The two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Similar documents
Kripke and Two-Dimensionalism. David Chalmers

240 Metaphysics. Frege s Puzzle. Chapter 26

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

Kripke on Frege on Sense and Reference. David Chalmers

Beliefs, we will assume, come in degrees. As a shorthand, we will refer to these. Syracuse University

On the Deeply Contingent A Priori. David J. Chalmers

In Meaning and Necessity (1947), Carnap laid the foundations for much of the

Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality

MODAL LOGIC WITH SUBJUNCTIVE MARKERS: A NEW PERSPECTIVE ON RIGID DESIGNATION

CONTINGENT OBJECTS AND COINCIDENT OBJECTS

Relations. Carl Pollard. October 11, Department of Linguistics Ohio State University

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Basics of Intensional Semantics, Part 1: The Motivation for Intensions and How to Formalize Them 1

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

The central problem: what are the objects of geometry? Answer 1: Perceptible objects with shape. Answer 2: Abstractions, mere shapes.

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

Gunk Mountains: A Puzzle

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Knowledge, Truth, and Mathematics

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass?

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Indicative conditionals

Truthmaker Maximalism defended again. Eduardo Barrio and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra

(1) If Bush had not won the last election, then Nader would have won it.

Soames s Argument 1 Against Strong Two-Dimensionalism

Semantics and Generative Grammar. An Introduction to Intensional Semantics 1

Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning

Non-normal Worlds. Daniel Bonevac. February 5, 2012

Propositional Logic Truth-functionality Definitions Soundness Completeness Inferences. Modal Logic. Daniel Bonevac.

Diodorus s Master Argument Nino B. Cocchiarella For Classes IC and IIC Students of Professor Giuseppe Addona

A Little Deductive Logic

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality

Wittgenstein on The Standard Metre

For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

by Bradley Monton Department of Philosophy, University of Kentucky, Lexington KY USA phone: fax:

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

VALIDITY IN SENTENTIAL LOGIC

is short for the thing which is Pond at t 1

Formalizing knowledge-how

Realism and Idealism External Realism

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Introduction to Metalogic 1

Barriers to Inference

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

PHIL 50 - Introduction to Logic

Draft of February 2019 please do not cite without permission. A new modal liar 1 T. Parent

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

VALIDITY IN SENTENTIAL LOGIC

Quantification in the predicate calculus

A Little Deductive Logic

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Meta-logic derivation rules

Aristotle s Philosophy of Science The Posterior Analytics. Aristotle s Philosophy of Science The Posterior Analytics

Contingent Existence and Iterated Modality

A Guide to Proof-Writing

Yet Another Paper on the Supervenience Argument against Coincident Entities

Introduction to Semantics. The Formalization of Meaning 1

Physicalism Feb , 2014

Symbolic Logic 3. For an inference to be deductively valid it is impossible for the conclusion to be false if the premises are true.

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

Structuralism and the Limits of Skepticism. David Chalmers Thalheimer Lecture 3

Announcements For The Logic of Atomic Sentences Counterexamples & Formal Proofs. Logical Consequence & Validity The Definitions.

Phil Introductory Formal Logic

Logic: Propositional Logic Truth Tables

Philosophy 244: #8 Counterfactuals, Neighborhood Semantics, Probability, Predicative Necessity, etc.

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

The Varieties of (Relative) Modality

PHIL12A Section answers, 16 February 2011

WHAT IS THE CORRECT LOGIC OF NECESSITY, ACTUALITY AND APRIORITY?

Simply Possible. Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000):

INTENSIONS MARCUS KRACHT

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

CSC Discrete Math I, Spring Propositional Logic

HANDOUT AND SET THEORY. Ariyadi Wijaya

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

Zombies are serious business

Lecture 15: Validity and Predicate Logic

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation.

Reference and Indexicality

Propositional Language - Semantics

Truth-Functional Logic

Model-theoretic Vagueness vs. Epistemic Vagueness

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy

Propositional Logic Review

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 1 Sets, Relations, and Arguments. Why logic? Arguments

[Handout 23] John Hawthorne, Three-Dimensionalism vs. Four-Dimensionalism

(c) Establish the following claims by means of counterexamples.

Intermediate Logic. Natural Deduction for TFL

Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem

In Newcomb s problem, an agent is faced with a choice between acts that

McTaggart s Argument for the Unreality of Time:

Priest s Motorbike and Tolerant Identity

HOW TO WRITE PROOFS. Dr. Min Ru, University of Houston

CHAPTER 4 CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL SEMANTICS

Semantics Basics for Syntacticians

Modality: A Standard Analysis. Modality

A New Semantic Characterization of. Second-Order Logical Validity

Truth Tables for Arguments

Propositional Logic. Fall () Propositional Logic Fall / 30

Transcription:

The two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind phil 93515 Jeff Speaks February 5, 2007 1 Primary and secondary intension........................ 1 2 Indexicality and intensions............................ 2 3 Dthat, actually, and rigidification...................... 2 4 Application to epistemic and metaphysical modalities............. 4 5 Some examples.................................. 6 On p. 56 of The Conscious Mind, Chalmers turns to consideration of a popular objection to conceivability arguments for dualism: the objection that the relationship between mental and physical properties might be necessary, though only discoverable a priori. His main response to this objection is to outline a semantic theory which explains apparent examples of the necessary a posteriori in a way which does not call into question Chalmers arguments. 1 Primary and secondary intension The key idea is that there are two distinct dimensions of meaning, which Chalmers calls primary intension and secondary intension. This is what he says: there are in fact two intensions associated with a given concept.... First, there is the dependence by which reference is fixed in the actual world, depending on how the world turns out... Second, there is the dependence by which reference in counterfactual worlds is determined, given that reference in the actual world is already fixed. Corresponding to each of these is an intension, which I will call the primary and secondary intensions, respectively. Later (p. 60), Chalmers explains the difference between these two intensions in terms of a difference between two ways of thinking about a possible world. If we consider the world as actual, we imagine that we are inhabiting that world, and ask what the

relevant term would refer to out of our mouths, as inhabitants of that world. To think this way is to think about the term s primary intension. If we consider the world as counterfactual, we imagine using the expression as an inhabitant of the actual world and then asking, given that use, what things it applies to in a given possible world. This way of thinking about a term corresponds to its secondary intension. On the same page, Chalmers usefully compares this distinction between two dimensions of meaning to Kaplan s distinction between character and content. To think of a world as actual is to think of it as the context of utterance; so the primary intension of an expression is (with some qualifications) a function from contexts of utterance to extensions in that context of utterance. This makes it closely related to Kaplan s character. (A difference is that Kaplan thought of characters as functions from contexts to contents, which then could be evaluated with respect to different circumstances of evaluation.) To think of a world as counterfactual is to think of it as a circumstance of evaluation, while letting the context of utterance be the actual world. So secondary intensions are like Kaplan s contents. In general: A sentence has a necessary primary intension it is true at all worlds considered as actual it has a character which is true in all contexts. A sentences has a necessary secondary intension (in a context C) relative to C, it is true at all worlds considered as counterfactual relative to C, it has a content which is true in all worlds 2 Indexicality and intensions Recall that in discussing Kaplan s semantics, we said that indexicals were terms with variable character: terms which deliver different contents for different contexts. For names and ordinary predicates, we said, there is no important distinction between content and character. Here we see an important difference between Kaplan and Chalmers, for Chalmers does think that there is an important distinction between the primary and secondary intensions of terms like water. It is for this reason that Chalmers says that water is implicitly indexical, and is related to a description which contains and indexical element, e.g. the dominant clear drinkable liquid in our environment. We can think of a description like this as roughly giving the primary intension of water. In general: the primary intensions of natural kind terms will be closely related to descriptions which contain some indexical element. 2

3 Dthat, actually, and rigidification What is the secondary intension of a term like water? We can see how to answer this question by thinking about the sentence Water is H 2 O. Chalmers agrees with Kripke that there is a reading of this sentence on which it is necessary. So, we know that either the primary or the secondary intension of the sentence should be necessary. But, recalling our discussion of the primary intension of water above, we can see that the primary intension will not be necessary. Remember that the primary intension of water is closely related to the indexical description the dominant clear drinkable liquid in our environment, and that a sentence has a necessary primary intension iff it is true in every world considered as actual i.e., true in every context. But now consider a world in which the dominant drinkable substance is XYZ. Water is H 2 O, if uttered in that context, would be false at that context. So the primary intension of Water is H 2 O is not necessary. It is not necessary because water will refer to different things depending on the context in which it is uttered. Accordingly, Chalmers says, the secondary intension is determined by first evaluating the primary intension at the actual world, and then rigidifying this evaluation so that the same sort of thing is picked out in all possible worlds. (59) So what we want is to begin with the description the dominant clear drinkable liquid in our environment, and turn it into a rigid designator. There are two main ways to do this. The first (which Chalmers endorses) is to use Kaplan s dthat operator, which he discusses in XII of Demonstratives. dthat is an expression which combines with a definite description to yield a singular term which directly refers to whatever is denoted by the description. So, for example, if I am a Millian about names, I will think that the following two expressions have the same content: George Bush dthat[the president of the United States in 2007] However, the two expressions will not have the same character, if George Bush has a constant character. The referent, and therefore the content, of the latter would be different if used in a context in which the president of the US in 2007 Bush. Chalmers suggests (with the qualification that the relevant description will be more complex) that water can be thought of as conceptually equivalent to the ridigified 3

description dthat[the dominant clear drinkable liquid in our environment]. Given this interpretation, we can see that Water is H 2 O. Will have a necessary secondary intension, but a contingent primary intension. A second, somewhat different way of achieving this result would be to rigidify the description using the actuality operator. Consider the description the actual president of the United States in 2007. This, like that dthat-rigidified description above, will rigidly designate Bush. But it will do so not by fiat by turning the description into a directly referring Millian term but by making the relevant descriptive condition such that, necessarily, Bush satisfies it if anything does. So if we consider the three terms: George Bush dthat[the president of the United States in 2007] the actual president of the United States in 2007 we can say that (if names have constant characters and are Millian), all three have the same secondary intension (even though, if we take contents to be structured, only the first two will agree in content), but only the second two agree in their primary intensions. 4 Application to epistemic and metaphysical modalities Recall that Kripke thought that there were examples of the necessary a posteriori and contingent a priori. Here are some of the examples of each category which have been defended by various authors: Necessary a posteriori Hesperus is Phospho- True identities: rus. True non-identities: Mars. Hesperus is not Attributions of essential properties: Bambi is a deer. Theoretical identities: Heat is molecular motion. Contingent a priori Truths of the logic of demonstratives: I am here now. actually biconditionals: Actually grass is green iff grass is green. Uses of reference fixing descriptions: Stick S is one meter long. On one interpretation of this claim, this would mean that there are propositions which are both necessary and a posteriori, and some which are both contingent and a priori. This seems to lead to the following results: 4

Let p be a proposition which is both necessary and a posteriori. Then we need empirical evidence to be justified in believing p (since it is a posteriori), even though there is no way that the world could be which would make p false. So what function could empirical evidence possibly have? It seems that it must be the case that there are some ways the world could conceivably be which are such that we cannot rule them out a priori which are such that the world could not genuinely be that way. I.e., there must be some epistemically possible ways the world can be which are not metaphysically possible. I.e., there must be some epistemically possible worlds which are metaphysically impossible. Let p be a proposition which is both contingent and a priori. Then there are some ways that the world could be that would make p false. Despite this, it is possible for us to know that the world is not that way without any observation of the world. But how could this be possible? Let s take the first of these results first. Suppose that we give the following Cartesian argument for the distinctness of mind and body: 1. Conceivable (mind body) 2. Conceivable(x y) Possible(x y) 3. Possible(mind body) (1,2) 4. Possible(x y) x y C. mind body (3,4) The necessary a posteriori in effect shows that an unrestricted version of P2 is false. It can be conceivable that such and such be the case without it s being genuinely possible that it is. Chalmers wants to block this kind of objection to Cartesian arguments for dualism. Two-dimensionalism is his way of doing this. The core idea is this: There are no propositions which are both a posteriori and necessary. Examples of the necessary a posteriori are examples of sentences which have a contingent primary intension and a necessary secondary intension. There are no propositions which are both a priori and contingent. Examples of the contingent a priori are examples of sentences which have a necessary primary intension and contingent secondary intension. The first principle guarantees that if we have a sentence which seems to express something which is epistemically but not metaphysically possible, what we have is a sentence whose primary and secondary intensions diverge. In this sense, there are no epistemic possibilities which are not metaphysically possible the appearance that there are rests on a failure to adequately distinguish the two dimensions of meaning. This is what Chalmers means when he says that there is only one relevant kind of possibility of worlds (63), as opposed to statements. 5

This opens up the possibility of a defense of the kind of Cartesian argument sketched above. If we can be sure that we are using only terms whose primary and secondary intensions do not diverge, we can be sure that instances of premise 2 will be unproblematic. This, as well as general puzzlement about how there could be such things as necessary a posteriori and contingent a priori propositions, is the source of much contemporary interest in two-dimensionalist semantics. 5 Some examples The explanatory burden of two-dimensionalism is then this: given a sentence which appears to be necessary and a posteriori, produce an analysis which has a contingent primary intension and necessary secondary intension. And, for any sentence which appears to be contingent and a priori, produce an analysis which has a necessary primary intension and contingent secondary intension. Think about how to draw a two dimensional matrix for the following such examples: I am here now. Water is H 2 O. Water is the watery stuff. 6