Pareto Optimal Allocations for Law Invariant Robust Utilities

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Pareto Optimal Allocations for Law Invariant Robust Utilities"

Transcription

1 Pareto Optimal Allocations for Law Invariant Robust Utilities on L 1 Claudia Ravanelli Swiss Finance Institute Gregor Svindland University of Munich and EPFL November 2012 Abstract We prove the existence of comonotone Pareto optimal allocations satisfying utility constraints when decision makers have probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences and thus representing criteria in the class of law invariant robust utilities. The total endowment is only required to be integrable. JEL Classifications: D81, D86. MSC 2000 Classifications: 91B16, 91B30, 91B32, 91B50. Keywords: Pareto optimal allocations, variational preferences, robust utility, probabilistic sophistication, law invariance, ambiguity aversion, weighted sup-convolution. 1 Introduction In this paper we prove the existence of Pareto optimal allocations of integrable random endowments when decision makers have probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences. Variational preferences were introduced and axiomatically characterized by Maccheroni, Marinacci, and Rustichini (2006). This broad class of preferences allows to model ambiguity aversion and includes several subclasses of preferences that have been extensively studied in the economic literature. In mathematical finance, variational preferences are known as robust utilities; see Föllmer, Schied, The authors gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the NCCR-FinRisk (Swiss National Science Foundation). 1

2 and Weber (2009) and the references therein. In particular, Föllmer et al. (2009) establish the connection between variational preferences and robust utilities as representing choice criteria of variational preferences on random endowments corresponding to Savage acts; see also Remark 2.2 for a brief summary of these results. Our study focuses on variational preferences which are in addition assumed to be probabilistic sophisticated 1 and thus can be represented by robust utilities which are law invariant. Probabilistic sophistication or law invariance means that the decision maker sees any two random endowments that have the same distribution under a reference probability measure as equivalent. To be consistent both with literature on decision making and (mathematical) finance, we use the term probabilistic sophistication whenever referring to preferences, and law invariance whenever referring to the representing robust utility. We pursue this approach in the spirit of Föllmer et al. (2009) in an attempt to unify the current knowledge on Pareto optimal allocations, and to emphasize the range of the results presented in this paper. The class of law invariant robust utilities which represent probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences are of the following type: (1.1) U(X) = inf (E Q [u(x)] + α(q)), X L 1, Q Q where u : R R { } is a (not necessarily strictly) concave (not necessarily strictly) increasing utility function, Q is a set of probability measures which is closed under densities with the same distribution, and α(q) is a suited law invariant penalization on Q Q; see Definition 2.1 for the details. This broad class nests many well-known choice criteria studied in the economic and finance literature, in particular, the von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947) expected utility, the probabilistic sophisticated maxmin expected utility preferences introduced by Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989), the multiplier preferences introduced by Hansen and Sargent (2000, 2001), and (apart from the sign) the law invariant cash (sub)-additive convex risk measures introduced by Artzner, Delbaen, Eber, and Heath (1999), Föllmer and Schied (2002), and Frittelli and Rosazza Gianin (2005) with the property of cash-invariance, and by El Karoui and Ravanelli (2010) with the generalized property of cash (sub)-additivity. 1 Probabilistic sophisticated preferences were introduced by Machina and Schmeidler (1992), further studied by Marinacci (2002) and by Maccheroni et al. (2006) and Strzalecki (2011) for the case of variational preferences. 2

3 We assume that the decision makers have preferences on a space of future random payoff profiles which we identify with L 1 := L 1 (Ω, F, P), i.e. the space of P-integrable random variables on a fixed non-atomic probability space (Ω, F, P) modulo P-almost sure equality, where P is the reference probability measure. So far, most of the existing literature makes the assumption that payoff profiles are bounded, i.e. in L, or even that the state space is finite. These assumptions are justified in many settings. But for applications in finance where nearly all models involve unbounded distributions, the boundedness assumption is not appropriate. This suggests the model space L 1 and the probabilistic sophistication of the preferences indeed allows for that; see Remark 2.2 or Filipović and Svindland (2012). In this paper we consider n 2 decision makers with probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences on L 1 represented by law invariant robust utilities as in (1.1). All decision makers share the same reference probability. Given the initial endowments W i L 1, i = 1,..., n, of the decision makers, we prove the existence of comonotone Pareto optimal allocations of the aggregate endowment W = W W n which satisfy individual rationality constraints. Indeed we show that under some mild conditions comonotone Pareto optima exist for basically any constraints on the utilities of the allocations as long as there is at least one allocation satisfying these constraints. Note that comonotonicity means that the endowments in the allocation are continuous increasing functions of the aggregate endowment W. The existence of Pareto optimal allocations has so far only been established for a few subclasses of law invariant robust utilities. In case that all decision makers have von Neumann Morgenstern expected utilities, existence results were already proved in the sixties by Borch (1962), Arrow (1963) and Wilson (1968). More recent is the proof of the existence of Pareto optimal allocations when all decision makers apply law invariant convex risk measures on L ; see Jouini, Schachermayer, and Touzi (2008) (and also Acciaio (2007) and Barrieu and El Karoui (2005)) and references therein. Filipović and Svindland (2008) extend this result to integrable (not necessarily bounded) aggregate endowments. Even more recently, Dana (2011) proves the existence of Pareto optimal allocations when the decision makers have choice criteria within a class of law invariant, finitely valued, continuous, concave utility functions on L not necessarily representing variational preferences. In Dana (2011) at least one utility function is required to be cash additive and the others are assumed to be strictly concave. Note that the cash addi- 3

4 tivity assumption is very useful when proving the existence of optimal allocations, because in conjunction with a comonotone improvement result, it immediately allows us to restrain the optimal allocation problem to an essentially compact set. Dropping the cash additivity assumption generates some difficulties which we are able to solve. We also reduce the problem to an optimization over an essentially compact set of comonotone allocations. However, in contrast to the cash additive case, in which this reduction can be simply imposed due to the invariance towards constant re-sharing of sure payoffs, in the concave (non cash additive) case it follows as a necessity from the concavity of the utility functions u in (1.1). Further results on the existence of Pareto optimal allocations are found in Kiesel and Rüschendorf (2008). Here the existence of optimal allocations is proved for convex risk functionals on L which are not necessarily law invariant, however, under the assumption that the aggregate endowment W is in the interior of the domain of the (infimal-)convolution of the convex risk functionals, and that there exists an interior point in the intersection of the domains of the dual functions of these risk functionals. Such interior point conditions are standard when arguing by means of convex duality theory. Unfortunately, such results are not applicable in our case. The reason is that on large model spaces like L 1 the interior of the domains of the robust utilities (1.1), as well as of their (sup-)convolutions, are in general empty. Reducing the model space to e.g. L could solve that problem, but then monotonicity implies that the interior of the domain of the dual function is always empty because it is concentrated on the positive cone of the dual space. Another result in the economic literature is provided by Rigotti, Shannon, and Strzalecki (2008). Here the authors prove the existence of Pareto optimal allocations for variational preferences on the positive cone of L under the strong assumption of mutual absolute continuity, which is in general not satisfied in our case. The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we introduce probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences and law invariant robust utilities on L 1, we recall some well-known subclasses of these preferences and some useful properties. The Pareto optimal allocations problem is studied throughout Section 3 in which we state our main results. In Section 4 we illustrate our results by means of some examples. 4

5 2 Setup Throughout this paper (Ω, F, P) is an atom-less probability space, i.e. a probability space supporting a random variable with continuous distribution. All equalities and inequalities between random variables are understood in the P-a.s. sense. Given two random variables X and Y we write X = d Y to indicate that both random variables have the same distribution under the reference probability measure P. The expectation (if well-defined) of a random variable X under a probability measure Q on (Ω, F) will be denoted by E Q [X]. In case Q = P we also write E[X] := E P [X]. We denote by L 1 := L 1 (Ω, F, P) the space of P-integrable random variables modulo P-almost sure equality. 2.1 Probabilistic Sophisticated Variational Preferences on L 1 Variational preferences were introduced by Maccheroni et al. (2006). In the same paper the authors also study the subclass of probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences. Probabilistic sophistication means that X d = Y implies X Y in the preference order. Definition 2.1. (i) A function u : R R { } is a utility function (on R) if it is concave, right-continuous, increasing, dom u := {x R u(x) > }, and not constant in the sense that there exist x, y dom u such that u(x) u(y). (ii) Let denote the set of all probability measures Q on (Ω, F) which are absolutely continuous and have bounded densities with respect to P, i.e. A F, P(A) = 0 Q(A) = 0, and ( ) there exists K > 0 such that P dq dp < K = 1. A set of probability measures Q is closed under densities with the same distribution if Q Q and Q with d Q dp implies that Q Q. d = dq dp (iii) A decision maker has probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences if for all X, Y L 1 : X Y inf (E Q [u(x)] + α(q)) inf (E Q [u(y )] + α(q)) Q Q Q Q where u is a utility function, Q is convex and closed under densities with the same distribution, and α : Q R is a convex and law invariant function on Q in the sense that Q, Q Q with d Q dp d = dq dp implies α( Q) = α(q). In addition α satisfies inf Q Q α(q) >. 5

6 The numerical representation (2.1) U : L 1 R { }, X inf (E Q [u(x)] + α(q)), Q Q is the law invariant robust utility used by the decision maker to quantify the utility of a payoff profile X L 1. The law invariant robust utility U in (2.1) is, clearly, law invariant 2 (X = d Y implies U(X) = U(Y )) and posseses some other useful properties which are collected in Lemma 2.3 below. Due to Jensen s inequality for concave functions, the expectations in (2.1) are all well-defined, possibly taking the value. Note that U(X) = is possible for some X L 1. The interpretation is that the payoff profiles with utility are totally unacceptable. We remark that what we call a utility function in Definition 2.1 (i) satisfies relatively weak requirements and nests the vast majority of utilities proposed in the economic, finance, and insurance literature, including extreme cases such as increasing linear or affine functions. Moreover, by allowing u to take the value we also incorporate the cases when the domain of the utility function u is bounded from below, as e.g. for the power utilities or the logarithmic utilities. Remark 2.2. A standard approach to modeling preferences in presence of model ambiguity (Knightian uncertainty) is to consider preference orders on the set M of all Markov kernels X (ω, dy) from (Ω, F) to (R, B(R)) (where B(R) denotes the Borel-σ-algebra) for which there exists a k > 0 such that X (ω, [ k, k]) = 1 for all ω Ω. It can then be shown under some mild additional assumptions that a preference order on M is in the class of variational preferences if and only if it admits a numerical representation of the form ( (2.2) U(X ) = inf Q C ) u(y)x (ω, dy) dq(ω) + α(q), X M. Here u is a utility function on R, and without loss of generality we may assume that C is the set of all finitely additive normalized measures, and α : C R { } is a convex law invariant function 2 Since U is defined via the law invariant penalization α, it is law invariant. This follows as in Föllmer and Schied (2004) Theorem Conversely, the dual function in the convex duality sense of a law invariant concave function U : L 1 R { }, which in particular can serve as a penalization α in the sense of (2.1), is always law invariant; again see Föllmer and Schied (2004) Theorem

7 with the additional property of being the minimal function for which U can be represented as in (2.2). For an axiomatic definition of variational preferences on Markov kernels and the details on their numerical representation (2.2) we refer to Föllmer et al. (2009). Notice that the space of all bounded payoff profiles L is naturally embedded into the space M by identifying each X L with the associated kernel X (ω, dy) = δ X(ω) (dy) where δ x denotes the Dirac measure given x R. The restriction of U to L then takes the form ( (2.3) U(X) = inf Q C ) u(x) dq + α(q), X L, which is a robust utility. In case of probabilistic sophistication/law invarinace, using results in Svindland (2010), it follows that U is σ(l, L )-upper semi continuous and thus we obtain a representation of U as an infimum over σ-additive probability measures in : (2.4) U(X) = inf (E Q [u(x)] + α(q)), X L, Q Q where Q := dom α. Hence, these preferences on L are indeed consistent with our definition of probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences on L 1 ; see Definition 2.1. Moreover, the representation (2.4) shows that the robust utility U and thus the corresponding preference order is canonically extended from L to L Properties of the Law Invariant Robust Utilities In the following Lemma 2.3 we collect some well-known properties of law invariant robust utilities on L 1 which we will make frequently use of. The proofs can be found or easily derived from results in for instance Dana (2005), Föllmer and Schied (2004) and Maccheroni et al. (2006). Lemma 2.3. Consider a law invariant robust utility U as in (2.1). Then U has the following properties: (i) properness: U < and the domain dom U := {X L 1 U(X) > } is not empty. (ii) concavity: U(λX + (1 λ)y ) λu(x) + (1 λ)u(y ) for all λ [0, 1]. (iii) monotonicity: X Y implies U(X) U(Y ). 7

8 (iv) ssd -monotonicity: X ssd Y implies U(X) U(Y ), where X ssd Y E[u(X)] E[u(Y )], for all utility functions u : R R, is the second order stochastic dominance order. (v) upper semi-continuity: for all k R the level sets E k := {X L 1 U(X) k} are closed in L 1 with respect to the topology induced by the norm 1 := E[ ]. Equivalently, if (X n ) L 1 converges to X L 1 (with respect to 1 ), then U(X) lim sup n U(X n ). Probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences do not only preserve second order stochastic dominance (Lemma 2.3 (iv)) but consequently also the concave order, i.e. X c Y implies U(X) U(Y ), where c denotes the concave order, that is (2.5) X c Y E[u(X)] E[u(Y )] for all concave functions u : R R. Clearly, X c Y implies X ssd Y. The property of preserving c is often referred to as Schur concavity of U. Indeed, in case of monotone concave upper semi-continuous functions ssd - monotonicity is equivalent to Schur concavity. See for instance Dana (2005) for more details on the concave order and second order stochastic dominance. 3 Pareto Optimal Allocations for Probabilistic Sophisticated Variational Preferences Consider n 2 decision makers with initial endowments W i L 1. All decision makers are assumed to have probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences on L 1 and corresponding law invariant robust utilities (3.1) U i (X) = inf Q Q i (E Q [u i (X)] + α i (Q)), X L 1, i = 1,..., n, as defined in (2.1). We assume that U i (W i ) > for all i = 1,..., n, and let W := W W n be the aggregate endowment. The aim of this section is to prove the existence of Pareto optimal allocations of W amongst the n agents within a set of reallocations of the aggregate endowment 8

9 W which are accepted by all agents. The set A(W ) of all acceptable allocations of W is (3.2) A(W ) := {(X 1,..., X n ) (L 1 ) n X i = W, U i (X i ) > and U i (X i ) U i (W i ) c i for all i {1,..., n}}, where c i R { }, i = 1,..., n. The constraint (3.3) U i (X i ) U i (W i ) c i expresses the individual (rationality) constraint of decision maker i, specifying which payoff profiles X i in a new re-allocation of W she is willing to accept. Clearly, c i = 0 represents the (classical) case when the decision maker will not accept any allocation which allots her an endowment which is not at least as good as her initial one. An extreme is c i = which means that the decision maker is willing to accept any allocation with finite utility. 3 We also allow for situations in which the decision maker is to some bounded extent willing to accept a worsening as compared to her initial endowment (c i > 0), or requires an improvement (c i < 0). Note that if c i 0 for all i {1,..., n}, then the initial allocation (W 1,..., W n ) is acceptable, so in particular A(W ). However, if some agents demand a strict improvement, it is in general not clear whether the set of acceptable allocations is non-empty. Hence, we make the following assumption. Assumption 3.1. A(W ). We are interested in those acceptable reallocations of W which are Pareto optimal. Definition 3.2. An allocation (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ) is Pareto optimal if (Y 1,..., Y n ) A(W ) and U i (Y i ) U i (X i ) for i = 1,..., n implies that U i (Y i ) = U i (X i ) for all i = 1,..., n. The following stability lemma shows that Pareto optimal allocations given some individual constraints c i on the utility remain Pareto optimal if we loosen these constraints. In other words, the optimality concept is not dependent on these constraints. 4 In particular, in Definition 3.2 we could replace the requirement (Y 1,..., Y n ) A(W ) by simply requiring (Y 1,..., Y n ) (L 1 ) n to be an allocation of W. 3 c i = is understood as the restriction U i(x i) U i(w i) := being redundant. 4 In fact, the constraints only serve as a means to show that we can find Pareto optima which satisfy the given individual constraints on the respective utilities. 9

10 Lemma 3.3. Let A(W ) be given by the constraints (c i ),...,n (R { }) n as in (3.2), and let (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ) be Pareto optimal. For any constraints ( c i ),...,n (R { }) n which satisfy c i c i, the allocation (X 1,..., X n ) is also Pareto optimal in Ã(W ) where Ã(W ) is the set of acceptable allocations given the individual constraints ( c i ),...,n in (3.2). Proof. Suppose (X 1,..., X n ) is not Pareto optimal in Ã(W ). Then there must be an allocation (Y 1,..., Y n ) Ã(W ) such that U i(y i ) U i (X i ) for all i = 1,..., n and U j (Y j ) > U j (X j ) for at least one j {1,..., n}. However, due to the Pareto optimality of (X 1,..., X n ) with respect to A(W ) we must have (Y 1,..., Y n ) Ã(W ) \ A(W ) (note that A(W ) Ã(W )). But this is a contradiction, because Ã(W ) \ A(W ) is either empty (if c i = c i for all i) or contains allocations such that there is at least one k {1,..., n} for which U k (Y k ) < U k (W k ) c k U k (X k ), so (Y 1,..., Y n ) cannot be an improvement of (X 1,..., X n ). 3.1 Characterization of Pareto Optimal Allocations The following well-known result characterizes Pareto optima as solutions to a weighted supconvolution optimization problem (3.4) Maximize λ i U i (X i ) subject to (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ), where λ i 0, i = 1,..., n, are Negishi weights associated to the Pareto optimal allocation. Note that under Assumption 3.1 the optimization problem (3.4) is well-posed. Proposition 3.4. If (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ) is Pareto optimal, then there exist weights λ i 0, i = 1,..., n, not all equal to zero, such that the allocation (X 1,..., X n ) solves (3.4) with these weights. Conversely, if (X 1,..., X n ) solves (3.4) for some strictly positive weights λ i > 0, i = 1,..., n, then (X 1,..., X n ) is Pareto optimal. It is one of the peculiarities of the characterization of Pareto optimal allocations that the associated Negishi weights in (3.4) are in general only non-negative. So we may have λ j = 0 for some j. 5 As we will see in Section 3.3, our techniques allow us to prove the existence of solutions 5 We think that Pareto optimal allocations that are associated to strictly positive weights are the most interesting ones. Indeed λ j = 0 implies that the decision maker j is not considered in the social welfare maximization problem (3.4), whereas λ j > 0 in many cases will lead to a social welfare that is strictly higher than in case λ j = 0. 10

11 to (3.4) only in case all Negishi weights are strictly positive, i.e. λ i > 0 for all i {1,..., n}; see Theorems 3.11 and So the question may arise when and what kind of Pareto optimal allocations we are neglecting. The following Lemma 3.5 shows that very often there are strictly positive Negishi weights for any Pareto optimum. Lemma 3.5. Let (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ) be Pareto optimal and suppose that for any i = 1,..., n there is some ɛ i > 0 such that U i (X i ɛ i ) dom U i and that (U i (X i ɛ i ), ) m U i (X i + m) is strictly increasing. Then there exists strictly positive Negishi weights associated to (X 1,..., X n ). Proof. Let (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ) be Pareto optimal. Then according to Lemma 3.3 the allocation (X 1,..., X n ) is also Pareto optimal in the set of allocations Ã(W ) where we replace the original constraints c i by the trivial constraints c i = for all i = 1,..., n. Since A(W ) Ã(W ), any Negishi weights (λ 1,..., λ n ) associated to (X 1,..., X n ) with Ã(W ) instead of A(W ) in (3.4) also serve as Negishi weights for the original problem with constraints (c i ),...,n. Assume that for some j {1,..., n} we have λ j = 0 and pick some k {1,..., n} such that λ k > 0. Consider the allocation ( X 1,..., X n ) Ã(W ) where X i = X i for all i j, k and X j = X j ɛ and X k = X k + ɛ for some ɛ (0, ɛ j ). As λ j = 0, we obtain λ i U i ( X i ) = (3.5) > which is a contradiction. λ i U i (X i ) + λ k U k (X k + ɛ) ;i k,j ;i k,j λ i U i (X i ) + λ k U k (X k ) = λ i U i (X i ). k=1 An immediate consequence of Lemma 3.5 and Proposition 3.4 is the following: Corollary 3.6. Suppose that the U i satisfy the following conditions for all i = 1,..., n: dom U i = dom U i + R, R m U i (X + m) is strictly increasing for all X dom U i. Then (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ) is Pareto optimal if and only if it solves (3.4) for some strictly positive weights λ i > 0, i = 1..., n. 11

12 3.2 Comonotone Pareto Optimal Allocations Definition 3.7. We denote by CF the set of all n-tuples (f 1,..., f n ) of increasing functions f i : R R, i = 1,..., n, such that n f i = Id R. These functions f i are necessarily 1-Lipschitzcontinuous. An allocation (Y 1,..., Y n ) (L 1 ) n of W, i.e. n Y i = W, is comonotone if there exists (f i ) n CF such that Y i = f i (W ) for all i = 1,..., n. It is known that if there exists a Pareto optimal allocation, then in particular there is also a comonotone one. This follows from the following Proposition and the ssd -monotonicity of the U i. Proposition 3.8. For any (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ) there is a comonotone allocation (Y 1,..., Y n ) A(W ) such that Y i c X i (and thus Y i ssd X i ) for all i = 1,..., n. Proof. First of all we, recall a result which is often referred to as comonotone improvement: for any allocation (X 1,..., X n ) (L 1 ) n of W there exists a comonotone allocation (Y 1,..., Y n ) (L 1 ) n of W such that Y i c X i for all i = 1,..., n. The proof for the case when W is supported by a finite set goes back to Landsberger and Meilijson (1994). This has been further extended to aggregate endowments W L 1 by Filipović and Svindland (2008), Dana and Meilijson (2011), and Ludkovski and Rüschendorf (2008). Finally, by ssd -monotonicity of the U i (see Lemma 2.3 (iv)) it follows that if (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ), then any comonotone improvement (Y 1,..., Y n ) of (X 1,..., X n ) is acceptable as well, i.e. (Y 1,..., Y n ) A(W ). When proving the existence of solutions to (3.4), and thus of Pareto optimal allocations, we will profit from the fact that we may restrict our attention to the set of comonotone acceptable allocations; see proofs of Theorems 3.11 and 3.12 in Appendix A. Remark 3.9. The comonotone allocations have another desirable property. Suppose that W L p L 1 for some p [1, ], and let (f i (W )) n be a comonotone allocation of W, i.e. (f i ) n CF. Then, by the 1-Lipschitz continuity of the f i, it is easily verified that (f i (W )) n (Lp ) n. Hence, any comonotone Pareto optimal allocation will posses the same integrability/boundedness properties as the aggregate endowment W. In that sense, further restricting the set of acceptable allocations by imposing additional integrability or even bound- 12

13 edness constraints in the formulation of problem (3.4) will yield the same comonotone solutions as solving the unrestricted problem. 3.3 Main Results Let s i := inf dom u i R { }, i = 1,..., n, and d i H := lim x s i u i (x) (which may be ) and d i L := lim x u i (x)( 0) where u denotes the right-hand-derivative of u. Finally, let N {1,..., n} be the set of all indices such that d i H = di L 6, and M := {1,..., n} \ N the set of all indices such that d i L < di H. Note that N = or M = is possible. Theorem (i) If s i > for all i = 1,..., n, then for any individual constraints (c 1, c 2,..., c n ) (R { }) n in A(W ) there exists a comonotone Pareto optimal allocation of W. (ii) If N 1, then for any (c 1, c 2,..., c n ) (R { }) n in A(W ) there exists a comonotone Pareto optimal allocation of W. (iii) Suppose that N 2. Given any choice of individual constraints (c 1, c 2,..., c n ) (R { }) n in A(W ), if s i = for all i N, and U j ( W ) > for all j N such that c j R, then there exists a comonotone Pareto optimal allocation of W. Moreover, in the situation of (iii), if N = n, then the Pareto optimal allocations have the property of being up to a reallocation of cash, that is if (X 1,..., X n ) is a Pareto optimal allocation of W, then also (X 1 + m 1,..., X n + m n ) is a Pareto optimal allocation whenever the numbers m i R satisfy n m i = 0 and (X 1 + m 1,..., X n + m n ) A(W ). The proof of Theorem 3.10 follows immediately from Proposition 3.4 and Theorems 3.11 and 3.12 below. In these theorems we specify a non-empty set of Negishi weights λ 1,..., λ n for which the associated optimization problem (3.4) admits a solution. Theorem Suppose that s i >, i = 1,..., n. Then for any set of individual constraints c i R { } and every set of strictly positive weights λ i > 0, i = 1,..., n, (3.4) admits a comonotone solution. 6 When d i L = d i H and s i = (i.e. dom u i = R), then the corresponding robust utility U i is cash additive in the sense that U i(x + m) = U i(x) + d i Hm for all m R and X L 1 and thus (if d i H = 1 and multiplied by 1) corresponds to a convex risk measure. 13

14 Theorem Consider the following bounds on the weights λ i, i = 1,..., n, and some δ > 0: (3.6) We consider two cases: λ i = δ d i H λ i d i L < δ < λ id i H for all i N, for all i M. (i) Suppose that N = or N = 1. Then (3.4) admits a comonotone solution for every set of individual constraints c i R { }, i = 1,..., n, and any set of weights λ i > 0, i = 1,..., n, satisfying the constraints (3.6). (ii) Suppose that N 2. If s i = for all i N, and U j ( W ) > for all j N such that c j R, then (3.4) admits a comonotone solution for every set of weights λ i > 0, i = 1,..., n, satisfying the constraints (3.6). In particular, if N = n, the solutions have the property of being up to a reallocation of cash in the sense that if (X 1,..., X n ) is a solution to (3.4) for some given weights, then also (X 1 + m 1,..., X n + m n ) is a solution to (3.4) with that weights whenever the numbers m i R satisfy n m i = 0 and (X 1 + m 1,..., X n + m n ) A(W ). We remark that when N =, the two conditions in (3.6) reduce to the last one. Note that Dana (2011) derives similar bounds on the weights λ i given in (3.6) in her setting. The proofs of Theorems 3.11 and 3.12 are provided in Appendix A. Theorem 3.12 is discussed in several examples in Section 4.2 in which we illustrate that if we drop one of the conditions on the weights stated in (3.6), we cannot in general expect the existence of solutions to (3.4) any longer. Remark If d i H = and di L = 0 for all i = 1,..., n, as for instance when the decision makers utilities u i are chosen amongst the exponential, logarithmic or power utilities, then the bounds in (3.6) are void. Hence, Theorem 3.12 (i) implies the existence of a solution to (3.4) for any set of strictly positive weights λ i > 0, i = 1,..., n. As regards the uniqueness of Pareto optimal allocations, we have the following result. To this end we recall that a function U : L 1 R { } is strictly concave if U(λX + (1 λ)y ) > λu(x) + (1 λ)u(y ) whenever λ (0, 1) and X Y. Corollary Suppose that under the conditions stated in Theorem 3.11 (and Theorem 3.12, respectively) (n 1) among the n law invariant robust utilities U i are strictly concave. Then, for 14

15 any given set of weights λ i > 0, i = 1,..., n, (and satisfying the bounds (3.6), respectively), the Pareto optimal allocation which solves the optimization problem (3.4) associated to (λ 1,..., λ n ) is unique and comonotone. Proof. For any given vector of positive weights (λ 1,..., λ n ) the set of solutions to the associated optimization problem (3.4) is convex because the U i are concave. This together with the strict concavity of (n 1) robust utilities implies that the solution to (3.4), if it exists, is unique. 4 Examples 4.1 Yaari Preferences Versus Multiplier Preferences Suppose that decision maker 1 has Yaari (1987) type preferences represented by the robust utility (4.1) U 1 (X) = 1 α α 0 q X (s) ds, X L 1, where α (0, 1) and q X (s) := inf{x : P(X x) s}, s (0, 1), is the quantile function of X. Note that U 1 is the well-known Average Value at Risk (AVaR), that is U 1 (X) = AVaR α (X) = min Q Q 1 E Q [X] = min Q Q q X (s)q dq (1 s) ds dp where Q 1 := {Q P dq dp 1 α }; see e.g. Föllmer and Schied (2004) Theorems 4.47 and As for decision maker 2, her probabilistic sophisticated variational preferences are represented by a law invariant robust utility U 2 as in (2.1) satisfying some additional properties which are listed in Proposition 4.2. Examples of such robust utilities are multiplier preferences or semi-deviation utilities with any strictly increasing utility u 2 : R R. Our case study is inspired by and extends an example in Jouini et al. (2008), Proposition 3.2. In Jouini et al. (2008) U 2 is required to be a monetary utility, i.e. cash additive (u 2 Id R ). Proposition 4.2 below shows that the functional form of the Pareto optimal allocations obtained in Jouini et al. (2008) stays the same also when we allow for a larger class of preferences for the second agent. The proof of Proposition 4.2 is essentially the same as in Jouini et al. (2008), so we omit it here. Before giving the result, we recall the definition of strict risk aversion conditional on lower-tail events. 15

16 Definition 4.1. (i) Let X L 1 and A F with P(A) > 0. The set A is a lower tail-event for X if ess inf A X < ess sup A X ess inf A c X where ess inf A X := sup{m R P(X > m A) = 1} (sup := ) and ess sup A X := inf{m R P(X m A) = 1} (inf := ). (ii) A function U : L 1 R { } is strictly risk averse conditional on lower tail-events if U(X) < U(X1 A c + E[X A]1 A ) for every X dom U and any set A which is a lower tail-event for X. Proposition 4.2. Let decision maker 1 be represented by (4.1) and decision maker 2 by a law invariant robust utility U 2 (X) = inf (E Q [u 2 (X)] + α 2 (Q)) Q Q as in (2.1) with the following additional properties dom U 2 = dom U 2 + R, U 2 is strictly monotone, i.e. X Y and P(X > Y ) > 0 implies U 2 (X) > U 2 (Y ), U 2 is strictly risk averse conditionally on lower-tail events. Given any initial endowments W i dom U i, i = 1, 2, and c 1, c 2 R { } such that A(W ), the comonotone Pareto optimal allocations of the aggregate endowment W = W 1 + W 2 exist and take the following form (4.2) (X 1, X 2 ) = ( (W l) + k, W l k) where l R { } and k = k(l) R with k U 1 (W 1 ) U 1 ( (W l) ) c 1. If U 2 is in addition strictly concave, then according to Corollary 3.14 all Pareto optimal allocations are comonotone and take the form in (4.2). 4.2 Examples Illustrating the Bounds (3.6) Since our examples will only involve two decision makers, in the following we give a version of Theorem 3.12 for two decision makers. Theorem 4.3. Suppose n = 2. We consider two cases: 16

17 (i) Suppose that d i L < di H for at least one i {1, 2}. If the weights λ 1 > 0 and λ 2 > 0 satisfy ( λ 2 d 1 ) (4.3) L λ 1 d 2, d1 H H d 2, L then for any c 1, c 2 R { } there exists a comonotone solution to (3.4). (ii) Suppose that d 1 H = d1 L, d2 H = d2 L, s 1 = s 2 = and U i ( W ) > for any i = 1, 2 such that c i R. If λ i = solution to (3.4). δ, i = 1, 2, for some δ > 0, then there exists a comonotone d i H Example 4.4. Illustration of Theorem 4.3 (i): Let U 1 (X) = E[d L X + d H X ] and U 2 (X) := E[X], X L 1, where 0 < d L < 1 < d H. Moreover, suppose that c 1 = c 2 = and that W 0. If λ 2 λ 1 < d L, consider the allocations (W + k, k) A(W ), k R +. Then λ 1 U 1 (W + k) + λ 2 U 2 ( k) = λ 1 E[d L (W + k)] λ 2 k = λ 1 E[d L W ] + (λ 1 d L λ 2 )k for k because λ 1 d L λ 2 > 0. Hence, (3.4) admits no solution. Analogously, (3.4) admits no solution in case λ 2 λ 1 > d H. However for λ 2 λ 1 comonotone allocation (0, W ). [d L, d H ] we have that (3.4) admits a solution which is the Notice that in Example 4.4 there exists a solution to (3.4) even if λ 2 λ 1 equals one of the bounds given in (4.3). Indeed, for λ 2 /λ 1 = d L any allocation (W + k, k), k 0, is optimal, whereas for λ 2 /λ 1 = d H all allocations ( k, W + k), k 0, are optimal. However, if the robust utility of one of the decision makers is strictly concave, then often (3.4) admits no solution at the interval bounds of (4.3) either. This is illustrated by the following example. Example 4.5. Illustration of Theorem 4.3 (i): Let W = 0, c 1 = c 2 = and consider two utility functions u 1 and u 2 with d i H < and di L > 0, i = 1, 2. Let U i(x) := E[u i (X)], X L 1. Suppose that u 2 (a) = d2 L a for large a > 0 (in particular u 2 does not attain d2 L ) and that u 1 ( a) = d1 H for a > 0. Then for λ 2 λ 1 sup a R = d1 H d 2 L λ 1 U 1 ( a) + λ 2 U 2 (a) = sup a R and some constant k > 0 we have λ 1 u 1 ( a) + λ 2 u 2 (a) sup λ 2 a + k =. a 0 Similar arguments show that in general we cannot expect the existence solutions to (3.4) in case λ 2 λ 1 equals the lower bound d1 L d 2 H either. 17

18 Example 4.6. Illustration of Theorem 4.3 (ii): Suppose that u 1 (x) = d 1 x and u 2 (x) = d 2 x for some d 1, d 2 > 0 and suppose that c 1 = c 2 =. If λ 2 λ 1 d1 d 2, then (λ 1 d 1 λ 2 d 2 ) 0 and considering the allocations of type (W + k, k) A(W ) for some constant k yields sup k R λ 1 U 1 (W + k) + λ 2 U 2 ( k) = λ 1 U 1 (W ) + λ 2 U 2 (0) + sup(λ 1 d 1 λ 2 d 2 )k =. k R Hence, (3.4) admits no solution. A Proofs of Theorems 3.11 and 3.12 In the proof of Theorems 3.11 and 3.12 we will apply the following facts about law invariant monetary utilities which apart from the sign are convex risk measures. We omit a proof since most arguments are standard and can for instance be found in Föllmer and Schied (2004). Lemma A.1. Let U(X) = inf (E Q [u(x)] + α(q)), X L 1, Q Q be a law invariant robust utility as (2.1). Define (A.1) so that U( ) = U(u( )). U(X) := inf (E Q [X] + α(q)), X L 1, Q Q Then, U is a proper, law invariant, ssd -monotone, upper semicontinuous, monotone, cash additive (U(X + m) = U(X) + m for all m R), and concave function. Moreover, we have that (A.2) U(X) E[X] + U(0) for all X L 1. Note that (A.2) follows from E[X] ssd X and the cash additivity of U. The next Lemma A.2 is an Arzela-Ascoli type argument which will also play a crucial role in the proof of Theorems 3.12 and It can be derived from Tychonoff s compactness theorem or by a diagonal sequence argument. For a proof see e.g. Filipović and Svindland (2008). Lemma A.2. Let f n : R R, n N, be a sequence of increasing 1-Lipschitz-continuous functions such that f n (0) [ K, K] for all n N where K 0 is a constant. Then there is a subsequence (f nk ) k N of (f n ) n N and an increasing 1-Lipschitz-continuous function f : R R such that lim k f nk (x) = f(x) for all x R. 18

19 Let CFN := {(f i ) n CF f 1(0) =... = f n (0) = 0}. Note that CF = {(f i + a i ) n (f i ) n CFN, a i R, a i = 0}. According to Proposition 3.8 there exists a solution to (3.4) for some given weights (λ 1,..., λ n ) if and only if there is a solution to (A.3) Maximize λ i U i (f i (W ) + a i ) subject to (f i ) n CFN, a i R, a i = 0, (f i (W ) + a i ) n A(W ). Proof of Theorem We will prove the existence of a solution to (A.3). Fix a set of weights (λ 1,..., λ n ) satisfying the conditions (3.6). First of all, we observe that if for some j M the right-hand-derivative u j does not attain the values dj H and/or dj L, we can always find nonnegative numbers d j H and/or d j L in the image of u j such that, for the already given set of weights (λ 1,..., λ n ), the conditions (3.6) still hold true if we replace the d j H and/or dj L by d j H and/or d j H. We assume that all d j H and/or dj L which are not attained by the corresponding u j are replaced as in the described manner, and for the sake of simplicity we keep the notation d j H and dj L. By concavity of the u i there is a constant k such that for all i = 1,..., n the affine functions R x d i L x + k and R x di H x + k both dominate u i 7. Using this, we will show that (A.4) { P := sup λ i U i (f i (W ) + a i ) (f i ) n CFN, a i R, } a i = 0, (f i (W ) + a i ) n A(W ) <, and that this supremum is realized over a bounded set of comonotone allocations where the bound is given by W. More precisely, we will prove that there exists some constant K > 0 depending on W such that (A.5) { P = sup λ i U i (f i (W ) + a i ) (f i ) n CFN, a i [ K, K], } a i = 0, (f i (W ) + a i ) n A(W ). 7 Note that if u is a concave function, then it is always dominated by x u (y)(x y) + u(y). 19

20 To this end, we define the functions U i (X) := inf Q Q i (E Q [X] + α i (Q)), X L 1, i = 1,..., n, as in Lemma A.1. Consider (f i ) n CFN and a i R such that n a i = 0 and (f i (W ) + a i ) n A(W ). Let I := {i {1,..., n} a i < 0} and J := {1,..., n} \ I. By applying monotonicity, cash additivity and finally property (A.2) of the U i (see Lemma A.1) we obtain: λ i U i (f i (W ) + a i ) = (A.6) k λ i U i (u i (f i (W ) + a i )) i I M λ i U i (d i H(f i (W ) + a i ) + k) + λ l U l (d l H(f l (W ) + a l ) + k) l N λ i + i I M λ i U i (d i Hf i (W ))+ j J M λ l U l (d l Hf l (W ))+ λ j U j (d j L f j(w )) + j J M l N ( ) ( ) min λ id i H a i + max λ jd j i I M j J M L a j + δ i I M j J M l N k λ i + E[W + ] λ i d i H + λ i U i (0)+ ( ) min λ id i H i I M i I M Suppose that N =, then we further estimate (A.7) (A.6) E[W + ] λ i d i H + k λ j U j (d j L (f j(w ) + a j ) + k)+ ( ) a i + max λ jd j j J M L a j + δ a l. j J M l N λ i + ( ) λ i U i (0) min λ id i H max λ jd j i I j J L a where a := i J a i ( 0). If N and l N a l < 0, then we estimate (A.8) (A.6) E[W + ] λ i d i H + k λ i + a l ( ) λ i U i (0) δ max λ jd j j J M L ã for ã := i J M a i ( 0) using (3.6). And similarly, if N and l N a l 0, then we estimate (A.9) (A.6) E[W + ] λ i d i H + k λ i + ( ) λ i U i (0) min λ id i H δ â i I M 20

21 for â := i J N a i ( 0). Consequently we infer that P E[W + ] λ i d i H + k λ i + λ i U i (0) <. Choose any allocation (X 1,..., X n ) A(W ). Letting Then we have that P n λ iu i (X i ) =: k. if N =, or A := min λ id i H max λ jd j,...,n j=1,...,n L {( ) ( )} A := min δ max λ jd j j M L, min λ id i H δ i M if N, we infer from (A.7), (A.8), and (A.9) that the supremum in (A.4) is realized over allocations such that a i k + E[W + ] n λ id i H + k n λ i + n λ iu i (0) =: K A for all i M, and i N a i K too. Note that A > 0 due to the conditions (3.6) on the weights λ i. In the following we argue that in case N > 1 we may also assume that the a i belonging to i N are bounded due to the insensitivity of the cash additive U i, i N, to constant re-sharings of 0 amongst themselves. To this end note that the choice of the λ i and the requirement s i = for i N implies (A.10) i N λ i U i (f i (W ) + a i + m i ) = i N λ i U i (f i (W ) + a i ) + δ i N m i = i N λ i U i (f i (W ) + a i ), whenever m i R such that i N m i = 0. Hence, adding constants m i such that i N m i = 0 to the endowments of the decision makers in N does not affect the contribution of the allocation to P. This immediately implies that we may assume a i K for all i N if c i = for all i N, because in that case we may choose m 1 = i N a i a 1 and m i = a i for all i 1 in (A.10), and the altered allocation satisfies the bound ( m 1 + a 1 = i N a i K, see above). If the set N b N of indices i N such that c i R is not empty, we also need to consider cash amounts that might be needed to make the endowment f i (W ) + a i acceptable. This is the point where the assumption U i ( W ) > for all i N b enters (whenever N > 1). Using the cash additivity (U i (Y + z) = U i (Y ) + d i H z, z R) and monotonicity of U i we obtain that f i (W ) + z is acceptable for decision maker i N b whenever z U i(w i ) U i ( W ) c i d i. H 21

22 Moreover, acceptability of f i (W ) + a i implies (again using cash additivity and monotonicity of U i ) for all i N b : a i U i(w i ) c i U i (f i (W i )) d i H U i(w i ) c i U i (0) d i H E[W + ] where we have used that U i (f i (W i )) U i (W + ) E[d i H W + ]+U i (0) according to (A.2). Therefore we know that there exists a joint constant K > 0 such that the a i, i N b, are bounded from below by K and such that the endowments f(w i ) + a i + m i stay acceptable for m i = [(a i K) 0], i N b. If N b = N, then choosing some j N b and letting m i = [(a i K) 0] for i N b \ {j} and m j = i N\{j} m i, we obtain that i N m i = 0, a i + m i K for all i N b \ {j}, and a j + m j a i + a i + m i K + N b K =: K. i N i N b \{j} Moreover, since a j a j + m j, also f(w j ) + a j + m j is acceptable, i.e. U j (f(w j ) + a j + m j ) U j (W j ) c j. If N u > 1 where N u := N \ N b, then we choose some j N u and let m i = [(a i K) 0] for all i N b and m i = a i for all i N u \ {j}, whereas m j = i N\{j} m i. Again, i N m i = 0, and a i + m i = 0 for all i N u \ {j}, a i + m i K for all i N b, and a j + m j a i + a i + m i K + N b K =: K. i N i N b Hence, (A.4) and (A.5) are proved. By virtue of (A.5) we may choose a sequence ((f p i )n ) p N CF with f p i (0) [ K, K] for all i = 1,..., n and p N such that (f p i (W ))n A(W ) for all p N and P = lim p λ i U i (f p i (W )). According to Lemma A.2 there exists a subsequence, which we for the sake of simplicity also denote by (f p i )n, which converges pointwise to some (f i) n CF. As f p i (W ) W + K for all i = 1,..., n and p N, we may apply the dominated convergence theorem which yields f i (W ) L 1, and lim p E[ f i (W ) f p i (W ) ] = 0 for all i = 1,..., n. By upper semi-continuity of the U i (Lemma 2.3) we have U i (W i ) c i lim sup U i (f p i (W )) U i(f i (W )), p 22

23 and P = lim p λ i U i (f p i (W )) λ i lim sup U i (f p i (W )) p λ i U i (f i (W )). Hence, we infer that (f i (W )) n A(W ) (since P > ) and P = λ i U i (f i (W )). For the last part of (ii) suppose that N = n, and let (X 1,..., X n ) be a solution to (3.4) for the given weights. If m i R such that n m i = 0, then the same computation as in (A.10) yields n λ iu i (X i + m i ) = n λ iu i (X i ). Proof of Theorem Recall (A.3) and let (f i ) n CFN, a i R with n a i = 0 such that (f i (W ) + a i ) n A(W ). Since in particuar U i(f i (W ) + a i ) >, we must have that f i (W ) + a i s i for all i = 1,..., n. Let K := n s i. Then ( W + K) f i (W ) + a i = W ( j i f j (W ) + a j ) W + K. Hence, we deduce that (A.5) holds with K := 2 essinf W + K. The rest of the proof now follows the lines of the proof of Theorem References Acciaio, B., Optimal risk sharing with non-monotone monetary functionals. Finance and Stochastics 11, Arrow, K. J., Uncertainty and the welfare economics of medical care. American Economic Review 5, Artzner, P., Delbaen, F., Eber, J. M., Heath, D., Coherent measures of risk. Mathematical Finance 9, Barrieu, P., El Karoui, N., Inf-convolution of risk measures and optimal risk transfer. Finance and Stochastics 9,

24 Borch, K., Equilibrium in a reinsurance market. Econometrica 30, Dana, R., A representation result for concave schur concave functions. Mathematical Finance 15, Dana, R., Comonotonicity, efficient risk-sharing and equilibria in markets with short selling for concave law-invariant utilities. Journal of Mathematical Economics 47, Dana, R. A., Meilijson, I., Modelling agents preferences in complete markets by second order stochastic dominance, cahier du Ceremade El Karoui, N., Ravanelli, C., Cash sub-additive risk measures under interest rate ambiguity. Mathematical Finance 19, Filipović, D., Svindland, G., Optimal capital and risk allocations for law- and cashinvariant convex functions. Finance and Stochastics 12, Filipović, D., Svindland, G., The canonical model space for law-invariant convex risk measures is L 1. Mathematical Finance 22, Föllmer, H., Schied, A., Convex measures of risk and trading constraints. Finance and Stochastics 6, Föllmer, H., Schied, A., Stochastic finance: An introduction in discrete time, 2nd Edition. De Gruyter Studies in Mathematics 27. Föllmer, H., Schied, A., Weber, S., Mathematical modeling and numerical methods in finance. In: Ciarlet, P., Bensoussan, A., Zhang, Q. (Eds.), Handbook of Numerical Analysis 15. New York: John Wiley and Sons. Frittelli, M., Rosazza Gianin, E., Law-invariant convex risk measures. Advances in Mathematical Economics 7, Gilboa, I., Schmeidler, D., Maxmin expected utility with non-unique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics 18, Hansen, L. P., Sargent, T., Wanting robustness in macroeconomics, mimeo, University of Chicago and Standford University. 24

25 Hansen, L. P., Sargent, T., Robust control and model uncertainty. American Economic Review 91, Jouini, E., Schachermayer, W., Touzi, N., Optimal risk sharing for law invariant monetary utility functions. Mathematical Finance 18, Kiesel, S., Rüschendorf, L., Characterization of optimal risk allocations for convex risk functionals. Statistics & Decisions 26, Landsberger, M., Meilijson, I., Comonotone allocations, bickel-lehmann dispersion and the arrow-pratt measure of risk aversion. Annals of Operations Research 52, Ludkovski, M., Rüschendorf, L., On comonotonicity of pareto optimal risk sharing. Statistics and Probability Letters 78, Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., Rustichini, A., Ambiguity aversion, robustness, and the variational representation of preferences. Econometrica 74, Machina, M. J., Schmeidler, D., A more robust definition of subjective probability. Econometrica 60, Marinacci, M., Probabilistic sophistication and multiple priors. Econometrica 70, Rigotti, L., Shannon, C., Strzalecki, T., Subjective beliefs and ex ante trade. Econometrica 76, Strzalecki, T., Probabilistic sophistication and variational preferences. Journal of Economic Theory 146, Svindland, G., Continuity properties of law-invariant (quasi-)convex risk functions. Mathematics and Financial Economics 3, von Neumann, J., Morgenstern, O., Theory of games and economic behaviour. Princeton: Princeton university press, 2nd Edition. Wilson, R., The theory of syndicates. Econometrica 36, Yaari, M., The dual theory of choice under risk. Econometrica 55,

A Note on Robust Representations of Law-Invariant Quasiconvex Functions

A Note on Robust Representations of Law-Invariant Quasiconvex Functions A Note on Robust Representations of Law-Invariant Quasiconvex Functions Samuel Drapeau Michael Kupper Ranja Reda October 6, 21 We give robust representations of law-invariant monotone quasiconvex functions.

More information

The Canonical Model Space for Law-invariant Convex Risk Measures is L 1

The Canonical Model Space for Law-invariant Convex Risk Measures is L 1 The Canonical Model Space for Law-invariant Convex Risk Measures is L 1 Damir Filipović Gregor Svindland 3 November 2008 Abstract In this paper we establish a one-to-one correspondence between lawinvariant

More information

Optimal Risk Sharing with Different Reference Probabilities

Optimal Risk Sharing with Different Reference Probabilities Optimal Risk Sharing with Different Reference Probabilities Beatrice Acciaio Gregor Svindland July 29, 2008 Abstract We investigate the problem of optimal risk sharing between agents endowed with cashinvariant

More information

On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures

On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures MATHEMATICS OF OPERATIONS RESEARCH Vol. 38, No. 1, February 213, pp. 142 152 ISSN 364-765X (print) ISSN 1526-5471 (online) http://dx.doi.org/1.1287/moor.112.563 213 INFORMS On Kusuoka Representation of

More information

Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market

Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market 1/51 Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market Ruodu Wang http://sas.uwaterloo.ca/ wang Department of Statistics and Actuarial Science University of Waterloo

More information

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences Conditional and Dynamic Preferences How can we Understand Risk in a Dynamic Setting? Samuel Drapeau Joint work with Hans Föllmer Humboldt University Berlin Jena - March 17th 2009 Samuel Drapeau Joint work

More information

On convex risk measures on L p -spaces

On convex risk measures on L p -spaces MMOR manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) On convex risk measures on L p -spaces M. Kaina and L. Rüschendorf University of Freiburg, Department of Mathematical Stochastics, Eckerstr. 1, 79104

More information

On optimal allocation of risk vectors

On optimal allocation of risk vectors On optimal allocation of risk vectors Swen Kiesel and Ludger Rüschendorf University of Freiburg Abstract In this paper we extend results on optimal risk allocations for portfolios of real risks w.r.t.

More information

Second-Order Expected Utility

Second-Order Expected Utility Second-Order Expected Utility Simon Grant Ben Polak Tomasz Strzalecki Preliminary version: November 2009 Abstract We present two axiomatizations of the Second-Order Expected Utility model in the context

More information

EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS UNDER LAW-INVARIANCE: A UNIFYING APPROACH. Department of Mathematics, University of Munich, Germany

EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS UNDER LAW-INVARIANCE: A UNIFYING APPROACH. Department of Mathematics, University of Munich, Germany EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS UNDER LAW-INVARIANCE: A UNIFYING APPROACH FELIX-BENEDIKT LIEBRICH GREGOR SVINDLAND Department of Mathematics, University of Munich, Germany Abstract. We study the problem of optimising

More information

Convex risk measures on L p

Convex risk measures on L p Convex risk measures on L p Damir Filipović Gregor Svindland Mathematics Institute University of Munich 8333 Munich, Germany 6 July 27 Abstract Convex risk measures are best known on L. In this paper we

More information

Multivariate comonotonicity, stochastic orders and risk measures

Multivariate comonotonicity, stochastic orders and risk measures Multivariate comonotonicity, stochastic orders and risk measures Alfred Galichon (Ecole polytechnique) Brussels, May 25, 2012 Based on collaborations with: A. Charpentier (Rennes) G. Carlier (Dauphine)

More information

RISK MEASURES ON ORLICZ HEART SPACES

RISK MEASURES ON ORLICZ HEART SPACES Communications on Stochastic Analysis Vol. 9, No. 2 (2015) 169-180 Serials Publications www.serialspublications.com RISK MEASURES ON ORLICZ HEART SPACES COENRAAD LABUSCHAGNE, HABIB OUERDIANE, AND IMEN

More information

Pareto optimal allocations and optimal risk sharing for quasiconvex risk measures

Pareto optimal allocations and optimal risk sharing for quasiconvex risk measures Pareto optimal allocations and optimal risk sharing for quasiconvex risk measures Elisa Mastrogiacomo University of Milano-Bicocca, Italy (joint work with Prof. Emanuela Rosazza Gianin) Second Young researchers

More information

Monetary Risk Measures and Generalized Prices Relevant to Set-Valued Risk Measures

Monetary Risk Measures and Generalized Prices Relevant to Set-Valued Risk Measures Applied Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 8, 2014, no. 109, 5439-5447 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/10.12988/ams.2014.43176 Monetary Risk Measures and Generalized Prices Relevant to Set-Valued

More information

Convex Risk Measures: Basic Facts, Law-invariance and beyond, Asymptotics for Large Portfolios

Convex Risk Measures: Basic Facts, Law-invariance and beyond, Asymptotics for Large Portfolios Convex Risk Measures: Basic Facts, Law-invariance and beyond, Asymptotics for Large Portfolios Hans Föllmer a Thomas Knispel b Abstract This paper provides an introduction to the theory of capital requirements

More information

When does aggregation reduce risk aversion?

When does aggregation reduce risk aversion? When does aggregation reduce risk aversion? Christopher P. Chambers and Federico Echenique April 22, 2009 Abstract We study the problem of risk sharing within a household facing subjective uncertainty.

More information

Coherent risk measures

Coherent risk measures Coherent risk measures Foivos Xanthos Ryerson University, Department of Mathematics Toµɛας Mαθηµατ ικὼν, E.M.Π, 11 Noɛµβρὶoυ 2015 Research interests Financial Mathematics, Mathematical Economics, Functional

More information

Strongly Consistent Multivariate Conditional Risk Measures

Strongly Consistent Multivariate Conditional Risk Measures Strongly Consistent Multivariate Conditional Risk Measures annes offmann Thilo Meyer-Brandis regor Svindland January 11, 2016 Abstract We consider families of strongly consistent multivariate conditional

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

Robust preferences and robust portfolio choice

Robust preferences and robust portfolio choice Robust preferences and robust portfolio choice Hans FÖLLMER Institut für Mathematik Humboldt-Universität Unter den Linden 6 10099 Berlin, Germany foellmer@math.hu-berlin.de Alexander SCHIED School of ORIE

More information

Representation theorem for AVaR under a submodular capacity

Representation theorem for AVaR under a submodular capacity 3 214 5 ( ) Journal of East China Normal University (Natural Science) No. 3 May 214 Article ID: 1-5641(214)3-23-7 Representation theorem for AVaR under a submodular capacity TIAN De-jian, JIANG Long, JI

More information

Risk Measures: Rationality and Diversification

Risk Measures: Rationality and Diversification Risk Measures: Rationality and Diversification Simone Cerreia-Vioglio a Fabio Maccheroni b Massimo Marinacci b Luigi Montrucchio c a Department of Economics, Columbia University b Department of Decision

More information

The Axiomatic Approach to Risk Measures for Capital Determination

The Axiomatic Approach to Risk Measures for Capital Determination The Axiomatic Approach to Risk Measures for Capital Determination Hans Föllmer Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin Stefan Weber Leibniz Universität Hannover January 5, 2015 1 Introduction The quantification

More information

Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets

Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets Tim Leung 1, Qingshuo Song 2, and Jie Yang 3 1 Columbia University, New York, USA; leung@ieor.columbia.edu 2 City

More information

Lectures for the Course on Foundations of Mathematical Finance

Lectures for the Course on Foundations of Mathematical Finance Definitions and properties of Lectures for the Course on Foundations of Mathematical Finance First Part: Convex Marco Frittelli Milano University The Fields Institute, Toronto, April 2010 Definitions and

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 6: Choice under Uncertainty

More information

Comonotonicity, Efficient Risk-sharing and Equilibria in markets with short-selling for concave law-invariant utilities

Comonotonicity, Efficient Risk-sharing and Equilibria in markets with short-selling for concave law-invariant utilities Comonotonicity, Efficient Risk-sharing and Equilibria in markets with short-selling for concave law-invariant utilities Rose-Anne Dana To cite this version: Rose-Anne Dana. Comonotonicity, Efficient Risk-sharing

More information

Efficient Allocations under Ambiguity

Efficient Allocations under Ambiguity Efficient Allocations under Ambiguity Tomasz Strzalecki Harvard University Jan Werner University of Minnesota May 2010 Abstract An important implication of the expected utility model under risk aversion

More information

Distribution-Invariant Risk Measures, Entropy, and Large Deviations

Distribution-Invariant Risk Measures, Entropy, and Large Deviations Distribution-Invariant Risk Measures, Entropy, and Large Deviations Stefan Weber Cornell University June 24, 2004; this version December 4, 2006 Abstract The simulation of distributions of financial positions

More information

EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS

EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS MANUELA GHICA We give some necessary conditions for weak efficiency and proper efficiency portfolios for a reinsurance market in nonconvex optimization

More information

THE ARROW PRATT INDEXES OF RISK AVERSION AND CONVEX RISK MEASURES THEY IMPLY

THE ARROW PRATT INDEXES OF RISK AVERSION AND CONVEX RISK MEASURES THEY IMPLY THE ARROW PRATT INDEXES OF RISK AVERSION AND CONVEX RISK MEASURES THEY IMPLY PAUL C. KETTLER ABSTRACT. The Arrow Pratt index of relative risk aversion combines the important economic concepts of elasticity

More information

A Theory for Measures of Tail Risk

A Theory for Measures of Tail Risk A Theory for Measures of Tail Risk Ruodu Wang http://sas.uwaterloo.ca/~wang Department of Statistics and Actuarial Science University of Waterloo, Canada Extreme Value Analysis Conference 2017 TU Delft

More information

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series The Knob of the Discord Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni Discussion Paper No.: 0405-14 Department of Economics Columbia University

More information

Optimal risk allocation in a market with non-convex preferences

Optimal risk allocation in a market with non-convex preferences arxiv:153.446v1 [q-fin.rm] 15 Mar 215 Optimal risk allocation in a market with non-convex preferences Hirbod Assa University of Liverpool Abstract The aims of this study are twofold. First, we consider

More information

4. Conditional risk measures and their robust representation

4. Conditional risk measures and their robust representation 4. Conditional risk measures and their robust representation We consider a discrete-time information structure given by a filtration (F t ) t=0,...,t on our probability space (Ω, F, P ). The time horizon

More information

Generalized quantiles as risk measures

Generalized quantiles as risk measures Generalized quantiles as risk measures Bellini, Klar, Muller, Rosazza Gianin December 1, 2014 Vorisek Jan Introduction Quantiles q α of a random variable X can be defined as the minimizers of a piecewise

More information

The newsvendor problem with convex risk

The newsvendor problem with convex risk UNIVERSIDAD CARLOS III DE MADRID WORKING PAPERS Working Paper Business Economic Series WP. 16-06. December, 12 nd, 2016. ISSN 1989-8843 Instituto para el Desarrollo Empresarial Universidad Carlos III de

More information

Optimal Risk Sharing with Optimistic and Pessimistic Decision Makers

Optimal Risk Sharing with Optimistic and Pessimistic Decision Makers Optimal Risk Sharing with Optimistic and Pessimistic Decision Makers A. Araujo 1,2, J.M. Bonnisseau 3, A. Chateauneuf 3 and R. Novinski 1 1 Instituto Nacional de Matematica Pura e Aplicada 2 Fundacao Getulio

More information

Risk Preferences and their Robust Representation

Risk Preferences and their Robust Representation Risk Preferences and their Robust Representation Samuel Drapeau Michael Kupper July 212 To address the plurality of interpretations of the subjective notion of risk, we describe it by means of a risk order

More information

An axiomatic characterization of capital allocations of coherent risk measures

An axiomatic characterization of capital allocations of coherent risk measures An axiomatic characterization of capital allocations of coherent risk measures Michael Kalkbrener Deutsche Bank AG Abstract An axiomatic definition of coherent capital allocations is given. It is shown

More information

Risk Measures on P(R) and Value At Risk with Probability/Loss function

Risk Measures on P(R) and Value At Risk with Probability/Loss function Risk Measures on P(R) and Value At Risk with Probability/Loss function Marco Frittelli Milano University, email: marco.frittelli@unimi.it Marco Maggis Milano University, email: marco.maggis@unimi.it Ilaria

More information

Risk Measures in non-dominated Models

Risk Measures in non-dominated Models Purpose: Study Risk Measures taking into account the model uncertainty in mathematical finance. Plan 1 Non-dominated Models Model Uncertainty Fundamental topological Properties 2 Risk Measures on L p (c)

More information

Probability and Measure

Probability and Measure Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 84 Paper 4, Section II 26J Let (X, A) be a measurable space. Let T : X X be a measurable map, and µ a probability

More information

Rationality and Uncertainty

Rationality and Uncertainty Rationality and Uncertainty Based on papers by Itzhak Gilboa, Massimo Marinacci, Andy Postlewaite, and David Schmeidler Warwick Aug 23, 2013 Risk and Uncertainty Dual use of probability: empirical frequencies

More information

Comonotonicity and Maximal Stop-Loss Premiums

Comonotonicity and Maximal Stop-Loss Premiums Comonotonicity and Maximal Stop-Loss Premiums Jan Dhaene Shaun Wang Virginia Young Marc J. Goovaerts November 8, 1999 Abstract In this paper, we investigate the relationship between comonotonicity and

More information

On Quasi-convex Risk Measures

On Quasi-convex Risk Measures On Quasi-convex Risk Measures Marco Frittelli based on joint papers with Marco Maggis Perspectives in Analysis and Probability Conference in Honor of Freddy Delbaen ETH Zurich September 24-28, 2012 Marco

More information

A Note on the Swiss Solvency Test Risk Measure

A Note on the Swiss Solvency Test Risk Measure A Note on the Swiss Solvency Test Risk Measure Damir Filipović and Nicolas Vogelpoth Vienna Institute of Finance Nordbergstrasse 15 A-1090 Vienna, Austria first version: 16 August 2006, this version: 16

More information

The Subdifferential of Convex Deviation Measures and Risk Functions

The Subdifferential of Convex Deviation Measures and Risk Functions The Subdifferential of Convex Deviation Measures and Risk Functions Nicole Lorenz Gert Wanka In this paper we give subdifferential formulas of some convex deviation measures using their conjugate functions

More information

Radner Equilibria under Ambiguous Volatility

Radner Equilibria under Ambiguous Volatility 493 Center for Mathematical Economics Working Papers December 213 Radner Equilibria under Ambiguous Volatility Patrick Beißner Center for Mathematical Economics(IMW) Bielefeld University Universitätsstraße

More information

Notes on Blackwell s Comparison of Experiments Tilman Börgers, June 29, 2009

Notes on Blackwell s Comparison of Experiments Tilman Börgers, June 29, 2009 Notes on Blackwell s Comparison of Experiments Tilman Börgers, June 29, 2009 These notes are based on Chapter 12 of David Blackwell and M. A.Girshick, Theory of Games and Statistical Decisions, John Wiley

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal May 0, 0 Abstract Machina (009, 0) lists a number of situations where standard models of ambiguity aversion are unable to capture

More information

Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs

Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs Spyros Galanis June 19, 2014 Abstract Using the notion of subjective beliefs from Rigotti et al. (2008), we provide, for a wide variety of dynamic models with

More information

On Kusuoka representation of law invariant risk measures

On Kusuoka representation of law invariant risk measures On Kusuoka representation of law invariant risk measures Alexander Shapiro School of Industrial & Systems Engineering, Georgia Institute of Technology, 765 Ferst Drive, Atlanta, GA 3332. Abstract. In this

More information

Decomposability and time consistency of risk averse multistage programs

Decomposability and time consistency of risk averse multistage programs Decomposability and time consistency of risk averse multistage programs arxiv:1806.01497v1 [math.oc] 5 Jun 2018 A. Shapiro School of Industrial and Systems Engineering Georgia Institute of Technology Atlanta,

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form of

More information

Finanzrisiken. Fachbereich Angewandte Mathematik - Stochastik Introduction to Financial Risk Measurement

Finanzrisiken. Fachbereich Angewandte Mathematik - Stochastik Introduction to Financial Risk Measurement ment Convex ment 1 Bergische Universität Wuppertal, Fachbereich Angewandte Mathematik - Stochastik @math.uni-wuppertal.de Inhaltsverzeichnis ment Convex Convex Introduction ment Convex We begin with the

More information

Ambiguity Aversion and Trade

Ambiguity Aversion and Trade Ambiguity Aversion and Trade Luciano I. de Castro Alain Chateauneuf First Version: March 2008 This version: April 2011 forthcoming, Economic Theory Abstract What is the effect of ambiguity aversion on

More information

Jaroslav Pazdera, Johannes Schumacher and Bas Werker Intra-group Risk Sharing under Financial Fairness

Jaroslav Pazdera, Johannes Schumacher and Bas Werker Intra-group Risk Sharing under Financial Fairness Jaroslav Pazdera, Johannes Schumacher and Bas Werker Intra-group Risk Sharing under Financial Fairness DP 05/2013-072 (revised version March 28, 2014) Intra-group Risk Sharing under Financial Fairness

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

Operations Research Letters. On a time consistency concept in risk averse multistage stochastic programming

Operations Research Letters. On a time consistency concept in risk averse multistage stochastic programming Operations Research Letters 37 2009 143 147 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Operations Research Letters journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/orl On a time consistency concept in risk averse

More information

Entropic risk measures: coherence vs. convexity, model ambiguity, and robust large deviations

Entropic risk measures: coherence vs. convexity, model ambiguity, and robust large deviations Entropic risk measures: coherence vs. convexity, model ambiguity, robust large deviations Hans Föllmer Thomas Knispel 2 Abstract We study a coherent version of the entropic risk measure, both in the lawinvariant

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.pr] 12 May 2013

arxiv: v2 [math.pr] 12 May 2013 arxiv:1304.3284v2 [math.pr] 12 May 2013 Existence and uniqueness of Arrow-Debreu equilibria with consumptions in L 0 + Dmitry Kramkov Carnegie Mellon University and University of Oxford, Department of

More information

A unified approach to time consistency of dynamic risk measures and dynamic performance measures in discrete time

A unified approach to time consistency of dynamic risk measures and dynamic performance measures in discrete time A unified approach to time consistency of dynamic risk measures and dynamic performance measures in discrete time Tomasz R. Bielecki a, Igor Cialenco a, and Marcin Pitera b First Circulated: September

More information

Coherent and convex monetary risk measures for unbounded

Coherent and convex monetary risk measures for unbounded Coherent and convex monetary risk measures for unbounded càdlàg processes Patrick Cheridito ORFE Princeton University Princeton, NJ, USA dito@princeton.edu Freddy Delbaen Departement für Mathematik ETH

More information

Journal of Mathematical Economics. Coherent risk measures in general economic models and price bubbles

Journal of Mathematical Economics. Coherent risk measures in general economic models and price bubbles Journal of Mathematical Economics ( ) Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Journal of Mathematical Economics journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jmateco Coherent risk measures in general

More information

Functional Analysis. Franck Sueur Metric spaces Definitions Completeness Compactness Separability...

Functional Analysis. Franck Sueur Metric spaces Definitions Completeness Compactness Separability... Functional Analysis Franck Sueur 2018-2019 Contents 1 Metric spaces 1 1.1 Definitions........................................ 1 1.2 Completeness...................................... 3 1.3 Compactness......................................

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1 Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1 Suguru Ito June 5 th, 2015 Abstract In this paper, we study an individual who faces a three-period decision problem when she accepts the partitional

More information

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty Yosuke Hashidate Abstract This paper presents a behavioral characteization of a reference-dependent choice under uncertainty in the Anscombe-Aumann

More information

Minimal Supersolutions of Backward Stochastic Differential Equations and Robust Hedging

Minimal Supersolutions of Backward Stochastic Differential Equations and Robust Hedging Minimal Supersolutions of Backward Stochastic Differential Equations and Robust Hedging SAMUEL DRAPEAU Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin BSDEs, Numerics and Finance Oxford July 2, 2012 joint work with GREGOR

More information

Generalized quantiles as risk measures

Generalized quantiles as risk measures Generalized quantiles as risk measures F. Bellini 1, B. Klar 2, A. Müller 3, E. Rosazza Gianin 1 1 Dipartimento di Statistica e Metodi Quantitativi, Università di Milano Bicocca 2 Institut für Stochastik,

More information

Rapporto n Risk Measures on P(R) and Value At Risk with Probability/Loss function. Marco Fritelli, Marco Maggis, Ilaria Peri.

Rapporto n Risk Measures on P(R) and Value At Risk with Probability/Loss function. Marco Fritelli, Marco Maggis, Ilaria Peri. Rapporto n. 225 Risk Measures on P(R) and Value At Risk with Probability/Loss function Marco Fritelli, Marco Maggis, Ilaria Peri Marzo 2012 Dipartimento di Metodi Quantitativi per le Scienze Economiche

More information

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume Duality for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume Headwords: CONVEXITY, DUALITY, LAGRANGE MULTIPLIERS, PARETO EFFICIENCY, QUASI-CONCAVITY 1 Introduction The word duality is

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION

THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION HALUK ERGIN AND TODD SARVER Abstract. Suppose (i) X is a separable Banach space, (ii) C is a convex subset of X that is a Baire space (when endowed

More information

About partial probabilistic information

About partial probabilistic information About partial probabilistic information Alain Chateauneuf, Caroline Ventura To cite this version: Alain Chateauneuf, Caroline Ventura. About partial probabilistic information. Documents de travail du Centre

More information

UTILITY OPTIMIZATION IN A FINITE SCENARIO SETTING

UTILITY OPTIMIZATION IN A FINITE SCENARIO SETTING UTILITY OPTIMIZATION IN A FINITE SCENARIO SETTING J. TEICHMANN Abstract. We introduce the main concepts of duality theory for utility optimization in a setting of finitely many economic scenarios. 1. Utility

More information

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Journal of Economic Theory 105, 531539 (2002) doi:10.1006jeth.2001.2824 Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Emre Ozdenoren Department of Economics, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan

More information

Translative Sets and Functions and their Applications to Risk Measure Theory and Nonlinear Separation

Translative Sets and Functions and their Applications to Risk Measure Theory and Nonlinear Separation Translative Sets and Functions and their Applications to Risk Measure Theory and Nonlinear Separation Andreas H. Hamel Abstract Recently defined concepts such as nonlinear separation functionals due to

More information

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect

More information

Dual utilities under dependence uncertainty

Dual utilities under dependence uncertainty Dual utilities under dependence uncertainty Ruodu Wang Zuo Quan Xu Xun Yu Zhou 5th July 218 Abstract Finding the worst-case value of a preference over a set of plausible models is a well-established approach

More information

The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs

The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs Lecture Notes by Walter Schachermayer Nachdiplom-Vorlesung, ETH Zürich, WS 15/16 1 Models on Finite Probability Spaces In this section we consider a stock price

More information

Robust Return Risk Measures

Robust Return Risk Measures Noname manuscript No. will be inserted by the editor) Robust Return Risk Measures Fabio Bellini Roger J. A. Laeven Emanuela Rosazza Gianin Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract In this paper we provide

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Merging of Opinions under Uncertainty

Merging of Opinions under Uncertainty Working Papers Institute of Mathematical Economics 433 Mai 2010 Merging of Opinions under Uncertainty Monika Bier and Daniel Engelage IMW Bielefeld University Postfach 100131 33501 Bielefeld Germany email:

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Indifference Pricing with. Uncertainty Averse Preferences

Indifference Pricing with. Uncertainty Averse Preferences Indifference Pricing with Uncertainty Averse Preferences Flavia Giammarino A thesis submitted to the Department of Statistics of the London School of Economics and Political Science for the degree of Doctor

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

Conditional Preference Orders and their Numerical Representations

Conditional Preference Orders and their Numerical Representations Conditional Preference Orders and their Numerical Representations Samuel Drapeau a,1, Asgar Jamneshan b,2 October 20, 2014 ABSTRACT This work provides an axiomatic framework to the concept of conditional

More information

Monetary Utility Functions with Convex Level Sets. Anniversary of the actuarial programme in Strasbourg September 2014

Monetary Utility Functions with Convex Level Sets. Anniversary of the actuarial programme in Strasbourg September 2014 Monetary Utility Functions with Convex Level Sets Freddy Delbaen ETH Zürich and UNI Zürich Anniversary of the actuarial programme in Strasbourg September 2014 Outline 1 Joint Work with 2 Notation 3 Definitions

More information

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley**

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Published as: Bhaskar Chakravorti and John P. Conley (2004) Bargaining Efficiency and the repeated Prisoners

More information

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Chiaki Hara April 5, 2004 Abstract We give a theorem on the existence of an equilibrium price vector for an excess

More information

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences in Expected Utility Alejandro Francetich Department of Decision Sciences and IGIER Bocconi University, Italy March 7, 204 Abstract Many choice-theoretic

More information

Existence, Incentive Compatibility and Efficiency of the Rational Expectations Equilibrium

Existence, Incentive Compatibility and Efficiency of the Rational Expectations Equilibrium Existence, ncentive Compatibility and Efficiency of the Rational Expectations Equilibrium Yeneng Sun, Lei Wu and Nicholas C. Yannelis Abstract The rational expectations equilibrium (REE), as introduced

More information

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games Daron Acemoglu and Martin Kaae Jensen Abstract We provide general comparative static results for large finite and infinite-dimensional aggregative games.

More information

Convex Risk Measures Beyond Bounded Risks, or The Canonical Model Space for Law-Invariant Convex Risk Measures is L^1

Convex Risk Measures Beyond Bounded Risks, or The Canonical Model Space for Law-Invariant Convex Risk Measures is L^1 Working Paer Series Working Paer No. 2 Convex Risk Measures Beyond Bounded Risks, or The Canonical Model Sace for Law-Invariant Convex Risk Measures is L^1 Damir Filiović and Gregor Svindland First version:

More information

Lecture 1: Entropy, convexity, and matrix scaling CSE 599S: Entropy optimality, Winter 2016 Instructor: James R. Lee Last updated: January 24, 2016

Lecture 1: Entropy, convexity, and matrix scaling CSE 599S: Entropy optimality, Winter 2016 Instructor: James R. Lee Last updated: January 24, 2016 Lecture 1: Entropy, convexity, and matrix scaling CSE 599S: Entropy optimality, Winter 2016 Instructor: James R. Lee Last updated: January 24, 2016 1 Entropy Since this course is about entropy maximization,

More information

Risk-Consistent Conditional Systemic Risk Measures

Risk-Consistent Conditional Systemic Risk Measures Risk-Consistent Conditional Systemic Risk Measures Thilo Meyer-Brandis University of Munich joint with: H. Hoffmann and G. Svindland, University of Munich Workshop on Systemic Risk and Financial Networks

More information