 requires something even weaker, that f( 1) 1 and f(ε) ε. 12 In other words, this theorem applies not only to decision makers who satisfy the strong definition of risk aversion, but also to those who satisfy its weaker form. 13 The analysis of theorem 5 extends to cumulative prospect theory (Tversky and Kahneman [47]), where a lottery is evaluated by a rank-dependent functional for outcomes above a reference point w, and with another rank dependent functional for outcomes below this point. The extension to this theory holds if all outcomes are better than w and H1 is assumed. If potential losses are involved, the utility function becomes convex, and the if part of theorem 5 is not satisfied. 12 Empirical and theoretical studies support this assumption. See Starmer [46] and Karni and Safra [23]. 13 There is another sense in which the statement of the theorem is stronger than required. As is clear from the proof, one needs to require H1 (and H1 ) only on [a L, a + d]. 19

20 Remark 2 Neilson [33] observed that Rabin s results extend to rank dependent functionals and lotteries of the form ( l, p; g, 1 p) for p = f 1 ( 1). 2 For example, if f(0.6) = 1, then a rejection of ( 100, 0.6; 110, 0.4) at all 2 wealth levels will lead to a rejection of any lottery where there is a 60% of losing $ But as values of f are not observable, in our framework the if part reads only as the decision maker rejects ( 100, 0.6; 110, 0.4) at all wealth levels. This certainly does not lead to any level of risk aversion with respect to large lotteries, as it is consistent with maximizing expected value. Moreover, empirical evidence suggests that f 1 ( 1) < 1 (see Starmer [46]) Dual Theory Yaari s [50] dual theory is a special case of the rank dependent model, where u(x) = x. According to this theory, the decision maker rejects the lottery ( l, 1; g, 1 ) at all wealth levels w iff w > (w l)f ( [ ( 1 2) + (w + g) 1 f 1 ( 2)] f 1 ) g 2 > l + g But this does not imply any outstanding risk aversion for large lotteries. For example, for f( 1) = 110, the decision maker will accept any lottery of the 10 form ( L, 1; G, 1 ) for all L and G such that G > 1.1L. As the results of Theorem 5 are not satisfied even though H1 trivially holds, it must follow that the dual theory violates (l, g) random risk aversion. By the proof of Theorem 5, it follows that for a sufficiently large number of equally probable outcomes n, the decision maker prefers (X l, 1; X + g, 1 ) to X. Whether this is how decision makers behave is an empirical question Quadratic Utility The quadratic functional was suggested by Machina [27, fnt. 45] and by Chew, Epstein, and Segal [7], and is given by V (F ) = ϕ(x, y)df (x)df (y) for some symmetric, continuous, and monotonic function ϕ. For finite lotteries V is given by V (x 1, p 1 ;... ; x n, p n ) = i j ϕ(x i, x j )p i p j. The local 14 For a related argument, see Cox and Sadiraj [10]. 20

21 utility is u(x; F ) = ϕ(x, y)df (y) To check H2, we want to show that ϕxx (x, y)df (y) ϕx (x, y)df (y) (16) is increasing as we replace F by H such that H dominates F by first order stochastic dominance. Obviously it is sufficient to check this requirement only for finite F where only one of the outcomes is replaced by a higher outcome. In other words, if F is the distribution of (x 1, p 1 ;... ; x n, p n ), then we want to show that the derivative of the expression in (16) with respect to x i is positive. In other words, H2 requires ϕ xxy ϕ x ϕ xx ϕ xy < 0. Likewise, H2 requires ϕ xxy ϕ x ϕ xx ϕ xy > 0. 6 Uncertainty Uncertainty, defined as a situation where the decision maker is not sure about the probabilities of different events, seems to be immune to Rabintype criticism, which crucially depends on attitudes towards risk, the lack of knowledge which outcome will obtain. In fact, even the terminology of this paper s theorems doesn t suit the world of uncertainty, where equally probable events don t necessarily exist. Recent developments in the literature enable us, however, to extend our results to decision under uncertainty. In fact, some of these results hardly need any modification at all. Our claims in this section rely heavily on Machina s [30] recent results, showing that under some assumptions, uncertain beliefs must contain a probabilistic kernel. Consider, for simplicity, the case where the set of states of the world is the segment T = [a, b] R. An act is a finite-valued, Lebesgue-measurable function f : T R, given by (x 1 ; E 1 ;... ; x n, E n ), where E 1,..., E n is a Lebesgue-measurable partition of T. The decision maker has a preference relation over acts which is representable by a function W. This function is smooth in the events if it is differentiable with respect to the events E 1,..., E n (for details, see Machina [30]. See also Epstein [14]). Machina observed that regardless of the underlying preferences over acts, as long as W 21

22 is event-differentiable, the decision maker will consider the event the n-th decimal point of x T is even as an almost probabilistic event of probability 1, becoming more so as n. Unfortunately, the limit of these 2 events does not exist, therefore Machina [30] obtains only almost objective probabilities on such events. For every p [0, 1] there is a sequence of almost objective events with p as the limit probability. We discuss next three models of decision making under uncertainty, and show how all three are vulnerable to the calibration results of our paper. 6.1 Non Additive Probabilities Choquet preferences over uncertain acts (x 1 ; E 1 ;... ; x n, E n ) where x 1... x n are representable by V (x 1 ; E 1 ;... ; x n, E n ) = u(x 1 ) + n i=2 u(x i ) [ ν ( ) ( i j=1e j ν i 1 j=1 E )] i where u : R R is increasing, ν( ) = 0, ν(t ) = 1, and E E = ν(e) ν(e ) (see Schmeidler [42] and Gilboa [17]). According to Machina [29, 31], on the almost objective events these preferences converge to rank dependent. Since the range of the almost objective probabilities is [0, 1], we can use the results of section to obtain that if the almost objective preferences satisfy the requirement of Theorem 5, then there must be some calibration quintuples to which these preferences are vulnerable. 6.2 MaxMin Gilboa and Schmeidler [18] suggested the following theory for evaluation of uncertain prospects. The decision maker has a family P of possible distributions over the set of events, and a certain utility function u. The expected utility of each uncertain prospect is evaluated with respect to this utility function and each of the possible distributions in P. The value of the prospect is the minimum of these evaluations. Machina [29, 30] shows that if P is finite, then on the probabilistic kernel such preferences converge to expected utility. Tables 1 and 2 thus apply directly to this theory. 22

23 6.3 Beliefs over Probabilities A third group of theories explaining decision under uncertainty assumes the existence of a set P of possible distributions over the set of events. The decision maker has beliefs over the likelihood of each of these distributions. Uncertain prospects are thus modeled as two stage lotteries. These lotteries are evaluated by using backward induction 15 where at each stage the decision maker is using the same non-expected utility functional (Segal [43]), or different expected utility functions (Klibanoff, Marinacci, and Mukerji [24] and Ergin and Gul [12]). A related theory is suggested by Halevy and Feltkamp [20], where the decision maker has beliefs over P, and is interested in the average outcome each possible element of P yields if played repeatedly. In all cases, if the reduction of compound lotteries axiom is assumed, such lotteries are equivalent to simple lotteries. Suppose the set P is finite, and each of its members is a non-atomic, countably additive probability measure on Σ, the Borel σ-algebra of T. Border, Ghirardato, and Segal [3] show that under these assumptions there is a sub-σ-algebra ˆΣ of Σ on which all the measures agree, and which is rich in the sense that for every real number r [0, 1], it contains a set of (unanimous) measure r. Let E 1,..., E n ˆΣ be a partition of T. As all the possible distributions in P agree on these events and give them the probabilities p 1,..., p n, the two stage lottery discussed above collapses to a simple lottery with these probabilities. Therefore, the preferences over uncertain prospects where all events are in P become either expected utility (as is the case with Klibanoff, Marinacci, and Mukerji [24], Ergin and Gul [12], and Halevy and Feltkamp [20]), or the underlying non-expected utility preferences (Segal [43]). The present paper s results apply to these probabilistic sub-preferences. 7 Some Alternative Explanations This paper makes two arguments. 1. Rabin s [37] analysis requires much smaller domains over which small lotteries are rejected, and 2. his analysis can be extended to many non-expected utility theories. The second result is troublesome. It is one thing to hammer another nail into the coffin of a 15 Without the reduction of compound lotteries axiom. See Kreps and Porteus [25] and Segal [44]. 23

24 battered theory. Yet having a general argument against (almost) all known alternatives to expected utility has not yet been done in the literature. How should we react to such results? 7.1 Final Wealth or Gains and Loses? Cox and Sadiraj [10] and Rubinstein [40] suggest that expected utility theory can still explain Rabin s results, provided decision makers utilities are defined on gains and losses rather than on final wealth levels (Markowitz [32]). Rejecting small gambles at all wealth levels reflects a certain degree of concavity at a given point (the zero point) of the utility function defined on gains and losses. As concavity level at one given point does not reflect on concavity levels at other points, this rejection of small gambles can coexist with the acceptance of pre-specified large gambles, even when lotteries evaluation is done in accordance with expected utility theory (applied to gains and losses). Note that although this explanation is in the spirit of prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky [22]), the use of a non-linear probability transformation function is not required. Section 4 seems to challenge this analysis. Suppose the reference point with respect to which the decision maker evaluates a lottery is its certainty equivalent For each wealth level w the decision maker has a vnm utility function u w ( ) with respect to which he evaluates lotteries on the indifference curve through δ w. So X (w, 1) if and only if E[u w (X)] u w (w), which implies that X Y (w, 1) iff E[u w (X)] = E[u w (Y )] = u w (w). Clearly, the preference relation over lotteries is representable by a betweenness functional, and the utility from changes from w is the local utility u w ( ) (see also Machina [27, p. 307]). As such, it is vulnerable to the analysis of theorems 1 and 2. A more sophisticated model of reference point may require the functional used to compare X and Y to depend on X and Y. Such theories are very likely to lead to violations of transitivity. Of course, such violations are inconsistent with all the theories we discussed in this paper. 7.2 Loss Aversion Rabin and Thaler [38] suggest two reasons for risk aversion in the small. The first is loss aversion (rather than diminishing marginal utility), the second is decision makers tendency to think about problems in isolation, not realizing 24

25 that the small risk they consider is added to a lot of existing risk. Decision makers therefore behave myopically and pay too much to avoid some risks. Loss aversion seems to be associated with kinks in the utility function at the current holding, which is linked to first order risk aversion (see Segal and Spivak [45]). But the disappointment aversion (section 4.3.2) and rank dependent (section 5.3.1) theories represent first order risk aversion, and yet are both vulnerable to Rabin-type objections. We agree with Rabin and Thaler that paying $15/day for loss damage waiver on Hyundai Sonata (price: $15,999) is wrong, as this rate is equivalent to an annual rate of $5475 just for a protection against theft and damage to the car. But these numbers are irrelevant to our analysis as the risk aversion we discuss (following Rabin [37]) is very modest a rejection of an even chance to win 110 or lose Summary Rabin [37] proved that if a risk averse expected utility maximizer is modestly risk averse in the small, then he must be absurdly risk averse in the large. This paper shows that this criticism is not limited to expected utility theory similar arguments can be made against (almost) all its known transitive alternatives, both under risk and under uncertainty. For these extensions we need one of two types of assumptions: Random risk aversion, that relates to noise added to an existing lottery, and H1 or H2 (or their opposites), that relate to changes in attitudes towards risk that result from moving from one lottery to another. Given risk aversion, random risk aversion seems a natural assumption. As (X l, 1; X +l, 1 ) is a mean preserving spread of X, risk aversion implies that X (X l, 1; X + g, 1 ) for g = l. Continuity implies such preferences for some g > l, and uniform continuity implies X (X l, 1; X + g, 1) on any given compact set of lotteries. The size of g (given l = 100) is an empirical question, as is the question whether subjects prefer the wealth level w to the simple lottery (w l, 1; w + g, 1). It shouldn t be too hard to find examples for preferences that on no set S = {X : δ a+20,000 X δ a } satisfy H1, H2, or their opposites. But are such preferences reasonable? There are after all good reasons why these assumptions were made (for example, in order to explain the Allais paradox). As we ve shown in this paper, none of the existing (transitive) theories can 25

26 escape the extended forms of our calibration results. Finding a relation that violates H1, H2, and their opposites is a theoretical possibility. But is tailoring such a functional the right thing to do? How complicated must a theory be before we decide that it is impractical to work with it? Our analysis suggests that the transitive alternatives to expected utility theory may have reached this point. Appendix Proof of Theorem 1 Let I be the indifference set of V through δ w and let u( ; δ w ) be one of the increasing vnm utilities obtained from I (note that all these utilities are related by positive affine transformations). Obviously, I is also an indifference set of the expected utility functional defined by U(F ) = u(x; δ w )df (x). By monotonicity, V and U increase in the same direction relative to the indifference set I. We show first that u( ; δ w ) is concave. Suppose not. Then there exist z and H such that z = E[H] and U(H) > u(z; δ w ). By monotonicity and continuity, there exist p and z such that (z, p; z, 1 p) I, hence (H, p; z, 1 p) is above I with respect to the expected utility functional U. Therefore, (H, p; z, 1 p) is also above I with respect to V, which is a violation of risk aversion, since (H, p; z, 1 p) is a mean preserving spread of (z, p; z, 1 p). Case 1: Assume H1 or H2. We show that for every x [a, b], u(x; δ b ) > 1 u(x l; δ 2 b) + 1u(x + g; δ 2 b). By betweenness, V (x, 1) > V (x l, 1; x + g, 1) implies that, for all ε > 0, V (x, 1) > V (x, 1 ε; x l, ε; x + g, ε ). Using the local utility at δ x we obtain u(x; δ x ) > 1 2 u(x l; δ x) u(x + g; δ x) (17) Eq. (17) holds in particular for x = b, and therefore H1 implies that for x b, u(x; δ b ) > 1 2 u(x l; δ b) u(x + g; δ b) (18) Also, since x b, H2 implies that the local utility u( ; δ b ) is more concave than the local utility u( ; δ x ). Hence starting at eq. (17) and moving from δ x to δ b, H2 implies eq. (18). By the expected utility calibration result of section 2, it now follows that the expected utility decision maker with the vnm function u( ; δ b ) satisfies 26

Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals

Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals Zvi Safra and Uzi Segal May 18, 2008 Abstract A reasonable level of risk aversion with respect to small gambles leads to a high, and absurd, level of risk

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal May 0, 0 Abstract Machina (009, 0) lists a number of situations where standard models of ambiguity aversion are unable to capture

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal January 9, 204 Abstract Machina (2009, 202) lists a number of situations where Choquet expected utility, as well as other known models

More information

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 56, No., February 05 RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES BY DAVID DILLENBERGER AND UZI SEGAL University of Pennsylvania, U.S.A.; Boston College, U.S.A., and Warwick

More information

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009 Measurable Ambiguity with Wolfgang Pesendorfer August 2009 A Few Definitions A Lottery is a (cumulative) probability distribution over monetary prizes. It is a probabilistic description of the DMs uncertain

More information

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger Uzi Segal. November 25, 2013

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger Uzi Segal. November 25, 2013 Skewed Noise David Dillenberger Uzi Segal November 5, 013 Experimental evidence suggests that individuals who face an asymmetric distribution over the likelihood of a specific event might actually prefer

More information

Quantum Decision Theory

Quantum Decision Theory Quantum Decision Theory V.I. Yukalov and D. Sornette Department of Management, Technology and Economics\ ETH Zürich Plan 1. Classical Decision Theory 1.1. Notations and definitions 1.2. Typical paradoxes

More information

Range-Dependent Utility

Range-Dependent Utility Range-Dependent Utility Micha l Lewandowski joint work with Krzysztof Kontek March 23, 207 Outline. Inspired by Parducci (964) we propose range-dependent utility (RDU) as a general framework for decisions

More information

Second-Order Expected Utility

Second-Order Expected Utility Second-Order Expected Utility Simon Grant Ben Polak Tomasz Strzalecki Preliminary version: November 2009 Abstract We present two axiomatizations of the Second-Order Expected Utility model in the context

More information

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 11, October 3 Outline 1 Subjective Expected Utility 2 Qualitative Probabilities 3 Allais and Ellsebrg Paradoxes 4 Utility

More information

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

Homework #6 (10/18/2017) Homework #6 (0/8/207). Let G be the set of compound gambles over a finite set of deterministic payoffs {a, a 2,...a n } R +. A decision maker s preference relation over compound gambles can be represented

More information

Choice under uncertainty

Choice under uncertainty Choice under uncertainty Expected utility theory The agent chooses among a set of risky alternatives (lotteries) Description of risky alternatives (lotteries) a lottery L = a random variable on a set of

More information

COMPARATIVE STATICS FOR RANK-DEPENDENT EXPECT- ED UTILITY THEORY

COMPARATIVE STATICS FOR RANK-DEPENDENT EXPECT- ED UTILITY THEORY COMPARATIVE STATICS FOR RANK-DEPENDENT EXPECT- ED UTILITY THEORY John Quiggin Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics University of Maryland Quiggin, J. (1991), Comparative statics for Rank-Dependent

More information

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger 1 Uzi Segal 2. 1 University of Pennsylvania 2 Boston College and WBS

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger 1 Uzi Segal 2. 1 University of Pennsylvania 2 Boston College and WBS Skewed Noise David Dillenberger 1 Uzi Segal 2 1 University of Pennsylvania 2 Boston College and WBS Introduction Compound lotteries (lotteries over lotteries over outcomes): 1 1 4 3 4 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1

More information

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu Econ 701A Fall 2018 University of Pennsylvania Recitation 7: Uncertainty Xincheng Qiu (qiux@sas.upenn.edu 1 Expected Utility Remark 1. Primitives: in the basic consumer theory, a preference relation is

More information

Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries

Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries April 2, 2012 Abstract Preferences may arise from regret, i.e., from comparisons with alternatives forgone by the decision maker. We show that

More information

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva May 2013 Abstract One of the most prominently observed behavioral patterns in decision making

More information

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus. Testing Revealed Preference Theory, I: Methodology The revealed preference theory developed last time applied to a single agent. This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices

More information

Expected Utility Framework

Expected Utility Framework Expected Utility Framework Preferences We want to examine the behavior of an individual, called a player, who must choose from among a set of outcomes. Let X be the (finite) set of outcomes with common

More information

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging Mark Dean and Pietro Ortoleva Abstract Two of the most well-known regularities observed in preferences under risk and uncertainty are ambiguity aversion and

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 6: Choice under Uncertainty

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

Cautious and Globally Ambiguity Averse

Cautious and Globally Ambiguity Averse Ozgur Evren New Economic School August, 2016 Introduction Subject: Segal s (1987) theory of recursive preferences. Ambiguity aversion: Tendency to prefer risk to ambiguity. (Ellsberg paradox) risk objective,

More information

A Bayesian Approach to Uncertainty Aversion

A Bayesian Approach to Uncertainty Aversion Review of Economic Studies (2005) 72, 449 466 0034-6527/05/00190449$02.00 c 2005 The Review of Economic Studies Limited A Bayesian Approach to Uncertainty Aversion YORAM HALEVY University of British Columbia

More information

Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn

Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn Econ Theory (2011) 48:425 436 DOI 10.1007/s00199-011-0652-4 SYMPOSIUM Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn Mark J. Machina Received: 5 April 2011 / Accepted: 9 June 2011 / Published online: 16 July 2011

More information

Preference for Commitment

Preference for Commitment Preference for Commitment Mark Dean Behavioral Economics G6943 Fall 2016 Introduction In order to discuss preference for commitment we need to be able to discuss preferences over menus Interpretation:

More information

WORKING PAPER SERIES

WORKING PAPER SERIES INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR ECONOMIC RESEARCH WORKING PAPER SERIES Paolo Ghirardato and Massimo Marinacci RISK, AMBIGUITY, AND THE SEPARATION OF UTILITY AND BELIEFS Working Paper no. 21/2001 September 2001

More information

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013 Uncertainty Michael Peters December 27, 20 Lotteries In many problems in economics, people are forced to make decisions without knowing exactly what the consequences will be. For example, when you buy

More information

Mathematical Social Sciences

Mathematical Social Sciences Mathematical Social Sciences 74 (2015) 68 72 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Mathematical Social Sciences journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase Continuity, completeness, betweenness

More information

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities William S. Neilson Department of Economics University of Tennessee Knoxville, TN 37996-0550 wneilson@utk.edu April 1993 Abstract

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

A Relationship between Risk and Time Preferences

A Relationship between Risk and Time Preferences A Relationship between Risk and Time Preferences Kota SAITO Department of Economics, Northwestern University kotasaito@northwestern.edu June 12, 2009 Abstract This paper investigates a general relationship

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

Transitive Regret. Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal. October 24, Abstract

Transitive Regret. Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal. October 24, Abstract Transitive Regret Sushil Bikhchandani and Uzi Segal October 24, 2009 Abstract Preferences may arise from regret, i.e., from comparisons with alternatives forgone by the decision maker. We ask whether regret-based

More information

A Theory of Subjective Compound Lotteries

A Theory of Subjective Compound Lotteries A Theory of Subjective Compound Lotteries Haluk Ergin Washington University in St Louis and Faruk Gul Princeton University September 2008 Abstract We develop a Savage-type model of choice under uncertainty

More information

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

1 Uncertainty and Insurance Uncertainty and Insurance Reading: Some fundamental basics are in Varians intermediate micro textbook (Chapter 2). A good (advanced, but still rather accessible) treatment is in Kreps A Course in Microeconomic

More information

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty Yosuke Hashidate Abstract This paper presents a behavioral characteization of a reference-dependent choice under uncertainty in the Anscombe-Aumann

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts Review of Economics & Finance Submitted on 28/Nov./2011 Article ID: 1923-7529-2012-02-65-11 Yutaka Matsushita Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure

More information

Ambiguity and Nonexpected Utility

Ambiguity and Nonexpected Utility Ambiguity and Nonexpected Utility Edi Karni, Fabio Maccheroni, Massimo Marinacci October 24, 2013 We gratefully thank Pierpaolo Battigalli, Veronica R. Cappelli, Simone Cerreia-Vioglio, and Sujoy Mukerji

More information

Partial Ambiguity. CHEW Soo Hong, MIAO Bin, and ZHONG Songfa. November 2016

Partial Ambiguity. CHEW Soo Hong, MIAO Bin, and ZHONG Songfa. November 2016 Partial Ambiguity CHEW Soo Hong, MIAO Bin, and ZHONG Songfa November 2016 Abstract We extend Ellsberg s two-urn paradox and propose three symmetric forms of partial ambiguity by limiting the possible compositions

More information

September 2007, France

September 2007, France LIKELIHOOD CONSISTENCY M h dabd ll i (& P t P W kk ) Mohammed Abdellaoui (& Peter P. Wakker) September 2007, France A new method is presented for measuring beliefs/likelihoods under uncertainty. It will

More information

The Distorted Theory of Rank-Dependent Expected Utility *

The Distorted Theory of Rank-Dependent Expected Utility * ANNALS OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE -, 33 63 (0) The Distorted Theory of Rank-Dependent Expected Utility * Hui Huang Faculty of Business Administration, University of Regina Regina, Saskatchewan, S4S 0A, Canada

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny. These notes correspond to chapter of Jehle and Reny. Uncertainty Until now we have considered our consumer s making decisions in a world with perfect certainty. However, we can extend the consumer theory

More information

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 3. Risk Aversion

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 3. Risk Aversion Reminders ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 009 Notes for lectures 3. Risk Aversion On the space of lotteries L that offer a finite number of consequences (C 1, C,... C n ) with probabilities

More information

Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs

Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs Spyros Galanis June 19, 2014 Abstract Using the notion of subjective beliefs from Rigotti et al. (2008), we provide, for a wide variety of dynamic models with

More information

Comments on prospect theory

Comments on prospect theory Comments on prospect theory Abstract Ioanid Roşu This note presents a critique of prospect theory, and develops a model for comparison of two simple lotteries, i.e. of the form ( x 1, p1; x 2, p 2 ;...;

More information

We consider choice over uncertain, monetary payoffs and study a general class of preferences. These preferences

We consider choice over uncertain, monetary payoffs and study a general class of preferences. These preferences Published online ahead of print June 15, 212 MANAGEMENT SCIENCE Articles in Advance, pp. 1 19 ISSN 25-199 (print) ISSN 1526-551 (online) http://dx.doi.org/1.1287/mnsc.112.1537 212 INFORMS Aspirational

More information

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory Review of Economic Analysis 4 (01) 67-75 1973-3909/01067 Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory TAPAN BISWAS University of Hull 1 Introduction The axiomatic foundation of the expected

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Alexander Zimper Working Paper Number 97 Department of Economics and Econometrics, University of Johannesburg Revisiting independence

More information

Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility. I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications. Decision Theory Spring 2014

Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility. I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications. Decision Theory Spring 2014 Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications Decision Theory Spring 2014 Origins Blaise Pascal, 1623 1662 Early inventor of the mechanical calculator Invented

More information

Axiomatic Foundations of Multiplier Preferences

Axiomatic Foundations of Multiplier Preferences Axiomatic Foundations of Multiplier Preferences Tomasz trzalecki Northwestern University Abstract This paper axiomatizes the robust control criterion of multiplier preferences introduced by Hansen and

More information

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva February 2014 Abstract Many violations of the Independence axiom of Expected Utility can be

More information

A New Look at Local Expected Utility

A New Look at Local Expected Utility A New Look at Local Expected Utility S. Cerreia-Vioglio, F. Maccheroni, M. Marinacci Department of Decision Sciences and GER, Università Bocconi February 22, 2014 Abstract We revisit the classical local

More information

An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences

An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences An Explicit Representation for Disappointment Aversion and Other Betweenness Preferences Simone Cerreia-Vioglio a, David Dillenberger b, Pietro Ortoleva c a Università Bocconi and Igier, b University of

More information

arxiv: v1 [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 2015

arxiv: v1 [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 2015 Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large under Rank-Dependent Utility arxiv:52.08037v [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 205 Louis R. Eeckhoudt IESEG School of Management Catholic University of Lille and CORE Louis.Eeckhoudt@fucam.ac.be

More information

Problem Set 4 - Solution Hints

Problem Set 4 - Solution Hints ETH Zurich D-MTEC Chair of Risk & Insurance Economics (Prof. Mimra) Exercise Class Spring 206 Anastasia Sycheva Contact: asycheva@ethz.ch Office Hour: on appointment Zürichbergstrasse 8 / ZUE, Room F2

More information

Msc Micro I exam. Lecturer: Todd Kaplan.

Msc Micro I exam. Lecturer: Todd Kaplan. Msc Micro I 204-205 exam. Lecturer: Todd Kaplan. Please answer exactly 5 questions. Answer one question from each of sections: A, B, C, and D and answer one additional question from any of the sections

More information

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series The Knob of the Discord Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni Discussion Paper No.: 0405-14 Department of Economics Columbia University

More information

September Math Course: First Order Derivative

September Math Course: First Order Derivative September Math Course: First Order Derivative Arina Nikandrova Functions Function y = f (x), where x is either be a scalar or a vector of several variables (x,..., x n ), can be thought of as a rule which

More information

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY August 18, 2003 Aanund Hylland: # DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY Standard theory and alternatives 1. Introduction Individual decision making under uncertainty can be characterized as follows: The decision

More information

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Journal of Economic Theory 105, 531539 (2002) doi:10.1006jeth.2001.2824 Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Emre Ozdenoren Department of Economics, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan

More information

Week of May 5, lecture 1: Expected utility theory

Week of May 5, lecture 1: Expected utility theory Microeconomics 3 Andreas Ortmann, Ph.D. Summer 2003 (420 2) 240 05 117 andreas.ortmann@cerge-ei.cz http://home.cerge-ei.cz/ortmann Week of May 5, lecture 1: Expected utility theory Key readings: MWG 6.A.,

More information

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect Simone Cerreia-Vioglio David Dillenberger Pietro Ortoleva August 2014 Abstract Many violations of the Independence axiom of Expected Utility can be traced

More information

Anchored Preference Relations

Anchored Preference Relations Anchored Preference Relations Jacob S. Sagi October 2002 Abstract This paper axiomatically explores minimal conditions under which reference dependent preferences over risky prospects are normatively admissible.

More information

Pre-probabilistic sophistication. Osamu Kada. July, 2009

Pre-probabilistic sophistication. Osamu Kada. July, 2009 Pre-probabilistic sophistication Osamu Kada Faculty of Engineering, Yokohama National University 79-5 Tokiwadai, Hodogaya, Yokohama 240-850, Japan (E-mail: smkada@ynu.ac.jp) July, 2009 We consider pre-probabilistic

More information

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture I Choice under risk. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture I Choice under risk. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011 Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa Lecture I Choice under risk The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011 Preferences Let X be some set of alternatives (consumption set). Formally,

More information

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger Uzi Segal. July 26, 2016

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger Uzi Segal. July 26, 2016 Skewed Noise David Dillenberger Uzi Segal July 6, 016 Abstract We study the attitude of decision makers to skewed noise. For a binary lottery that yields the better outcome with probability p, we identify

More information

Game Theory without Decision-Theoretic Paradoxes

Game Theory without Decision-Theoretic Paradoxes Game Theory without Decision-Theoretic Paradoxes Pierfrancesco La Mura Department of Economics and Information Systems HHL - Leipzig Graduate School of Management Jahnallee 59, 04109 Leipzig (Germany)

More information

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries Chapter 2 Decision Making under Risk In the previous lecture I considered abstract choice problems. In this section, I will focus on a special class of choice problems and impose more structure on the

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

Choice Under Uncertainty

Choice Under Uncertainty Choice Under Uncertainty Z a finite set of outcomes. P the set of probabilities on Z. p P is (p 1,...,p n ) with each p i 0 and n i=1 p i = 1 Binary relation on P. Objective probability case. Decision

More information

Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility. Pavlo R. Blavatskyy

Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility. Pavlo R. Blavatskyy Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility Pavlo R. Blavatskyy Institute of Public Finance University of Innsbruck Universitaetsstrasse 15 A-6020 Innsbruck Austria Phone: +43 (0) 512 507 71 56 Fax: +43

More information

RISK AND TRADEOFFS Lara Buchak, UC Berkeley 1

RISK AND TRADEOFFS Lara Buchak, UC Berkeley 1 1 RISK AND TRADEOFFS Lara Buchak, UC Berkeley 1 1. Introduction Decision theories are theories of instrumental rationality: they formalize constraints of consistency between rational agents ends and the

More information

Stochastic Dominance and Prospect Dominance with Subjective Weighting Functions

Stochastic Dominance and Prospect Dominance with Subjective Weighting Functions Stochastic Dominance and Prospect Dominance with Subjective Weighting Functions Haim Levy *, Zvi Wiener * Second version 2/15/98 Please address your correspondence to Haim Levy at Business School, The

More information

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty*

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* journal of economic theory 75, 194204 (1997) article no. ET962280 On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* Elchanan Ben-Porath Tel-Aviv University, Ramit-Aviv, 69 978 Tel-Aviv, Israel; and Northwestern

More information

Projective Expected Utility

Projective Expected Utility Projective Expected Utility Pierfrancesco La Mura Department of Microeconomics and Information Systems Leipzig Graduate School of Management (HHL) April 24, 2006 1 Introduction John von Neumann (1903-1957)

More information

Individual decision-making under certainty

Individual decision-making under certainty Individual decision-making under certainty Objects of inquiry Our study begins with individual decision-making under certainty Items of interest include: Feasible set Objective function (Feasible set R)

More information

Uniform Sources of Uncertainty for Subjective Probabilities and

Uniform Sources of Uncertainty for Subjective Probabilities and Uniform Sources of Uncertainty for Subjective Probabilities and Ambiguity Mohammed Abdellaoui (joint with Aurélien Baillon and Peter Wakker) 1 Informal Central in this work will be the recent finding of

More information

AUSI expected utility: An anticipated utility theory of relative disappointment aversion

AUSI expected utility: An anticipated utility theory of relative disappointment aversion Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization Vol. 37 (1998) 277±290 AUSI expected utility: An anticipated utility theory of relative disappointment aversion Simon Grant *, Atsushi Kajii Australian National

More information

Glimcher Decision Making

Glimcher Decision Making Glimcher Decision Making Signal Detection Theory With Gaussian Assumption Without Gaussian Assumption Equivalent to Maximum Likelihood w/o Cost Function Newsome Dot Task QuickTime and a Video decompressor

More information

4.1. Chapter 4. timing risk information utility

4.1. Chapter 4. timing risk information utility 4. Chapter 4 timing risk information utility 4.2. Money pumps Rationality in economics is identified with consistency. In particular, a preference relation must be total and transitive Transitivity implies

More information

MATH 446/546 Homework 2: Due October 8th, 2014

MATH 446/546 Homework 2: Due October 8th, 2014 MATH 446/546 Homework 2: Due October 8th, 2014 Answer the following questions. Some of which come from Winston s text book. 1. We are going to invest $1,000 for a period of 6 months. Two potential investments

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

Optimal Reference Points and Anticipation

Optimal Reference Points and Anticipation Optimal Reference Points and Anticipation Todd Sarver June 18, 2012 Abstract This paper considers a model of reference-dependent utility in which the individual makes a conscious choice of her reference

More information

Overbidding in First-Price Auctions: Risk Aversion vs. Probability Weighting Function

Overbidding in First-Price Auctions: Risk Aversion vs. Probability Weighting Function Overbidding in First-Price Auctions: Risk Aversion vs. Probability Weighting Function Olivier Armantier Nicolas Treich January 2008 Abstract There is a long standing debate about whether or not risk aversion

More information

Dynamic Choice under Ambiguity

Dynamic Choice under Ambiguity Dynamic Choice under Ambiguity Marciano Siniscalchi October 28, 2010 Abstract This paper analyzes dynamic choice for decision makers whose preferences violate Savage s Sure-Thing principle [40], and therefore

More information

Extrapolated Social Preferences

Extrapolated Social Preferences Extrapolated Social Preferences Maya Eden World Bank July 17, 2017 Abstract This paper proposes a simpler interpretation of Harsanyi s impartial observer idea. It postulates an impartiality axiom with

More information

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES ISSN 1471-0498 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES ORDERING AMBIGUOUS ACTS Ian Jewitt and Sujoy Mukerji Number 553 June 2011 Revised July 2013 Revised January 2014 Manor Road Building, Manor

More information

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank No. 1611 March 2010 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working Paper No. 1611

More information

Uncertainty & Decision

Uncertainty & Decision Uncertainty & Decision von Neumann Morgenstern s Theorem Stéphane Airiau & Umberto Grandi ILLC - University of Amsterdam Stéphane Airiau & Umberto Grandi (ILLC) - Uncertainty & Decision von Neumann Morgenstern

More information

Preferences and Utility

Preferences and Utility Preferences and Utility How can we formally describe an individual s preference for different amounts of a good? How can we represent his preference for a particular list of goods (a bundle) over another?

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Recursive Smooth Ambiguity Preferences 1

Recursive Smooth Ambiguity Preferences 1 Recursive Smooth Ambiguity Preferences 1 Peter Klibanoff MEDS Dept., Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern University peterk@kellogg.northwestern.edu Massimo Marinacci Collegio Carlo Alberto, Università

More information

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization Edi Karni Johns Hopkins University and Warwick Business School Quitzé Valenzuela-Stookey Northwestern University Marie-Louise Vierø Queen s University December 10,

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form of

More information

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Adam Dominiak 1 and Gerelt Tserenjigmid 2 1,2 Department of Economics, Virginia Tech September 10, 2018 Abstract In this paper, we study choice under growing awareness

More information