Strongly Consistent Multivariate Conditional Risk Measures

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Strongly Consistent Multivariate Conditional Risk Measures"

Transcription

1 Strongly Consistent Multivariate Conditional Risk Measures annes offmann Thilo Meyer-Brandis regor Svindland January 11, 2016 Abstract We consider families of strongly consistent multivariate conditional risk measures. We show that under strong consistency these families admit a decomposition into a conditional aggregation function and a univariate conditional risk measure as introduced offmann et al Further, in analogy to the univariate case in Föllmer 2014, we prove that under law-invariance strong consistency implies that multivariate conditional risk measures are necessarily multivariate conditional certainty equivalents. Keywords: multivariate risk measures, systemic risk measures, strong consistency, systemic risk, law-invariance, conditional certainty equivalents. MSC 2010 classifications: 91B30, Introduction Over the recent years the study of multivariate risk measures ρ : L d F R, 1.1 that associate a risk level ρx to a d-dimensional vector X = X 1,..., X d of random risk factors at a given future time horizon T, has increasingly gained importance. ere, L d denotes the space of d-dimensional bounded and - measurable random vectors on a probability space Ω, F, P for some σ-algebra F, i.e. in this article we restrict the analysis to bounded risk factors X for technical simplicity. In particular since the financial crisis, it has become Department of Mathematics, University of Munich, Theresienstraße 39, Munich, ermany. s: hannes.hoffmann@math.lmu.de, meyer-brandis@math.lmu.de and gregor.svindland@math.lmu.de. 1

2 clear that the traditional approach to individually manage the stand-alone risks X i of single institutions in a financial network by a univariate risk measure i.e. d = 1 in 1.1 fails to encompass the perilous systemic risk which arises due to the interconnectedness and corresponding contagion effects between the system entities. This has triggered a rapidly growing literature on how to define more appropriate multivariate risk measures, also referred to as systemic risk measures, that are capable of capturing systemic risk by assessing the risk of a financial system as a whole, and on how to identify those financial institutions of the system which shall be deemed as systemic, i.e. those components of the system which might prevent the system from working properly. See e.g. Bisias et al and the references therein for an excellent survey on systemic risk. Most of the systemic risk measures proposed in the literature are of the form ρx = η ΛX, 1.2 where one first aggregates the d-dimensional risk factors X into a univariate risk by some aggregation function Λ : R d R, and then applies a univariate risk measure η : L F R. Some prominent examples are the Contagion Index of Cont et al or the SystRisk of Brunnermeier and Cheridito Chen et al were the first to describe axiomatically this intuitive type of multivariate risk measures ρ which allow for a decomposition 1.2 on a finite state space. In Kromer et al. 2014b this has been extended to general L p -spaces. An interesting extension of the static viewpoint of deterministic risk measurement in 1.1 is to consider conditional risk measures which allow for systemic risk measurement under varying information. A conditional multivariate risk measure is a map ρ : L d F L, 1.3 that associates to a d-dimensional risk factor a -measurable bounded random variable, where F is a sub-σ-algebra. We interpret ρ X as the risk of X given the information. In the present literature, conditional risk measures have mostly been studied within the framework of univariate dynamic risk measures, where one adjusts the risk measurement in response to the flow of information that is revealed when time elapses. For a good overview on univariate dynamic risk measures we refer the reader to Acciaio and Penner 2011 or Tutsch One possible motivation to study conditional multivariate risk measures is thus the extension from univariate to multivariate dynamic risk measures, and to study the question of what happens to the risk of a system as new information arises in the course of time. In the context of multivariate risk measures, however, also a second interesting and important dimension of conditioning arises, besides dynamic conditioning: Risk measurement conditional on information in space in order to identify systemic relevant structures. In that case represents for example information on the state of a subsystem, and one is interested in questions of the type: ow is the overall risk of the system affected, given that a subsystem is in distress? Or how is the risk of a single institution affected, given the entire 2

3 system is in distress? The systemic risk measures CoVaR of Adrian and Brunnermeier 2011 or the systemic expected shortfall of Acharya et al can be considered conditional systemic risk measures of this type. Also, in Föllmer 2014 and Föllmer and Klüppelberg 2014 the authors analyze so-called spatial risk measures, which are univariate conditional risk measures where again the conditioning is with respect to information on the state of subsystems. In analogy to 1.2, we observe that the conditional systemic risk measures proposed in the literature can be written in the form ρ = η Λ X, 1.4 where now η : L F L is a univariate conditional risk measure, and Λ is a conditional aggregation function. In offmann et al we extend the axiomatic approach of Chen et al and Kromer et al. 2014b to the conditional setting 1.3 and give a characterization of multivariate risk measures which allow for a decomposition 1.4. When dealing with families of univariate conditional risk measures, a frequently imposed requirement is that the conditional risk measurement behaves consistent in one way or another with respect to the flow of information. In particular, in the literature on univariate dynamic risk measures most often the so-called strong consistency is studied; c.f. Detlefsen and Scandolo 2005; Cheridito et al. 2006; Cheridito and Kupper 2011; Kupper and Schachermayer 2009; Penner Two univariate conditional risk measures ρ and ρ with corresponding σ-algebras F are called strongly consistent if for all X, Y L F ρ X ρ Y = ρ X ρ Y, 1.5 i.e. strong consistency states that if Y is riskier than X given the information, then this risk preference also holds under less information. The purpose of this paper is to extend the concept and characterization of strong consistency to multivariate conditional risk measures. To this end, we define strong consistency of two multivariate conditional risk measures ρ and ρ with F as in 1.5 for any d-dimensional risk vectors X and Y, i.e. the interpretation of strong consistency for multivariate risk measures is in exact analogy to the univariate case. As a first main result we prove that the members of any family of strongly consistent multivariate conditional risk measures are necessarily of type 1.4. A requirement here, which is automatically satisfied in the univariate case, is that the family contains a terminal risk measure ρ F : L d F L F under full information F. Such a terminal risk measure is nothing but a statewise aggregation rule for the components of a risk X L d F. In the univariate case, if X L F, there is of course no aggregation necessary. Indeed letting the terminal risk measure correspond to the identity mapping, i.e. ρ F = id, we have that any univariate risk measure ρ with F is strongly consistent with ρ F by monotonicity, so the existence of such a terminal risk measure which is strongly consistent with the other risk measures of the 3

4 family is no further restriction. In the truly multivariate case, however, it is very natural that also under full information, there is a rule for aggregating risk over the dimensions, and the risk measures in the family should be consistent with this terminal aggregation rule. If this is the case, we show, as already mentioned, that the members of the family are necessarily of type 1.4. Indeed we show that by strong consistency the risk measures inherit a property called risk-antitonicity in offmann et al from the terminal risk measure. This property is the essential axiom behind allowing for a decomposition of type 1.4; see Theorem Along the path to this result we characterize strong consistency in terms of a tower property. It is well-known, see e.g. Tutsch 2007, that for univariate conditional risk measures which are normalized on constants η a = a for all a L, strong consistency 1.5 is equivalent to the following tower property: ρ X = ρ ρ X for all X L F. 1.6 The recursive formulation 1.6 is often more useful than 1.5 when analyzing strong consistency. The formulation 1.6, however, cannot be extended in a straight forward manner to the multivariate case. Firstly, note that 1.6 is not even well-defined in the multivariate case since ρ X is not a d-dimensional random vector but a random number. Secondly, also in the univariate case the equivalence only holds for risk measures that are normalized on constants, which in the monetary univariate case is implied up to a normalization by requiring that this class of risk measures satisfy cash-additivity η X + a = η X a. For multivariate risk measures there is neither a canonical extension of the concept of cash-additivity nor is it clear that such a property is desirable at all. In a first step we therefore derive a generalization of the recursive formulation 1.6 of strong consistency for not necessarily cash-additive multivariate risk measures. Indeed, under some typical regularity assumptions, one of our first results is that two multivariate conditional risk measures ρ and ρ with F are strongly consistent if and only if for all X L d F ρ X = ρ f ρ ρ X1 d, 1.7 where 1 d is a d-dimensional vector with all entries equal to 1, and fρ is the well-defined inverse function of the function f ρ associated to ρ given by f ρ : L L ; α ρ α1 d. 1.8 The map f ρ describes the risk of a system where each component is equipped with the same amount of -constant cash α. Note that if ρ is a univariate risk measure that is normalized on constants then f ρ = id is minus the identity map and 1.7 reduces to 1.6. In this sense, for a multivariate risk measure ρ the generalization of the normalization on constants property that is suited for our purposes is the requirement f ρ = id. Further, we remark that one can always normalize a given conditional risk measure ρ by putting ρ := f ρ ρ X

5 Then ρ is a multivariate conditional risk measure with f ρ = id. After studying strong consistency for general families of multivariate conditional risk measures, we move on to give a characterization of strongly consistent multivariate conditional risk measures which are also conditionally law-invariant. In contrast to before we do not require consistency with respect to a risk measure under full information, but with respect to the initial risk measure given the trivial information {, Ω}. These studies were triggered by the results obtained in Föllmer 2014 for univariate risk measures, where it is shown that the only family of univariate, strongly consistent, conditional, cash-additive, convex risk measures is the family of conditional entropic risk measures, i.e. the conditional risk measures are conditional certainty equivalents of the form ρ X = u E P [ux ], X L F, with deterministic utility function ux = a + be βx or ux = a + bx, where a R and b, β > 0 are constants. We also remark that Kupper and Schachermayer 2009 showed this characterization for the case of dynamic risk measures by an alternative proof. In the multivariate case we will see that every strongly consistent family of multivariate conditionally law-invariant conditional risk measures consists of risk measures of type ρ X = f ρ f u EP [ux ], X L d F, 1.10 where u : R d R is a multivariate utility function and f u x := ux1 d, x R. In other words they can be decomposed into the function f ρ in 1.8 applied to a multivariate conditional certainty equivalent fu EP [ux ]. Moreover, we will derive the decomposition 1.4 from 1.10, i.e. in terms of u and f u. Structure of the paper In Section 2 we introduce our notation and multivariate conditional risk measures. Moreover, we give the definition and some auxiliary results for the function f ρ which has been motivated above. In Sections 3 and 4 we prove the results mentioned above for two strongly consistent conditional risk measures, where the law-invariant case is studied in Section 4. Throughout Section 5 we extend these results to families of multivariate conditional risk measures. 2 Definitions and basic results Throughout this paper Ω, F, P is a probability space. For d N we denote by L d F := {X = X 1,..., X d : X i L Ω, F, P i} the space of equivalence classes of F-measurable, P-almost surely a.s. bounded random vectors. It is a Banach space when equipped with the norm X d, := max i=1,...,d X i where F := esssup F is the supremum norm for F L Ω, F, P. We will use the usual componentwise orderings on R d and L d F, i.e. x = x 1,..., x d y = 5

6 y 1,..., y d for x, y R d if and only if x i y i for all i = 1,..., d, and similarly X Y if and only if X i Y i a.s. for all i = 1,..., d. Furthermore 1 d and 0 d denote the d-dimensional vectors whose entries are all equal to 1 or all equal to 0, respectively. Definition 2.1. Let F. A conditional risk measure CRM is a function possessing the following properties: ρ : L d F L, i There exists a position with zero risk, i.e. 0 Im ρ. ii Strict Antitonicity: X Y and PX > Y > 0 implies ρ X ρ Y and P ρ X < ρ Y > 0. iii -Locality: For all A we have ρ X1 A + Y 1 A C = ρ X1 A + ρ Y 1 A C. iv Lebesgue property: If X n n N L d F is a d, -bounded sequence such that X n X P-a.s., then ρ X = lim ρ X n P-a.s. We remark that the properties in Definition 2.1 are standard in the literature on conditional risk measures. Note that strict antitonicity is sometimes also referred to as strong sensitivity in the literature. In order to stress the dimension we often use the term univariate conditional risk measure for a conditional risk measure as defined in Definition 2.1 with d = 1 and we typically denote it by η. For d > 1 the risk measure ρ of Definition 2.1 is called multivariate conditional risk measure. A standard assumption on univariate CRMs is cash-additivity, i.e. η X + α = η X α for all α L, which in particular implies that we postulate a certain behavior of the risk measure η on -constants α L which turns out to be helpful in the study of consistency. Since we do not require this property - given that a multivariate analogue is tricky to define and probably not reasonable to ask for - we will have to extract the behavior of a CRM on constants in the following way. Definition 2.2. For every CRM ρ we introduce the function and the corresponding inverse function f ρ : L L ; α ρ α1 d f ρ : Im f ρ L ; β α such that f ρ α = β. 6

7 Remark 2.3. Note that the strict antitonicity of ρ implies that the inverse function fρ in Definition 2.2 is well-defined. Indeed let β Im f ρ and α 1, α 2 L such that f ρ α 1 = β = f ρ α 2. Suppose that PA > 0 where A := {α 1 > α 2 }. Then by strict antitonicity and -locality we obtain that β1 A + ρ 0 d 1 A C = ρ α 1 1 d 1 A + ρ 0 d 1 A C = ρ α 1 1 d 1 A ρ α 2 1 d 1 A = ρ α 2 1 d 1 A + ρ 0 d 1 A C = β1 A + ρ 0 d 1 A C, and the inequality is strict with positive probability which is a contradiction. Thus we have that Pα 1 > α 2 = 0. The same argument for {α 1 < α 2 } yields α 1 = α 2 P-a.s. Next we will show that properties of ρ transfer to f ρ and fρ. Since the domain of fρ might be only a subset of L, we need to adapt the definition of the Lebesgue property for fρ in the following way: If β n n N Im f ρ is a sequence which is lower- and upper-bounded by some β, β Im f ρ, i.e. β β n β for all n N, and such that β n β P-a.s., then fρ β n fρ β P-a.s. Note that this alternative definition of the Lebesgue property is equivalent to Definition 2.1 iv if the domain is L. The properties strict antitonicity and locality of f ρ or fρ are defined analogous to Definition 2.1 ii and iii. Lemma 2.4. Let f ρ and fρ be as in Definition 2.2. Then f ρ and fρ are strictly antitone, -local and fulfill the Lebesgue property. Proof. For f ρ the statement follows immediately from the definition and the corresponding properties of ρ. Concerning the properties of fρ, we start by proving strict antitonicity. Let β 1, β 2 Im f ρ such that β 1 β 2 and Pβ 1 > β 2 > 0. Suppose that PA > 0 where A := { fρ β 1 > fρ β 2 }. Then β 1 1 A + f ρ 01 A C = f ρ f ρ β 1 1 A + f ρ 01 A C f ρ f ρ β 2 1 A = β2 1 A + f ρ 01 A C, = f ρ f ρ β 1 1 A and the inequality is strict on a set with positive probability since f ρ is strictly antitone. This of course contradicts β 1 β 2. ence fρ β 1 fρ β 2. Moreover, as Pβ 1 > β 2 = P f ρ f ρ β 1 > f ρ f ρ β 2 > 0 we must have f ρ β 1 f ρ β 2 with positive probability, i.e. P f ρ β 1 < f ρ β 2 > 0. Now we show that fρ is -local. Let β 1, β 2 Im f ρ as well as A be arbitrary. Further let α i = fρ β i, i = 1, 2, i.e. f ρ α i = β i. Then we have that f ρ α 1 1 A + α 2 1 A C = f ρ α 1 1 A + f ρ α 2 1 A C = β 1 1 A + β 2 1 A C. 7

8 Thus f ρ β 1 1 A + β 2 1 A C = α 1 1 A + α 2 1 A C. Finally for the Lebesgue property let β, β Im f ρ and let β n n N Im f ρ be a sequence with β β n β for all n N and β n β P-a.s. Consider the bounded sequences βn u := sup k n β k and βn d := inf k n β k, n N which converge monotonically almost surely to β, i.e. βn u β βn u β for all n N which by antitonicity of fρ f ρ β, we observe that the sequence f ρ β u n n N β P-a.s. and βn d β P-a.s. Since yields fρ β fρ βn u is uniformly bounded in L. Note that by the same argumentation also the sequences fρ βn d n N and fρ β n are uniformly bounded in n N L. Next we will show that β u n Im f ρ for all n N. Fix n N and set recursively A n n := {β u n = β} and A n k := {β u n = β k }\ k i=n A n i, k n, then it follows from induction that A n k, k n 1. Since sup {β, β k : k n} = max {β, β k : k n}, we have that C k n k An is a P-nullset. It follows from -locality and the Lebesgue property of f ρ that f ρ fρ β1 A n n + fρ β k 1 A n k k n = β1 A n n + f ρ = β1 A n n + lim m lim m m k=n f ρ β k 1 A n k 1 k n An k m β k 1 A n k + f ρ 0 1 k m An k k=n = β1 A n n + k n β k 1 A n k = β u n, which implies βn u Im f ρ. By a similar argumentation we obtain βn d Im f ρ. Recall that βn u β P-a.s. which by antitonicity of fρ implies that the sequence f ρ βn u is isotone and thus α = lim n N fρ βn u exists in L. It follows from antitonicity and the Lebesgue property of f ρ that β = lim β u n = lim f ρ f ρ β u n = f ρ α, and hence that indeed α = fρ β. Analogously, we obtain that f ρ ˆα = β for ˆα = lim fρ βn, d and thus ˆα = α = fρ β. ence, by antitonicity of fρ fρ β = lim fρ βn u lim inf f ρ β n lim sup fρ β n lim fρ βn d = fρ β, so lim fρ β n = fρ β, i.e. fρ has the Lebesgue property. 8

9 An important observation that will be needed later on is that the domain of f ρ is equal to the image of ρ, i.e. f ρ ρ X is well-defined for all X L d F. Lemma 2.5. For a CRM ρ : L d F L it holds that ρ L d F = f ρ L. Proof. Clearly, ρ L d F f ρ L. For the reverse inclusion let X L d F. Our aim is to show that there exists an α L such that ρ X = f ρ α. 2.1 Define P := { α L : f ρ α ρ X }. As X d, 1 d X X d, 1 d we have that X d, P, so P. Moreover, P is bounded from above by X d, since if A := {α > X d, } for α L has positive probability, then by -locality and strict antitonicity f ρ α1 A = f ρ α1 A 1 A f ρ X d, 1 A 1 A = f ρ X d, 1 A ρ X1 A where the first inequality is strict with positive probability, so α P. By - locality it also follows that P is upwards directed. ence, for α := esssup P there is a uniformly bounded sequence α n n N P such that α = lim α n P-a.s.; see Föllmer and Schied 2011 Theorem A.33. Thus it follows that α L and f ρ α = lim f ρ α n ρ X, i.e. α P. Let B := {f ρ α > ρ X} and note that by the Lebesgue property B = n N{f ρ α + 1/n > ρ X} P-a.s. ence, if PB > 0 it follows that PB n > 0 for some B n := {f ρ α + 1/n > ρ X}. Note that B n and that α 1 B C n + α + 1/n1 Bn P by -locality of f ρ. But this contradicts the definition of α. ence, PB = 0. Sometimes it will be useful to normalize the CRM in the following sense: 9

10 Definition 2.6. We call a CRM ρ : L d F L normalized on constants if f ρ α = α for all α L. Indeed let ρ : L d F L be a CRM and define ρ := f ρ ρ. Then ρ is a CRM Lemma 2.4 and Lemma 2.5 which is normalized in the sense of being normalized on constants as defined above. We call ρ the normalized CRM of ρ. 3 Strong consistency In this section we study consistency of CRMs. We consider the most frequently used consistency condition for univariate risk measures in the literature which is known as strong consistency and extend it to the multivariate case. We refer to Detlefsen and Scandolo 2005, Cheridito et al. 2006, Cheridito and Kupper 2011, Kupper and Schachermayer 2009, and Penner 2007 for more information on strong consistency of univariate risk measures, and to Feinstein and Rudloff 2013, 2015 for an extension to set-valued risk measures. Kromer et al. 2014a also study a kind of consistency for multivariate risk measures, however, as we will point out in Remark 4.11 below, their definition of consistency differs from our approach. For the remainder of this section we let and be two sub-σ-algebras of F such that, and let ρ : L d F L and ρ : L d F L be the corresponding CRMs. Definition 3.1 Strong consistency. The pair {ρ, ρ } is called strongly consistent if ρ X ρ Y ρ X ρ Y X, Y L d F. 3.1 Strong consistency states that if one risk is preferred to another risk in almost surely all states under more information, then this preference already holds under less information. Our first result shows that strong consistency can be equivalently defined by a recursive relation. Lemma 3.2. Equivalent are: i {ρ, ρ } is strongly consistent; ii For all X L d F it holds that ρ X = ρ f ρ ρ X 1 d, where f ρ was defined in Definition 2.2. Proof. i ii: As for all X L d F ρ X = ρ f ρ ρ X 1 d, 10

11 it follows from strong consistency that ρ X = ρ f ρ ρ X 1 d. ii i: Let X, Y L d F be such that ρ X ρ Y. Then by antitonicity of fρ and ρ it follows that ρ X = ρ fρ ρ X 1 d ρ fρ ρ Y 1 d = ρ Y. Remark 3.3. Let η and η be two univariate CRMs, where η is normalized on constants, i.e. η α = α for all α L. Then f η α = fη α = α and thus strong consistency is equivalent to η F = η η F, F L F. Remark 3.4. If {ρ, ρ } is strongly consistent so is the pair of normalized CRMs { ρ, ρ } as defined in Definition 2.6 and vice versa. Since f ρ = f ρ = id strong consistency of the normalized CRMs is equivalent to ρ F = ρ ρ F 1 d, F L F, in analogy to Remark 3.3. In the following lemma we will show that strong consistency of {ρ, ρ } uniquely determines the normalized CRM ρ. Lemma 3.5. If {ρ, ρ } is strongly consistent, then ρ uniquely determines the normalized CRM ρ = f ρ ρ. Proof. Suppose that there are two CRMs ρ 1 and ρ2 which are strongly consistent with respect to ρ, i.e. ρ f ρ ρ 1 1 X 1 d = ρ X = ρ f ρ ρ 2 2 X 1 d, X L d F. We will show that f ρ 1 ρ 1 X = f ρ 2 ρ 2 X. Suppose that there exists an { } X L d F such that A := f ρ 1 ρ 1 X > f ρ 2 ρ 2 X has positive probability. Then, by the -locality of ρ 1 and ρ2, we obtain ρ X1 A = ρ f ρ ρ 1 1 X1 A 1 d = ρ f ρ ρ 1 1 X 1 A 1 d ρ ρ 2 X 1 A 1 d = ρ f ρ 2 X1 A 1 d f ρ 2 = ρ X1 A. 3.2 where the inequality 3.2 is strict with positive probability as ρ is strictly antitone, and hence we have a contradiction. Reverting the role of ρ 1 and ρ2 in the definition of A proves the lemma. 11 ρ 2

12 In offmann et al we studied under which conditions a multivariate conditional risk measure can be decomposed as in 1.4, i.e. into a conditional aggregation function and a univariate conditional risk measure. We will pursue showing that strong consistency of {ρ, ρ F } is already sufficient to guarantee a decomposition 1.4 for both ρ and ρ F. To this end we need to clarify what we mean by a conditional aggregation function: Definition 3.6. We call a function Λ : L d F L F a conditional aggregation function if it fulfills the following properties: Strict isotonicity: X Y and PX > Y > 0 implies ΛX ΛY and P ΛX > ΛY > 0. F-Locality: ΛX1 A + Y 1 A C = ΛX1 A + ΛY 1 A C for all A F; Lebesgue property: For any uniformly bounded sequence X n n N in L d F such that X n X P-a.s., we have that ΛX = lim ΛX n P-a.s. Moreover for F, we call Λ a -conditional aggregation function if in addition ΛL d J L J for all J F. Remark 3.7. The name -conditional aggregation function refers to the fact that Λx L for all x R d. Thus every conditional aggregation function is at least a F-conditional aggregation function. As for conditional risk measures we define: Definition 3.8. For a conditional aggregation function Λ : L d F L F let and f Λ : L F L F; F ΛF 1 d f Λ : Im f Λ L F; F such that f Λ F =. Lemma 3.9. Let Λ : L d F L F be a conditional aggregation function. Then f Λ and f Λ are strictly isotone, F-local, and fulfill the Lebesgue property. Moreover, ΛL d F = f ΛL F and ΛX = Λ f Λ ΛX1 d for all X L d F. The well-definedness of f Λ follows as in Remark 2.3. Further the proof of Lemma 3.9 is analogous to the proofs of Lemma 2.4 and Lemma 2.5 and therefore omitted here. In order to state the decomposition result for strongly consistent CRMs, we first recall the main result from offmann et al adapted to the framework of this paper in Proposition 3.11 for which we need the following definition. 12

13 Definition We say that a function ρ : L d F L has a continuous realization ρ,, if for all X L d F there exists a representative ρ X, of the equivalence class ρ X such that ρ : R d Ω R; x, ω ρ x, ω is continuous in its first argument P-a.s. Proposition Let ρ : L d F L be a CRM and suppose that there exists a continuous realization ρ, which satisfies risk-antitonicity: ρ Xω, ω ρ Y ω, ω P-a.s., implies ρ X ρ Y. Then there exists a -conditional aggregation function Λ : L d F L F and a univariate CRM η : Im Λ L such that ρ X = η Λ X for all X L d F and This decomposition is unique. η Λ X = Λ X for all X L d. 3.3 Proof. Since ρ is antitone, R d x ρ x is antitone. It has been shown in offmann et al Theorem 2.10 that this property in conjunction with the fact that ρ has a continuous realization which fulfills risk-antitonicity is sufficient for the existence and uniqueness of a function Λ : L d F L F which is isotone, F-local and fulfills the Lebesgue property and a function η : Im Λ L which is antitone such that ρ = η Λ and η Λ x = Λ x for all x R d. 3.4 Note that in the proof of Theorem 2.10 in offmann et al Λ is basically constructed by setting Λ Xω = ρ Xω, ω, which implies that Λ is necessarily F-local even though this is not directly mentioned in the paper. Indeed in offmann et al we do not require or mention locality at all. It remains to be shown that Λ is a -conditional aggregation function, η is a univariate CRM on Im Λ, and that 3.3 holds. First of all, we show that F- locality and 3.4 imply 3.3. To this end denote by S the set of F-measurable simple random vectors, i.e. X S if X is of the form X = k i=1 x i1 Ai, where k N, x i R d and A i F, i = 1,..., k, are disjoint sets such that PA i > 0 and P k i=1 A i = 1. Now let X L d. Pick a uniformly bounded sequence kn X n n N = S such that A n i for all i = 1,..., k n, n N, i=1 xn i 1 A n i n N and X n X P-a.s. Then by 3.4, F-locality and the Lebesgue property of Λ and ρ we infer that Λ X = lim Λ X n = = lim k n i=1 lim k n i=1 Λ x n i 1 A n i ρ x n i 1 A n i = lim ρ X n = ρ X, 13

14 which proves 3.3. Next we show that Λ is a -conditional aggregation function. The yet missing properties which need to be verified are strict antitonicity and that Λ is -conditional. The latter follows from offmann et al Lemma 3.1. As for strict antitonicity let X, Y L d F with X Y such that PX > Y > 0. Then by isotonicity of Λ we have that Λ X Λ Y. Suppose that Λ X = Λ Y P-a.s., then ρ X = η Λ X = η Λ Y = ρ Y which contradicts strict antitonicity of ρ. Thus Λ fulfills all properties of a -conditional aggregation function. As for η, note that by Lemma 3.9 for all F Im Λ we have that where f Λ η F = η Λ f Λ F 1 d = ρ f Λ F 1 d, 3.5 are strictly monotone, -local, and fulfill the Lebesgue property, so does η, i.e. η is a univariate CRM on Im Λ. was defined in Definition 3.8. Since ρ and f Λ Theorem Let ρ : L d F L and ρ F : L d F L F be CRMs such that {ρ, ρ F } is strongly consistent. Moreover, suppose that f ρ F ρ F x R for all x R d. 3.6 If ρ has a continuous realization ρ,, then there exists a -conditional aggregation function Λ : L d F L F and a univariate CRM η : Im Λ L such that and ρ X = η Λ X for all X L d F 3.7 η Λ X = Λ X for all X L d. Let Λ F := ρ F and η F := id so that ρ F = η F Λ F for the F-conditional aggregation function Λ F and the univariate CRM η F. Then Λ F X Λ F Y = Λ X Λ Y X, Y L d F, 3.8 i.e. Λ and Λ F are strongly consistent. Conversely, suppose that the CRM ρ : L d F L satisfies 3.7, then {ρ, ρ F } is strongly consistent where ρ F := Λ is a CRM. We remark that in Theorem 3.12 we require consistency of the pair {ρ, ρ F } where ρ F is a CRM given the full information F. Note that ρ F is apart from the sign simply a conditional aggregation function as defined in Definition 3.6, so ρ is required to be consistent with some aggregation function under full information. This also explains Λ F. For d = 1 this consistency is automatically satisfied by monotonicity and the aggregation is simply the identity function, 14

15 and clearly the assertion is trivial anyway. For higher dimensions, Theorem 3.12 states that if there exists an aggregation function which is consistent with ρ, then ρ is automatically of type 3.7. Clearly, if we already know that 3.7 holds true, then ρ is consistent with ρ F = Λ. Consistency with an aggregation under full information is a very natural requirement, because even under full information, so without risk, typically the losses still need to be aggregated in some way, and therefore any CRM under less information should respect this aggregation. Note also that the condition 3.6 is a slight strengthening of being normalized on constants, the latter being automatically satisfied by the very definition of the normalization fρ F ρ F ; see above. The following proof of Theorem 3.12 is based on two observations: ρ F is necessarily risk-antitone as defined in Proposition Strong consistency in turn implies that risk-antitonicity of ρ F is passed on backwards to ρ, and hence Proposition 3.11 applies. Proof of Theorem 3.12: In case we already know that 3.7 holds, then by antitonicity of η it follows that {ρ, Λ } is strongly consistent, and clearly Λ : L d F L F is also a CRM. Thus the last assertion of Theorem 3.12 is proved. In order to show the first part of Theorem 3.12, we recall that the only property which remains to be shown in order to apply Proposition 3.11 is riskantitonicity of ρ : For this purpose we first consider simple random vectors X, Y S where S was defined in the proof of Proposition Note that there is no loss of generality by assuming that X = n i=1 x i1 Ai S and Y = n i=1 y i1 Ai S, i.e. the partition A i i=1,...,n of Ω is the same for X and Y. Suppose that ρ Xω, ω ρ Y ω, ω P-a.s. It follows that ρ x i, ω ρ y i, ω for all ω A i \N, i = 1,..., n, where N is a P-nullset. We claim that this implies f ρ ρ x i f ρ ρ y i for all i = 1,..., n. 3.9 In order to verify this, we first notice that as ρ and ρ F are strongly consistent and by 3.6 we have for all x R d that f ρ ρ x = f ρ ρ f ρ F ρf x 1 d = f ρ F ρf x R ere we also used that the normalization fρ ρ is normalized on constants. In other words fρ ρ x i and fρ ρ y i are real numbers. Next we define B i := {ω Ω ρ x i, ω ρ y i, ω}. Then A i \ N B i and hence PB i > 0 for all i = 1,..., n. Using antitonicity and -locality of fρ we obtain f ρ ρ x i 1 Bi = f ρ ρ x i 1 Bi 1Bi f ρ ρ y i 1 Bi 1Bi = f ρ ρ y i 1 Bi. As f ρ ρ y i are indeed real numbers, 3.9 follows. 15

16 Now by strong consistency of {ρ, ρ F }, F-locality of ρ F 3.10 as well as antitonicity of ρ we obtain ρ X = ρ f ρ F ρf X 1 d n = ρ i=1 = ρ Y, f ρ ρ x i 1 Ai 1 d = ρ n i=1 f ρ F ρf x i 1 Ai 1 d ρ n i=1 and f ρ F, and by f ρ ρ y i 1 Ai 1 d which proves risk-antitonicity for simple random vectors X, Y S. For general X, Y L d F with ρ Xω, ω ρ Y ω, ω for P-a.e. ω Ω we can find uniformly bounded sequences X n n N, Y n n N S such that X n X and Y n Y P-a.s. for n. Then by antitonicity ρ X n ω, ω ρ Xω, ω ρ Y ω, ω ρ Y n ω, ω for P-a.s. Therefore, ρ X n ρ Y n and the Lebegue property of ρ yield ρ X = lim ρ X n lim ρ Y n = ρ Y. Thus ρ is risk-antitone and we apply Proposition ence, there is a - conditional aggregation function Λ : L d F L F and a univariate CRM η : Im Λ L such that ρ = η Λ and η Λ X = Λ X for all X L d. Let X, Y L d F such that Λ F X = ρ F X ρ F Y = Λ F Y and let X n n N S and Y n n N S be uniformly bounded sequences such that X n X and Y n Y P-a.s. for n. Again there is no loss in assuming that both X n and Y n for given n N are defined over the same partition, i.e. X n = k n i=1 xn i 1 A n and Y i n = k n i=1 yn i 1 A n. By the F-locality and antitonicity of i ρ F it follows that for all n N k n i=1 ρ F x n i 1 A n i ρ F X ρ F Y k n i=1 ρ F y n i 1 A n i. As fρ F ρ F x n i and fρ F ρ F yi n are real numbers according to assumption 3.6 and as the above computation shows that fρ F ρ F x n i fρ F ρ F yi n on A n i, we obtain, as above that indeed fρ F ρ F x n i fρ F ρ F yi n, i = 1,..., k n. Now strong consistency and 3.3 imply that Λ x n i = ρ x n i = ρ f ρ F ρ F x n i ρ f ρ F ρ F y n i = ρ y n i = Λ y n i 16

17 and hence by -locality of Λ Λ X n = k n i=1 Λ x n i 1 A n i k n i=1 Λ y n i 1 A n i = Λ Y n. Finally we conclude with the Lebesgue property that Λ X = lim Λ X n lim Λ Y n = Λ Y. Remark We know from Lemma 3.9 that the inverse function f Λ of f Λ is isotone and that Λ X = Λ f Λ Λ X1 d for all X L d F. Therefore it can be shown as in Lemma 3.2, that 3.8 is equivalent to f Λ Λ X = f Λ F ΛF X, for all X L d F. Note that we cannot write the recursive form of the strong consistency of two CRMs ρ and ρ F as above, since f ρ is only defined on L and not on L F in constrast to f Λ. In the following Theorem we summarize our findings from Proposition 3.11 and Theorem 3.12 on CRMs which extend the results in offmann et al for strong consistency: Theorem If ρ : L d F L is a CRM with a continuous realization ρ, and satisfies fρ ρ x R for all x R d, then the following three statements are equivalent i ρ, is risk-antitone; ii ρ is decomposable as in 3.7; iii ρ is strongly consistent with some aggregation function Λ : L d F L F, i.e. {ρ, Λ} is strongly consistent. Proof. The equivalence of ii and iii has been shown in Theorem 3.12 and that i implies ii follows from Proposition Finally, the proof of Theorem 3.12 shows that iii implies i. 4 Conditional law-invariance and strong consistency As in the previous section, if not otherwise stated, throughout this section we let and be two sub-σ-algebras of F such that, and let ρ : L d F L and ρ : L d F L be the corresponding CRMs. 17

18 Definition 4.1. A CRM ρ is conditional law-invariant if ρ X = ρ Y whenever the -conditional distributions µ X and µ Y of X, Y L d F are equal, i.e. if PX A = PY A for all Borel sets A BR d. In case = {, Ω} is trivial, conditional law-invariance of ρ is also referred to as law-invariance. In the law-invariant case we will often have to require a little more regularity of the underlying probability space Ω, F, P: Definition 4.2. We say that Ω, F, P is atomless, if Ω, F, P supports a random variable with continuous distribution; conditionally atomless given F, if Ω, F, P supports a random variable with continuous distribution which is independent of. The next lemma shows that conditional law-invariance is passed from ρ forward to ρ by strong consistency. The proof is based on Föllmer is conditionally law- Lemma 4.3. If {ρ, ρ } is strongly consistent and ρ invariant, then ρ is also conditionally law-invariant. Proof. Let X, Y L F such that µ X = µ Y and let A := {ρ X > ρ Y }. Then the random variables X1 A and Y 1 A have the same conditional distribution given. As ρ is conditionally law-invariant and strongly consistent with ρ we obtain ρ f ρ ρ X1 A + ρ 0 d 1 A C 1d = ρ X1 A = ρ Y 1 A = ρ fρ ρ Y 1 A + ρ 0 d 1 A C On the other hand, by strict antitonicity of ρ and f ρ ρ fρ ρ X1 A + ρ 0 d 1 A C 1d ρ f ρ ρ Y 1 A + ρ 0 d 1 A C 1d. 1d, and the inequality is strict with positive probability if PA > 0. Thus A must be a P-nullset and interchanging X and Y in the definition of A shows that indeed ρ X = ρ Y. While in Theorem 3.12 we had to require that the strongly consistent pair {ρ, ρ } satisfies = F, in this section we in some sense require the opposite extreme, namely that = {, Ω} is trivial while F. Assumption 1. For the rest of the section we assume that = {, Ω}. For simplicity we will write ρ := ρ = ρ {,Ω}. Lemma 4.4. Let {ρ, ρ } be strongly consistent and suppose that ρ is law-invariant and thus ρ is conditionally law-invariant by Lemma 4.3. If Ω,, P is an atomless probability space and X L d F is independent of, then fρ ρ X = fρ ρx. 18

19 The proof of Lemma 4.4 is adapted from Kupper and Schachermayer Proof. We distinguish three cases: Suppose that fρ ρ X fρ ρx and strictly smaller with positive probability. Then by strong consistency f ρ ρx = f ρ ρ f ρ ρ X 1 d < fρ ρ f ρ ρx 1d = f ρ ρx, by strict antitonicity of ρ which is a contradiction. Analogously it follows that it is not possible that fρ ρ X fρ ρx and Pfρ ρ X > fρ ρx > 0. There exist A, B such that PA = PB > 0 and fρ ρ X > fρ ρx on A and f ρ ρ X < fρ ρx on B. Then we have for an arbitrary m = a1 d where a R that ρx1 A + m1 A C = ρ fρ ρ X1 A + m1 A C 1 d = ρ fρ ρ X 1 A 1 d + m1 A C < ρ fρ ρx 1A 1 d + m1 A C 4.1 and similarly ρx1 B + m1 B C > ρ f ρ ρx 1B 1 d + m1 B C. 4.2 owever, as X is independent of the random vector X1 A +m1 A C has the same distribution under P as X1 B +m1 B C. Note that also fρ ρx 1A + a1 A C and fρ ρx 1B +a1 B C share the same distribution under P. ence, as ρ is law-invariant, 4.1 and 4.2 yield a contradiction. Now we are able to extend the representation result of Föllmer 2014 to multivariate CRMs. Theorem 4.5. Let Ω,, P be atomless and let Ω, F, P be conditionally atomless given. Suppose that ρ is law-invariant. Then, {ρ, ρ } is strongly consistent if and only if ρ and ρ are of the form ρx = g f u EP [ux] for all X L d F 4.3 and ρ X = g f u EP [ux ] for all X L d F

20 where u : R d R is strictly increasing and continuous, fu : Im f u R is the inverse function of f u : R R; x ux1 d and g : R R and g : L L are strictly antitone, fulfill the Lebesgue property, 0 Im g Im g, and g is -local. In particular, for any CRM of type 4.3 or 4.4 we have that g = f ρ g = f ρ, where f ρ and f ρ are defined in Definition 2.2. The common function u : R d R appearing in 4.3 and 4.4 can be seen as a multivariate utility where u being strictly increasing means that x, y R d with x y and x y implies ux > uy. So fu EP [u ] and fu EP [u ] are conditional certainty equivalents in the univariate case d = 1 we clearly have fu = u. Thus if ρ and/or ρ in Theorem 4.5 are normalized on constants and hence f ρ id or f ρ id, then ρ and/or ρ equal minus certainty equivalents. But 4.3 and 4.4 also comprise other prominent classes of risk measures. For instance if f ρ = f u or f ρ = f u, then ρ X = E P [ux] is an multivariate expected utility whereas ρ X = E P [ux ] is a multivariate conditional expected utility. Proof. For the last assertion of the theorem note that since u is a deterministic function, we have for α L that f ρ α = ρ α1 d = g f u EP [uα1 d ] = g f u fu α = g α and analogously we obtain f ρ g. Next we prove sufficiency in the first statement of the theorem: Let ρ and ρ be as in 4.4 and 4.3. It is easily verified that ρ and ρ are conditionally lawinvariant CRMs. Furthermore, since fu is strictly increasing and g is strictly antitone and -local, we have for each X, Y L d F with ρ X ρ Y that E P [ux ] E P [uy ]. But this implies that also E P [ux] E P [uy ] and thus that ρx ρy, i.e. {ρ, ρ } is strongly consistent. Now we prove necessity in the first statement of the theorem: We assume in the following that ρ and ρ are normalized on constants and follow the approach of Föllmer 2014 Theorem 3.4. The idea is to introduce a preference order on multivariate distributions µ, ν on R d, BR d with bounded support given by µ ν ρx > ρy, with X µ and Y ν. ere BR d denotes the Borel-σ-algebra on R d and X µ means that the distribution of X L d F under P is µ. It is well-known that if this preference 20

21 order fulfills a set of conditions, then there exists a von Neumann-Morgenstern representation, that is µ ν ux µdx < ux νdx, 4.5 where u : R d R is a continuous function. Sufficient conditions to guarantee 4.5 are that is continuous and fulfills the independence axiom; cf. Föllmer and Schied 2011 Corollary We refer to Föllmer and Schied 2011 for a definition and comprehensive discussion of preference orders and the mentioned properties. Suppose for the moment that we have already proved 4.5. Note that strict antitonicity of ρ implies that δ x δ y whenever x, y R d satisfy x y and x y. ence ux = us δ x ds > us δ y ds = uy, and we conclude that u is necessarily strictly increasing as claimed. Now we prove 4.5: The proof of continuity of is completely analogous to the corresponding proof in Föllmer 2014 Theorem 3.4, so we omit it here. The crucial property is the independence axiom, which states that for any three distributions µ, ν, ϑ such that µ ν and for all λ 0, 1], we have λµ + 1 λϑ λν + 1 λϑ. Since Ω, F, P is conditionally atomless given, we can find X, Y, Z L d F which are independent of such that X µ, Y ν and Z ϑ. Furthermore, since Ω,, P is atomless, we can find an A with PA = λ. It can be easily seen that X1 A +Z1 A C λµ+1 λϑ and Y 1 A +Z1 A C λν+1 λϑ. Moreover, since µ ν, we have that ρx ρy. As {ρ, ρ } is strongly consistent and as ρ is law-invariant, we know from Lemma 4.3 that ρ is conditionally lawinvariant. This ensures that we can apply Lemma 4.4 to the random vectors X and Y which are independent of. Therefore, by -locality of ρ and recalling Remark 3.4 ρ X1 A + Z1 A C = ρ ρ X1 A + Z1 A C 1 d = ρ ρ X1 A 1 d ρ Z1 A C1 d = ρ ρx1 A 1 d ρ Z1 A C1 d ρ ρy 1 A 1 d ρ Z1 A C1 d = ρ Y 1 A + Z1 A C, which is equivalent to λµ + 1 λϑ λν + 1 λϑ. Thus there exists a von Neumann-Morgenstern representation 4.5 with a continuous and strictly increasing utility function u : R d R. In the next step we define f u : R R; x ux1 d. Then f u is strictly increasing and continuous and thus fu exists. Let µ be an arbitrary distribution on R d, BR d with bounded support and X µ. Then ρ X d, 1 d ρx ρ X d, 1 d 21

22 and hence f u X d, = ux δ X d, 1 d dx ux µdx ux δ X d, 1 d dx = f u X d,. The intermediate value theorem now implies the existence of a constant cµ R such that f u cµ = ux µdx cµ = fu ux µdx. Finally, since δ cµ1d µ, we have ρx = ρ cµ1 d = cµ = f u ux µdx = fu EP [ux]. ence, we have proved 4.3 with g id. Define ψ X := fu EP [ux ], X L d F, then we have seen in the first part of the proof that ψ is a CRM which is strongly consistent with ρ. Moreover, ψ is normalized on constants. Thus it follows by Lemma 3.5 that ρ = ψ. If ρ and/or ρ are not normalized on constants, then considering the normalized CRMs fρ ρ and fρ ρ as introduced after Definition 2.6, the result follows from ρ = f ρ fρ ρ and ρ = f ρ fρ ρ, i.e. g = f ρ and g = f ρ. Recall Theorem 3.12 where we proved that if a multivariate CRM ρ is strongly consistent in a forward looking way with an aggregation ρ F under full information F and ρ F fulfills 3.6, then the multivariate CRM can be decomposed as in 3.7. The following Theorem 4.6 shows that we also obtain such a decomposition 3.7 under law-invariance by requiring strong consistency of ρ in a backward looking way with ρ given trivial information {, Ω}. When stating Theorem 4.6 we will need an extension of f ρ to L F: Suppose that the process R a f ρ a allows for a continuous realization. Due to the fact that ρ is strictly antitone and -local, we can find a possibly different realization f ρ, such that f ρ : R Ω R : x f ρ x, ω is continuous and strictly decreasing in the first argument for all ω Ω. Note that there exists a well-defined inverse f ρ, ω of f ρ, ω for all ω Ω. Now define the functions f ρ : L F L F; F f ρ F ω, ω 4.6 and f ρ : Im f ρ L F; F f ρ F ω, ω, 22

23 where we with the standard abuse of notation identify the random variable f ρ F ω, ω or f ρ F ω, ω with the equivalence classes they generate in L F. By construction of f ρ we have that f ρ L J L J for all σ-algebras J such that σ f ρ a,, a R J F, c.f. offmann et al Lemma 3.1. By definition f ρ is also F-local and has the Lebesgue property due to continuity of R a f ρ a, ω. Moreover, -locality and continuity also imply that indeed f ρ X = f ρ X for all X approximation by simple random variables, so f ρ is indeed an extension of f ρ to L F. Theorem 4.6. Under the same conditions as in Theorem 4.5 let {ρ, ρ } be strongly consistent. Then ρ can be decomposed as where Λ : L d F L F; ρ = η Λ, is a {, Ω}-conditional aggregation function, X f ρ f u ux η : Im Λ R; F U E P [UF ] is a law-invariant univariate certainty equivalent given by the deterministic utility U : Im ρ R; a f u f ρ a which is strictly increasing and continuous. ere u : R d R is the multivariate utility function from Theorem 4.5. If the function R a f ρ a has a continuous realization, then ρ can be decomposed as ρ = η Λ, with where η Λ X = Λ X, for all X L d, Λ : L d F L F; X f ρ fu ux is a σ f ρ a, : a R- conditional aggregation function f ρ a, denotes a continuous realization with strictly increasing paths; η : Im Λ L ; F U E P [U F ] is a univariate conditional certainty equivalent; the stochastic utility U : Im Λ L F; F f u f ρ F is strictly isotone, F-local, fulfills the Lebesgue property and U Im U L L ; 23

24 f ρ is given in 4.6. Moreover, it holds that U Λ = u = U Λ 4.7 are deterministic and independent of the chosen information or {Ω, }. Finally we also have that f Λ Λ = fu u = f Λ Λ, i.e. {Λ, Λ } is strongly consistent as defined in 3.8. Proof. By Theorem 4.5 we have that ρ X = f ρ f u E P [ux ] = f ρ f u EP [ fu f ρ fρ f u ux ], where u and f u are given in Theorem 4.5. ence, recalling the definitions of U, η, and Λ, we have ρ = η Λ. It can be readily seen that U as well as U, and thus also Λ, are F-local, strictly isotone, and fulfill the Lebesgue property. As f ρ L J L J for all σ-algebras J such that σ f ρ a, ω : a R J F, the same also applies to Λ = f ρ fu u and we conclude that Λ is a σ f ρ a, ω : a R-conditional aggregation function. Moreover, for X L d η Λ X = f ρ f u ux = U ux = Λ X. The result for ρ follows similarly to the proof above without requiring a continuous realization and by using the canonical extension of f ρ from R to L d F, i.e. f ρ F ω = f ρ F ω for all ω Ω and F L F. We remark that 4.7 is the crucial fact which ensures that ρ and ρ are strongly consistent and conditionally law-invariant. In Theorem 4.6 we have seen that basically every CRM which is strongly consistent with a law-invariant CRM under trivial information can be decomposed into a conditional aggregation function and a univariate conditional certainty equivalent. For the rest of this section we study the effect of additional properties of the CRMs on this decomposition. For instance, we want to identify conditions under which the univariate conditional certainty equivalent is generated by a deterministic instead of a stochastic utility function; see Corollary 4.7. Also we study what happens if the univariate CRMs η and η from Theorem 4.6 are required to be strongly consistent; see Corollary 4.9. Corollary 4.7. In the situation of Theorem 4.6, if ρ is normalized on constants, then ΛX = fu ux, X L d F, and ηf = ρf 1 d = f u E P [f u F ], F L F. If ρ is normalized on constants, then similarly Λ X = f u ux, X L d F, 24

25 and η F = ρ F 1 d = f u E P [f u F ], F L F. In particular the univariate conditional certainty equivalent η is now given by the deterministic univariate utility function f u, and thus η is conditionally lawinvariant. If both ρ and ρ are normalized on constants, then Λ = Λ. Remark 4.8. Suppose that ρ and ρ from Theorem 4.6 are normalized on constants and that for all F, L F, m, λ R with λ 0, 1 as well as ρf 1 d + m1 d = ρf 1 d m 4.8 ρ λf 1 d + 1 λ1 d λρf 1d + 1 λρ1 d. 4.9 Recalling Corollary 4.7 it follows that ηf = ρf 1 d is cash-additive 4.8 and convex 4.9. Since f u is a deterministic function it can be easily checked that η and η are strongly consistent conditionally law-invariant univariate CRMs. Therefore we are in the framework of Föllmer There it is shown that the univariate CRMs must be either linear or of entropic type, i.e. f u x = ax + b or f u x = ae βx + b, x R, for constants a, b, β R with a, β > 0, which implies that η F = E P [ F ] or η F = 1 β log E P [ e βf ] and similarly for η. Clearly, this also has consequences for the aggregation function Λ = Λ = fu u since x ux1 d = f u x is either of linear or exponential form. For instance, a possible aggregation would be given by ux 1,..., x d = a d i=1 w ix i + b, where w i 0, 1 for i = 1,..., d such that d i=1 w i = 1, because f u x = ax + b. In this case the aggregation function is simply Λx = d i=1 w ix i. Corollary 4.9. In the situation of Theorem 4.6, suppose that η and η defined on all of L F. Then {η, η } are strongly consistent if and only if are η = ũ E P [ũf ] and η = ũ E P [ũf ] for a continuous and strictly increasing utility function ũ : R R. Moreover, the corresponding conditional aggregation functions are given by Λ = f ρ f u u and Λ = f ρ f u a u, where a F = αf + β, F L F, is a positive affine transformation given by α, β L with Pα > 0 = 1. 25

Risk-Consistent Conditional Systemic Risk Measures

Risk-Consistent Conditional Systemic Risk Measures Risk-Consistent Conditional Systemic Risk Measures Thilo Meyer-Brandis University of Munich joint with: H. Hoffmann and G. Svindland, University of Munich Workshop on Systemic Risk and Financial Networks

More information

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences Conditional and Dynamic Preferences How can we Understand Risk in a Dynamic Setting? Samuel Drapeau Joint work with Hans Föllmer Humboldt University Berlin Jena - March 17th 2009 Samuel Drapeau Joint work

More information

The Canonical Model Space for Law-invariant Convex Risk Measures is L 1

The Canonical Model Space for Law-invariant Convex Risk Measures is L 1 The Canonical Model Space for Law-invariant Convex Risk Measures is L 1 Damir Filipović Gregor Svindland 3 November 2008 Abstract In this paper we establish a one-to-one correspondence between lawinvariant

More information

4. Conditional risk measures and their robust representation

4. Conditional risk measures and their robust representation 4. Conditional risk measures and their robust representation We consider a discrete-time information structure given by a filtration (F t ) t=0,...,t on our probability space (Ω, F, P ). The time horizon

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

An axiomatic characterization of capital allocations of coherent risk measures

An axiomatic characterization of capital allocations of coherent risk measures An axiomatic characterization of capital allocations of coherent risk measures Michael Kalkbrener Deutsche Bank AG Abstract An axiomatic definition of coherent capital allocations is given. It is shown

More information

6 Classical dualities and reflexivity

6 Classical dualities and reflexivity 6 Classical dualities and reflexivity 1. Classical dualities. Let (Ω, A, µ) be a measure space. We will describe the duals for the Banach spaces L p (Ω). First, notice that any f L p, 1 p, generates the

More information

Comparative and qualitative robustness for law-invariant risk measures

Comparative and qualitative robustness for law-invariant risk measures Comparative and qualitative robustness for law-invariant risk measures Volker Krätschmer Alexander Schied Henryk Zähle Abstract When estimating the risk of a P&L from historical data or Monte Carlo simulation,

More information

Estimates for probabilities of independent events and infinite series

Estimates for probabilities of independent events and infinite series Estimates for probabilities of independent events and infinite series Jürgen Grahl and Shahar evo September 9, 06 arxiv:609.0894v [math.pr] 8 Sep 06 Abstract This paper deals with finite or infinite sequences

More information

A Unified Approach to Systemic Risk Measures via Acceptance Sets

A Unified Approach to Systemic Risk Measures via Acceptance Sets A Unified Approach to Systemic Risk Measures via Acceptance Sets Francesca Biagini Jean-Pierre Fouque Marco Frittelli Thilo Meyer-Brandis July 12, 2017 Abstract We specify a general methodological framework

More information

Lecture 4 Lebesgue spaces and inequalities

Lecture 4 Lebesgue spaces and inequalities Lecture 4: Lebesgue spaces and inequalities 1 of 10 Course: Theory of Probability I Term: Fall 2013 Instructor: Gordan Zitkovic Lecture 4 Lebesgue spaces and inequalities Lebesgue spaces We have seen how

More information

Measure Theory on Topological Spaces. Course: Prof. Tony Dorlas 2010 Typset: Cathal Ormond

Measure Theory on Topological Spaces. Course: Prof. Tony Dorlas 2010 Typset: Cathal Ormond Measure Theory on Topological Spaces Course: Prof. Tony Dorlas 2010 Typset: Cathal Ormond May 22, 2011 Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 The Riemann Integral........................................ 2 1.2 Measurable..............................................

More information

Empirical Processes: General Weak Convergence Theory

Empirical Processes: General Weak Convergence Theory Empirical Processes: General Weak Convergence Theory Moulinath Banerjee May 18, 2010 1 Extended Weak Convergence The lack of measurability of the empirical process with respect to the sigma-field generated

More information

A Note on Robust Representations of Law-Invariant Quasiconvex Functions

A Note on Robust Representations of Law-Invariant Quasiconvex Functions A Note on Robust Representations of Law-Invariant Quasiconvex Functions Samuel Drapeau Michael Kupper Ranja Reda October 6, 21 We give robust representations of law-invariant monotone quasiconvex functions.

More information

Measures and Measure Spaces

Measures and Measure Spaces Chapter 2 Measures and Measure Spaces In summarizing the flaws of the Riemann integral we can focus on two main points: 1) Many nice functions are not Riemann integrable. 2) The Riemann integral does not

More information

A unified approach to time consistency of dynamic risk measures and dynamic performance measures in discrete time

A unified approach to time consistency of dynamic risk measures and dynamic performance measures in discrete time A unified approach to time consistency of dynamic risk measures and dynamic performance measures in discrete time Tomasz R. Bielecki a, Igor Cialenco a, and Marcin Pitera b First Circulated: September

More information

5 Measure theory II. (or. lim. Prove the proposition. 5. For fixed F A and φ M define the restriction of φ on F by writing.

5 Measure theory II. (or. lim. Prove the proposition. 5. For fixed F A and φ M define the restriction of φ on F by writing. 5 Measure theory II 1. Charges (signed measures). Let (Ω, A) be a σ -algebra. A map φ: A R is called a charge, (or signed measure or σ -additive set function) if φ = φ(a j ) (5.1) A j for any disjoint

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Dynkin (λ-) and π-systems; monotone classes of sets, and of functions with some examples of application (mainly of a probabilistic flavor)

Dynkin (λ-) and π-systems; monotone classes of sets, and of functions with some examples of application (mainly of a probabilistic flavor) Dynkin (λ-) and π-systems; monotone classes of sets, and of functions with some examples of application (mainly of a probabilistic flavor) Matija Vidmar February 7, 2018 1 Dynkin and π-systems Some basic

More information

Birgit Rudloff Operations Research and Financial Engineering, Princeton University

Birgit Rudloff Operations Research and Financial Engineering, Princeton University TIME CONSISTENT RISK AVERSE DYNAMIC DECISION MODELS: AN ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION Birgit Rudloff Operations Research and Financial Engineering, Princeton University brudloff@princeton.edu Alexandre Street

More information

( f ^ M _ M 0 )dµ (5.1)

( f ^ M _ M 0 )dµ (5.1) 47 5. LEBESGUE INTEGRAL: GENERAL CASE Although the Lebesgue integral defined in the previous chapter is in many ways much better behaved than the Riemann integral, it shares its restriction to bounded

More information

Probability and Measure

Probability and Measure Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 84 Paper 4, Section II 26J Let (X, A) be a measurable space. Let T : X X be a measurable map, and µ a probability

More information

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries Chapter 1 Measure Spaces 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets 1.1.1 Notation and preliminaries We shall denote by X a nonempty set, by P(X) the set of all parts (i.e., subsets) of X, and by the empty set.

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

Introduction and Preliminaries

Introduction and Preliminaries Chapter 1 Introduction and Preliminaries This chapter serves two purposes. The first purpose is to prepare the readers for the more systematic development in later chapters of methods of real analysis

More information

LARGE DEVIATIONS OF TYPICAL LINEAR FUNCTIONALS ON A CONVEX BODY WITH UNCONDITIONAL BASIS. S. G. Bobkov and F. L. Nazarov. September 25, 2011

LARGE DEVIATIONS OF TYPICAL LINEAR FUNCTIONALS ON A CONVEX BODY WITH UNCONDITIONAL BASIS. S. G. Bobkov and F. L. Nazarov. September 25, 2011 LARGE DEVIATIONS OF TYPICAL LINEAR FUNCTIONALS ON A CONVEX BODY WITH UNCONDITIONAL BASIS S. G. Bobkov and F. L. Nazarov September 25, 20 Abstract We study large deviations of linear functionals on an isotropic

More information

Process-Based Risk Measures for Observable and Partially Observable Discrete-Time Controlled Systems

Process-Based Risk Measures for Observable and Partially Observable Discrete-Time Controlled Systems Process-Based Risk Measures for Observable and Partially Observable Discrete-Time Controlled Systems Jingnan Fan Andrzej Ruszczyński November 5, 2014; revised April 15, 2015 Abstract For controlled discrete-time

More information

Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets

Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets Tim Leung 1, Qingshuo Song 2, and Jie Yang 3 1 Columbia University, New York, USA; leung@ieor.columbia.edu 2 City

More information

ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES

ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES Submitted to the Annals of Probability ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES By Mark J. Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph B. Kadane, Carnegie

More information

Lebesgue-Radon-Nikodym Theorem

Lebesgue-Radon-Nikodym Theorem Lebesgue-Radon-Nikodym Theorem Matt Rosenzweig 1 Lebesgue-Radon-Nikodym Theorem In what follows, (, A) will denote a measurable space. We begin with a review of signed measures. 1.1 Signed Measures Definition

More information

1/12/05: sec 3.1 and my article: How good is the Lebesgue measure?, Math. Intelligencer 11(2) (1989),

1/12/05: sec 3.1 and my article: How good is the Lebesgue measure?, Math. Intelligencer 11(2) (1989), Real Analysis 2, Math 651, Spring 2005 April 26, 2005 1 Real Analysis 2, Math 651, Spring 2005 Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski 1/12/05: sec 3.1 and my article: How good is the Lebesgue measure?, Math. Intelligencer

More information

Coherent risk measures

Coherent risk measures Coherent risk measures Foivos Xanthos Ryerson University, Department of Mathematics Toµɛας Mαθηµατ ικὼν, E.M.Π, 11 Noɛµβρὶoυ 2015 Research interests Financial Mathematics, Mathematical Economics, Functional

More information

Journal of Mathematical Economics. Coherent risk measures in general economic models and price bubbles

Journal of Mathematical Economics. Coherent risk measures in general economic models and price bubbles Journal of Mathematical Economics ( ) Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Journal of Mathematical Economics journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jmateco Coherent risk measures in general

More information

Signed Measures. Chapter Basic Properties of Signed Measures. 4.2 Jordan and Hahn Decompositions

Signed Measures. Chapter Basic Properties of Signed Measures. 4.2 Jordan and Hahn Decompositions Chapter 4 Signed Measures Up until now our measures have always assumed values that were greater than or equal to 0. In this chapter we will extend our definition to allow for both positive negative values.

More information

A von Neumann Morgenstern Representation Result without Weak Continuity Assumption

A von Neumann Morgenstern Representation Result without Weak Continuity Assumption A von Neumann Morgenstern Representation Result without Weak Continuity Assumption Freddy Delbaen Samuel Drapeau Michael Kupper April 17, 2011 In the paradigm of VON NEUMANN AND MORGENSTERN, a representation

More information

Fundamental Inequalities, Convergence and the Optional Stopping Theorem for Continuous-Time Martingales

Fundamental Inequalities, Convergence and the Optional Stopping Theorem for Continuous-Time Martingales Fundamental Inequalities, Convergence and the Optional Stopping Theorem for Continuous-Time Martingales Prakash Balachandran Department of Mathematics Duke University April 2, 2008 1 Review of Discrete-Time

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.ag] 24 Jun 2015

arxiv: v2 [math.ag] 24 Jun 2015 TRIANGULATIONS OF MONOTONE FAMILIES I: TWO-DIMENSIONAL FAMILIES arxiv:1402.0460v2 [math.ag] 24 Jun 2015 SAUGATA BASU, ANDREI GABRIELOV, AND NICOLAI VOROBJOV Abstract. Let K R n be a compact definable set

More information

Maths 212: Homework Solutions

Maths 212: Homework Solutions Maths 212: Homework Solutions 1. The definition of A ensures that x π for all x A, so π is an upper bound of A. To show it is the least upper bound, suppose x < π and consider two cases. If x < 1, then

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures

On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures MATHEMATICS OF OPERATIONS RESEARCH Vol. 38, No. 1, February 213, pp. 142 152 ISSN 364-765X (print) ISSN 1526-5471 (online) http://dx.doi.org/1.1287/moor.112.563 213 INFORMS On Kusuoka Representation of

More information

VISCOSITY SOLUTIONS. We follow Han and Lin, Elliptic Partial Differential Equations, 5.

VISCOSITY SOLUTIONS. We follow Han and Lin, Elliptic Partial Differential Equations, 5. VISCOSITY SOLUTIONS PETER HINTZ We follow Han and Lin, Elliptic Partial Differential Equations, 5. 1. Motivation Throughout, we will assume that Ω R n is a bounded and connected domain and that a ij C(Ω)

More information

1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming

1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming 1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming Formally, a stochastic dynamic program has the same components as a deterministic one; the only modification is to the state transition equation. When events in the future

More information

Generalized quantiles as risk measures

Generalized quantiles as risk measures Generalized quantiles as risk measures Bellini, Klar, Muller, Rosazza Gianin December 1, 2014 Vorisek Jan Introduction Quantiles q α of a random variable X can be defined as the minimizers of a piecewise

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

L p Spaces and Convexity

L p Spaces and Convexity L p Spaces and Convexity These notes largely follow the treatments in Royden, Real Analysis, and Rudin, Real & Complex Analysis. 1. Convex functions Let I R be an interval. For I open, we say a function

More information

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 Index Page 1 Topology 2 1.1 Definition of a topology 2 1.2 Basis (Base) of a topology 2 1.3 The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 1.4 Basic topology concepts: limit points, closed sets,

More information

Helly's Theorem and its Equivalences via Convex Analysis

Helly's Theorem and its Equivalences via Convex Analysis Portland State University PDXScholar University Honors Theses University Honors College 2014 Helly's Theorem and its Equivalences via Convex Analysis Adam Robinson Portland State University Let us know

More information

Measure and integration

Measure and integration Chapter 5 Measure and integration In calculus you have learned how to calculate the size of different kinds of sets: the length of a curve, the area of a region or a surface, the volume or mass of a solid.

More information

arxiv: v2 [q-fin.mf] 24 Apr 2015

arxiv: v2 [q-fin.mf] 24 Apr 2015 A Unified Approach to Systemic Risk Measures via Acceptance Sets arxiv:1503.06354v2 [q-fin.mf] 24 Apr 2015 Francesca Biagini Jean-Pierre Fouque Marco Frittelli Thilo Meyer-Brandis September 22, 2018 Abstract

More information

2 Sequences, Continuity, and Limits

2 Sequences, Continuity, and Limits 2 Sequences, Continuity, and Limits In this chapter, we introduce the fundamental notions of continuity and limit of a real-valued function of two variables. As in ACICARA, the definitions as well as proofs

More information

Lecture 21: Expectation of CRVs, Fatou s Lemma and DCT Integration of Continuous Random Variables

Lecture 21: Expectation of CRVs, Fatou s Lemma and DCT Integration of Continuous Random Variables EE50: Probability Foundations for Electrical Engineers July-November 205 Lecture 2: Expectation of CRVs, Fatou s Lemma and DCT Lecturer: Krishna Jagannathan Scribe: Jainam Doshi In the present lecture,

More information

Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm

Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm Chapter 13 Radon Measures Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm (13.1) f = sup x X f(x). We want to identify

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

A Unified Approach to Systemic Risk Measures via Acceptance Sets

A Unified Approach to Systemic Risk Measures via Acceptance Sets A Unified Approach to Systemic Risk Measures via Acceptance Sets Francesca Biagini Jean-Pierre Fouque Marco Frittelli Thilo Meyer-Brandis March 7, 207 Abstract We specify a general methodological framework

More information

On Unitary Relations between Kre n Spaces

On Unitary Relations between Kre n Spaces RUDI WIETSMA On Unitary Relations between Kre n Spaces PROCEEDINGS OF THE UNIVERSITY OF VAASA WORKING PAPERS 2 MATHEMATICS 1 VAASA 2011 III Publisher Date of publication Vaasan yliopisto August 2011 Author(s)

More information

Isomorphisms between pattern classes

Isomorphisms between pattern classes Journal of Combinatorics olume 0, Number 0, 1 8, 0000 Isomorphisms between pattern classes M. H. Albert, M. D. Atkinson and Anders Claesson Isomorphisms φ : A B between pattern classes are considered.

More information

MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction

MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction 1 INTRODUCTION MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, 2014 1 Introduction Definition. If A, B are sets and there exists a bijection A B, they have the same cardinality, which we write as A, #A. If there exists

More information

Ergodic Theorems. Samy Tindel. Purdue University. Probability Theory 2 - MA 539. Taken from Probability: Theory and examples by R.

Ergodic Theorems. Samy Tindel. Purdue University. Probability Theory 2 - MA 539. Taken from Probability: Theory and examples by R. Ergodic Theorems Samy Tindel Purdue University Probability Theory 2 - MA 539 Taken from Probability: Theory and examples by R. Durrett Samy T. Ergodic theorems Probability Theory 1 / 92 Outline 1 Definitions

More information

HOPF S DECOMPOSITION AND RECURRENT SEMIGROUPS. Josef Teichmann

HOPF S DECOMPOSITION AND RECURRENT SEMIGROUPS. Josef Teichmann HOPF S DECOMPOSITION AND RECURRENT SEMIGROUPS Josef Teichmann Abstract. Some results of ergodic theory are generalized in the setting of Banach lattices, namely Hopf s maximal ergodic inequality and the

More information

Measure Theory and Lebesgue Integration. Joshua H. Lifton

Measure Theory and Lebesgue Integration. Joshua H. Lifton Measure Theory and Lebesgue Integration Joshua H. Lifton Originally published 31 March 1999 Revised 5 September 2004 bstract This paper originally came out of my 1999 Swarthmore College Mathematics Senior

More information

Convex Optimization Notes

Convex Optimization Notes Convex Optimization Notes Jonathan Siegel January 2017 1 Convex Analysis This section is devoted to the study of convex functions f : B R {+ } and convex sets U B, for B a Banach space. The case of B =

More information

Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces

Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces T. C. Dorlas Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies School of Theoretical Physics 10 Burlington Road, Dublin 4, Ireland. Email: dorlas@stp.dias.ie

More information

3 (Due ). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure?

3 (Due ). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure? MA 645-4A (Real Analysis), Dr. Chernov Homework assignment 1 (Due ). Show that the open disk x 2 + y 2 < 1 is a countable union of planar elementary sets. Show that the closed disk x 2 + y 2 1 is a countable

More information

If Y and Y 0 satisfy (1-2), then Y = Y 0 a.s.

If Y and Y 0 satisfy (1-2), then Y = Y 0 a.s. 20 6. CONDITIONAL EXPECTATION Having discussed at length the limit theory for sums of independent random variables we will now move on to deal with dependent random variables. An important tool in this

More information

2 Lebesgue integration

2 Lebesgue integration 2 Lebesgue integration 1. Let (, A, µ) be a measure space. We will always assume that µ is complete, otherwise we first take its completion. The example to have in mind is the Lebesgue measure on R n,

More information

Risk-Averse Dynamic Optimization. Andrzej Ruszczyński. Research supported by the NSF award CMMI

Risk-Averse Dynamic Optimization. Andrzej Ruszczyński. Research supported by the NSF award CMMI Research supported by the NSF award CMMI-0965689 Outline 1 Risk-Averse Preferences 2 Coherent Risk Measures 3 Dynamic Risk Measurement 4 Markov Risk Measures 5 Risk-Averse Control Problems 6 Solution Methods

More information

A SHORT INTRODUCTION TO BANACH LATTICES AND

A SHORT INTRODUCTION TO BANACH LATTICES AND CHAPTER A SHORT INTRODUCTION TO BANACH LATTICES AND POSITIVE OPERATORS In tis capter we give a brief introduction to Banac lattices and positive operators. Most results of tis capter can be found, e.g.,

More information

Lecture 17 Brownian motion as a Markov process

Lecture 17 Brownian motion as a Markov process Lecture 17: Brownian motion as a Markov process 1 of 14 Course: Theory of Probability II Term: Spring 2015 Instructor: Gordan Zitkovic Lecture 17 Brownian motion as a Markov process Brownian motion is

More information

GEOMETRIC APPROACH TO CONVEX SUBDIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS October 10, Dedicated to Franco Giannessi and Diethard Pallaschke with great respect

GEOMETRIC APPROACH TO CONVEX SUBDIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS October 10, Dedicated to Franco Giannessi and Diethard Pallaschke with great respect GEOMETRIC APPROACH TO CONVEX SUBDIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS October 10, 2018 BORIS S. MORDUKHOVICH 1 and NGUYEN MAU NAM 2 Dedicated to Franco Giannessi and Diethard Pallaschke with great respect Abstract. In

More information

Final. due May 8, 2012

Final. due May 8, 2012 Final due May 8, 2012 Write your solutions clearly in complete sentences. All notation used must be properly introduced. Your arguments besides being correct should be also complete. Pay close attention

More information

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi Real Analysis Math 3AH Rudin, Chapter # Dominique Abdi.. If r is rational (r 0) and x is irrational, prove that r + x and rx are irrational. Solution. Assume the contrary, that r+x and rx are rational.

More information

Conditional Preference Orders and their Numerical Representations

Conditional Preference Orders and their Numerical Representations Conditional Preference Orders and their Numerical Representations Samuel Drapeau a,1, Asgar Jamneshan b,2 October 20, 2014 ABSTRACT This work provides an axiomatic framework to the concept of conditional

More information

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction Lecture notes Course Analysis for PhD students Uppsala University, Spring 2018 Rostyslav Kozhan Chapter 1 Measures 1.1 Some prerequisites I will follow closely the textbook Real analysis: Modern Techniques

More information

REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: 1.4 OUTER MEASURE

REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: 1.4 OUTER MEASURE REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: 1.4 OUTER MEASURE CHRISTOPHER HEIL 1.4.1 Introduction We will expand on Section 1.4 of Folland s text, which covers abstract outer measures also called exterior measures).

More information

Decomposition of Riesz frames and wavelets into a finite union of linearly independent sets

Decomposition of Riesz frames and wavelets into a finite union of linearly independent sets Decomposition of Riesz frames and wavelets into a finite union of linearly independent sets Ole Christensen, Alexander M. Lindner Abstract We characterize Riesz frames and prove that every Riesz frame

More information

2 (Bonus). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure?

2 (Bonus). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure? MA 645-4A (Real Analysis), Dr. Chernov Homework assignment 1 (Due 9/5). Prove that every countable set A is measurable and µ(a) = 0. 2 (Bonus). Let A consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is

More information

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller Real Analysis Notes Thomas Goller September 4, 2011 Contents 1 Abstract Measure Spaces 2 1.1 Basic Definitions........................... 2 1.2 Measurable Functions........................ 2 1.3 Integration..............................

More information

The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs

The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs Lecture Notes by Walter Schachermayer Nachdiplom-Vorlesung, ETH Zürich, WS 15/16 1 Models on Finite Probability Spaces In this section we consider a stock price

More information

4th Preparation Sheet - Solutions

4th Preparation Sheet - Solutions Prof. Dr. Rainer Dahlhaus Probability Theory Summer term 017 4th Preparation Sheet - Solutions Remark: Throughout the exercise sheet we use the two equivalent definitions of separability of a metric space

More information

Math 564 Homework 1. Solutions.

Math 564 Homework 1. Solutions. Math 564 Homework 1. Solutions. Problem 1. Prove Proposition 0.2.2. A guide to this problem: start with the open set S = (a, b), for example. First assume that a >, and show that the number a has the properties

More information

An introduction to Mathematical Theory of Control

An introduction to Mathematical Theory of Control An introduction to Mathematical Theory of Control Vasile Staicu University of Aveiro UNICA, May 2018 Vasile Staicu (University of Aveiro) An introduction to Mathematical Theory of Control UNICA, May 2018

More information

Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies

Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies BS V c Gabriel Nagy Banach Spaces V: A Closer Look at the w- and the w -Topologies Notes from the Functional Analysis Course (Fall 07 - Spring 08) In this section we discuss two important, but highly non-trivial,

More information

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2011 Lecture 5 Friday July 29, 2011

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2011 Lecture 5 Friday July 29, 2011 Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2011 Lecture 5 Friday July 29, 2011 Section 2.6 (cont.) Properties of Real Functions Here we first study properties of functions from R to R, making use of the additional structure

More information

THE CORONA FACTORIZATION PROPERTY AND REFINEMENT MONOIDS

THE CORONA FACTORIZATION PROPERTY AND REFINEMENT MONOIDS THE CORONA FACTORIZATION PROPERTY AND REFINEMENT MONOIDS EDUARD ORTEGA, FRANCESC PERERA, AND MIKAEL RØRDAM ABSTRACT. The Corona Factorization Property of a C -algebra, originally defined to study extensions

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.fa] 14 Jul 2018

arxiv: v1 [math.fa] 14 Jul 2018 Construction of Regular Non-Atomic arxiv:180705437v1 [mathfa] 14 Jul 2018 Strictly-Positive Measures in Second-Countable Locally Compact Non-Atomic Hausdorff Spaces Abstract Jason Bentley Department of

More information

The Skorokhod reflection problem for functions with discontinuities (contractive case)

The Skorokhod reflection problem for functions with discontinuities (contractive case) The Skorokhod reflection problem for functions with discontinuities (contractive case) TAKIS KONSTANTOPOULOS Univ. of Texas at Austin Revised March 1999 Abstract Basic properties of the Skorokhod reflection

More information

Lecture 5. If we interpret the index n 0 as time, then a Markov chain simply requires that the future depends only on the present and not on the past.

Lecture 5. If we interpret the index n 0 as time, then a Markov chain simply requires that the future depends only on the present and not on the past. 1 Markov chain: definition Lecture 5 Definition 1.1 Markov chain] A sequence of random variables (X n ) n 0 taking values in a measurable state space (S, S) is called a (discrete time) Markov chain, if

More information

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515 THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515 Proposition 1 (=comment on page 17). If A is an algebra, then any finite union or finite intersection of sets in A is also in A. Proposition 2 (=Proposition 1.1). For every

More information

CHAPTER 6. Differentiation

CHAPTER 6. Differentiation CHPTER 6 Differentiation The generalization from elementary calculus of differentiation in measure theory is less obvious than that of integration, and the methods of treating it are somewhat involved.

More information

Monte-Carlo MMD-MA, Université Paris-Dauphine. Xiaolu Tan

Monte-Carlo MMD-MA, Université Paris-Dauphine. Xiaolu Tan Monte-Carlo MMD-MA, Université Paris-Dauphine Xiaolu Tan tan@ceremade.dauphine.fr Septembre 2015 Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 The principle.................................. 1 1.2 The error analysis

More information

Appendix B Convex analysis

Appendix B Convex analysis This version: 28/02/2014 Appendix B Convex analysis In this appendix we review a few basic notions of convexity and related notions that will be important for us at various times. B.1 The Hausdorff distance

More information

COMPARISON PROPERTIES OF THE CUNTZ SEMIGROUP AND APPLICATIONS TO C*-ALGEBRAS

COMPARISON PROPERTIES OF THE CUNTZ SEMIGROUP AND APPLICATIONS TO C*-ALGEBRAS COMPARISON PROPERTIES OF THE CUNTZ SEMIGROUP AND APPLICATIONS TO C*-ALGEBRAS JOAN BOSA AND HENNING PETZKA ABSTRACT. We study comparison properties in the category Cu aiming to lift results to the C*-algebraic

More information

1 Functional Analysis

1 Functional Analysis 1 Functional Analysis 1 1.1 Banach spaces Remark 1.1. In classical mechanics, the state of some physical system is characterized as a point x in phase space (generalized position and momentum coordinates).

More information

SPRING 2006 PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION SOLUTIONS

SPRING 2006 PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION SOLUTIONS SPRING 006 PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION SOLUTIONS 1A. Let G be the subgroup of the free abelian group Z 4 consisting of all integer vectors (x, y, z, w) such that x + 3y + 5z + 7w = 0. (a) Determine a linearly

More information

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define 1 Measures 1.1 Jordan content in R N II - REAL ANALYSIS Let I be an interval in R. Then its 1-content is defined as c 1 (I) := b a if I is bounded with endpoints a, b. If I is unbounded, we define c 1

More information

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE D-MAXIMAL SETS PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE Abstract. Soare [23] proved that the maximal sets form an orbit in E. We consider here D-maximal sets, generalizations of maximal sets introduced

More information

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS REAL AND COMPLE ANALYSIS Third Edition Walter Rudin Professor of Mathematics University of Wisconsin, Madison Version 1.1 No rights reserved. Any part of this work can be reproduced or transmitted in any

More information

Math212a1413 The Lebesgue integral.

Math212a1413 The Lebesgue integral. Math212a1413 The Lebesgue integral. October 28, 2014 Simple functions. In what follows, (X, F, m) is a space with a σ-field of sets, and m a measure on F. The purpose of today s lecture is to develop the

More information