Conditionals. Daniel Bonevac. February 12, 2013

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Conditionals. Daniel Bonevac. February 12, 2013"

Transcription

1 Neighborhood February 12, 2013

2 Neighborhood are sentences formed, in English, with the particle if. Some are indicative; some are subjunctive. They are not equivalent, as this pair seems to show: 1. If Oswald didn t shoot Kennedy, someone else did. 2. If Oswald hadn t shot Kennedy, someone else would have.

3 Neighborhood Crows The logic of conditionals is notoriously controversial. Callimachus said that debates among the Stoics were so intense that Even the crows on the rooftops caw about which conditionals are true, and they are no less intense in contemporary logic.

4 Neighborhood Stoic Logic The Stoics developed four theories of the conditional, two of which remain competitive today:

5 Neighborhood Philo The material conditional (Philo): a conditional is true if and only if it does not have a true antecedent and a false consequent. Thus, If A, then B is equivalent to not (A and not B). This approach to the conditional is standard in classical first-order logic, and is still popular as an account of indicative conditionals.

6 Neighborhood Material Conditional There are three primary arguments for the material conditional: A strong version of the deduction theorem (If A, then B follows from given information if and only if that information, together with A, implies B) implies that the conditional is material; If A, then B appears to be equivalent to Either not A or B, which is equivalent to not (A and not B); first-order logic requires a material conditional in its analysis of universally quantified sentences.

7 Neighborhood Chrysippus The strict conditional (Chrysippus): a conditional is true if and only if its antecedent implies its consequent. This view, as developed by C. I. Lewis, holds that a conditional is true only when the corresponding material conditional is necessary. It remains a popular view of conditionals in logic and mathematics. It enjoys a revival in dynamic semantics, where changes in context allow for flexibility.

8 Neighborhood Strict Conditional The chief argument for the strict conditional is its ability to avoid the paradoxes of material implication by preventing If A, then B from following from not A or from B.

9 Neighborhood Rules These two accounts agree in their rules for exploiting conditional information: If A then B; A; therefore B (modus ponens) If A then B; not B; therefore not-a (modus tollens)

10 Neighborhood Admissibility They agree on a general strategy from establishing conditionals: To show If A, then B, assume A and derive B. They differ, however, about what information may be admitted in the course of that derivation. The material conditional allows any information to be used; the strict conditional allows only necessary information. On many conceptions of necessity, this implies that strict conditionals, if true, are necessarily true.

11 Neighborhood Counterfactuals The most popular account of counterfactual conditionals differs from both of the above: The variably strict conditional (R. Stalnaker, D. Lewis): If A, then it would be the case that B is true at a possible world w if and only if B is true in all the A-worlds closest to w. Counterfactuals are not material conditionals, for their antecedents are typically false, but they are not thereby true. They are not strict conditionals, for they do not satisfy inference patterns such as transitivity, contraposition, and strengthening of the antecedent.

12 Neighborhood Other Logics Four other conceptions of the conditional are subjects of active research:

13 Neighborhood Probabilistic The probabilistic conditional (E. Adams, R. Jeffrey, B. Ellis): This account replaces truth with probability: The probability of a conditional If A then B is the conditional probability of B on the condition that A. D. Lewis showed that this fails if there are three possible but pairwise incompatible sentences (such as p and q, p and not q, and q and not p). Its advocates, however, have proposed revisions treating embedded conditionals differently or replacing truth with assertibility.

14 Neighborhood Conditional Assertion The conditional assertion (D. Edgington): do not have truth values, for they are not assertions. Instead, they assert the consequent conditional on the truth of the antecedent. If A then B asserts that B, if A is true, and asserts nothing otherwise. This view was recognized but generally rejected (for example, by Paul of Venice) in medieval times because of the difficulty it has in explaining embedded conditionals.

15 Neighborhood Defeasible The defeasible conditional (N. Asher, M. Morreau): If A, then B is true at a possible world w if and only if B is true in all the A-worlds that are normal from the perspective of w. This view denies the deductive validity of modus ponens, since a world may be abnormal by its own lights. But it develops a concept of defeasible validity, which modus ponens does satisfy.

16 Neighborhood Relevant The relevant conditional (A. Anderson, N. Belnap, R. Routley, R. Meyer): If A, then B is true at a world w if and only if, for every pair < x, y > of test worlds relevant to w, if A is true at x, then B is true at y. Inspired by the Chrysippan thought that a conditional is true just when its antecedent implies its consequent, but seeking to deny implication in cases in which formulas are irrelevant to one another, this conditional satisfies modus ponens and counts a conditional valid only if antecedent and consequent share some propositional component.

17 Neighborhood Strict C. I. Lewis developed modal logic in large part to replace the material conditional of classical logic. The paradoxes of material implication are only the most obvious drawback of the material conditional. Lewis defines A B (A B), and proposes the strict conditional as an analysis of the natural language conditional.

18 Neighborhood Other Puzzling Inferences A A B B A B (A B) (B A) (A B) ( A B) ((A B) C) ((A C) (B C))

19 Neighborhood Paradoxes of Strict Implication It, however, is subject to the paradoxes of strict implication: A = A B B = A B

20 Neighborhood Other Inferences More seriously, it validates the following: Strengthening of the Antecedent. A B = (A C) B Transitivity. A B, B C = A C Contraposition. A B = B A

21 Neighborhood Counterfactuals But it seems that none is valid in general. Consider the counterfactuals: If Kennedy hadn t been assassinated, he would have been reelected. So, if Kennedy hadn t been assassinated, and, in fact, had never been born at all, he would have been reelected.

22 Neighborhood Counterfactuals If Kennedy hadn t been assassinated, he would have been reelected. If Kennedy had never been born, he wouldn t have been assassinated. So, if Kennedy had never been born, he would have been reelected.

23 Neighborhood Counterfactuals If Kennedy hadn t been assassinated, he would not have been reelected in So, if Kennedy had been reelected in 1964, he would have been assassinated.

24 Neighborhood Indicatives This might seem to distinguish subjunctive from indicative conditionals. But actually we can devise similar indicatives casting doubt on these inferences: If you strike the match, it will light. So, if you strike the match and there s no oxygen present, it will light. If Tweety is a bird, Tweety can fly. If Tweety is a penguin, Tweety is a bird. So, if Tweety is a penguin, Tweety can fly. If we don t operate, he won t survive. So, if he survives, we ll operate.

25 Neighborhood In Between The strict conditional looks at the entire set of possible worlds; A B holds iff every A-world is a B-world. The material conditional looks only at the world of evaluation. It seems reasonable to think that we need something in between. If we ask, What if Kennedy hadn t been assassinated?, we re asking about worlds other than the actual world but not about every world, or even every world in which Kennedy is assassinated. We presumably neglect worlds in which he is not shot in Dallas, but in which aliens take over the earth, or Buffy learns that he is a vampire and stakes him.

26 Neighborhood Well-Behaved Worlds? We might think that the relevant worlds are those that are in some sense well-behaved. It will not do, however, to isolate a set of well-behaved worlds, and limit our evaluations to those, for the above inferences would still be valid. Which set of worlds we choose depends on the antecedent under consideration. It seems plausible to think that it depends only on the antecedent and the world of evaluation, since we can meaningfully ask What if? questions, but that is a substantive hypothesis.

27 Neighborhood Selection Functions Let f w [A] be the set of worlds relevant to evaluating conditionals with A as antecedent in w. We might think of this as the set of closest A-worlds (Lewis), as the A-worlds most similar to the world of evaluation (also Lewis), or as the set of A-normal worlds (Asher and Morreau).

28 Neighborhood We can then characterize truth conditions for conditionals. A > B is true at w iff B is true at all the selected A-worlds: ν w (A > B) = 1 f w [A] [B]

29 Neighborhood Accessibility We can develop the same idea in terms of accessibility relations. Let a model I =< W, {R A : A F}, ν > be a triple consisting of a set of worlds, a set of accessibility relations for each formula, and an assignment function. We can define the accessibility relations in terms of the selection function, or vice versa; f w [A] = {w : wr A w }. We can thus express the truth condition as: ν w (A > B) = 1 w (wr A w ν w (B) = 1)

30 Neighborhood Modal Logic Notice the similarity between the truth condition expressed in this form and the truth condition for necessity. We have in effect defined a necessity operator relative to formulas: A > B A B.

31 Neighborhood Tableau Rules Tableau rules for > allow us to go from A > B, i and ir A j to B, j, and from (A > B), i to ir A j and B, j, where j is new. The logic that results, C, is very weak; among the few valid schemata are Weakening of the Consequent: A > B = A > (B C). A paradox of strict implication also holds; B = A > B. Even idempotence (A > A) and modus ponens (A > B, A = B) fail in C.

32 Neighborhood C and C+ C+ adds conditions to C that make idempotence and modus ponens valid. Nothing in C requires that the worlds relevant to evaluating conditionals with A as antecedent are A-worlds. Adding a rule allowing us to go from ir A j to A, j makes idempotence valid. That corresponds to a semantic constraint of facticity: f w [A] [A].

33 Neighborhood Closest A-worlds This is implicit in the terminology that Lewis introduces; the closest A-worlds are indeed A-worlds.

34 Neighborhood Centering We may validate modus ponens by splitting a branch into two: the left containing A, i, the right containing A, i and ir A i. That corresponds to a semantic constraint of Weak Centering: w [A] w f w [A]. The world of evaluation, if it is an A-world, is among the closest A-worlds to itself.

35 Neighborhood C+ Are there reasons for declining to adopt these conditions? Facticity is appealing, but conditional obligation would not accord with it. It may also be useful to deny it to devise a concept of an anomaly. There are some powerful reasons to reject modus ponens, which we will examine further in the context of nonmonotonic logic.

36 Neighborhood Spheres We might rank worlds according to their degree of closeness to w, forming a sequence of spheres S w 0 Sw 1... W. We can then define the selection function in terms of the system of spheres: f w [A] = if [A] = ; f w [A] = S w [A] for i the smallest S w overlapping [A]. i This validates the facticity and weak centering constraints.

37 Neighborhood Constraints It also validates three other constraints: [A] f w [A] f w [A] [B] f w [B] [A] f w [A] = f w [B] f w [A] [B] f w [A B] f w [A] The first of these is obvious: if there are A-worlds, there are closest A-worlds. The second says that if all the closest A-worlds are B-worlds, and all the closest B-worlds are A-worlds, then the closest A-worlds are exactly the closest B-worlds. That corresponds to the schema: (A > B) (B > A) = (A > C) (B > C)

38 Neighborhood Counterfactual Antecedents Say that A and B are tantamount to each other in w iff A > B and B > A are both true in w. This says that formulas that are tantamount to each other have the same counterfactual consequences. Since logically equivalent formulas are tantamount to each other, they too have the same counterfactual consequences; [A] = [B] f w [A] = f B (w). This justifies our thinking of the selection function as defined not by formulas but by propositions, that is, sets of worlds: A > B is true at w iff f [A] (w) [B].

39 Neighborhood Weak Transitivity This makes valid a series of weak transitivity inferences: A > B, B > A, B > C = A > C (A B), A > C = B > C A > B, (B > A), B > C = A > C

40 Neighborhood Strong Centering Lewis and Stalnaker extend this system in different ways. Lewis maintains that, if w is an A-world, it is the unique closest A-world to itself. The sphere system implies that w is, in those circumstances, among the closest A-worlds. The constraint of Strong Centering asserts that it is the only one; no world can be as close to w as w is to itself. w [A] w f w [A] w = w (or equivalently w [A] f w [A] = {w})

41 Neighborhood Strong Centering This validates the inference from a conjunction to a corresponding conditional: A B = A > B.

42 Neighborhood Stalnaker Stalnaker goes further. He assumes that the selection always yields a singleton, a unique closest world. His constraint: w f w [A] w f w [A] w = w (or equivalently w f w [A] f w [A] = {w }) This validates Conditional Excluded Middle: (A > B) (A > B).

43 Neighborhood Might Lewis defines might in terms of would, as follows: A B (A > B). Stalnaker plainly cannot do the same, since it would make might equivalent to would not in his system. So, he defines it differently: for Stalnaker, A B (A > B).

44 Neighborhood Ramsey Test We might follow the lead of Ramsey and Gentzen in taking testing as essential to conditionality. introduce antecedent-oriented situations, and then perform consequent-determined tests on them. Ramsey (1929, 155), for example, gives this account of what conditionals do: If two people are arguing If p, will q? and are both in doubt as to p, they are adding p hypothetically to their stock of knowledge and arguing on that basis about q.

45 Neighborhood Antecedents Abstracting from the epistemic character of this understanding, we can talk of what is the case, and think of the world-relativity of the conditional as linked specifically to the antecedent. The selection function f builds this into the semantics of the conditional; the proposition representing the antecedent A relative to a world w is a function f w [A] of the antecedent proposition [A] itself and w. We can think of f w [A] as the set of test worlds relative to A and w. On a pointwise conception, the conditional asserts that each test world satisfies B: f w [A] [B].

46 Neighborhood Generalizing The conditional, on a more general conception, relates the test proposition f w [A] to the consequent proposition [B]. We might express this as R(f w [A], B) [B] h(f w [A]) or, by analogy with the power set version, f w [A] g[b].

47 Neighborhood Neighborhood Semantics f w [A], on the neighborhood conception, picks out the modal neighborhood relevant to the testing of A in w. The conditional A B asserts that that neighborhood has the property associated with B. The test conception thus naturally leads to the truth condition w [A B] f w [A] g[b]

48 Neighborhood Weakness That truth condition is nevertheless extremely weak so weak, in fact, that it threatens to make conditionals inferentially inert. We have so far said nothing, however, about the nature of or relations between the functions f and g. The inferential features of the conditional spring from the assumptions we make about those natures and relations.

49 Neighborhood Weaker Logics We might think about placing some constraints on f and g to give us a richer logic and characterize the behavior of conditionals more faithfully.

50 Neighborhood Conservativity The earliest treatments of conditionals (e.g., in Theophrastus) linked their analysis to syllogisms; they reduced If A then B to All A-cases are B-cases. We might find something about this attractive even if we reject the assimilation of conditionals to universal affirmatives. Suppose we were to assume that a conditional corresponds to a quantifier of some type over cases or worlds. Then the general form of a truth conditional analysis ought to be something like Q([A], [B]) or, perhaps, Q(f w [A], [B]). But that is just a notational variant of f w [A] g[b].

51 Neighborhood Conservativity One linguistic universal applying to quantifiers but not to relations in general, however, is Conservativity (C): X g(y) X g(x Y)

52 Neighborhood Living on an Antecedent This constraint validates an inference pattern indicates that a conditional lives on its antecedent: A B = A (A B)

53 Neighborhood Monotonicity One attractive constraint stems naturally from the inferential role of the conditional. Suppose we introduce a subderivation starting with the assumption that A. We are now in a neighborhood f w [A] relevant to testing what happens if A. We proceed to apply logical rules to derive other formulas within the subproof.

54 Neighborhood Monotonicity Ignore for the moment the complication that some of these might come from outside the subproof, and think solely of the applications of rules within the subproof itself. If such application is possible, then we are assuming that if the neighborhood has the property associated with B, and B entails C, the neighborhood has the property associated with C.

55 Neighborhood Monotonicity Assuming that we wish our system of inference to permit the application of logical rules in subderivations, we would naturally want to assume that the function g giving the extensions of the associated properties is monotonic. Monotonicity (M): X Y g(x) g(y)

56 Neighborhood Monotonicity This constraint amounts to the assumption that the quantifier appropriate to the conditional is monotonic increasing. The powerset conception builds such an assumption into the truth condition, for it in effect assumes that the quantifier relevant to the conditional is all. It holds iff the conditional obeys weakening of the consequent. Weakening of the Consequent (W): A B & B = C A C

57 Neighborhood Additional Constraints The quantification constraint and the associated conservativity constraint, C, and monotonicity, M, are arguably the only constraints essential to the test and inferential role conceptions of the conditional. Those and only those properties are essential to conditionality.

58 Neighborhood Additional Constraints Most conditionals in the literature, however, are much stronger, validating many inference patterns inessential to conditionals as such. There may moreover be good arguments for imposing additional constraints, especially in certain contexts or as analyses of certain constructions. It is therefore important to explore additional algebraic constraints.

59 Neighborhood Downward Closure A constraint assumed in the powerset conception is downward closure. It corresponds to the assumption that the quantifier appropriate to the conditional is, in the language of Barwise and Cooper 1981, antipersistent (as all is). Downward Closure (D): X Y & Y g(z) X g(z)

60 Neighborhood Downward Closure The pointwise conception makes this attractive, for if something is true of a set of test conditions, it is tempting to think that it is true of each subset of that set. On the neighborhood conception, however, it is much less plausible. That a property holds of a neighborhood does not entail that it holds of each subset of the neighborhood.

61 Neighborhood Strengthening of the Antecedent Given certain assumptions about the selection function f, D holds iff the conditional validates the inference pattern: Strengthening of the Antecedent (SA): A = B & B C A C

62 Neighborhood Strengthening of the Antecedent That too would constitute an argument against D in many contexts, since SA is one of the inference patterns well known to be invalid for counterfactual conditionals. The Lewis and Asher-Morreau conditionals obey D, but do not validate SA, however, so the requisite assumptions about f are clearly quite strong. Assume that f([b], w) g[c] and [A] [B]. Given D, we can obtain f([a], w) g[c] if we have f([a], w) f([b], w). The constraint on f required to validate SA is thus the monotonicity of f: [A] [B] f w [A] f w [B]

63 Neighborhood Boundary Conditions on g Another set of constraints in effect impose boundary conditions on the conditional, telling us how g(x) and X relate to each other. Again, they are assumed in the powerset conception. Together with downward closure, they moreover entail that conception. Anchoring (ANCH): X g(x)

64 Neighborhood Boundary Conditions on g This seems plausible on the powerset conception; the things in X have the property associated with X. It seems somewhat less attractive in a more general setting; the neighborhood X does not necessarily itself have the property associated with it.

65 Neighborhood Seriality It is useful to assume a principle of seriality: Seriality (S): X Y X g(y)

66 Neighborhood Seriality This says that What if? questions always have answers. S, C, and M entail ANCH. Someone who maintains C can resist ANCH, therefore, but must give up M or S to do so.

67 Neighborhood Idempotence ANCH has some connection with idempotence, the validity of A A. But it suffices for it only in the company of two other assumptions: downward closure, which gives us Y X Y g(x), and boundedness, which yields f w [A] [A].

68 Neighborhood Boundary Conditions The following boundary condition limits g(x) to subsets of X. It says, in other words, that the property associated with a set holds only of subsets of that set. In a quantificational setting, this forces the relevant quantifier to be all. It is thus optional on a pointwise conception.

69 Neighborhood Boundary Conditions On a neighborhood conception, it says that the property associated with a neighborhood applies only to parts of that neighborhood. It thus specifies the property associated with a neighborhood as being a part of that neighborhood. That is one interpretation of the associated property admittedly, a fairly salient one but not by any means the only possible one. Limitation (L): g(x) X

70 Neighborhood Boundary Conditions These boundary conditions are very powerful. L entails g(x) (X) while ANCH and D together entail (X) g(x). ANCH, L, and D thus yield the powerset conception, which entails every constraint we have so far considered. Since ANCH follows from C, M, and S, {C, M, S, L, D} suffice for the powerset conception.

71 Neighborhood Theorem: C, M, S, L, D all Theorem: If g satisfies C, M, S, L, and D, then X g(y) iff X Y. Proof. Assume g satisfies C, M, S, L, and D. The right-to-left direction: Say X Y. By S, there is some Z such that Y g(z). By C, Y g(y Z). By M, Y g(y). But then, by D, X g(y). To proceed left-to-right: Assume that X g(y). By L, g(y) Y; so X Y.

72 Neighborhood C, L, D Since M and S seem plausible for any reasonable account of the conditional at least, any account based on inferential role and the test conception this suggests that one can move away from the assimilation of if to all only by denying C, L, or D.

73 Neighborhood Denying C The first is the most radical, amounting to the denial that a conditional is any kind of quantifier over cases, and rejecting the inference from A B to A (A B).

74 Neighborhood Denying L The second amounts to holding that If A then B can hold even if the A-worlds, or the selected A-worlds, are not all B-worlds. It thus amounts to the idea that a conditional can be true even though the antecedent could be true while the consequent was false. Lewis and Stalnaker conditionals already allow that possibility for worlds that are not among the closest A-worlds; Asher and Morreau already allow it for worlds that are not A-normal. Probabilistic and threshold conditionals adopt this strategy.

75 Neighborhood Denying D The third is to reject downward closure. Lewis, Stalnaker, Asher, and Morreau get the effect of rejecting downward closure by employing the selection function. Once the inference form in general is rejected, however, what s the argument for keeping it in the underlying logic?

76 Neighborhood Weaker Quantifiers There are candidates for quantifiers that would have these properties and might serve as ways of interpreting conditionals: most, the vast majority of, almost all, and, perhaps most plausibly, the null quantifier of generics such as Birds fly.

Indicative conditionals

Indicative conditionals Indicative conditionals PHIL 43916 November 14, 2012 1. Three types of conditionals... 1 2. Material conditionals... 1 3. Indicatives and possible worlds... 4 4. Conditionals and adverbs of quantification...

More information

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013 March 20, 2013 The earliest attempts to devise a relevance logic that avoided the problem of explosion centered on the conditional. FDE, however, has no conditional operator, or a very weak one. If we

More information

First-Degree Entailment

First-Degree Entailment March 5, 2013 Relevance Logics Relevance logics are non-classical logics that try to avoid the paradoxes of material and strict implication: p (q p) p (p q) (p q) (q r) (p p) q p (q q) p (q q) Counterintuitive?

More information

127: Lecture notes HT17. Week 8. (1) If Oswald didn t shoot Kennedy, someone else did. (2) If Oswald hadn t shot Kennedy, someone else would have.

127: Lecture notes HT17. Week 8. (1) If Oswald didn t shoot Kennedy, someone else did. (2) If Oswald hadn t shot Kennedy, someone else would have. I. Counterfactuals I.I. Indicative vs Counterfactual (LfP 8.1) The difference between indicative and counterfactual conditionals comes out in pairs like the following: (1) If Oswald didn t shoot Kennedy,

More information

(1) If Bush had not won the last election, then Nader would have won it.

(1) If Bush had not won the last election, then Nader would have won it. 24.221 Metaphysics Counterfactuals When the truth functional material conditional (or ) is introduced, it is normally glossed with the English expression If..., then.... However, if this is the correct

More information

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology Andrew Bacon 28th June 2013 1 The data You pick a card at random from a standard deck of cards. How confident should I be about asserting the following sentences?

More information

Propositional Logic Truth-functionality Definitions Soundness Completeness Inferences. Modal Logic. Daniel Bonevac.

Propositional Logic Truth-functionality Definitions Soundness Completeness Inferences. Modal Logic. Daniel Bonevac. January 22, 2013 Modal logic is, among other things, the logic of possibility and necessity. Its history goes back at least to Aristotle s discussion of modal syllogisms in the Prior Analytics. But modern

More information

about conditionals. It is a good example of what might be called systematic ordinary

about conditionals. It is a good example of what might be called systematic ordinary Wheeler: Lycan s Real Conditionals page 1 William Lycan s Real Conditionals (Oxford University Press 2001; isbn 0-19-924207-0; 223 pp.) Real Conditionals is the result of a couple of decades of William

More information

Propositional Logic. Spring Propositional Logic Spring / 32

Propositional Logic. Spring Propositional Logic Spring / 32 Propositional Logic Spring 2016 Propositional Logic Spring 2016 1 / 32 Introduction Learning Outcomes for this Presentation Learning Outcomes... At the conclusion of this session, we will Define the elements

More information

Propositional Logic Review

Propositional Logic Review Propositional Logic Review UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016 John MacFarlane The task of describing a logical system comes in three parts: Grammar Describing what counts as a formula Semantics Defining

More information

Notes on Inference and Deduction

Notes on Inference and Deduction Notes on Inference and Deduction Consider the following argument 1 Assumptions: If the races are fixed or the gambling houses are crooked, then the tourist trade will decline. If the tourist trade declines

More information

La logique des conditionnels. Rentrée Cogmaster

La logique des conditionnels. Rentrée Cogmaster La logique des conditionnels Rentrée Cogmaster M. Cozic & P. Egré IHPST/Paris 1, CNRS, DEC-ENS IJN, CNRS, DEC-ENS What are conditional sentences? If P then Q (1) If it s a square, then it s rectangle.

More information

Capturing Lewis s Elusive Knowledge

Capturing Lewis s Elusive Knowledge Zhaoqing Xu Department of Philosophy, Peking University zhaoqingxu@gmail.com September 22, 2011 1 Introduction 2 Philosophical Background Dretske s Relevant Alternatives Theory Lewis s Elusive Knowledge

More information

Natural deduction for truth-functional logic

Natural deduction for truth-functional logic Natural deduction for truth-functional logic Phil 160 - Boston University Why natural deduction? After all, we just found this nice method of truth-tables, which can be used to determine the validity or

More information

Aim of today s lecture. From syllogism to common sense: atourthroughthelogicallandscape Conditionals. What are conditionals? And now...

Aim of today s lecture. From syllogism to common sense: atourthroughthelogicallandscape Conditionals. What are conditionals? And now... Aim of today s lecture From syllogism to common sense: atourthroughthelogicallandscape Conditionals Mehul Bhatt Oliver Kutz Thomas Schneider 12 January 2012 Interpreting the implication p q via the truth

More information

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus 3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus 1. Interpretations Formulas of the propositional calculus express statement forms. In chapter two, we gave informal descriptions of the meanings of the logical

More information

Module 7 D and Equivalent Systems

Module 7 D and Equivalent Systems Module 7 D and Equivalent Systems G J Mattey May 2, 2007 Contents 1 he Semantical System DI 1 2 he Derivational System DD 4 3 he Axiom System D 6 4 Applications of the D-Systems 6 In this and subsequent

More information

Propositional Logic. Fall () Propositional Logic Fall / 30

Propositional Logic. Fall () Propositional Logic Fall / 30 Propositional Logic Fall 2013 () Propositional Logic Fall 2013 1 / 30 1 Introduction Learning Outcomes for this Presentation 2 Definitions Statements Logical connectives Interpretations, contexts,... Logically

More information

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge 1 3 Conceivability and Modal Knowledge Christopher Hill ( 2006 ) provides an account of modal knowledge that is set in a broader context of arguing against the view that conceivability provides epistemic

More information

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10 Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10 Philosophy 691: Conditionals Northern Illinois University Fall 2011 Geoff Pynn terminology 1. Chapters 10-18 concern subjunctive conditionals, which Bennett distinguishes

More information

Conditionals. Chapter 11. Frank Jackson. The Equivalence Theory

Conditionals. Chapter 11. Frank Jackson. The Equivalence Theory Chapter 11 Conditionals Frank Jackson Examples of conditionals are: If it rains, then the match will be canceled, If Oswald did not shoot Kennedy, then someone else did, and If Carter had been re-elected,

More information

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa Kai von Fintel and Anthony S. Gillies MIT and Rutgers November 21 University of Latvia Ramsey s Test If two people are arguing If p will q? and are both in doubt as to p,

More information

Philosophy 244: #8 Counterfactuals, Neighborhood Semantics, Probability, Predicative Necessity, etc.

Philosophy 244: #8 Counterfactuals, Neighborhood Semantics, Probability, Predicative Necessity, etc. Philosophy 244: #8 Counterfactuals, Neighborhood Semantics, Probability, Predicative Necessity, etc. Modal operators are non-truth-functional; the truth-value of α at a world is not determined by α s s

More information

Section 1.2: Propositional Logic

Section 1.2: Propositional Logic Section 1.2: Propositional Logic January 17, 2017 Abstract Now we re going to use the tools of formal logic to reach logical conclusions ( prove theorems ) based on wffs formed by some given statements.

More information

Epistemic Modals and Informational Consequence

Epistemic Modals and Informational Consequence Epistemic Modals and Informational Consequence [This is a penultimate draft. Please quote only from the published version. The paper is already available through Online First at http://www.springerlink.com/content/0039-7857]

More information

Logic, Sets, and Proofs

Logic, Sets, and Proofs Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A. Cox and Catherine C. McGeoch Amherst College 1 Logic Logical Operators. A logical statement is a mathematical statement that can be assigned a value either true or false.

More information

Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009

Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009 1 Propositional Logic Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009 1.1 More efficient truth table methods The method of using truth tables to prove facts about propositional formulas can be a very tedious

More information

A Little Deductive Logic

A Little Deductive Logic A Little Deductive Logic In propositional or sentential deductive logic, we begin by specifying that we will use capital letters (like A, B, C, D, and so on) to stand in for sentences, and we assume that

More information

6. Conditional derivations

6. Conditional derivations 6. Conditional derivations 6.1 An argument from Hobbes In his great work, Leviathan, the philosopher Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) gives an important argument for government. Hobbes begins by claiming that

More information

A Quick Lesson on Negation

A Quick Lesson on Negation A Quick Lesson on Negation Several of the argument forms we have looked at (modus tollens and disjunctive syllogism, for valid forms; denying the antecedent for invalid) involve a type of statement which

More information

Doxastic Logic. Michael Caie

Doxastic Logic. Michael Caie Doxastic Logic Michael Caie There are at least three natural ways of interpreting the object of study of doxastic logic. On one construal, doxastic logic studies certain general features of the doxastic

More information

(So-Called) Paradoxes of Material Implication. Recall the truth table for the material conditional:

(So-Called) Paradoxes of Material Implication. Recall the truth table for the material conditional: (So-Called) Paradoxes of Material Implication Recall the truth table for the material conditional: ϕ 1 ϕ 2 (ϕ 1 ϕ 2 ) T T T T F F F T T F F T There are a number of places where the material conditional

More information

Contingent Existence and Iterated Modality

Contingent Existence and Iterated Modality !1 Contingent Existence and Iterated Modality CIAN DORR Boris Kment s Modality and Explanatory Reasoning is a rich and rewarding book. Along the way to his conclusions about the cognitive function of modal

More information

Berlin, May 16 / 2003

Berlin, May 16 / 2003 Berlin, May 16 / 2003 1 The challenge of free choice permission The basic puzzle epistemic variants wide disjunction FC permission and quantification Conjunctive permission 2 The basic puzzle (1) a. You

More information

Non-normal Worlds. Daniel Bonevac. February 5, 2012

Non-normal Worlds. Daniel Bonevac. February 5, 2012 Non-normal Worlds Daniel Bonevac February 5, 2012 Lewis and Langford (1932) devised five basic systems of modal logic, S1 - S5. S4 and S5, as we have seen, are normal systems, equivalent to K ρτ and K

More information

Module 5 K and Equivalent Systems

Module 5 K and Equivalent Systems Module 5 K and Equivalent Systems G. J. Mattey July 8, 2010 Contents 1 The Semantical System KI 2 1.1 Specification of KI....................................... 2 1.2 Semantical Properties and Relations

More information

Proofs: A General How To II. Rules of Inference. Rules of Inference Modus Ponens. Rules of Inference Addition. Rules of Inference Conjunction

Proofs: A General How To II. Rules of Inference. Rules of Inference Modus Ponens. Rules of Inference Addition. Rules of Inference Conjunction Introduction I Proofs Computer Science & Engineering 235 Discrete Mathematics Christopher M. Bourke cbourke@cse.unl.edu A proof is a proof. What kind of a proof? It s a proof. A proof is a proof. And when

More information

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds 1. Epistemically possible worlds David Chalmers Metaphysically possible worlds: S is metaphysically possible iff S is true in some metaphysically possible

More information

Nonmonotonic Logic. Daniel Bonevac. April 16, Accident victims who are cool to the touch may be in shock.

Nonmonotonic Logic. Daniel Bonevac. April 16, Accident victims who are cool to the touch may be in shock. Nonmonotonic Logic Daniel Bonevac April 16, 2012 We organize our thought with general principles: 1. 2. Acids are corrosive. 3. Handguns are dangerous. 4. Promises ought to be kept. 5. What goes up must

More information

A new resolution of the Judy Benjamin problem

A new resolution of the Judy Benjamin problem A new resolution of the Judy Benjamin problem Igor Douven Institute of Philosophy University of Leuven Jan-Willem Romeijn Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen Contents 1 The Judy Benjamin problem

More information

Equivalents of Mingle and Positive Paradox

Equivalents of Mingle and Positive Paradox Eric Schechter Equivalents of Mingle and Positive Paradox Abstract. Relevant logic is a proper subset of classical logic. It does not include among itstheoremsanyof positive paradox A (B A) mingle A (A

More information

SEMANTICAL CONSIDERATIONS ON NONMONOTONIC LOGIC. Robert C. Moore Artificial Intelligence Center SRI International, Menlo Park, CA 94025

SEMANTICAL CONSIDERATIONS ON NONMONOTONIC LOGIC. Robert C. Moore Artificial Intelligence Center SRI International, Menlo Park, CA 94025 SEMANTICAL CONSIDERATIONS ON NONMONOTONIC LOGIC Robert C. Moore Artificial Intelligence Center SRI International, Menlo Park, CA 94025 ABSTRACT Commonsense reasoning is "nonmonotonic" in the sense that

More information

Presuppositions (introductory comments)

Presuppositions (introductory comments) 1 Presuppositions (introductory comments) Some examples (1) a. The person who broke the typewriter was Sam. b. It was Sam who broke the typewriter. c. John screwed up again. d. John likes Mary, too. e.

More information

Proofs. Introduction II. Notes. Notes. Notes. Slides by Christopher M. Bourke Instructor: Berthe Y. Choueiry. Fall 2007

Proofs. Introduction II. Notes. Notes. Notes. Slides by Christopher M. Bourke Instructor: Berthe Y. Choueiry. Fall 2007 Proofs Slides by Christopher M. Bourke Instructor: Berthe Y. Choueiry Fall 2007 Computer Science & Engineering 235 Introduction to Discrete Mathematics Sections 1.5, 1.6, and 1.7 of Rosen cse235@cse.unl.edu

More information

Formal Logic. Critical Thinking

Formal Logic. Critical Thinking ormal Logic Critical hinking Recap: ormal Logic If I win the lottery, then I am poor. I win the lottery. Hence, I am poor. his argument has the following abstract structure or form: If P then Q. P. Hence,

More information

From Causal Models To Counterfactual Structures

From Causal Models To Counterfactual Structures From Causal Models To Counterfactual Structures Joseph Y. Halpern Cornell University halpern@cs.cornell.edu June 14, 2011 Abstract Galles and Pearl [1998] claimed that for recursive models, the causal

More information

In this chapter, we specify a deductive apparatus for PL.

In this chapter, we specify a deductive apparatus for PL. Handout 5 PL Derivations In this chapter, we specify a deductive apparatus for PL Definition deductive apparatus A deductive apparatus for PL is a set of rules of inference (or derivation rules) that determine

More information

Tooley on backward causation

Tooley on backward causation Tooley on backward causation Paul Noordhof Michael Tooley has argued that, if backward causation (of a certain kind) is possible, then a Stalnaker-Lewis account of the truth conditions of counterfactuals

More information

Must... stay... strong!

Must... stay... strong! Alex Goebel 620 Spring 2016 Paper Presentation of von Fintel & Gillies (2010) Synopsis Must... stay... strong! Von Fintel & Gillies (vf&g) argue against a weakened semantics of must and propose an alternative

More information

2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary. Aaron Tan August 2017

2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary. Aaron Tan August 2017 2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary Aaron Tan 21 25 August 2017 1 2. The Logic of Compound Statements 2.1 Logical Form and Logical Equivalence Statements; Compound Statements; Statement Form (Propositional

More information

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/8/16

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/8/16 Propositional Logic (5A) Young W. Lim Copyright (c) 2016 Young W. Lim. Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License, Version

More information

Foundations of Advanced Mathematics, version 0.8. Jonathan J. White

Foundations of Advanced Mathematics, version 0.8. Jonathan J. White Foundations of Advanced Mathematics, version 0.8 Jonathan J. White 1/4/17 2 Chapter 1 Basic Number Theory and Logic Forward These notes are intended to provide a solid background for the study of abstract

More information

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 2/23/17

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 2/23/17 Propositional Logic (5A) Young W. Lim Copyright (c) 2016 Young W. Lim. Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License, Version

More information

Abstract: In this paper, I present a schema for generating counterexamples to the

Abstract: In this paper, I present a schema for generating counterexamples to the Why Hypothetical Syllogism is Invalid for Indicative Conditionals Moti Mizrahi St. John s University [Forthcoming in Thought: A Journal of Philosophy] Abstract: In this paper, I present a schema for generating

More information

8. Reductio ad absurdum

8. Reductio ad absurdum 8. Reductio ad absurdum 8.1 A historical example In his book, The Two New Sciences, Galileo Galilea (1564-1642) gives several arguments meant to demonstrate that there can be no such thing as actual infinities

More information

HANDOUT AND SET THEORY. Ariyadi Wijaya

HANDOUT AND SET THEORY. Ariyadi Wijaya HANDOUT LOGIC AND SET THEORY Ariyadi Wijaya Mathematics Education Department Faculty of Mathematics and Natural Science Yogyakarta State University 2009 1 Mathematics Education Department Faculty of Mathematics

More information

6. Conditional derivations

6. Conditional derivations 6. Conditional derivations 6.1 An argument from Hobbes In his great work, Leviathan, the philosopher Thomas Hobbes gives an important argument for government. Hobbes begins by claiming that without a common

More information

Formal (natural) deduction in propositional logic

Formal (natural) deduction in propositional logic Formal (natural) deduction in propositional logic Lila Kari University of Waterloo Formal (natural) deduction in propositional logic CS245, Logic and Computation 1 / 67 I know what you re thinking about,

More information

CHAPTER 1 - LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS

CHAPTER 1 - LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS CHAPTER 1 - LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS 1.1 - Logical Form and Logical Equivalence Definition. A statement or proposition is a sentence that is either true or false, but not both. ex. 1 + 2 = 3 IS a statement

More information

Against Preservation

Against Preservation Against Preservation Matthew Mandelkern * and Justin Khoo July 22, 2018 Penultimate draft; to appear in Analysis Abstract Richard Bradley offers a quick and convincing argument that no Boolean semantic

More information

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation. Outline 1 2 3 4 5 1 / 41 2 / 41 The Liar Sentence Let L be the sentence: This sentence is false This sentence causes trouble If it is true, then it is false So it can t be true Thus, it is false If it

More information

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer Last time, when discussing the surprise exam paradox, we discussed the possibility that some claims could be true, but not knowable by certain individuals

More information

Glossary of Logical Terms

Glossary of Logical Terms Math 304 Spring 2007 Glossary of Logical Terms The following glossary briefly describes some of the major technical logical terms used in this course. The glossary should be read through at the beginning

More information

Neale and the slingshot Fabrice Correia

Neale and the slingshot Fabrice Correia a Neale and the slingshot Fabrice Correia 'Slingshot arguments' is a label for a class of arguments which includes Church's argument to the effect that if sentences designate propositions, then there are

More information

Counterfactuals as Strict Conditionals

Counterfactuals as Strict Conditionals Counterfactuals as Strict Conditionals University of Turin BIBLID [0873-626X (2015) 41; pp. 165-191] Abstract This paper defends the thesis that counterfactuals are strict conditionals. Its purpose is

More information

Conditionals. Ray Briggs Stanford University

Conditionals. Ray Briggs Stanford University Conditionals Ray Briggs Stanford University Example Conditionals 1. If the Axiom of Choice is true, then every set can be well ordered. 2. You will probably get lung cancer if you smoke. 3. If the syrup

More information

4 Derivations in the Propositional Calculus

4 Derivations in the Propositional Calculus 4 Derivations in the Propositional Calculus 1. Arguments Expressed in the Propositional Calculus We have seen that we can symbolize a wide variety of statement forms using formulas of the propositional

More information

Modal Sentential Logic I

Modal Sentential Logic I Modal Sentential Logic I G J Mattey July 20, 2001 1 Syntax of MSL Modal Sentential Logic (MSL) is a formal language which is an extension of Sentential Logic (SL) All expressions of SL are expressions

More information

8. Reductio ad absurdum

8. Reductio ad absurdum 8. Reductio ad absurdum 8.1 A historical example In his book, The Two New Sciences, 10 Galileo Galilea (1564-1642) gives several arguments meant to demonstrate that there can be no such thing as actual

More information

The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern AAL/ALC Modal 2011 Logic 1 / 26

The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern AAL/ALC Modal 2011 Logic 1 / 26 The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern Modal Logic Edwin Mares Victoria University of Wellington AAL/ALC 2011 The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern

More information

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/30/16

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/30/16 Propositional Logic (5A) Young W. Lim Copyright (c) 2016 Young W. Lim. Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License, Version

More information

Generality & Existence II

Generality & Existence II Generality & Existence II Modality & Quantifiers Greg Restall arché, st andrews 2 december 2015 My Aim To analyse the quantifiers Greg Restall Generality & Existence II 2 of 60 My Aim To analyse the quantifiers

More information

A Little Deductive Logic

A Little Deductive Logic A Little Deductive Logic In propositional or sentential deductive logic, we begin by specifying that we will use capital letters (like A, B, C, D, and so on) to stand in for sentences, and we assume that

More information

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Winter

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Winter CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH Winter 2017 http://cseweb.ucsd.edu/classes/wi17/cse20-ab/ Today's learning goals Distinguish between a theorem, an axiom, lemma, a corollary, and a conjecture. Recognize direct proofs

More information

Chapter 1 Elementary Logic

Chapter 1 Elementary Logic 2017-2018 Chapter 1 Elementary Logic The study of logic is the study of the principles and methods used in distinguishing valid arguments from those that are not valid. The aim of this chapter is to help

More information

5. And. 5.1 The conjunction

5. And. 5.1 The conjunction 5. And 5.1 The conjunction To make our logical language more easy and intuitive to use, we can now add to it elements that make it able to express the equivalents of other sentences from a natural language

More information

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1 Logic One reason for studying logic is that we need a better notation than ordinary English for expressing relationships among various assertions or hypothetical states of affairs. A solid grounding in

More information

Collins' notes on Lemmon's Logic

Collins' notes on Lemmon's Logic Collins' notes on Lemmon's Logic (i) Rule of ssumption () Insert any formula at any stage into a proof. The assumed formula rests upon the assumption of itself. (ii) Double Negation (DN) a. b. ( Two negations

More information

Precis of Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic

Precis of Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. XC No. 3, May 2015 doi: 10.1111/phpr.12185 2015 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Precis of Aristotle

More information

Propositional Logic. Jason Filippou UMCP. ason Filippou UMCP) Propositional Logic / 38

Propositional Logic. Jason Filippou UMCP. ason Filippou UMCP) Propositional Logic / 38 Propositional Logic Jason Filippou CMSC250 @ UMCP 05-31-2016 ason Filippou (CMSC250 @ UMCP) Propositional Logic 05-31-2016 1 / 38 Outline 1 Syntax 2 Semantics Truth Tables Simplifying expressions 3 Inference

More information

Proof strategies, or, a manual of logical style

Proof strategies, or, a manual of logical style Proof strategies, or, a manual of logical style Dr Holmes September 27, 2017 This is yet another version of the manual of logical style I have been working on for many years This semester, instead of posting

More information

Manual of Logical Style

Manual of Logical Style Manual of Logical Style Dr. Holmes January 9, 2015 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Conjunction 3 2.1 Proving a conjunction...................... 3 2.2 Using a conjunction........................ 3 3 Implication

More information

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH Fall 2017 http://cseweb.ucsd.edu/classes/fa17/cse20-ab/ Today's learning goals Distinguish between a theorem, an axiom, lemma, a corollary, and a conjecture. Recognize direct proofs

More information

Chapter 1, Logic and Proofs (3) 1.6. Rules of Inference

Chapter 1, Logic and Proofs (3) 1.6. Rules of Inference CSI 2350, Discrete Structures Chapter 1, Logic and Proofs (3) Young-Rae Cho Associate Professor Department of Computer Science Baylor University 1.6. Rules of Inference Basic Terminology Axiom: a statement

More information

Introduction to Metalogic

Introduction to Metalogic Philosophy 135 Spring 2008 Tony Martin Introduction to Metalogic 1 The semantics of sentential logic. The language L of sentential logic. Symbols of L: Remarks: (i) sentence letters p 0, p 1, p 2,... (ii)

More information

CSCI.6962/4962 Software Verification Fundamental Proof Methods in Computer Science (Arkoudas and Musser) Chapter p. 1/33

CSCI.6962/4962 Software Verification Fundamental Proof Methods in Computer Science (Arkoudas and Musser) Chapter p. 1/33 CSCI.6962/4962 Software Verification Fundamental Proof Methods in Computer Science (Arkoudas and Musser) Chapter 4.1-4.8 p. 1/33 CSCI.6962/4962 Software Verification Fundamental Proof Methods in Computer

More information

Logic and Proofs. (A brief summary)

Logic and Proofs. (A brief summary) Logic and Proofs (A brief summary) Why Study Logic: To learn to prove claims/statements rigorously To be able to judge better the soundness and consistency of (others ) arguments To gain the foundations

More information

THE LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS

THE LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS THE LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS All dogs have four legs. All tables have four legs. Therefore, all dogs are tables LOGIC Logic is a science of the necessary laws of thought, without which no employment

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

Axiomatic systems. Revisiting the rules of inference. Example: A theorem and its proof in an abstract axiomatic system:

Axiomatic systems. Revisiting the rules of inference. Example: A theorem and its proof in an abstract axiomatic system: Axiomatic systems Revisiting the rules of inference Material for this section references College Geometry: A Discovery Approach, 2/e, David C. Kay, Addison Wesley, 2001. In particular, see section 2.1,

More information

1.1 Statements and Compound Statements

1.1 Statements and Compound Statements Chapter 1 Propositional Logic 1.1 Statements and Compound Statements A statement or proposition is an assertion which is either true or false, though you may not know which. That is, a statement is something

More information

CSE 20: Discrete Mathematics

CSE 20: Discrete Mathematics Spring 2018 Summary Last time: Today: Logical connectives: not, and, or, implies Using Turth Tables to define logical connectives Logical equivalences, tautologies Some applications Proofs in propositional

More information

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/29/16

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/29/16 Propositional Logic (5A) Young W. Lim Copyright (c) 2016 Young W. Lim. Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License, Version

More information

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv + 408 pages by Bradley Monton June 24, 2009 It probably goes without saying that

More information

References A CONSTRUCTIVE INTRODUCTION TO FIRST ORDER LOGIC. The Starting Point. Goals of foundational programmes for logic:

References A CONSTRUCTIVE INTRODUCTION TO FIRST ORDER LOGIC. The Starting Point. Goals of foundational programmes for logic: A CONSTRUCTIVE INTRODUCTION TO FIRST ORDER LOGIC Goals of foundational programmes for logic: Supply an operational semantic basis for extant logic calculi (ex post) Rational reconstruction of the practice

More information

The Process of Mathematical Proof

The Process of Mathematical Proof 1 The Process of Mathematical Proof Introduction. Mathematical proofs use the rules of logical deduction that grew out of the work of Aristotle around 350 BC. In previous courses, there was probably an

More information

CHAPTER 2 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

CHAPTER 2 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC CHAPTER 2 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 1 Motivation and History The origins of the classical propositional logic, classical propositional calculus, as it was, and still often is called,

More information

An Invitation to Modal Logic: Lecture 1

An Invitation to Modal Logic: Lecture 1 An Invitation to Modal Logic: Lecture 1 Philosophy 150 Eric Pacuit Stanford University November 26, 2007 Eric Pacuit: Invitation to Modal Logic, Philosophy 150 1 Setting the Stage Much of this course has

More information

Logic and Mathematics:

Logic and Mathematics: Logic and Mathematics: Mathematicians in Schools Program Lashi Bandara Mathematical Sciences Institute, Australian National University April 21, 2011 Contents 1 Russell s Paradox 1 2 Propositional Logic

More information

Logic for Computer Science - Week 4 Natural Deduction

Logic for Computer Science - Week 4 Natural Deduction Logic for Computer Science - Week 4 Natural Deduction 1 Introduction In the previous lecture we have discussed some important notions about the semantics of propositional logic. 1. the truth value of a

More information