Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Similar documents
Intensional semantics: worlds, modals, conditionals

Indicative conditionals

Presuppositions (introductory comments)

Fox/Menendez-Benito 11/14/06. Wrapping up discussion on Kratzer 2005 (inconclusively!)

Classical Menu of Pronouns

127: Lecture notes HT17. Week 8. (1) If Oswald didn t shoot Kennedy, someone else did. (2) If Oswald hadn t shot Kennedy, someone else would have.

Deontic Modality in Natural Language

Singleton Indefinites (re. Schwarzschild 2000)

Homogeneity and Plurals: From the Strongest Meaning Hypothesis to Supervaluations

Must... stay... strong!

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology

Epistemic Modals and Informational Consequence

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

Global Approach to Scalar Implicatures in DRT*

about conditionals. It is a good example of what might be called systematic ordinary

Two kinds of long-distance indefinites Bernhard Schwarz The University of Texas at Austin

TEMPORAL AND CIRCUMSTANTIAL DEPENDENCE IN COUNTERFACTUAL MODALS. DORIT ABUSCH Department of Lingusitics Cornell University

5. And. 5.1 The conjunction

5. And. 5.1 The conjunction

Philosophy 244: Modal Logic Preliminaries

March 2, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Quick Introduction to the Semantics of Modals 1

A Little Deductive Logic

(An)Thony S. Gillies. Chicago Philosophy of Language/Semantics Workshop

Comments on Conditional propositions and conditional assertions

3.5 Generalized Quantifiers in DRT A Simple Extension to Non-Universal Quantifiers

P Q (P Q) (P Q) (P Q) (P % Q) T T T T T T T F F T F F F T F T T T F F F F T T

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

564 Lecture 25 Nov. 23, Continuing note on presuppositional vs. nonpresuppositional dets.

Spring 2018 Ling 620 Introduction to Semantics of Questions: Questions as Sets of Propositions (Hamblin 1973, Karttunen 1977)

Introduction to Semantics. The Formalization of Meaning 1

Philosophy 4310: Conditionals Spring 2017

Strengthening Principles and Counterfactual Semantics

A Little Deductive Logic

First-Degree Entailment

Indicative Conditionals

Basics of conversational implicatures

Spring 2017 Ling 620. The Semantics of Modals, Part 3: The Ordering Source 1

Kripke on Frege on Sense and Reference. David Chalmers

The Semantics of Questions Introductory remarks

Relational semantics and domain semantics for epistemic modals

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Basics of Intensional Semantics, Part 1: The Motivation for Intensions and How to Formalize Them 1

Truth Table Definitions of Logical Connectives

Generalized Quantifiers Logical and Linguistic Aspects

Introduction to Pragmatics

Basic Probability. Introduction

Spring 2017 Ling 620. An Introduction to the Semantics of Tense 1

Deriving indirectness and questioning entailment for epistemic must 1

Assignment 3 Logic and Reasoning KEY

*Karle Laska s Sections: There is no class tomorrow and Friday! Have a good weekend! Scores will be posted in Compass early Friday morning

The Inductive Proof Template

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 5)

MODAL LOGIC WITH SUBJUNCTIVE MARKERS: A NEW PERSPECTIVE ON RIGID DESIGNATION

Introduction to Metalogic 1

Breaking de Morgan s law in counterfactual antecedents

Semantics and Generative Grammar. The Semantics of Adjectival Modification 1. (1) Our Current Assumptions Regarding Adjectives and Common Ns

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Spring 2017 Ling 620 Conditionals as Modal Modifiers Conditional Constructions: Some Basic Terminology, Questions, and Assumptions

Against generalized quantifiers (and what to replace them with)

Holding on and letting go: Facts, counterfactuals, and before

Definition 2. Conjunction of p and q

Logic. Readings: Coppock and Champollion textbook draft, Ch

Final Exam Theory Quiz Answer Page

Modal subordination is neither modal nor subordinate...discuss

The Puzzles of Deontic Logic

Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009

Scalar Implicatures: Are There Any?

Probability and Independence Terri Bittner, Ph.D.

Essential facts about NP-completeness:

Conditionals. Daniel Bonevac. February 12, 2013

An Alternative Semantics for English Aspectual Particles

Gender in conditionals

Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality

P (E) = P (A 1 )P (A 2 )... P (A n ).

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

Outline. A Uniform Theory of Conditionals Stalnaker and Beyond. Stalnaker (1975) Uniform Theory of Conditionals and Response to Direct Argument

On Indicative and Subjunctive Conditionals

Topic 1: Propositional logic

(1) If Bush had not won the last election, then Nader would have won it.

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus

Introduction to Metalogic

Semantics and Pragmatics of NLP. SPNLP: Dynamic Semantics and Drawbacks

Berlin, May 16 / 2003

To every formula scheme there corresponds a property of R. This relationship helps one to understand the logic being studied.

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern AAL/ALC Modal 2011 Logic 1 / 26

CS1021. Why logic? Logic about inference or argument. Start from assumptions or axioms. Make deductions according to rules of reasoning.

The Foundations of Mathematics. Frege s Logicism

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

Solutions to In-Class Problems Week 14, Mon.

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 10

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Conditionals in Causal Decision Theory

The problem Countable additivity Finite additivity Conglomerability Structure Puzzle. The Measure Problem. Alexander R. Pruss

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

MODALITY AND EXPRESSIBILITY

Modality: A Standard Analysis. Modality

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Semantics of Modals, Part 1: Basics of the Quantificational Analysis, and the Appearance of Ambiguity 1

Modal Dependence Logic

Foundation of proofs. Jim Hefferon.

Transcription:

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa Kai von Fintel and Anthony S. Gillies MIT and Rutgers November 21 University of Latvia

Ramsey s Test If two people are arguing If p will q? and are both in doubt as to p, they are adding p hypothetically to their stock of knowledge and arguing on that basis about q.

Our Starting Point Simple conditionals are epistemic conditionals. (1) If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. Makes a claim about the state of the evidence available.

Implementations 1. conditionals have epistemic semantics 2. conditionals have bare bones semantics + epistemic pragmatics material conditional + assertibility conditions NTV +?

One Challenge Tug of war between subjectivity and objectivity (cf. Gibbard s Riverboat Puzzle) Solution based on our Might Made Right being developed in our The Subjectivity of Conditionals in a New Light

Edgington s Stress Test Any theory of conditionals has consequences for less-than-certain judgements. Something is proposed of the form: If A, B is true iff A*B. If a clear-headed person, free from confusions of a logical, linguistic or referential sort, can be nearly sure that A*B yet far from sure that if A, B, or vice versa, then this is strong evidence against the proposal. (Edgington 1995/2007)

A Plethora of Hedges It s X-probable that if p, q It s likely that if p, q I guess/suppose that if p, q It s plausible that if p, q It might be that if p, q I m not sure that if p, q I doubt that if p, q Do these hedged conditionals have the meanings predicted by the epistemic account?

Expectation Simple conditional: if p, q Hedged conditional: HEDGE (if p, q) Meaning of simple conditional should be what it contributes to the meaning of the hedged conditional.

The Compelling Intuition Hedged conditionals express conditional hedges (2) a. HEDGE(if p, q) = b. HEDGE p (q) Special Case: probability of a conditional = conditional probability.

pose I present you with a board with intersecting circles marked P and Q, as. Jackson on the Compelling Intuition P Q you the following question, If you throw a dart at the board, how likely is it to n the area marked Q if it lands in the area marked P? It is compelling that the er to this question is nothing other than how likely the dart is to land in the ection of P and Q given it lands in P. which equals the probability of its landing intersection of P and Q as a fraction of the probability of its landing in P. In words, the answer is The probability of the dart's landing in Q if it lands in P = probability of its landing in the intersection of P and Q divided by the probability of its landing in P. I ask you the following question, If you throw a dart at the board, how likely is it to land in the area marked Q if it lands in the area marked P? It is compelling that the answer to this question is nothing other than how likely the dart is to land in the intersection of P and Q given it lands in P, which equals the probability of its landing in the intersection of P and Q as a fraction of the probability of its landing in P. (Jackson Indicative Conditionals Revisited, March 27, 2006)

Compelling Across the Board (3) a. Maybe if he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. = b. Maybe he told Tom (given he didn t tell Harry). (4) a. Presumably if it s raining, it s cold. = b. Presumably it s cold (given it s raining).

The Trouble(s) with the Compelling Intuition (Under plausible assumptions) it seems there is no (good) way to give truth-conditions to if p, q such that hedging of those truth-conditions being satisfied = hedging-within-p that q.

For Instance: Probably Lewis and successors: There is no (sane) way to give truth-conditions to if p, q such that the probability of those truth-conditions being satisfied = the conditional probability of q given p. Jackson 2006: There are no such-and-such conditions associated with if p, q (not its assertibility conditions, not its acceptability conditions, nothing) such that the probability of those such-and-such conditions being satisfied = the conditional probability of q given p.

Jackson s Despair Jackson 2006: The Compelling Intuition is a mistake. The probability of a conditional is not the conditional probability. Our usage of the indicative conditional construction is governed by a mistaken intuition [... ]. We [... ] wrongly think and speak as if the indicative conditional in fact has truth conditions such that its probability is the conditional probability of its consequent given its antecedent.

NTV Simple conditionals have no meaning that could be embedded. So, what happens when it looks as if they re embedded?...

A Special Reading Can a hedged conditional ever be interpreted in the predicted complex-nested fashion? (5) It is almost certainly false that if the die comes up even, it will be a six since it almost certainly is a fair die.

The Lewis-Kratzer Way Out When we ask (6) What is the probability that q, if p? (7) How likely is it that q, if p? we are not asking what the probability of an indicative / epistemic conditional is. Instead, the if-clause restricts the probability operator. What does a restricted probability operator express? Conditional probability.

Lewis The if of our restrictive if-clauses should not be regarded as a sentential connective. It has no meaning apart from the adverb it restricts. The if in always if...,..., sometimes if...,..., and the rest is on a par with the non-connective and in between... and..., with the non-connective or in whether... or..., or with the non-connective if in the probability that... if.... It serves merely to mark an argument-place in a polyadic construction.

Lewis on Adverbs of Quantification (8) This dog almost always/usually/sometimes/never bites if he is approached.

Kratzer s Thesis Lewis wasn t just right about adverbial quantification. His analysis is right about other occurrences of if. The history of the conditional is the story of a syntactic mistake. There is no two-place if... then connective in the logical forms of natural languages. If-clauses are devices for restricting the domains of various operators. (Kratzer Conditionals, 1986) In other words: there are no conditionals, just constructions involving an if-clause and an operator that the if-clause restricts.

Tripartite Structures Heim s dissertation: Quantifier/Operator [Restriction] [(Nuclear) Scope] Heim achieved a solution to the problem of donkey anaphora, which ensured that the Lewis/Kratzer/Heim view of the partition of conditionals into Operator + if-clause + consequent became the received view in linguistic semantics.

Before Lewis, Kratzer, Heim C if A

After Lewis, Kratzer, Heim C Operator if A

Bare Conditionals (9) If this dog is approached, he bites. (10) If John was here on time, he left Cambridge at noon. Kratzer: covert operator restricted by if-clause covert frequency adverb in (9) ( always ) covert epistemic necessity modal in (10) ( must )

Back to our Problem(s) Instead of X-probably C if A

we are actually dealing with C X-probably if A

The restrictor view of the embedding problem Simple conditional: -if p, q Hedged conditional: HEDGE-if p, q Shared surface string if p q, but no shared logical constituent!

Similar Cases A surface string can receive one parse when occurring on its own and a very different one when occurring embedded: (11) a. A randomly tossed coin comes up heads. b. The probability that a randomly tossed coin comes up heads is fifty-fifty. (12) a.?on a given day, the Red Sox win. b. The probability that on a given day the Red Sox win is about 60%. (13) a. This dog bites if he is approached. b. This dog quite often bites if he is approached. c. It almost never happens that this dog bites if he is approached.

Why This Interpretation? There are three reasons why structures where a conditional apparently occurs under a probability expression are (almost) always parsed not as involving an embedded conditional with a covert operator but as having the if-clause restrict the probability operator: positing covert operator is a last resort strategy the probability operator would like to be restricted epistemic modals resist embedding under probability operators

Resisting Embedding (14) a. If she threw an even number, it must have been a six. b.?the probability that if she threw an even number it must have been a six is....

Objection If the following two structures do not share a constituent corresponding to the conditional, then how come they are felt to be talking about the same thing? (15) a. If she is not in her office, she must be at home. b. Actually, it is not very likely that she is at home if she is not in her office.

Reply Because they both talk about possible scenarios in which she is not in her office. Compare: (16) a. All students smokes. b. Actually, MOST students smoke. shared surface string ( students smoke ) no shared logical constituent but shared subject matter (proportion of students who smoke)

The Cross-Speaker Problem (17) A: If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. B: Probably so. B : That s very unlikely. We don t just have an intuition that there is a shared logical constituent (if p, q), but we actually use anaphors like so and that to pick it up.

What now? Despair

What now? Copy & reparse Copy the string if p,q into the slot held by the anaphor then reparse the second sentence

What now? Divide & conquer Belnap Higher type

Divide & Conquer (18) A: Every student smokes. B: Most (of them) (do). (19) A: If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. B: Probably so. B : That s very unlikely.

Something to worry about (20) A: If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. B: I m not sure that s true. A: No, really. I know he told one of them. (21) A: If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. B: I m not sure (it s true that) he told Tom. A: Me either./??no, really. I know he told one of them.

Something to worry about (22) A: If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. B: That may be true./that s plausible./i guess that s true. A: No, really. I know he told one of them. (23) A: If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. B: Maybe (it s true that) he told Tom./It s plausible that he told Tom./I guess it s true he told Tom. A:??No, really. I know he told one of them. (24) A: If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. B 1 : I doubt that s true. B 2 : I doubt (it s true that) he told Tom.

Belnap s Alternative Belnap s meaning for conditionals: if p, q is true if p and q are true, false if p is true but q is false, and has no truth-value if p is false. Embedding operators are restricted to quantify over worlds where the embedded proposition has a truth-value.

Escape? If he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom. must (if he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom) Probably so. probably (if he didn t tell Harry, he told Tom)

The Belnapian s To Do List Can Belnap s conditional stand on its own, or does it always require an operator to embed it? (If yes, then we would mimic the restrictor analysis very closely.) Partial propositions of the kind that the Belnap-conditional expresses are usually used to model presuppositions. But here, we absolutely do not want to say that if p, q presupposes that p is true. So, we need a new technical system that distinguishes presuppositions from Belnap-partiality.

Going to high types Re-Schönfinkel (or re-curry) the meaning of if if: λp.λq.λo. O p q

All together now Despair Copy + Reparse Divide & Conquer Belnap Retyping if What now?