A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY PART 1: SPECIAL RELATIVITY ARICK SHAO

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY PART 1: SPECIAL RELATIVITY ARICK SHAO"

Transcription

1 A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY PART 1: SPECIAL RELATIVITY ARICK SHAO These notes are the first of a pair of brief articles containing an informal introduction to the mathematics behind the theory of relativity. Here, we survey special relativity, which represents the case in which gravitational effects are negligible, and which served as a precursor to general relativity. In order to keep these notes appropriately short, most of the details e.g., technical definitions, proofs, and computations are omitted. Background knowledge in differential geometry would be helpful here for understanding various points, but will not be strictly required due to the informal nature of the discussions. An important disclaimer is that these notes focus primarily on the mathematical, rather than the physical, aspects of the theory. This is mostly by necessity, since I am a mathematician (and not a physicist), with background in partial differential equations and differential geometry (and not in theoretical physics). Consequently, this article will approach the subject from a mathematical viewpoint, in particular in terms of geometry of Minkowski spacetime. Physicists will rightfully have a different perspective on many of these points. For a detailed mathematical reference, see [3, Ch. 6] for a formal development of Minkowski geometry and special relativity. For a (physics) text containing both mathematical and physical elements, see [4, Ch. 4]. Furthermore, on the physics side, many elementary references to the topics touched upon here are widely available on the Internet. 1. Minkowski Geometry The postulates for special relativity were first formulated by Albert Einstein in Quoting Nobelprize.org [2], Einstein s postulates state that: (1) The principle of relativity: The laws of physics are the same in all inertial frames of reference. (2) The constancy of speed of light in vacuum: The speed of light in vacuum has the same value c in all inertial frames of references. From these postulates and various physical considerations, Einstein was able to derive many mind-blowing consequences. For instance, two observers moving at different velocities will 1 Unfortunately, here we are ignoring vast amounts of physics history which eventually led to this point; see, for instance, [1, 5] for some basic summaries. 1

2 2 ARICK SHAO perceive lengths of objects differently. These results had a profound effect on modern physics and on the way physicists viewed the world. On the mathematical side, a major contribution came from Hermann Minkowski, who in 1908 gave a mathematical formulation of special relativity in terms of differential geometry. Aside from providing a rigorous mathematical model for the universe under special relativity, Minkowski s viewpoint was also important because it would later be extended by Einstein into the theory of general relativity Minkowski Spacetime. Minkowski s mathematical model melded time and space into a single entity spacetime. More specifically, this spacetime is modeled by 2 R 4 := {(t, x, y, z) t, x, y, z R}, for which we can naively think of the first component as the time component and the remaining three components as the spatial components. Now, the description of spacetime as the set of 4-tuples (t, x, y, z) is philosophically not so accurate. In light of the relativity principle, all inertial reference frames, or coordinate systems in mathematical lingo, should be treated the same. In other words, since there should not be a single preferred system of coordinates, we should not privilege the Cartesian coordinates t, x, y, z, as in the above. Thus, the mathematical object for describing spacetime should not just be R 4, but instead this R 4 modulo coordinate systems. The notion for capturing this coordinate-independent object is precisely that of a (differential) manifold. As a result, we can formally define the Minkowski universe as R 4, but viewed as a 4-dimensional manifold. 3 Remark. The above should be contrasted with Newtonian theory, for which space itself can be modelled by the manifold R 3 (modulo coordinate systems), and for which time is similarly described by R modulo coordinates. The difference, however, is that the Newtonian theory posits a clear split between space and time, whereas in special relativity, space and time are combined into a single aggregate object R 4. Next, recall that in the classical Newtonian setting, the squared distance between two points in space is the Euclidean distance: d 2 E((x 1, y 1, z 1 ), (x 2, y 2, z 2 )) := (x 2 x 1 ) 2 + (y 2 y 1 ) 2 + (z 2 z 1 ) 2. 2 There are some caveats; see further below. 3 A manifold is, roughly, an object that near each point looks like a copy of R n. While R 4 trivially satisfies this characterization, the pedagogical point here is that this manifold description of R 4 does not make any particular coordinate system more special than any other.

3 A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY 3 In Minkowski spacetime, an analogous squared distance is constructed on R 4, except that we flip the sign of the time component: 4 d 2 M((t 1, x 1, y 1, z 1 ), (t 2, x 2, y 2, z 2 )) := (t 2 t 1 ) 2 + (x 2 x 1 ) 2 + (y 2 y 1 ) 2 + (z 2 z 1 ) 2. Remark. We note that although d 2 E and d2 M are defined above using special fixed coordinates, both can in fact also be expressed in a coordinate-independent manner. Since we would like to take derivatives, we wish to state the above in a differential form. In the Newtonian setting, this is captured by the Euclidean metric on R 3 : g E := dx 2 + dy 2 + dz 2. More explicitly, given two tangent vectors about some point in space, v = (v x, v y, v z ), w = (w x, w y, w z ), their inner product with respect to g E is g E (v, w) = v x w x + v y w y + v z w z, that is, the standard dot product in 3 dimensions. 5 On the other hand, the metric on R 4 corresponding to d 2 M is g M := dt 2 + dx 2 + dy 2 + dz 2. In other words, given two tangent vectors about a point in spacetime, v = (v t, v x, v y, v z ), w = (w t, w x, w y, w z ), we measure their inner product with respect to this Minkowski metric as g M (v, w) = v t w t + v x w x + v y w y + v z w z. Thus, we formally define Minkowski spacetime to be the manifold-and-metric pair (R 4, g M ). This geometric object describes the universe as modeled by special relativity. 6 Consequently, the mathematics behind special relativity is precisely the study of this Minkowski geometry. Because of this change in sign in the time component, Minkowski geometry has vastly different properties compared to the more familiar Euclidean geometry that is associated with classical Newtonian physics. 4 Since we are more concerned with the mathematical aspects here, we simplify notations by assuming units such that the speed of light is 1. 5 We remark that d E can be recovered from g E by integrating along curves. 6 This is not entirely accurate, as in addition to (R 4, g M ), one also has a time orientation, that is, a way of distinguishing between future and past directions.

4 4 ARICK SHAO 1.2. Causal Character. In contrast to the Euclidean metric and distance, which are always positive-definite, the Minkowski product g M (v, v) no longer has a definite sign. This lends itself to the notion of the causal character of a direction: A tangent vector v is timelike iff g M (v, v) < 0. v is spacelike iff either g M (v, v) > 0 or v = 0. v is null, or lightlike, iff g M (v, v) = 0 and v 0. Examples of each type of vector can be found in Figure 1. In particular, the set of all null directions from the origin form a double cone about the origin (represented by the dotted lines), called the light, or null, cone. Directions lying within the light cone are timelike, while directions lying in the exterior are spacelike. t timelike null null spacelike spacelike x, y, z Figure 1. Timelike, spacelike, and null directions about the origin. For visual clarity, the three spatial dimensions are compacted into two dimensions. This partition into causal characters has physical interpretations as well. A point in Minkowski spacetime, called an event, represents a single particle at a particular time, while a timelike curve in R 4 represents an observer, that is, a single particle existing throughout time. Null lines, on the other hand, represent light rays. Note these prescriptions of observers and of timelike directions being within the light cone automatically imply that objects cannot travel faster than the speed of light. Furthermore, this leads to the basic tenets of causality: an event A at some time t > 0 can be affected by an event O at the origin if and only if A lies in the (future) null cone centered at O, or equivalently, O and A are connected by a timelike curve.

5 A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY Inertial Coordinates. Recall the principle of relativity states that the laws of physics should not change in any inertial, or nonaccelerating, frame of reference. Since the physical content is given through the Minkowski metric g M, the relativity principle can thus be formulated as follows: if one were to change from the usual Cartesian coordinates to another inertial coordinate system ( t, x, ȳ, z), then the metric should look the same with respect to these new coordinates, g M = d t 2 + d x 2 + dȳ 2 + d z 2. Another way to view this mathematically is to think of this change of (global) coordinates as a mapping from R 4 to itself, (t, x, y, z) Φ(t, x, y, z) := ( t, x, ȳ, z). From this perspective, the preceding statement about the metric being preserved can be precisely expressed as this map Φ being an isometry, that is, a map that does not change the geometry of the spacetime (represented by the metric g M ). 7 So, then, what are some of these isometries, or equivalently, changes of inertial coordinate systems? The simplest ones are the translations, (t, x, y, z) (t + t 0, x + x 0, y + y 0, z + z 0 ), which shift the time and spatial coordinates by a fixed amount. Another family of isometries are the spatial rotations, which leave t constant but rotate the (x, y, z)-coordinates. Note that these translations and rotations are also isometries of Euclidean geometry. What is interesting, and new to Minkowski geometry, are the isometries known as Lorentz boosts. These can be thought of as spacetime rotations involving also the time coordinate. However, because of this reversal in sign for the time coordinate in g M, the Lorentz boosts are quite different in nature from the usual rotations. For simplicity let us consider a boost involving only t and x. This is given by ( ) 1 (t, x, y, z) ( t, x, ȳ, z) = (t vx), 1 (x vt), y, z, 1 v 2 1 v 2 where v R satisfies v < 1. 8 This is the Lorentz transformation that is usually found in elementary physics texts, and it represents the change of coordinates from a constant shift in velocity in the x-direction. More specifically, if an observer is moving with velocity (v, 0, 0) with respect to (t, x, y, z)-coordinates, then the same observer is at rest with respect to the ( t, x, ȳ, z)-coordinates. Analogous boosts can, of course, be defined involving (t, y) or (t, z), or for any composition of the the preceding three boosts. Finally, any combination of translations, rotations, and boosts produces yet another isometry. 7 In differential geometric language, this means that the pullback Φ g M is g M itself. 8 Recall that the speed of light is 1 here.

6 6 ARICK SHAO A natural consequence of this discussion is the fact that, similar to Newtonian mechanics, there is no absolute notion of velocity in special relativity. Consider, for example, an observer who is at rest with respect to one inertial coordinate system (t, x, y, z). Then, by a Lorentz transformation, we can produce another inertial coordinate system in which this observer is moving at a constant velocity. Since neither coordinate system should be favored over the other due to the relativity principle, one has no way of determining what is the absolute velocity of the observer, or whether this observer is at rest. Indeed, these notions of velocity and at rest only exist relative to an observer or a coordinate system. However, one drastic departure from Newtonian theory is that in special relativity, there is also no canonical notion of time elapsed between two events. Indeed, given two events P, Q R 4, the elapsed times t(q) t(p ) and t(q) t(p ) with respect to two inertial coordinate systems (t, x, y, z) and ( t, x, ȳ, z) need not be the same. 9 We will demonstrate this in more detail in the upcoming discussions on physical consequences. Remark. Given an observer A, one does have the notion of proper time, i.e., the time lapse as measured by A itself. If P and Q lie on the curve A, then this proper time is the length of the curve segment between P and Q, measured with respect to the distance d M Energy-Momentum. Consider a timelike curve α in R 4 satisfying g M (α (τ), α (τ)) = 1. Here, α (τ), which we note is a vector with four components, denotes the tangent vector of α at the point α(τ). One can view this as the Minkowski analogue of arc length parametrization (or in other words, α is parametrized by proper time). Suppose now that α represents a particle with mass m. We then define the energymomentum vector field for this particle α by P (τ) := m α (τ). The idea is that both the energy and the momentum contents of the particle are contained within this single 4-vector field. Roughly speaking, the energy is expressed in the timelike part of P, while the momentum is expressed in the spacelike part. However, like for the notions of velocity at at rest above, this timelike part and spacelike part can only be defined relative to an observer. To be more specific, consider another observer A, which intersects α at α(τ), at which A measures the energy-momentum of α (see Figure 2). At α(τ), we can decompose P (τ) as P (τ) = ET + X, where: 9 For example, this can be the case if the coordinate systems are related via a nontrivial Lorentz boost.

7 A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY 7 E 0 is a number. The vector T is unit (with respect to g M ), timelike, and points in the direction of A. The vector X is (Minkowski) orthogonal to T (i.e., g M (T, X) = 0). 10 The number E and the vector X represent the energy and the momentum of α at α(τ), as measured by A. A quick computation yields that m 2 = g M (P (τ), P (τ)) = E 2 + g M (X, X) E 2. In particular, this implies that m E, and that the difference E m arises from the measured momentum of the particle. A α T P (τ) α(τ) X Figure 2. An observer A measuring the energy-momentum of α at the event α(τ). Again, the above is only defined relative to an observer A. Measuring with respect to a different observer would result in a different decomposition P (τ) = E T + X, which would yield a different measurement of energy and momentum. It is natural, though, to measure with respect to the particle α itself. From this frame of reference, the particle is of course at rest, resulting in the decomposition P (τ) = m α (τ) + 0 = E r T r + X r. In particular, we have that X r = 0, T r = α (τ), E r = m, i.e., the momentum vanishes, and the rest energy, E r, is just the mass m itself. 10 In particular, X is necessarily spacelike.

8 8 ARICK SHAO Note that throughout this discussion, we had, for mathematical convenience, assumed that the speed of light is 1. If we were to have worked with a different value c for the speed of light throughout all the preceding discussions, then the revised expression for the rest energy would now be given by the infamous formula E r = mc 2. In other words, from the mass, one can measure the (rest) energy of the particle, and vice versa. In physics, this is known as mass-energy equivalence. 2. Some Physical Consequences To conclude our discussions and to further demonstrate the mathematical theory, we show that many of the seemingly strange physical consequences of Einstein s postulates can be quite straightforwardly derived from understanding Minkowski geometry Simultaneity. The first seemingly counterintuitive consequence is that there is no absolute notion of two events happening at the same time. This is closely tied to the fact that there is no absolute measure of time or elapsed time. To demonstrate, we consider two observers, A and B, in Minkowski spacetime. Suppose A is at rest with respect to some inertial coordinates (t, x, y, z), that is, the curve represented by A is precisely given by x = y = z = 0. Furthermore, suppose B is moving at a constant velocity away from A, as depicted in Figure 3. A : x=y=z=0 B : x=ȳ= z=0 t = c A 0 B 0 t = c Figure 3. Two observers A and B (figure centered about A). 11 Of course, there is a certain amount of cheating here. The significant achievement is Einstein s discovery of these physical consequences and, on the mathematical side, Minkowski s discovery of the rigorous geometric model for capturing these observations. However, it is still quite instructive to show just how these physical observations are naturally manifested in the mathematical theory.

9 A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY 9 Consider the event A 0 observer A at a given time. What observer A perceives as simultaneous to A 0 is the hypersurface t = t(a 0 ) := c, or, in coordinate-independent terms, the hypersurface normal to A at A 0 with respect to the Minkowski metric. In particular, in Figure 3, according to observer A, the event B 0 is occurring at the same time as A 0. Next, let us consider the perspective of observer B. For this, we examine new inertial coordinates ( t, x, ȳ, z), with respect to which B is at rest and A is moving at a constant nonzero velocity. At the event B 0, what B perceives as simultaneous is the hypersurface t = t(b 0 ) := c, i.e., the hypersurface normal to B at B 0, again with respect to Minkowski metric. Note that t = c intersects observer A at a different point than A 0. In summary, these two observers, moving at different velocities, see different events as occurring simultaneously. Figure 4 below displays the same information as Figure 3, but with respect to the inertial coordinates centered about observer B. A : x=y=z=0 B : x=ȳ= z=0 A 0 B 0 t = c t = c Figure 4. Two observers A and B (figure centered about B) Length Contraction. The next consequence, often referred to as Lorentz-Fitzgerald contraction, is the property that observers moving at different velocities will perceive the length of an object differently. Consider an observer A and a rod, which are at rest with respect to each other. Moreover, consider another observer B, which is moving at a constant velocity away from A and the rod. This basic setup is sketched in Figure 5. Observers A and B are represented as before, while the rod is represented by the gray shaded region. The length of the rod as measured by observer A is represented by the length of the bolded blue line segment (t = c) within the gray area. On the other hand, the length of the rod according to B is represented by the length of the bolded red line segment ( t = c) within the gray area. Now, Euclidean intuitions would suggest that the red line would be longer. However, recall that in Minkowski metric, the time direction has the opposite sign as opposed to the spatial

10 10 ARICK SHAO A : x=y=z=0 B : x=ȳ= z=0 t = c A 0 B 0 t = c Figure 5. Length contraction: two observers A and B and a rod. directions. As a result of this, the tilt in the dotted red line results in this red segment having a shorter length than the blue segment. Consequently, observer B s measurement of the rod will yield a shorter length than observer A s measurement. In summary, this principle of length contraction states that an observer in motion with respect to an object will perceive that object to have shorter length than an observer at rest with respect to the object Time Dilation. Another similar phenomenon is that of time dilation: two observers moving at different velocities will measure different time lapses between two events. To demonstrate, we consider the situation depicted in Figure 6. In this figure, we have two (inertial) observers A and B, both carrying clocks that are synchronized at the event O. First, A measures from its own clock the time elapsed between events O and A 0 on A. This is equal to the proper time elapsed for A, i.e., the Minkowski length of the bolded blue line segment in Figure 6 connecting O to A 0. Suppose that, at the same time, A also measures the time elapsed on B s clock. This is the time elapsed between O and the event B 0 on B occuring at the same time (according to A) as A 0. Note this is the proper time elapsed for B, that is, the g M -length of the bolded red segment between O and B 0. Again, Euclidean intuitions would have one believe that the red line segment would be longer than the blue. However, since both curves are timelike, and the red line picks up an extra spacelike component, which in the metric has the opposite sign, the actual effect is that the red line segment is shorter than the blue. Thus, A will measure less time elapsed on B s clock, which is in motion relative to A, than on its own clock, which is relatively at rest.

11 A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY 11 A : x=y=z=0 B : x =y =z =0 A 0 B 0 t = c O Figure 6. Time dilation: two observers A and B The Twin Paradox. One of the most widely discussed points of confusion when first studying special relativity is the twin paradox (though not so appropriately named, since there is in fact no paradox here). Mathematically speaking, this phenomenon is captured by the following rather unprovocative observation: two different timelike curves connecting two events can have different (Minkowski) lengths. 12 To explain more concretely, consider the scenario depicted in Figure 7. Suppose one person, A, stays in bed at home, while a second person, B, gets in a spaceship and blasts away on a long journey. Eventually, B gets tired of traveling and flies back on the spaceship to meet A, who is still in bed and has not yet bothered to move. When A and B meet, they will observe that A has aged more than B. A B Figure 7. Twin paradox: A at rest, while B flies off on a spaceship. Here, the time elapsed for A is given by its proper time, that is, the Minkowski length of the blue curve segment. Similarly, the time elapsed for B is the length of its red curve segment. When comparing the two lengths, the idea is similar to the preceding time dilation setting: the direction of B has an extra spacelike component compared to that of A. Since 12 The analogous principle also holds, of course, in Euclidean geometry.

12 12 ARICK SHAO both curves are timelike, this extra spacelike component yields the opposite sign and makes the length of the red segment for B smaller than that of the blue segment for A. So what exactly is the supposed paradox here? Consider now a different coordinate system ( t, x, ȳ, z), in which B is at rest and A now travels in an arc; see Figure 8. If we rerun the above argument, then it would seem that B, who is now at rest, should age slower than A! A B Figure 8. Twin paradox: coordinates adapted to B. The error hidden in the above argument is that B is not engaged in inertial (i.e., nonaccelerated) motion, so the ( t, x, ȳ, z)-coordinates fail to be inertial, that is, g M d t 2 + d x 2 + dȳ 2 + d z 2. In other words, the map from the original coordinates to the barred coordinates fails to preserve g M. Thus, the preceding (correct) argument fails to hold in the setting of Figure 8, where the roles of A and B are interchanged. References 1. Nobelprize.org: History of special relativity, 2. Nobelprize.org: The postulates of special relativity, 3. B. O Neill, Semi-Riemannian geometry with applications to relativity, Academic Press, R. Wald, General relativity, The University of Chicago Press, Wikipedia: History of special relativity,

A Brief Introduction to Mathematical Relativity

A Brief Introduction to Mathematical Relativity A Brief Introduction to Mathematical Relativity Arick Shao Imperial College London Arick Shao (Imperial College London) Mathematical Relativity 1 / 31 Special Relativity Postulates and Definitions Einstein

More information

CHAPTER 2 Special Theory of Relativity-part 1

CHAPTER 2 Special Theory of Relativity-part 1 CHAPTER 2 Special Theory of Relativity-part 1 2.1 The Apparent Need for Ether 2.2 The Michelson-Morley Experiment 2.3 Einstein s Postulates 2.4 The Lorentz Transformation 2.5 Time Dilation and Length Contraction

More information

The spacetime of special relativity

The spacetime of special relativity 1 The spacetime of special relativity We begin our discussion of the relativistic theory of gravity by reviewing some basic notions underlying the Newtonian and special-relativistic viewpoints of space

More information

Minkowski spacetime. Pham A. Quang. Abstract: In this talk we review the Minkowski spacetime which is the spacetime of Special Relativity.

Minkowski spacetime. Pham A. Quang. Abstract: In this talk we review the Minkowski spacetime which is the spacetime of Special Relativity. Minkowski spacetime Pham A. Quang Abstract: In this talk we review the Minkowski spacetime which is the spacetime of Special Relativity. Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Minkowski spacetime 2 3 Lorentz transformations

More information

Consequences of special relativity.

Consequences of special relativity. PHYS419 Lecture 12 Consequences of special relativity 1 Consequences of special relativity. The length of moving objects. Recall that in special relativity, simultaneity depends on the frame of reference

More information

Tech Notes 4 and 5. Let s prove that invariance of the spacetime interval the hard way. Suppose we begin with the equation

Tech Notes 4 and 5. Let s prove that invariance of the spacetime interval the hard way. Suppose we begin with the equation Tech Notes 4 and 5 Tech Notes 4 and 5 Let s prove that invariance of the spacetime interval the hard way. Suppose we begin with the equation (ds) 2 = (dt) 2 (dx) 2. We recall that the coordinate transformations

More information

Consequences of special relativity.

Consequences of special relativity. PHYS419 Lecture 12 Consequences of special relativity 1 Consequences of special relativity. The length of moving objects. Recall that in special relativity, simultaneity depends on the frame of reference

More information

Spacetime and 4 vectors

Spacetime and 4 vectors Spacetime and 4 vectors 1 Minkowski space = 4 dimensional spacetime Euclidean 4 space Each point in Minkowski space is an event. In SR, Minkowski space is an absolute structure (like space in Newtonian

More information

Hyperbolic Geometry of 2+1 Spacetime: Static Hypertext Version

Hyperbolic Geometry of 2+1 Spacetime: Static Hypertext Version Page 1 of 9 Hyperbolic Geometry of 2+1 Spacetime: Static Hypertext Version In order to develop the physical interpretation of the conic construction that we made on the previous page, we will now replace

More information

Accelerated Observers

Accelerated Observers Accelerated Observers In the last few lectures, we ve been discussing the implications that the postulates of special relativity have on the physics of our universe. We ve seen how to compute proper times

More information

Changing coordinates - the Lorentz transformation

Changing coordinates - the Lorentz transformation Changing coordinates - the Lorentz transformation In figure 5, we have two observers, A and B, and the two photons passing through the event E are shown. Each observer assigns coordinates to the event

More information

Introduction. Classical vs Modern Physics. Classical Physics: High speeds Small (or very large) distances

Introduction. Classical vs Modern Physics. Classical Physics: High speeds Small (or very large) distances Introduction Classical vs Modern Physics High speeds Small (or very large) distances Classical Physics: Conservation laws: energy, momentum (linear & angular), charge Mechanics Newton s laws Electromagnetism

More information

Lecture: Lorentz Invariant Dynamics

Lecture: Lorentz Invariant Dynamics Chapter 5 Lecture: Lorentz Invariant Dynamics In the preceding chapter we introduced the Minkowski metric and covariance with respect to Lorentz transformations between inertial systems. This was shown

More information

Kinematics of special relativity

Kinematics of special relativity Chapter 2 Kinematics of special relativity 2.1 Special Relativity 2.1.1 Principles of Relativity Einstein postulated that there was still Galilean invariance, i. e. all uniformly moving observers had the

More information

The Lorentz Transformation

The Lorentz Transformation The Lorentz Transformation During the fourth week of the course, we spent some time discussing how the coordinates of two different reference frames were related to each other. Now that we know about the

More information

EPGY Special and General Relativity. Lecture 4B

EPGY Special and General Relativity. Lecture 4B Lecture 4B In the previous lecture we found that the proper description of the universe is one consisting of a four-dimensional manifold (space) endowed with a Lorentzian metric, (of course we are restricting

More information

Modern Physics. Third Edition RAYMOND A. SERWAY CLEMENT J. MOSES CURT A. MOYER

Modern Physics. Third Edition RAYMOND A. SERWAY CLEMENT J. MOSES CURT A. MOYER Modern Physics Third Edition RAYMOND A. SERWAY CLEMENT J. MOSES CURT A. MOYER 1 RELATIVITY 1.1 Special Relativity 1.2 The Principle of Relativity, The Speed of Light 1.3 The Michelson Morley Experiment,

More information

4-Vector Notation. Chris Clark September 5, 2006

4-Vector Notation. Chris Clark September 5, 2006 4-Vector Notation Chris Clark September 5, 2006 1 Lorentz Transformations We will assume that the reader is familiar with the Lorentz Transformations for a boost in the x direction x = γ(x vt) ȳ = y x

More information

Black Holes and Thermodynamics I: Classical Black Holes

Black Holes and Thermodynamics I: Classical Black Holes Black Holes and Thermodynamics I: Classical Black Holes Robert M. Wald General references: R.M. Wald General Relativity University of Chicago Press (Chicago, 1984); R.M. Wald Living Rev. Rel. 4, 6 (2001).

More information

2.1 The Ether and the Michelson-Morley Experiment

2.1 The Ether and the Michelson-Morley Experiment Chapter. Special Relativity Notes: Some material presented in this chapter is taken The Feynman Lectures on Physics, Vol. I by R. P. Feynman, R. B. Leighton, and M. Sands, Chap. 15 (1963, Addison-Wesley)..1

More information

Chapter 11. Special Relativity

Chapter 11. Special Relativity Chapter 11 Special Relativity Note: Please also consult the fifth) problem list associated with this chapter In this chapter, Latin indices are used for space coordinates only eg, i = 1,2,3, etc), while

More information

The Foundations of Special Relativity

The Foundations of Special Relativity The Foundations of Special Relativity 1 Einstein's postulates of SR: 1. The laws of physics are identical in all inertial reference frames (IFs). 2. The speed of light in vacuum, c, is the same in all

More information

2.1 Einstein s postulates of Special Relativity. (i) There is no ether (there is no absolute system of reference).

2.1 Einstein s postulates of Special Relativity. (i) There is no ether (there is no absolute system of reference). Chapter 2 Special Relativity The contradiction brought about by the development of Electromagnetism gave rise to a crisis in the 19th century that Special Relativity resolved. 2.1 Einstein s postulates

More information

Our Current Concept of Locality may be Incomplete

Our Current Concept of Locality may be Incomplete Our Current Concept of Locality may be Incomplete Armin Nikkhah Shirazi 1 June 13, 2013 Department of physics University of Michigan, Ann Arbor 1 armin@umich.edu Armin Nikkhah Shirazi Our Current Concept

More information

8.20 MIT Introduction to Special Relativity IAP 2005 Tentative Outline

8.20 MIT Introduction to Special Relativity IAP 2005 Tentative Outline 8.20 MIT Introduction to Special Relativity IAP 2005 Tentative Outline 1 Main Headings I Introduction and relativity pre Einstein II Einstein s principle of relativity and a new concept of spacetime III

More information

Einstein for Everyone Lecture 4: Paradoxes; Minkowski Spacetime

Einstein for Everyone Lecture 4: Paradoxes; Minkowski Spacetime Einstein for Everyone Lecture 4: Paradoxes; Minkowski Spacetime Dr. Erik Curiel Munich Center For Mathematical Philosophy Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität 1 Velocity Addition 2 Paradoxes 3 Spacetime and

More information

Einstein Toolkit Workshop. Joshua Faber Apr

Einstein Toolkit Workshop. Joshua Faber Apr Einstein Toolkit Workshop Joshua Faber Apr 05 2012 Outline Space, time, and special relativity The metric tensor and geometry Curvature Geodesics Einstein s equations The Stress-energy tensor 3+1 formalisms

More information

Simultaneity, Time Dilation, and Length Contraction Using Minkowski Diagrams and Lorentz Transformations

Simultaneity, Time Dilation, and Length Contraction Using Minkowski Diagrams and Lorentz Transformations Simultaneity, Time Dilation, and Length Contraction Using Minkowski Diagrams and Lorentz Transformations Dr. Russell L. Herman January 25, 2008 (modified: January 17, 2018) Abstract In these notes we present

More information

Correct Resolution of the Twin Paradox

Correct Resolution of the Twin Paradox Correct Resolution of the Twin Paradox Michael Huemer In the following, I explain the Twin Paradox, which is supposed to be a paradoxical consequence of the Special Theory of Relativity (STR). I give the

More information

Superluminal motion in the quasar 3C273

Superluminal motion in the quasar 3C273 1 Superluminal motion in the quasar 3C273 The cowboys have a way of trussing up a steer or a pugnacious bronco which fixes the brute so that it can neither move nor think. This is the hog-tie, and it is

More information

A. B. Lahanas University of Athens, Physics Department, Nuclear and Particle Physics Section, Athens , Greece

A. B. Lahanas University of Athens, Physics Department, Nuclear and Particle Physics Section, Athens , Greece SPECIAL RELATIVITY A. B. Lahanas University of Athens, Physics Department, Nuclear and Particle Physics Section, Athens 157 71, Greece Abstract We give an introduction to Einstein s Special Theory of Relativity.

More information

On the Arbitrary Choice Regarding Which Inertial Reference Frame is "Stationary" and Which is "Moving" in the Special Theory of Relativity

On the Arbitrary Choice Regarding Which Inertial Reference Frame is Stationary and Which is Moving in the Special Theory of Relativity Regarding Which Inertial Reference Frame is "Stationary" and Which is "Moving" in the Special Theory of Relativity Douglas M. Snyder Los Angeles, CA The relativity of simultaneity is central to the special

More information

Relativistic Mechanics

Relativistic Mechanics Physics 411 Lecture 9 Relativistic Mechanics Lecture 9 Physics 411 Classical Mechanics II September 17th, 2007 We have developed some tensor language to describe familiar physics we reviewed orbital motion

More information

1 Euclidean geometry. 1.1 The metric on R n

1 Euclidean geometry. 1.1 The metric on R n 1 Euclidean geometry This chapter discusses the geometry of n-dimensional Euclidean space E n, together with its distance function. The distance gives rise to other notions such as angles and congruent

More information

Notes on Minkowski space-time

Notes on Minkowski space-time Notes on Minkowski space-time Following Hermann Minkowski, the arena for special relativity is Minkowski space-time. The squared interval S between points X = (t, x, y, z) and X = (t, x, y, z ) is: S =

More information

Communicating with accelerated observers in Minkowski spacetime

Communicating with accelerated observers in Minkowski spacetime IOP PUBLISHING Eur. J. Phys. 29 (2008) 73 84 EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHYSICS doi:10.1088/0143-0807/29/1/007 Communicating with accelerated observers in Minkowski spacetime F J Flores Philosophy Department,

More information

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime The Philosophy of Physics Lecture Five Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York Special Relativity a quick refresher Special Relativity and Minkowski

More information

2.6 Invariance of the Interval

2.6 Invariance of the Interval 2.6 Invariance of the Interval Note. In this section, we define a quantity called the interval between two events which is invariant under a change of spacetime coordinates from one inertial frame to another

More information

A brief introduction to Semi-Riemannian geometry and general relativity. Hans Ringström

A brief introduction to Semi-Riemannian geometry and general relativity. Hans Ringström A brief introduction to Semi-Riemannian geometry and general relativity Hans Ringström May 5, 2015 2 Contents 1 Scalar product spaces 1 1.1 Scalar products...................................... 1 1.2 Orthonormal

More information

Gravitation: Special Relativity

Gravitation: Special Relativity An Introduction to General Relativity Center for Relativistic Astrophysics School of Physics Georgia Institute of Technology Notes based on textbook: Spacetime and Geometry by S.M. Carroll Spring 2013

More information

The Lorentz Transformations

The Lorentz Transformations The Lorentz Transformations Michael Fowler, UVa Physics. /6/08 Problems with the Galilean Transformations We have already seen that Newtonian mechanics is invariant under the Galilean transformations relating

More information

2 General Relativity. 2.1 Curved 2D and 3D space

2 General Relativity. 2.1 Curved 2D and 3D space 22 2 General Relativity The general theory of relativity (Einstein 1915) is the theory of gravity. General relativity ( Einstein s theory ) replaced the previous theory of gravity, Newton s theory. The

More information

Readings for Unit I from Ryan (Topics from linear algebra)

Readings for Unit I from Ryan (Topics from linear algebra) Readings for Unit I from Ryan (Topics from linear algebra) I.0 : Background Suggested readings. Ryan : pp. 193 202 General convention. In most cases, the background readings for a section of the course

More information

Initial-Value Problems in General Relativity

Initial-Value Problems in General Relativity Initial-Value Problems in General Relativity Michael Horbatsch March 30, 2006 1 Introduction In this paper the initial-value formulation of general relativity is reviewed. In section (2) domains of dependence,

More information

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006 Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University pbokulic@bu.edu Draft: 3 Feb. 2006 Key Points: 1. Petkov assumes that the standard relativistic interpretations of measurement

More information

Lorentz Transformation & the Meaning of Einstein s 1905 Special Theory of Relativity

Lorentz Transformation & the Meaning of Einstein s 1905 Special Theory of Relativity Lorentz Transformation & the Meaning of Einstein s 1905 Special Theory of Relativity 334 Article Alexandru C. V. Ceapa * ABSTRACT When the Lorentz transformation as a complementary time-dependent coordinate

More information

Physics. Special Relativity

Physics. Special Relativity Physics Special Relativity 1 Albert Einstein, the high school dropout and patent office clerk published his ideas on Special Relativity in 1905. 2 Special vs. General Relativity Special Relativity deals

More information

Lecture 5. The Lorentz Transformation

Lecture 5. The Lorentz Transformation Lecture 5 The Lorentz Transformation We have learned so far about how rates of time vary in different IRFs in motion with respect to each other and also how lengths appear shorter when in motion. What

More information

Special and General Relativity based on the Physical Meaning of the Spacetime Interval

Special and General Relativity based on the Physical Meaning of the Spacetime Interval Special and General Relativity based on the Physical Meaning of the Spacetime Interval Alan Macdonald Department of Mathematics Luther College macdonal@luther.edu http://faculty.luther.edu/ macdonal Abstract

More information

04. Kinematical Effects 1. Time Dilation

04. Kinematical Effects 1. Time Dilation 04. Kinematical Effects 1. Time Dilation B D y' S' P x' Consider a "light clock" that defines a reference frame S'. One "tick" of this clock = time for light to travel PBP = t = 2D c. y y' S' x' S-clock

More information

We begin our discussion of special relativity with a power point presentation, available on the website.

We begin our discussion of special relativity with a power point presentation, available on the website. Special Relativity We begin our discussion of special relativity with a power point presentation, available on the website.. Spacetime From the power point presentation, you know that spacetime is a four

More information

Inconsistencies in Special Relativity? Sagnac Effect and Twin Paradox

Inconsistencies in Special Relativity? Sagnac Effect and Twin Paradox Inconsistencies in Special Relativity? Sagnac Effect and Twin Paradox Olaf Wucknitz Astrophysics Seminar Potsdam University, Germany 7 July 2003 And now for something completely different... Special relativity

More information

Special Relativity 1

Special Relativity 1 Special Relativity 1 Special Relativity: A Summary Caitlyn Edwards Dr. Gan Modern Physics November 2017 Special Relativity 2 Abstract The physics of Einstein s theory of special relativity differs dramatically

More information

Covariant Formulation of Electrodynamics

Covariant Formulation of Electrodynamics Chapter 7. Covariant Formulation of Electrodynamics Notes: Most of the material presented in this chapter is taken from Jackson, Chap. 11, and Rybicki and Lightman, Chap. 4. Starting with this chapter,

More information

Absolute motion versus relative motion in Special Relativity is not dealt with properly

Absolute motion versus relative motion in Special Relativity is not dealt with properly Absolute motion versus relative motion in Special Relativity is not dealt with properly Roger J Anderton R.J.Anderton@btinternet.com A great deal has been written about the twin paradox. In this article

More information

Chapter 12. Electrodynamics and Relativity. Does the principle of relativity apply to the laws of electrodynamics?

Chapter 12. Electrodynamics and Relativity. Does the principle of relativity apply to the laws of electrodynamics? Chapter 12. Electrodynamics and Relativity Does the principle of relativity apply to the laws of electrodynamics? 12.1 The Special Theory of Relativity Does the principle of relativity apply to the laws

More information

Newtonian Mechanics. Chapter Classical space-time

Newtonian Mechanics. Chapter Classical space-time Chapter 1 Newtonian Mechanics In these notes classical mechanics will be viewed as a mathematical model for the description of physical systems consisting of a certain (generally finite) number of particles

More information

Special Relativity: Derivations

Special Relativity: Derivations Special Relativity: Derivations Exploring formulae in special relativity Introduction: Michelson-Morley experiment In the 19 th century, physicists thought that since sound waves travel through air, light

More information

Rotational Mechanics and Relativity --- Summary sheet 1

Rotational Mechanics and Relativity --- Summary sheet 1 Rotational Mechanics and Relativity --- Summary sheet 1 Centre of Mass 1 1 For discrete masses: R m r For continuous bodies: R dm i i M M r body i Static equilibrium: the two conditions for a body in static

More information

The Special Theory of relativity

The Special Theory of relativity Chapter 1 The Special Theory of relativity 1.1 Pre - relativistic physics The starting point for our work are Newtons laws of motion. These can be stated as follows: Free particles move with constant velocity.

More information

Lecture 13 Notes: 07 / 20. Invariance of the speed of light

Lecture 13 Notes: 07 / 20. Invariance of the speed of light Lecture 13 Notes: 07 / 20 Invariance of the speed of light The Michelson-Morley experiment, among other experiments, showed that the speed of light in vacuum is a universal constant, as predicted by Maxwell's

More information

Minkowski space - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Minkowski space - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia 1 of 7 27/03/2013 12:38 Minkowski space From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In mathematical physics, Minkowski space or Minkowski spacetime (named after the mathematician Hermann Minkowski) is the mathematical

More information

Class 1: Special Relativity

Class 1: Special Relativity Class 1: Special Relativity In this class we will review some important concepts in Special Relativity, that will help us build up to the General theory Class 1: Special Relativity At the end of this session

More information

Relativity, Dimensionality, and Existence

Relativity, Dimensionality, and Existence Chapter 7 Relativity, Dimensionality, and Existence Vesselin Petkov Since the [relativity] postulate comes to mean that only the four-dimensional world in space and time is given by phenomena, but that

More information

Curved Spacetime... A brief introduction

Curved Spacetime... A brief introduction Curved Spacetime... A brief introduction May 5, 2009 Inertial Frames and Gravity In establishing GR, Einstein was influenced by Ernst Mach. Mach s ideas about the absolute space and time: Space is simply

More information

4 Relativistic kinematics

4 Relativistic kinematics 4 Relativistic kinematics In astrophysics, we are often dealing with relativistic particles that are being accelerated by electric or magnetic forces. This produces radiation, typically in the form of

More information

Special Theory of Relativity (I) Newtonian (Classical) Relativity. Newtonian Principle of Relativity. Inertial Reference Frame.

Special Theory of Relativity (I) Newtonian (Classical) Relativity. Newtonian Principle of Relativity. Inertial Reference Frame. Special Theory of Relativity (I) Newtonian (Classical) Relativity Einstein s Postulates The Lorentz Transformation Time Dilation and Length Contraction Addition of Velocities Assumption It is assumed that

More information

Chapter 26 Special Theory of Relativity

Chapter 26 Special Theory of Relativity Chapter 26 Special Theory of Relativity Classical Physics: At the end of the 19 th century, classical physics was well established. It seems that the natural world was very well explained. Newtonian mechanics

More information

Spacetime Diagrams and Einstein s Theory For Dummies

Spacetime Diagrams and Einstein s Theory For Dummies 1 Spacetime Diagrams and Einstein s Theory For Dummies A Set of Five Lesson Plans for School Teachers Dr. Muhammad Ali Yousuf Assistant Program Manager CTY Summer Programs And Physics and Mathematics Instructor

More information

arxiv:gr-qc/ v1 6 Jul 2004

arxiv:gr-qc/ v1 6 Jul 2004 Spacetime and Euclidean Geometry 1 Dieter Brill and Ted Jacobson, University of Maryland, College Park, MD 20742-4111 Institut d Astrophysique de Paris, 98bis bvd. Arago, 75014 Paris, France arxiv:gr-qc/0407022v1

More information

Relativity. An explanation of Brownian motion in terms of atoms. An explanation of the photoelectric effect ==> Quantum Theory

Relativity. An explanation of Brownian motion in terms of atoms. An explanation of the photoelectric effect ==> Quantum Theory Relativity Relativity In 1905 Albert Einstein published five articles in Annalen Der Physik that had a major effect upon our understanding of physics. They included:- An explanation of Brownian motion

More information

Chapter S3 Spacetime and Gravity. Agenda. Distinguishing Crackpots

Chapter S3 Spacetime and Gravity. Agenda. Distinguishing Crackpots Chapter S3 Spacetime and Gravity Agenda Announce: Online Quizzes Observations Extra Credit Lecture Distinguishing Crackpot/Genuine Science Review of Special Relativity General Relativity Distinguishing

More information

Spacetime Trigonometry: a Cayley-Klein Geomety approach to Special and General Relativity

Spacetime Trigonometry: a Cayley-Klein Geomety approach to Special and General Relativity Spacetime Trigonometry: a Cayley-Klein Geomety approach to Special and General Relativity Rob Salgado UW-La Crosse Dept. of Physics outline motivations the Cayley-Klein Geometries (various starting points)

More information

In defence of classical physics

In defence of classical physics In defence of classical physics Abstract Classical physics seeks to find the laws of nature. I am of the opinion that classical Newtonian physics is real physics. This is in the sense that it relates to

More information

,, rectilinear,, spherical,, cylindrical. (6.1)

,, rectilinear,, spherical,, cylindrical. (6.1) Lecture 6 Review of Vectors Physics in more than one dimension (See Chapter 3 in Boas, but we try to take a more general approach and in a slightly different order) Recall that in the previous two lectures

More information

Relativity SPECIAL, GENERAL, AND COSMOLOGICAL SECOND EDITION. Wolfgang Rindler. Professor of Physics The University of Texas at Dallas

Relativity SPECIAL, GENERAL, AND COSMOLOGICAL SECOND EDITION. Wolfgang Rindler. Professor of Physics The University of Texas at Dallas Relativity SPECIAL, GENERAL, AND COSMOLOGICAL SECOND EDITION Wolfgang Rindler Professor of Physics The University of Texas at Dallas OXPORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Contents Introduction l 1 From absolute space

More information

The Twin Paradox in Static Spacetimes and Jacobi Fields

The Twin Paradox in Static Spacetimes and Jacobi Fields The Twin Paradox in Static Spacetimes and Jacobi Fields Leszek M. Sokołowski Abstract The twin paradox of special relativity formulated in the geometrical setting of general relativity gives rise to the

More information

Syllabus. May 3, Special relativity 1. 2 Differential geometry 3

Syllabus. May 3, Special relativity 1. 2 Differential geometry 3 Syllabus May 3, 2017 Contents 1 Special relativity 1 2 Differential geometry 3 3 General Relativity 13 3.1 Physical Principles.......................................... 13 3.2 Einstein s Equation..........................................

More information

Relativistic simultaneity and causality

Relativistic simultaneity and causality Relativistic simultaneity and causality V. J. Bolós 1,, V. Liern 2, J. Olivert 3 1 Dpto. Matemática Aplicada, Facultad de Matemáticas, Universidad de Valencia. C/ Dr. Moliner 50. 46100, Burjassot Valencia),

More information

1 Tensors and relativity

1 Tensors and relativity Physics 705 1 Tensors and relativity 1.1 History Physical laws should not depend on the reference frame used to describe them. This idea dates back to Galileo, who recognized projectile motion as free

More information

Minkowski spacetime. Chapter Events. 2.2 Reference frames

Minkowski spacetime. Chapter Events. 2.2 Reference frames Chapter 2 Minkowski spacetime 2.1 Events An event is some occurrence which takes place at some instant in time at some particular point in space. Your birth was an event. JFK s assassination was an event.

More information

Chapter 37. PowerPoint Lectures for University Physics, Twelfth Edition Hugh D. Young and Roger A. Freedman. Lectures by James Pazun

Chapter 37. PowerPoint Lectures for University Physics, Twelfth Edition Hugh D. Young and Roger A. Freedman. Lectures by James Pazun Chapter 37 Relativity PowerPoint Lectures for University Physics, Twelfth Edition Hugh D. Young and Roger A. Freedman Lectures by James Pazun 37. Relativity 1. Maxwell s equations (and especially the wave

More information

Review Special Relativity. February 3, Absolutes of Relativity. Key Ideas of Special Relativity. Path of Ball in a Moving Train

Review Special Relativity. February 3, Absolutes of Relativity. Key Ideas of Special Relativity. Path of Ball in a Moving Train February 3, 2009 Review Special Relativity General Relativity Key Ideas of Special Relativity No material object can travel faster than light If you observe something moving near light speed: Its time

More information

Fundamental equations of relativistic fluid dynamics

Fundamental equations of relativistic fluid dynamics CHAPTER VII Fundamental equations of relativistic fluid dynamics Under a number of extreme conditions for instance inside compact astrophysical objects, in the early Universe, or in high-energy collisions

More information

Cambridge University Press The Mathematics of Signal Processing Steven B. Damelin and Willard Miller Excerpt More information

Cambridge University Press The Mathematics of Signal Processing Steven B. Damelin and Willard Miller Excerpt More information Introduction Consider a linear system y = Φx where Φ can be taken as an m n matrix acting on Euclidean space or more generally, a linear operator on a Hilbert space. We call the vector x a signal or input,

More information

4.7 The Levi-Civita connection and parallel transport

4.7 The Levi-Civita connection and parallel transport Classnotes: Geometry & Control of Dynamical Systems, M. Kawski. April 21, 2009 138 4.7 The Levi-Civita connection and parallel transport In the earlier investigation, characterizing the shortest curves

More information

Fundamental equations of relativistic fluid dynamics

Fundamental equations of relativistic fluid dynamics CHAPTER VI Fundamental equations of relativistic fluid dynamics When the energy density becomes large as may happen for instance in compact astrophysical objects, in the early Universe, or in high-energy

More information

Relativity, Dimensionality, and Existence

Relativity, Dimensionality, and Existence Relativity, Dimensionality, and Existence Vesselin Petkov Science College, Concordia University 1455 de Maisonneuve Boulevard West Montreal, Quebec, Canada H3G 1M8 vpetkov@alcor.concordia.ca Since the

More information

Lecture I: Vectors, tensors, and forms in flat spacetime

Lecture I: Vectors, tensors, and forms in flat spacetime Lecture I: Vectors, tensors, and forms in flat spacetime Christopher M. Hirata Caltech M/C 350-17, Pasadena CA 91125, USA (Dated: September 28, 2011) I. OVERVIEW The mathematical description of curved

More information

Lorentz covariance and special relativity

Lorentz covariance and special relativity Chapter 4 Lorentz covariance and special relativity To go beyond Newtonian gravitation we must consider, with Einstein, the intimate relationship between the curvature of space and the gravitational field.

More information

An introduction to General Relativity and the positive mass theorem

An introduction to General Relativity and the positive mass theorem An introduction to General Relativity and the positive mass theorem National Center for Theoretical Sciences, Mathematics Division March 2 nd, 2007 Wen-ling Huang Department of Mathematics University of

More information

Basics of Special Relativity

Basics of Special Relativity Basics of Special Relativity You must understand special relativity in order to really understand general relativity. Here s a brief summary of the basic ideas and terminology of special relativity (there

More information

The Lorentz Transformation from Light-Speed Invariance Alone

The Lorentz Transformation from Light-Speed Invariance Alone The Lorentz Transformation from Light-Speed Invariance Alone Steven Kenneth Kauffmann Abstract The derivation of the Lorentz transformation normally rests on two a priori demands namely that reversing

More information

Articles. A Paradox of Two Space Ships in Special Relativity

Articles. A Paradox of Two Space Ships in Special Relativity AAPPS Bulletin February 2004 3 Articles A Paradox of Two Space Ships in Special Relativity Takuya Matsuda and Atsuya Kinoshita A paradox in special relativity is proposed and discussed. Two spaceships

More information

Postulates of Special Relativity

Postulates of Special Relativity Relativity Relativity - Seen as an intricate theory that is necessary when dealing with really high speeds - Two charged initially stationary particles: Electrostatic force - In another, moving reference

More information

GEOMETRY OF THE KERR BLACK HOLES

GEOMETRY OF THE KERR BLACK HOLES GEOMETRY OF THE KERR BLACK HOLES ANH HOANG TRONG NAM Abstract. In this paper, we will explore the geometry of the Kerr spacetime, a solution to the Einstein Equation in general relativity. We will first

More information

Lecture Notes on Relativity. Last updated 10/1/02 Pages 1 65 Lectures 1 10

Lecture Notes on Relativity. Last updated 10/1/02 Pages 1 65 Lectures 1 10 Lecture Notes on Relativity Last updated 10/1/02 Pages 1 65 Lectures 1 10 Special Relativity: Introduction Describes physics of fast motion i.e. when objects move relative to each other at very high speeds,

More information

Announcement. Einstein s Postulates of Relativity: PHYS-3301 Lecture 3. Chapter 2. Sep. 5, Special Relativity

Announcement. Einstein s Postulates of Relativity: PHYS-3301 Lecture 3. Chapter 2. Sep. 5, Special Relativity Announcement PHYS-3301 Lecture 3 Sep. 5, 2017 2 Einstein s Postulates of Relativity: Chapter 2 Special Relativity 1. Basic Ideas 6. Velocity Transformation 2. Consequences of Einstein s Postulates 7. Momentum

More information

Speed limits in general relativity

Speed limits in general relativity Class. Quantum Grav. 16 (1999) 543 549. Printed in the UK PII: S0264-9381(99)97448-8 Speed limits in general relativity Robert J Low Mathematics Division, School of Mathematical and Information Sciences,

More information

Knot Physics: Entanglement and Locality. Abstract

Knot Physics: Entanglement and Locality. Abstract Knot Physics: Entanglement and Locality C. Ellgen (Dated: July 18, 2016) Abstract We describe entanglement and locality in knot physics. In knot physics, spacetime is a branched manifold. The quantum information

More information