Finite Automata, Random Fields, Quantum Fluctuations, and Bell Inequalities

Similar documents
Statistical Mechanics

Delayed Choice Paradox

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Michael H. Shulman, 2006 (Revisited ) WHY QUANTUM MECHANICS IS NON-LOCAL?

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

Phase Transitions. µ a (P c (T ), T ) µ b (P c (T ), T ), (3) µ a (P, T c (P )) µ b (P, T c (P )). (4)

Lecture 14, Thurs March 2: Nonlocal Games

INTRODUCTORY NOTES ON QUANTUM COMPUTATION

Dependent (Contextual) Events

MAKING BOHMIAN MECHANICS COMPATIBLE WITH RELATIVITY AND QUANTUM FIELD THEORY. Hrvoje Nikolić Rudjer Bošković Institute, Zagreb, Croatia

A Uni ed Sheaf-Theoretic Account of Non-Locality and Contextuality: Part I

Topic 10: Bohm s Theory

How quantization of gravity leads to a discrete space-time

Objective probability-like things with and without objective indeterminism

Where is quantum theory headed?

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem. Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

Understanding the path-entangled communications device

Numerical Methods in Quantum Field Theories

Pure Quantum States Are Fundamental, Mixtures (Composite States) Are Mathematical Constructions: An Argument Using Algorithmic Information Theory

From the Kochen-Specker theorem to noncontextuality inequalities without assuming determinism

Question 1: Axiomatic Newtonian mechanics

The Two-State Vector Formalism

Monte Carlo (MC) Simulation Methods. Elisa Fadda

Quantum Measurements: some technical background

de = j ν dvdωdtdν. (1)

Renormalization Group: non perturbative aspects and applications in statistical and solid state physics.

Caltech Ph106 Fall 2001

Relativistic Quantum Mechanics

Verschränkung versus Stosszahlansatz: The second law rests on low correlation levels in our cosmic neighborhood

RUNS: A_B, A_B', A'_B,

Does the ψ-epistemic view really solve the measurement problem?

Quantum Thermodynamics

Causality and Local Determinism versus Quantum Nonlocality.

Quantum Gravity Phenomenology

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

Phase Transitions: A Challenge for Reductionism?

The subquantum arrow of time

PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICS. \Hp. Ni Jun TSINGHUA. Physics. From Quantum Field Theory. to Classical Mechanics. World Scientific. Vol.2. Report and Review in

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

84 My God, He Plays Dice! Chapter 12. Irreversibility. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/reversibility

Two-State Vector Formalism

From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity. Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL

Lecture 11: Continuous-valued signals and differential entropy

Length Contraction on Rotating Disc: an Argument for the Lorentzian Approach to Relativity

An interpretation of the squared amplitude of a solution of the Schrodinger wave equation. Tim C Jenkins.

19 Entanglement Entropy in Quantum Field Theory

where the last equality follows from the divergence theorem. Now since we did this for an arbitrary volume τ, it must hold locally:

Does time-symmetry in quantum theory imply retrocausality?

The Consistency of Quantum Mechanics Implies Its Non-Determinism arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 19 Oct 2010

3. Quantum Mechanics in 3D

Physics 411 Lecture 22. E&M and Sources. Lecture 22. Physics 411 Classical Mechanics II

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

9 Quantum Field Theory for Children

1. Why photons? 2. Photons in a vacuum

Why quantum field theory?

A Deeper Look into Phase Space: The Liouville and Boltzmann Equations

1 Realist and empiricist interpretations of quantum mechanics

1.1.1 Bell Inequality - Spin correlation

Singlet State Correlations

On the role of Decoherence in Bohmian Mechanics

Astro 507 Lecture 28 April 2, 2014

Decoherence and the Classical Limit

Statistical Mechanics in a Nutshell

A Brief Introduction to Statistical Mechanics

Bell s Theorem...What?! Entanglement and Other Puzzles

Why Complexity is Different

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

arxiv:gr-qc/ v2 30 Oct 2005

Equilibrium, out of equilibrium and consequences

April 18, 2018 Dr. Matthew Leifer HSC112

Path Integrals in Quantum Field Theory C6, HT 2014

Solving the Einstein Podolsky Rosen puzzle: The origin of non-locality in Aspect-type experiments

Quantum Black Holes and Global Symmetries

Note 1: Some Fundamental Mathematical Properties of the Tetrad.

Entanglement. arnoldzwicky.org. Presented by: Joseph Chapman. Created by: Gina Lorenz with adapted PHYS403 content from Paul Kwiat, Brad Christensen

Lecture 1 - Electrons, Photons and Phonons. September 4, 2002

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 7 Nov 2005

Construction of Field Theories

arxiv: v2 [physics.pop-ph] 12 Jul 2012

For the seminar: Ausgewählte Probleme der Quantenmechanik Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna, WS 2011/2012 Christian Knobloch a

Problem Set: TT Quantum Information

ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* I. Introduction

Advanced Quantum Mechanics, Notes based on online course given by Leonard Susskind - Lecture 8

CONSTRAINED PERCOLATION ON Z 2

The particle model for the Higgs condensate and the anomalous geometrical diffraction

The Uniqueness of Maxwell's Equations Dr. Christopher S. Baird University of Massachusetts Lowell

Phase Transitions: A Challenge for Reductionism?

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

The Quantum Universe

IV. Classical Statistical Mechanics

Equivalence of Kelvin-Planck and Clausius statements

The Franck-Hertz Experiment David Ward The College of Charleston Phys 370/Experimental Physics Spring 1997

MSci EXAMINATION. Date: XX th May, Time: 14:30-17:00

The Vacuum and the Cosmological Constant Problem

electrodynamics and Lorentz violation

4.1 Constant (T, V, n) Experiments: The Helmholtz Free Energy

Transcription:

Finite Automata, Random Fields, Quantum Fluctuations, and Bell Inequalities Peter Morgan, Yale University NKS 2007 Wolfram Science Conference Small-scale physics is probabilistic/statistical. In the presence of significant thermal or quantum fluctuations, a probabilistic approach is needed. NKS Chapter 6 looks for patterns in the evolution of randomly chosen single instances of an underlying system. 1

A random field is an indexed set of random variables. A lattice as an index set is appropriate for a probabilistic approach to finite automata. A random field deals with evolution of probabilities directly, instead of with an underlying classical evolution. The NKS community does not make enough contact with the Bell inequalities argument, which is probabilistic. Some of the resistance of the Physics community to NKS is because finite automata appear to satisfy the assumptions required to derive Bell inequalities. Three necessities: an NKS approach must have a non-trivial concept of a particle that is not point-like. an NKS approach must have a contextual measurement model (best to model experiments instead of measurements). an NKS approach must model quantum and thermal fluctuations. 2

Quantum fluctuations for the Klein-Gordon field The Klein-Gordon field is differentiable and satisfies the differential equation 2 φ t 2 φ 2 x 2 φ 2 y 2 φ 2 z + 2 m2 φ = 0. My work is with continuous random fields, which are closely related to quantum fields (not with an infinitesimal lattice as index set, but sort of). There is a quantized Klein-Gordon field, and there is also a classical Klein-Gordon random field. A continuous random field is not a continuous field, there is a probabilistic fractal structure all the way down. I have no ontological commitment to continuity. Continuity is just mathematically useful. For the Klein-Gordon random field, interactions and renormalization are not dealt with (so physicists are not much impressed). 3

The Gibbs probability density for the equilibrium state of the classical Klein-Gordon random field at temperature T : ρ C [Φ t ] N = e βh[φ t] = exp 1 k B T Φ t (k) 1 ( 2 k 2 + m 2) Φt (k) d3 k (2π) 3 The probability density for the vacuum state of the quantized Klein-Gordon field (on any hyperplane): ρ 0 [Φ t ] N = exp 1 h Φ t (k) k 2 + m 2 Φ t (k) d3 k (2π) 3 Four changes to obtain the quantum case: there s a square root; k B T becomes Planck s constant (with action units instead of energy units); the Lorentz symmetry (the classical Klein-Gordon dynamics is Lorentz invariant, but the Gibbs probability density as an initial condition is not). there is also a restriction to positive frequency in the quantum vacuum state. 4

The Gibbs probability density for the equilibrium state of the classical Klein-Gordon random field at temperature T : ρ C [Φ t ] N = e βh[φ t] = exp 1 k B T Φ t (k) 1 ( 2 k 2 + m 2) Φt (k) d3 k (2π) 3 The probability density for the vacuum state of the quantized Klein-Gordon field (on any hyperplane): ρ 0 [Φ t ] N = exp 1 h Φ t (k) k 2 + m 2 Φ t (k) d3 k (2π) 3 The equilibrium state probability density of the quantized Klein-Gordon field at temperature T : ρ T [Φ t ] N = exp 1 h h k 2 + m 2 tanh 2k B T Φ t (k) k 2 + m 2 Φ t (k) d3 k (2π) 3 There is a difference between quantum fluctuations and thermal fluctuations, and this is the best characterization of what the difference is (that I know of). 5

Bell inequalities for random fields Bell inequalities can be derived for non-contextual particle property models. Bell inequalities cannot be derived for random fields that have thermal or quantum fluctuations. I argue this at length in J. Phys. A 39 (2006) 7441-7455. We can use four random variables to model an experiment that violates a Bell inequality: s A and A are measurement settings and measurement results associated with a space-time region A. s B and B are measurement settings and measurement results associated with a space-time region B. s A, A A B s B, B In fact, we only have statistics, but we take probabilities to be good models for statistics. 6

time t 1 t 2 t 2 +ɛ t 3 t 4 t 5 place A A B A B B measurement setting s A or s a 2 a 1 b 2 a 1 b 2 b 1 B measurement result A or B + + + + The experimental data we have is a list of events: the times and places at which the events happened, the settings, and the results. In general we have control neither of when measurement events happen nor of the measurement settings. This is still idealized, but less so than a probability distribution. 7

time t 1 t 2 t 2 +ɛ t 3 t 4 t 5 place A A B A B B measurement setting s A or s a 2 a 1 b 2 a 1 b 2 b 1 B measurement result A or B + + + + The source sends pairs of photons, one in each direction. Each photon encounters a two-channel polariser whose orientation (s A = a 1 or a 2 ) can be set by the experimenter. Signals from each channel are detected and coincidences of four types (++,, + and +) are counted. 8

time t 1 t 2 t 2 +ɛ t 3 t 4 t 5 place A A B A B B measurement setting s A or s a 2 a 1 b 2 a 1 b 2 b 1 B measurement result A or B + + + + t 7 A 7 t 6 A 6 t 5 B 5 t 4 B 4 t 3 A 3 t 2 A 2 t 2 +ɛ B 2 t 1 A 1 9

time t 1 t 2 t 2 +ɛ t 3 t 4 t 5 place A A B A B B measurement setting s A or s a 2 a 1 b 2 a 1 b 2 b 1 B measurement result A or B + + + + We find pairs of events at nearly matching times in regions A and B, to construct a list of simultaneous events. time t 2 t 9 t 12 s A a 1 a 1 a 2 A + s B b 2 b 1 b 1 B + + Taking the ergodic hypothesis to justify taking the data at t 2, t 9, t 12,... to be an ensemble of independent events, and ignoring the times, we can model the statistics of this data by a probability distribution p(s A, A, s B, B). 10

s A, A A B s B, B The probability distribution p(s A, A, s B, B) is just part of an initial condition, at the time of the experiment, for a random field model. Initial conditions are not constrained by classical physics, but more experimental effort is needed to set up unlikely initial conditions, which have higher free energy. Experiments that violate Bell inequalities are not easy. The experimentally grounded p(s A, A, s B, B) at the time of the experiment (partially) determines what the initial conditions must have been in the past and will be in the future. What Bell says is that the field in the past cannot have been what it would have had to have been to result in what the field is now, because that would be weird. Saying that weird initial conditions in the past are OK is known as the conspiracy loophole. 11

To derive Bell inequalities, Bell introduces various a priori constraints on what the initial conditions in the past are allowed to have been. A a, λ c, ν b, µ B Bell s constraints are based on an idea of common cause that is well-founded for a classical particle model, but is relatively unmotivated for a random field. For a classical particle model, two particles come from a single source, the common cause of two correlated events. The correlations of a random field (and of a quantum field) evolve from correlations at earlier times. There is a distributed cause, not a common cause. 12

Correlations now evolve out of past correlations and into future correlations. For example, there is equilibrium now because there was equilibrium before. There are non-local correlations between observables of a classical field at thermal equilibrium, enough to make it impossible to derive Bell inequalities. Where do equilibrium correlations come from? They re just there (or we arranged it). The violation of Bell inequalities shows that there are no simply localized particles that would imply pervasive common causes. 13

s A, A A B s B, B There is a distinct tradition of discussing Bell inequalities as about measurement incompatibility, or as showing that particle properties must be contextual, not as about nonlocality, starting with Accardi (1981) and Fine (1982). From the experimental data, we can construct probability distributions p(a, B a 1, b 1 ), p(a, B a 2, b 1 ), p(a, B a 2, b 2 ), and p(a, B a 2, b 1 ). Without making any assumptions about locality, we can prove that we cannot in general construct a probability distribution p(a 1, A 2, B 1, B 2 a 1, a 2, b 1, b 2 ) that has all four of the above as marginals. We cannot talk about measuring both a 1 and a 2 at the same time. The Kochen-Specker paradox says the same thing. When we construct an NKS or random field model, we must ensure that there are no well-defined particle properties. 14

s A, A A B s B, B The experimental data idealized as a probability distribution p(s A, A, s B, B) is a (partial) initial condition for a quantum field model as much as it is for a random field model. A quantum field state determined by this experimental data determines correlations at future and past times to the same extent as a classical random field. So there is as much conspiracy in a quantum field model as there is in a continuous random field model. We should not conclude that quantum field theory is unreasonable, but that a continuous random field model is as reasonable. 15

Measurement for random fields Ideal classical measurements do not affect other measurements or the system they measure. If the quantum fluctuations of a measurement device are significant, we model the measurement device and its quantum interactions with the measured system explicitly. Equally, when we construct a quantum field model, if the thermal fluctuations of a measurement device are significant, we model the measurement device and its thermal interactions with the measured system explicitly. A random field model is not much more difficult than a quantum field model if thermal fluctuations already have to be taken into account. Even if we cannot reduce quantum fluctuations, we can imagine what results we would obtain if we could. 16

A quantum model is intrinsically contextual, through measurement incompatibility, whereas a random field has to be explicitly contextual. We have to include a description of experimental apparatus and the effects of its thermal and quantum fluctuations in our random field models. A random field model is contextual insofar as it includes apparatus degrees of freedom. This is not contextuality in the usually pejorative sense that particle properties depend on what apparatus is used. There are no precise particle properties. 17

Discrete event measurements A discrete event measurement device is a metastable thermodynamic state that is tuned not to transition to its registration state (except for its dark rate statistics). e.g. CCDs, photographic plates, semiconductor devices, bubble chambers. When a transition to the registration state happens, a feedback process returns the device to its metastable state as quickly as possible (unless it s a photographic plate; a bubble chamber is returned to its metastable state cyclically rather than through feedback). When the device is put near various plugged-in and turnedon apparatuses, different statistics for transitions to its registration state are observed a change of the environment changes the response. Discrete transition events are a consequence of (engineered) thermodynamic properties more than of any discrete structure of the external field. The discrete events do not have to be taken to represent the arrival of individual particles. 18

Conclusion NKS modelling should be probabilistic, and include something like quantum fluctuations, distinct from thermal fluctuations. If it s a classical model, it s a random field model. NKS modelling should include thermodynamic transitions. NKS modelling should have different effective evolutions at different scales and in different thermodynamic conditions. The effective dynamics should in some conditions lead to identifiable particles, in other conditions not. NKS modelling should be more formally cognizant of constraints. 19