Why the Ultimatum Game may not be the Ultimate Experiment?

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Why the Ultimatum Game may not be the Ultimate Experiment?"

Transcription

1 Why the Ultimatum Game may not be the Ultimate Experiment? Yoram Halevy Michael Peters y July 11, 2006 Abstract The Ultimatum Game seems to be the ideal experiment to test for the structure of preferences or the sequential rationality assumptions underlying subgame perfection. We study the theoretical implications of introducing the possibility of misconceptions - that actions may potentially a ect continuation payo s - and show that the set of Perfect Bayesian Nash Equilibria does not converge to the subgame perfect equilibrium when the possibility of misconception approaches zero. The perfect equilibria studied corresponds qualitatively to the experimental ndings of fair o ers made and unfair o ers rejected. 1 Introduction and Discussion One of the appealing and important properties of experimental economics stems from its ability to test the predictions of economic theory: as more information is collected in experiments (both laboratory and eld), economists are able to sort theories to those that are consistent with the data and those that can be refuted by it. A prominent example of this methodology has been the test of the assumption that decision makers have sel sh preferences. Many bargaining experiments have shown that in certain environments the equilibrium predictions of economic theory which are based on backwards induction and sel sh preferences are not consistent with the University of British Columbia y University of British Columbia 1

2 experimental results (see Roth [14] for an extensive review). This has been demonstrated most clearly in one of the simplest and most in uential experiments: the ultimatum game. A proposer makes an o er of x (between 0 and x). If the responder accepts the o er then the proposer receives (x x) while the responder receives x: If the responder rejects - both receive zero. This is the simplest dynamic game of complete and perfect information, for which the backwards induction argument is exactly devised. The latter (together with sel sh preferences) predicts that the responder should accept any positive o er and therefore the proposer should o er only a minimal o er. As is now well known (since Güth et al [10]), the experimental evidence refute these predictions: low o ers are rejected, and the modal o er involves equal split. Di erent researchers have drawn di erent conclusions from this experiment. One group of researchers have assumed that although the backwards induction argument is valid, the agents have other regarding preferences. They care about their relative payo (Bolton [5], Rabin [13], Levine [11], Fehr and Schmidt [7], Bolton-Ockenfels [6] and many others). Another group (Binmore, Samuelson and others [9, 3, 2, 4]) have been arguing that excessive attention has been given to the backwards induction arguments. They claim that since the set of Nash equilibria is much larger, one should try and describe the outcome of the game in terms of another process that leads to NE, but not necessarily to SPE - like an evolutionary model. The goal of the current study is to study how robust is the backwards induction outcome in the ultimatum game to perturbations - representing possible misconceptions of participants concerning the game structure. The conclusions drawn from this study may be viewed in two di ering levels of insight. First, it points out (what is almost obvious in a hindsight) that the equilibrium predictions of game theory are based not only on assumptions about the preferences, but also on common knowledge of the game structure. But we show much more than that: even when the game structure subjects have in mind is in nitesimally close to the structure the experimenter intended to induce in the experiment, but allows for the possibility that the other party holds di erent information, or does not understand the experiment (the mapping from actions to payo s) in the way the experimenter intended, the theoretical equilibrium behavior may be very di erent from the equilibrium outcome in the game the experimenter had in mind and corresponds much better to the experimental results. Why is it natural and important to study the implications of misconcep- 2

3 tions in experimental games? We argue that participants arrive at the experiment with very poor information about the payo s associated with actions they take during the experiment, and if and how these actions will a ect their future payo s (e.g. subsequent experiment). Any experimenter knows that explaining the game to subjects could be the most challenging part of the experiment. In the ultimatum game - this task is extremely di cult: subjects may nd the environment super cially similar to bargaining environment from their day to day life. Indeed, Aumann [1] argues that the rule of rejecting low o ers is a case of rule rationality : a decision making process that rewards a behavior that utilizes a rule which works well in the repeated environmentthe subjects encounter in every day life. When applying the decision rule to the one-shot environment, the behavior may be hard to rationalize. 1 The resemblance between the ultimatum game and naturally occurring repeated bargaining environment suggests that the natural focus should be that continuation payo s might depend on the actions subjects take during the experiment. A perfectly designed experiment should dispel any uncertainty about these, and leave the participants convinced that though their continuation payo s may be uncertain, they are independent of any action they take during the experiment. This is presumably accomplished by the messages the experimenter sends to the subjects when the rules and outcomes are described, the way the experiment is described when participants are solicited, the reputation of the experimenter and so on. When one allows for the possibility of misconceptions, it is easy to explain why a proposer won t demand everything in the ultimatum game: he is afraid his proposal will be rejected. It is harder to explain why the responder rejects a positive o er. The simple intuition is that she believes her continuation payo s are higher when she rejects o ers. 2 However, consideration of exactly why she rejects the o er leads to the positive conclusions about the ultimatum game. If the experiment is very well designed, but not perfect, participants will still assign positive, though small, probability to the possibility that continuation payo s are a ected by behavior in the experi- 1 One path some researchers have chosen in order to minimize misconceptions, is to allow subjects to gain experience in previous rounds. However, In light of the above view of the problematic nature of the experiment, this might not be the optimal way to pursue since it reinforces a perception that the game may be repeated. 2 There is never any uncertainty here about the fact that her payo s during the (stage) experiment are lower if she rejects the o er. 3

4 ment. Both participants will have some information about this that depends on their conversations with the experimenter, maybe previous experimental experience, etc. The structure of the ultimatum game is such that there will always be equilibria in which the actions of both players depend on this information. In a well designed experiment, the proposer should think it very unlikely that the responder has any information that would lead her to believe that she would be better o rejecting. Even so, he may think it very likely that they are playing an equilibrium in which certain proposals will be perceived to convey high informational content. If a responder thinks it is very unlikely that a proposer with normal information would demand a high share of the pie, then it might make perfect sense after appropriate prior revision, for the responder to reject low o ers. This logic can be carried to the limit of a perfectly designed experiment. In such case the subjects can imagine the possibility that their continuation payo s depend in some ways on their actions in the experiment., but they assign zero probability to this possibility. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium then admits the following equilibrium: the proposer in the ultimatum game demands half of the pie, and the responder accepts it. Since this outcome is supposed to occir with probability 1, anything else that happens is now o the equilibrium path. So any deviation by the proposer is rejected because the responder revises her beliefs in a way that assigns high probability to continuation payo s being much higher when an o er (any o er) is rejected than when it is accepted. Sequential rationality is consistent with just about any o er, even in a perfectly designed experiment. The theoretical contribution in this paper, is simply to analyze these equilibria. All these equilibria involve various proposals being accepted and rejected with positive probability on the equilibrium path. As uncertainty about the continuation payo s shrinks, the set of equilibria of this kind converges to the set of all pure Nash equilibria of the ultimatum game. As is well known, there is a continuum of such equilibria. Beyond the methodological issues, the practical conclusion is that the ultimatum game is not the ultimate experiment to test for, say, sel sh preferences. Sel sh preferences and sequential rationality impose no restriction at all on the o er made by the proposer. This is true even in a perfectly designed experiment, unless participants simply aren t able to conceive of the possibility that their behavior in the experiment will a ect their continuation payo. 4

5 2 A Simple Model of the Ultimatum Game This example is a stylized version of the ultimatum game. 100 dollars are to be split in the usual way, except that the proposer only has two alternatives - demand 99 dollars, leaving 1 for the responder, or demand 50 dollars, leaving the other 50 for the responder. The perturbation considered here is that the proposer has some information about the joint payo s of the players in the continuation. For simplicity, assume that this joint payo in the continuation is and that it is the same for both players. The rst type of proposer has a signal 1 that tells him that these continuation payo s are independent of the responder s behavior during the experiment, and for simplicity are normalized to zero. The payo s from the experiment for both players are the entries in the following table: rr ar ra aa 99 0; 0 99; 1 0; 0 99; ; 0 0; 0 50; 50 50; 50 The rows represent the di erent demands (100 minus the proposal): 99 or 50. The columns index the various strategies for the responder. For example, ar means: accept 99 and reject 50. If the responder adopts the strategy ar, then the proposer gets 99 dollars plus his payo (zero) from the continuation if he demands 99, but gets only his continuation payo (zero) if he o ers 50. The other entries are interpreted similarly. There are multiple Nash equilibria in this game. The (unique) sub-game perfect equilibrium, of course, has the proposer demanding 99 and the responder accepting both o ers. There is another Nash equilibrium in which the proposer demands 50, while the responder accepts 50 and rejects 99. Another equilibrium exists where the proposer demands 50 and the responder randomizes over ra and aa, playing the rst with probability The second type of proposer has a signal that suggests that continuation payo s depend on the behavior of the responder. In particular, this proposer s information suggests that both players will be strictly better o in the continuation if the responder rejects an o er. Call the signal of the proposer in this case 2, and suppose that such a signal suggests the following payo matrix: rr ar ra aa 99 x; x 99; 1 x; x 99; 1 50 x; x x; x 50; 50 50; 50 5 ( 1 ) ( 2 )

6 To be concrete, suppose the proposer in this case knows that if the pair disagree - they will be involved in a subsequent experiment, but if they agree - they will be sent home. The expected payo from the second experiment is the entry x that appears in the matrix. We are interested in what happens when 1 < x < 50. The responder doesn t know the signal the proposer has received. The responder in the example believes that the proposer has received signal 1 with probability q which could be (and in fact should be, if the experiment is well designed) very close to one. This belief is common knowledge.

7 A second, more interesting, pooling equilibrium exists in which the proposer o ers 50 independently of his signal. If he demands 99 (which is now o equilibrium) the responder revises her beliefs so that she assumes that the proposer has surely received the signal 2. The responder is then certain she will be better o rejecting the o er of 1. We now prove that there is a third equilibrium, in which the type 1 proposer randomizes. First note that there cannot be an equilibrium in which both types of proposer randomize. Let and be the probabilities with which the responder accepts 99 and 50 respectively. Suppose that proposer of type 1 is indi erent between o ering 99 and 50. Then If the proposer of type 2 is also indi erent This gives 99 = 50 (2) 99 + (1 )x = 50 + (1 )x (3) 50 + (1 )x = 50 + (1 )x (4) or =. So if there is an equilibrium where both types of the proposer randomize, the responder must accept both o ers with the same probability. This is a contradiction, since this will make the proposer o er 99 for sure. So in every equilibrium, at least one proposer type uses a pure strategy. Suppose that the type 2 proposer uses a pure strategy of demanding 99. Then the type 1 proposer either uses the same pure strategy (the equilibrium we have already described), or the type 1 proposer will reveal his type with positive probability. Since 2 is demanding 99, 1 cannot reveal his type by the identical demand, so he must be the one who o ers 50. If so, 99 must be rejected with positive probability and 50 accepted (since x < 50). To make him indi erent 99 = 50 (5) or = In that case the type 2 proposer has payo which makes demanding 99 a best reply x > 50 (6)

8 Now the type 1 proposer has to demand 99 with just the right probability to make the responder indi erent between accepting and rejecting. Let be the probability with which the proposer demands 99. Let p be the posterior probability that the proposer s type is 1 (so that continuation payo s are independent of the responder s action) conditional on receiving an o er of 1 (demand of 99). Using Bayes rule, p is then: p = q q + (1 q) (7) The responder will be indi erent about whether or not to accept the demand of 99 if: (1 p)x = 1 giving 1 p = 1. So the appropriate randomization is x q q + (1 q) = 1 1 x (8) This has a unique solution provided q > 1 1 x. To summarize, this equilibrium has the proposer demanding 99 if he is of type 2 and randomizing between 99 and 50 if he is of type 1. The proposal 99 is rejected a little less than half the time, though the o er 50 is always accepted. Figure 2: Perfect Bayesian Nash Equilibrium of the Ultimatum Game q 1 q (50,50) (50,50) a a r (0,0) (x,x) r 50 θ1 θ 2 ( ) 1 q λ = x 1 q 1 λ a r (99,1) (99,1) a (0,0) (x,x) r

9 The number q measures the degree of uncertainty (possible misconception ) involved in this game. When q is close to one, the responder is almost sure about the payo matrix of the game, the proposer is almost sure the responder is sure and so on. First, note that the demand of 99 is rejected about half of the time no matter what q is. Furthermore, it is straightforward to check that the probability with which the demand 99 is made shrinks to zero as q approaches one ( = (x 1) (1 q) =q). As q goes to one, the set of Perfect Bayesian equilibria of the ultimatum game converges to the set of Nash equilibria of the perfect information game - 1. The implications of subgame perfection are not robust to possible uncertainty about the contiuation payo s of the game. 3 Comparison with Existing Literature Subjects behavior varies across experiments, but usually proposers demand only 50, and responders who are o ered only 1 often reject. As mentioned before, one way to account for these experimental results is to imagine that players preferences aren t sel sh. For example, the responder may care not only about his own monetary reward, but also about the di erence between his reward and the proposer s reward. Let x p be the proposer s monetary payo and x r be the responder s monetary payo. Suppose the proposer s utility function is u p = x p max[0; x r x p ] (9) and the responders is Then the payo matrix becomes u r = x r max[0; x p x r ] (10) rr ar ra aa 99 0,0 99,-97 0,0 99, ,0 0,0 50,50 50,50 (11) One Nash equilibrium has 99 being o ered and rejected (because 50 is also rejected), the other has 50 being o ered and accepted. Only the latter survives the subgame perfection requirement. Strictly speaking, neither equilibria has 99 being rejected on the equilibrium path, though uncertainty about the degree of aversion to payo di erences could presumably be used to support 9

10 such rejection on the equilibrium path associated with a Bayesian equilibrium. Fudenberg, Kreps and Levine [11] (henceforth FKL) study the robustness of equilibrium re nements to possible payo perturbations. They consider an elaboration of an extensive form game, in which one of several di erent versions of a game is chosen at random by nature. Versions di er only in the players payo s, which might be di erent from the original payo s in the game. Generally, players may hold private information concerning the version of the game. FKL s interest lies in small perturbations, for which they de ne a convergence criterion for a sequence of elaborations: the probability that a version with payo s asymptotically equal to the original game is chosen, approaches one (in addition to requiring that the number of versions and payo s are bounded). A strategy in the original game is near strict under general elaborations if there exists a sequence of elaborations that converges to the original game, and a sequence of strict equilibria for each elaboration that converges (in a well de ned way) to the strategy in the original game. FKL prove (Proposition 3) that a pure strategy pro le in the original game is near strict under general elaborations if and only if it is a Nash equilibrium in the original game. That is, any Nash equilibrium can be supported if one allows arbitrary doubts about each other s payo s. The example presented in Section 2 is a speci c FKL elaboration of the original ultimatum game. This particular elaboration represents a speci c type of possible misconception about the original game. The general model presented in the following section studies more general elaborations. Di erently from FKL, our interest lies in understanding the Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium in an elaboration, and not necessarily strict Nash equilibrium in an arbitrary elaboration. The payo to this modeling strategy is that we are able to capture behavior (as rejections of low o ers) that is not consistent with Nash equilibrium in the original game. Furthermore, while introducing a new state (even if it is assigned a prior probability zero) - we are able to disentangle the relation between common knowledge of the game structure and common certainty of it - giving rise to a PBNE in which high o ers are made and accepted, while low o ers (if made) - are rejected with probability 1. In light of FKL s result, the convergence of the PBE to the set of Nash equilibria as q approaches 1 - is not surprising, and will not be pursued further in the general model. As alluded in the introduction, an alternative explanation for the experimental results is a failure of the common knowledge assumptions that play a 10

11 key role in the Nash and subgame perfect Nash prediction. Even if a player understands the instructions given by the experimenter, and fully accepts the claims by the experimenter about payo s, the player can never be sure that the other player does. The other player might misinterpret the experimenter s instructions, or make unwarranted inferences about payo s from statements made by the experimenter. Indeed, even if the other player does none of these things, the other player might believe that the original player has misunderstood, etc. As is now known, variations in these higher order beliefs can be used to support a wide range of behavior as Bayesian Nash equilibria (Yildiz and Weinstein [15]). Their theorems provide bounds on the sets of actions that can be supported on the equilibrium path of Bayesian games with higher order uncertainty. Though our example uses the similar reasoning, it goes further by showing that rejection of an o er is consistent with Perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Technically, the assumption that the payo s in the game are common knowledge is relaxed. That is, although the game structure (including payo s) is common knowledge, the responder does not know her payo (as well as the proposer s) when she decides to accept or reject an o er. An important distinction to be made here is between common knowledge and common certainty - which is achived in the example in the case of q = 1: The existence of PBNE in this case relies on the existence of type 2 (although he recieves probability zero ex-ante). Within the experimental economics literature, Plott and Zeiler [12] have recently demonstrated the role of possible misconception in a decision theoretic experiment. They studies the observed di erence between willingness to pay (WTP) and willingness to accept (WTA.) Many previous experiments (though not all) have attributed this di erence to preferences ( endowment e ect ). Plott and Zeiler showed that this conclusion was premature. They presented convincing evidence that when misconceptions are minimized the di erence disappears. What is the source of these misconceptions? How do they in uence the results of other experiments in which decision makers interact strategically with each other? Plott and Zeiler leave these questions unanswered, and this study attempts to give some preliminary answers. It shows that in an experimental test of interactive decision making the problem of misconception is exacerbated since even if one subject has no misconception (whatever that may mean) (s)he can never be absolutely sure that the other participant(s) have no misconceptions. 11

12 4 The Model More generally, let P be a nite collection of feasible o ers for the proposer. These are normalized to lie between 0 and 1. Suppose these o ers are indexed in such a way that 0 = p 1 < p 2 < : : : < p n = 1. The lowest demand p 1 is assumed to give all the surplus in the experiment to the responder. The highest demand p n is assumed to give all the surplus from the experiment to the proposer. The proposer receives a signal s 2 [s; s] S that a ects the payo of both players. The distribution of signals is given by F;and is assumed to be continuous with full support. Let 2 f0; 1g denote the action of the responder, = 1 meaning that she accepts the proposal. The payo s are treated asymmetrically. The payo to the proposer is given by u p (p; ; s) where s is his signal. Condition 1 Let p 0 > p. Then 1. u p (p 0 ; 1; s) > u p (p; 1; s) and u p (p 0 ; 0; s) u p (p; 0; s) for all s 2 S; 2. if u p (p; 1; s) > u p (p; 0; s) for some s 2 S then u p (p; 1; s) > u p (p 0 ; 0; s). The rst part of the condition states that independetly of whether an o er is accepted or rejected, the proposer is always better o with a higher demand (lower o er). The second part states that if the proposer receives signal s and prefers the o er p to be accepted rather than being rejected, then he must also prefer that the o er p be accepted to a rejection of a higher o er. The combination of the two parts imply that if u p (p; 1; s) > u p (p; 0; s) for some s 2 S then u p (p; 1; s) > u p (p 0 ; 0; s) > u p (p; 0; s) : The following condition is also used repeatedly. Condition 2 Let s 0 and s be such that u p (p; 0; s) u p (p; 1; s) < u p (p; 0; s 0 ) u p (p; 1; s 0 ) and suppose that for some p j > p k and q j < q k, q j u p (p j ; 1; s) + (1 q j )u p (p j ; 0; s) q k u p (p k ; 1; s) + (1 q k )u p (p k ; 0; s) Then the same inequality holds strictly for type s 0. This single-crossing condition states that if the proposer s utility loss as a result of being rejected at s 0 is lower than at s, and if the proposer s expected utility from a high demand (with a certain probability of acceptance) is at least as high as the expected utility of a lower demand (with higher 12

13 probability of acceptance) at s, then he strictly prefers the high demand at s 0 : The payo to the responder also depends on the proposer s signal. This payo function is given by u r (p; ; s): We assume that: Condition 3 The function u r (p; 0; s) u r (p; 1; s) is monotonically increasing in s and super modular in p and s. Furthermore u r (p; 0; s) u r (p; 1; s) 0 with strict inequality holding at each demand except p 1 = 0. u r (p; 0; s) u r (p; 1; s) < 0 for all p 2 P. The assumption is made on the responder s marginal utility of rejection, if she knows the proposer s signal s: It is assumed that the marginal utility of rejection is increasing in the signal, and supermodular in the proposer demand and the signal. The payo s for the responder are not too extreme: a responder who believes that the proposer s signal is s will reject all o ers except (amybe) the one that gives her the entire surplus from the experiment. By monotonicity and continuity a responder will accept the demand p 1 (which gives her all the surplus) no matter what her beliefs about the signal. This isn t true for other o ers. However, we assume: Condition 4 Z s s fu r (p; 0; s) u r (p; 1; s)g df (s) < 0 for every p < 1 This assumption implies that a responder using her prior beliefs would accept every o er except possibly the o er p = 1 (where the proposer gets the entire surplus from the experiment). This game has many equilibrium outcomes. The nature of these outcomes depends on the function u p (p; 0; s) u p (p; 1; s). We begin with the case where this function is strictly increasing. Then, the higher the signal the proposer receives, he believes that both he and the responder will gain more in the coninuation if the responder rejects the o er than if she accepts. Theorem 1 Suppose that u p (p; 0; s) u p (p; 1; s) is strictly increasing and that p < 1 is a demand such that u p (p; 1; s) > u p (p; 0; s). Then there is a Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium in which all proposers make the o er p and this is accepted. 13

14 Proof. By Condition 4, the responder wants to accept every o er except 1 given his or her prior beliefs. Let p 0 > p, and suppose that responders believe that such a proposal is made by a proposer whose type lies in the interval (s ; s] where s is chosen such that Z s s fu r (p 0 ; 0; s) u r (p 0 ; 1; s)g df (s) = 0 By Condition 3 and continuity of F, such an s always exists. Then a responder who receives the o er p 0 will be just indi erent about whether or not to accept it. Choose q 0 such that q 0 u p (p 0 ; 1; s) + (1 q 0 )u p (p 0 ; 0; s) = u p (p; 1; s) q 0 is chosen such that a proposer who received a signal s is indi erent between demanding p and p 0. By Condition 1 and the assumption that u p (p; 1; s) > u p (p; 0; s), u p (p 0 ; 1; s) > u p (p; 1; s) > u p (p 0 ; 0; s), so a unique q 0 satisfying this condition exists. Then if any proposer whose type is less than s strictly prefers to o er p 0, then by Condition 2, the highest type proposer must also. This contradiction proves that all proposer types at least weakly prefer the o er p to p 0. A similar argument is used to make downward deviations unpro table. It is possible to support equilibrium with multiple o ers in this model, but in a restricted way. Theorem 2 Suppose that u p (p; 0; s) u p (p; 1; s) is strictly increasing in s. Let p j > p k be a pair of demands and s the solution to Z s s fu r (p j ; 0; s) u r (p j ; 1; s)g df (s) = 0: If u p (p j ; 1; s) > u p (p j ; 0; s) and u p (p k ; 1; s ) > u p (p k ; 0; s ), then there is a perfect Bayesian Nash equilibrium in which proposers whose signal is in the interval [s ; s] demand p j, while proposers whose signal is below s demand p k. Responders accept p k for sure and reject p j with positive probability. Proof. By Conditions 3 and 4, there is a unique signal s satisfying the property R s fu s r (p j ; 0; s) u r (p j ; 1; s)g df (s) = 0. If the responder believes that the o er p j comes from a proposer whose type is in the interval [s ; s], 14

15 then she is indi erent between accepting and rejecting the o er. By Condition 4, the responder will strictly prefer to accept the o er p k if she believes that it is made by proposers whose type is in the interval [s; s ). Since u p (p k ; 1; s ) > u p (p k ; 0; s ), by Condition 1, u p (p j ; 1; s ) > u p (p k ; 1; s ) > u p (p j ; 0; s ). Thus there is a unqiue q j satisfying u p (p k ; 1; s ) = q j u p (p j ; 1; s ) + (1 q j )u p (p j ; 0; s ) Then if the responder accepts the demand p j with probability q j, Condition 2 says that since proposer type s weakly prefers the higher price lower probability o er p j, every higher proposer type strictly prefers to o er p j. In a similar fashion, for each o equilibrium o er p 0, nd x 0 such that the responder is indi erent between accepting and rejecting p 0 if she thinks that the o er was made by a proposer whose type is in the interval [x 0 ; s]. The acceptance probability now depends on the o er. If p 0 > p j, then repeating the arguments above and using the assumption that the highest proposer type prefers to have p j accepted, it is possible to choose the acceptance probability such that a proposer of the highest type is indi erent between the o ers p j and p 0. Similarly, if p j > p 0 > p k, then the acceptance probability is set so that a proposer of type x is indi erent between the proposal p j and the proposal p 0. If p 0 < p k, then the acceptance probability is chosen such that a proposer of type s (who prefers all o ers to be accepted) at least weakly prefers p k to p 0. This makes it possible to check deviations to o equilibrium prices. There are three cases, p 0 > p j, p j > p 0 > p k, and p 0 < p k. In the rst case, the highest type proposer s weakly prefers the o er p j to the o er p 0 by the choice of q 0. If there is a proposer type s < s who strictly prefers p 0 to p j, then the same must be true for a proposer of type s by Condition2. Thus the deviation must be unpro table for all proposer types. If p 0 < p k, then since the proposer with the lowest type is indi erent, all proposer types must at least weakly prefer p k by Condition 2. If p j > p 0 > p k, then all proposer types above x prefer p j by the single crossing condition. If there is a proposer type less than x who strictly prefers the proposal p 0 to p k, then type x must also have this strict preference if Condition 2 holds. This contradiction shows that types below x prefer p k. The conditions required for these two theorems are easy to check. For example, one might assume that every type of proposer does strictly better when every non-zero o er is accepted. In this case, every non-zero price 15

16 can be supported as a pooling equilibrium, and any pair of prices can be supported as a separating equilibrium. This is not the most interesting case. It seems more reasonable to study the possibility that proposers who have very high signals would strictly prefer that some very low demands that they might make would be rejected. One standard property of experimental results is that higher demands are less likely to be accepted. The model described so far is ill suited to explain the experimental results in a way that is consistent with a single equilibrium being played. The following theorem illustrates. Theorem 3 Suppose that u p (p; 0; s) u p (p; 1; s) is strictly increasing. Then all perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcomes in which higher demands are accepted with lower probability involve at most two demands that are accepted with strictly positive probability. Proof. Suppose more than two demands are accepted with positive probability in some perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Let p k and p j be the lowest and next lowest demands made with strictly positive probability in this equilibrium, and let p 0 be any other demand that is accepted with strictly positive probability. Let q k, q j and q 0 be the probabilities with which these o ers are accepted along the equilibrium path. By hypothesis, q k > q j > q 0. Let ~s be the supremum of the the set of types for the proposer that o er p k with strictly positive probability. If any lower type proposer weakly prefers to demand p j or p 0, then by Condition 2, a proposer of type ~s must strictly prefer the higher demand. Thus ~s < s, and for each type below ~s, q k u p (p k ; 1; s) + (1 q k )u p (p k ; 0; s) > q j u p (p j ; 1; s) + (1 q j )u p (p j ; 0; s) and similarly for p 0. The strict inequality is reversed for types s > ~s. Repeat the argument for the supremum of the set of types, say ^s, for the proposer who o er p j. Exactly as above, ^s < s. Then if p j is o ered on the equilibrium path, the responder must believe that the proposer s type is in the interval (~s; ^s]. If the proposer makes the o er p 0, the responder must believe the proposer s type is in the interval (^s; s]. Now since 0 < q j < q k, responders who see the o er p j must be just indi erent about whether or not they accept it. As a consequence, a responder who thought that the proposer s type was ^s, would strictly prefer to reject. Since u r (p; 0; s) u r (p; 1; s) is super modular by Condition 3, the higher demand coupled with beliefs that the higher demand is made by a proposer with 16

17 a higher signal means that the responder must strictly prefer to reject the demand p 0, a contradiction. The theorems above resemble the outcomes in the example described in the introduction. They don t provide enough richness to explain existing experimental results as a single equilibrium since experimental results involve many o ers and declining acceptance probabilities. At the same time, they are all independent of the particular distribution of types F for the proposer. So they do illustrate that the strong predictions associated with the subgame perfect equilibrium are not robust to mis-speci cations of the information structure. To provide an account of experimental results using a single equilibrium, we now modify the argument slightly and assume that u p (p; 0; s) u p (p; 1; s) is monotonically decreasing. A proposer with a high signal now believes that his own continuation payo is hurt by responder rejections. Responders continue to believe that their own continuation payo s are enhanced by rejection if the proposer has a high signal and the proposer knows this. Roughly speaking, the proposer now has an incentive to try to hide his information from the responder because their interests are not aligned. The following assumption is required to construct an equilibrium: Condition 5 For any o er p let s be such that u r (p 0 ; 1; s) < u r (p 0 ; 0; s) for each p 0 > p. Then u p (p; 1; s) > u p (p; 0; s) That is, if for every p 0 > p; a responder who knows the proposer s signal prefers to reject p 0, then the proposer prefers p to be accepted. In other words: let ^s be the solution to u r (p; 0; s) = u r (p; 1; s). This is the proposer s type such that if the responder believed the proposer had that type for sure, he would be just indi erent between accepting and rejecting the demand p. Roughly the Condition above states that provided a type s isn t too much lower than ^s, the proposer of type s would strictly prefer to have the demand p accepted. Condition 6 The payo to the proposer from a rejected o er is independent of p. That is, u p (p; 0; s) = u p (p 0 ; 0; s) for each p; p 0 2 P and for each s 2 S. Theorem 4 If u p (p; 0; s) u p (p; 1; s) is strictly decreasing and Conditions 1, 2, 3, 5 and 6 hold, there exists a Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium in which 17

18 multiple o ers are made along the equilibrium path. The o er p 1 is made with strictly positive probability and accepted for sure. The o er p n is made with strictly positive probability. All o ers other than p 1 are accepted with probability strictly less than one. If q k is the probability with which an o er p k is accepted on the equilibrium path and p j > p k then q j < q k. Proof. The proof is constructive. We construct a decreasing collection of m n demands 1 = m > m 1 > : : : > 1 = 0 that will be made with positive probability on the equilibrium path. Some demands in P may not be included in this set. Begin by setting m = p n. Select an interval [s; s m ) such that Z sm s fu r ( m ; 0; s) u r ( m ; 1; s)g df (s) = 0 The existence of such an interval is guaranteed by Condition 3. Now given the sequence f( m ; s m ); ( m 1 ; s m 1 ); : : : ; ( k+1 ; s k+1 )g; let k be the highest demand less than k+1 such that if the responder knew that the proposer s type is s k+1 then she would accept that demand. u r ( k ; 0; s k+1 ) u r ( k ; 1; s k+1 ) 0 (12) This highest price always exists because by Condition 3, a responder at least weakly prefers to accept the o er p 1 no matter what her beliefs about the proposer s. Now select s k such that Z sk s k+1 fu r ( k+1 ; 0; s) u r ( k+1 ; 1; s)g df (s) = 0 Again, the existence of such an interval for each strictly positive demand k follows from Condition 3. Proceed in this way until k = p 1. In this case set s k = s. Now re-index the demands and cuto s such that m is the number of demands in the sequence. Let s m+1 s (see Figure 3). We now construct the acceptance probabilities that support the equilibrium. Observe rst that by construction, for each o er k that is made with positive probability in this equilibrium, the set of types [s k+1 ; s k ) has the property that k is the highest demand less than k+1 that a responder would accept if he believed the proposer s type were exactly s k+1. Then by Condition 5, u p ( k ; 1; s k+1 ) > u p ( k ; 0; s k+1 ). The second part of Condition 1 then implies that u p ( k+1 ; 1; s k+1 ) > u p ( k+1 ; 0; s k+1 ). The rst part of Condition 1 then gives that u p ( k ; 1; s k+1 ) > u p ( k+1 ; 0; s k+1 ). 18

19 Figure 3: Construction of demands in Equilibrium 1 = π m π m 1 π k π k 1 π 2 π = 0 1 s s s s k s 2 s = s m m 1s m 2 = s k Begin with the o er 1 which is accepted for sure, i.e., q 1 = 1. Now for each k > 0, select q k+1 such that q k+1 u p ( k+1 ; 1; s k+1 )+(1 q k+1 )u p ( k+1 ; 0; s k+1 ) = q k u p ( k ; 1; s k+1 )+(1 q k )u p ( k ; 0; s k+1 ) (13) For k = 1, the existence of a q 2 satisfying (13) is guaranteed by the inequality u p ( 2 ; 1; s 2 ) > u p ( 1 ; 1; s 2 ) > u p ( 2 ; 0; s 2 ) just proved. For each subsequent k, the existence of a solution to (13) is guaranteed by the inequality u p ( k+1 ; 1; s k+1 ) > u p ( k ; 1; s k+1 ) > u p ( k+1 ; 0; s k+1 ) = u p ( k ; 0; s k+1 ), where the equality follows from Condition 6. From this construction, a proposer whose signal is s k+1 is just indi erent between demanding k and k+1. By the single crossing Condition 2, proposers whose signals are below s k+1 strictly prefer the demand k+1 to the demand k. On the other hand, if a proposer whose signal exceeds s k+1 strictly prefers to make the demand k+1, then a proposer whose signal is s k+1 must also. Applying this argument at each value of k, it follows that the best equilibrium path o er for a proposer whose type is in the interval (s k ; s k+1 ] is the o er k. To deal with o equilibrium o ers, observe that every proposer type has an equilibrium path o er that makes them better o than they are when an o er is rejected. If p 0 is an o er that doesn t appear in the equilibrium sequence 1 ; : : : ; m, then by construction, there is an s k in the equilibrium sequence s 1 ; : : : ; s m such that u r (p 0 ; 0; s k ) u r (p 0 ; 1; s k ) > 0 19

20 If that is the case, then assume that whenever the o er p 0 is made o the equilibrium path, then the responder believes that it must have been made by a proposer whose type is s k, so that the o er is rejected for sure. Then each proposer type can improve upon this payo by selecting some equilibrium path o er. One property of particular interest is the expected payo to proposers associated with di erent o ers. In a collection of experimental results, for example, one might check empirically how often an o er p k is accepted, then compute the product of p k and the observed acceptance probability in order to compute an expected payo. To check this here specialize the payo function for the proposer as follows and u p (p; 1; s) = p u p (p; 0; s) = (s) where, in this application, (s) is a decreasing function. This formulation satis es Condition 6, and can be made to satisfy Condition 5 by appropriate choice of. From (13) in the proof of Theorem 4 or q k+1 p k+1 + (1 q k+1 )(s k+1 ) = q k p k + (1 q k )(s k+1 ) q k+1 p k+1 q k p k = (q k+1 q k )(s k+1 ) By Theorem 4, q k+1 < q k. The proposers who make the low demands are those whose signals are very high. These are the proposers who think that a responder rejection will lower their continuation payo, i.e., proposers who would prefer that the responder accept demands very close to 0. The condition u p (p 1 ; 0; s) u p (p 1 ; 1; s) < 0 in this special case reduces to (s) < 0. Thus for very low values of k, we conclude that q k+1 p k+1 > q k p k. At some point (s k ) becomes positive, and thereafter q k+1 p k+1 < q k p k. The implication is that the apparent gains from the experiment are single peaked in this equilibrium. References [1] Aumann, Robert J. (1997): Rationality and Bounded Rationality, Games and Economic Behavior, 21,

21 [2] Binmore, Ken, John McCarthy, Giovanni Ponti, Larry Samuelson (2002): A Backward Induction Experiment, Journal of Economic Theory, 104, [3] Binmore, Ken and Larry Samuelson (1999): Evolutionary Drift and Equilibrium Selection, Review of Economic Studies, 66, [4] Binmore, Ken and Larry Samuelson (2006): The Evolution of Focal Points, Games and Economic Behavior, 55, [5] Bolton, Gary E. (1991): A Comparative Model of Bargaining: Theory and Evidence, American Economic Review, 81, [6] Bolton, Gary E. and Axel Ockenfels (2000): ERC: A Theory of Equity Reciprocity and Competition, American Economic Review, 90, [7] Fehr, Ernst and Klaus M. Schmidt (1999): A Theory of Fairness, Competition and Cooperation, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114, [8] Fudenberg, Drew, David M. Kreps and David K. Levine (1988): On the Robustness of Equilibrium Re nments, Journal of Economic Theory, 44 (2), [9] Gale, John, Kenneth G. Binmore and Larry Samuelson (1995): Learning to Be Imprefect: The Ultimatum Game, Games and Economic Behavior, 8, [10] Güth, Werner, R. Schmittberger and B. Schwarz (1982): An Experimental Analysis of Ultimatum Bargaining, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3, [11] Levine, David K. (1998): Modeling Altruism and Spitefulness in Experiments, Review of Economic Dynamics, 1, [12] Plott, Charles R. and Kathryn Zeiler (2005): The Willingness to Pay Willingness to Accept Gap, the Endowment E ect, Subject Misconceptions, and Experimental Procedures for Eliciting Valuations, American Economic Review, 95,

22 [13] Rabin, Matthew (1993): Endogeneous Preferences in Games, American Economic Review, 83, [14] Roth, Alvin E. (1995): Bargaining Experiments, in: The Handbook of Experimental Economics, Ed. John H. Kagel and Alvin E. Roth. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. [15] Yildiz, Muhamet and Jonathan Weinstein (2006): Finite Order Implications of Any Equilibrium (mimeo). 22

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE)

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE) EconS 3 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE). Based on MWG 9.B.3 Consider the three-player nite game of perfect information depicted in gure. L R Player 3 l r a b

More information

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

Some Notes on Adverse Selection Some Notes on Adverse Selection John Morgan Haas School of Business and Department of Economics University of California, Berkeley Overview This set of lecture notes covers a general model of adverse selection

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion:

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: Interpretation and Step-by-Step Examples Ana Espínola-Arredondo School of Economic Sciences Washington State University Pullman, WA 99164 Félix Muñoz-García y School

More information

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibrium Refinements Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game... subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium Play starting

More information

Bounded Rationality Lecture 4

Bounded Rationality Lecture 4 Bounded Rationality Lecture 4 Mark Dean Princeton University - Behavioral Economics The Story So Far... Introduced the concept of bounded rationality Described some behaviors that might want to explain

More information

Notes on Mechanism Designy

Notes on Mechanism Designy Notes on Mechanism Designy ECON 20B - Game Theory Guillermo Ordoñez UCLA February 0, 2006 Mechanism Design. Informal discussion. Mechanisms are particular types of games of incomplete (or asymmetric) information

More information

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Gagan Ghosh Bingchao Huangfu Heng Liu October 19, 2017 (PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE: COMMENTS WELCOME) Abstract We study wars of attrition between two bidders who

More information

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information:

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: Signalling Games In general, a dynamic game of incomplete information is any extensive form game in which at least one player is uninformed about some

More information

Solving Extensive Form Games

Solving Extensive Form Games Chapter 8 Solving Extensive Form Games 8.1 The Extensive Form of a Game The extensive form of a game contains the following information: (1) the set of players (2) the order of moves (that is, who moves

More information

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

Limit pricing models and PBE 1 EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Limit pricing models and PBE 1 1 Model Consider an entry game with an incumbent monopolist (Firm 1) and an entrant (Firm ) who analyzes whether or not to join the

More information

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours.

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours. University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring 2012 EC941: Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Final Exam Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours. 1. Consider

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen 1 Bayesian Games So far we have assumed that all players had perfect information regarding the elements of a game. These are called games with complete information.

More information

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Lecture Notes on Bargaining Lecture Notes on Bargaining Levent Koçkesen 1 Axiomatic Bargaining and Nash Solution 1.1 Preliminaries The axiomatic theory of bargaining originated in a fundamental paper by Nash (1950, Econometrica).

More information

Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model

Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model Yu (Larry) Chen School of Economics, Nanjing University Fall 2015 Principal-Agent Relationship Principal-agent relationship

More information

Behavioral predictions and hypotheses for "An experimental test of the deterrence hypothesis"

Behavioral predictions and hypotheses for An experimental test of the deterrence hypothesis Behavioral predictions and hypotheses for "An experimental test of the deterrence hypothesis" Hannah Schildberg-Hörisch a, Christina Strassmair b a Institute for Empirical Research in Economics, Department

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 Rational Choice The central gure of economics theory is the individual decision-maker (DM). The typical example of a DM is the consumer. We shall assume

More information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Pei-yu Lo 1 Introduction Recap: BoS. Look for all Nash equilibria. show how to nd pure strategy Nash equilibria. Show how to nd mixed strategy Nash equilibria.

More information

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games John Morgan University of California at Berkeley Preliminaries Our running example is that of a decision maker (DM) consulting a knowledgeable expert for advice about

More information

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form)

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form) Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form) A Game in Normal (strategic) Form consists of three components. A set of players. For each player, a set of strategies (called actions in textbook). The interpretation

More information

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich Volume 30, Issue 3 Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich Abstract The Milgrom-Shannon single crossing property is essential for monotone

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key EconS 50 - Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam # - Answer Key 1. Revenue comparison in two auction formats. Consider a sealed-bid auction with bidders. Every bidder i privately observes his valuation

More information

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics. Puri cation 1 Stephen Morris Princeton University July 2006 1 This survey was prepared as an entry for the second edition of the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. In a mixed strategy equilibrium of

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY 1 / 32 BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY Heinrich H. Nax hnax@ethz.ch & Bary S. R. Pradelski bpradelski@ethz.ch May 15, 217: Lecture 1 2 / 32 Plan Normal form games Equilibrium invariance Equilibrium

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen Strategic Form Games In this part we will analyze games in which the players choose their actions simultaneously (or without the knowledge of other players

More information

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation joint work with Stephen Morris August 2009 Barcelona Introduction mechanism design and implementation literatures are theoretical successes mechanisms

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY

ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY Appendix B. Modeling Games as Decisions In this appendix we describe how one can move seamlessly

More information

Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs

Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs Guofu Tan and Okan Yilankaya January 2005 Abstract We investigate equilibria of sealed-bid second price auctions with bidder participation costs

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 13: Extensive Form Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 13: Extensive Form Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Lecture 13: Extensive Form Games Asu Ozdaglar MIT March 18, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information One-stage Deviation Principle

More information

Lecture 7. Simple Dynamic Games

Lecture 7. Simple Dynamic Games Lecture 7. Simple Dynamic Games 1. Two-Stage Games of Complete and Perfect Information Two-Stages dynamic game with two players: player 1 chooses action a 1 from the set of his feasible actions A 1 player

More information

Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence

Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence June 9, 2009 GENERAL OUTLINE Economic Rationality is Individual Optimization and Group Equilibrium Narrow version: Restrictive Assumptions about Objective

More information

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium For an important class of extensive games, a solution concept is available that is simpler than sequential equilibrium, but with similar properties. In a Bayesian extensive

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES SUBGAME PERFECT IMPLEMENTATION WITH ALMOST PERFECT INFORMATION AND THE HOLD-UP PROBLEM

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES SUBGAME PERFECT IMPLEMENTATION WITH ALMOST PERFECT INFORMATION AND THE HOLD-UP PROBLEM NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES SUBGAME PERFECT IMPLEMENTATION WITH ALMOST PERFECT INFORMATION AND THE HOLD-UP PROBLEM Philippe Aghion Drew Fudenberg Richard T. Holden Working Paper 567 http://www.nber.org/papers/w567

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Repeated Games

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Repeated Games EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Repeated Games. MWG 9.B.9 Consider the game in which the following simultaneous-move game as depicted in gure is played twice: Player Player 2 b b 2 b

More information

8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS

8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS 8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS We have studied competitive markets where there are a large number of rms and each rm takes market prices as given. When a market contain only a few relevant rms, rms may

More information

Sequential Games with Incomplete Information

Sequential Games with Incomplete Information Sequential Games with Incomplete Information Debraj Ray, November 6 For the remaining lectures we return to extensive-form games, but this time we focus on imperfect information, reputation, and signalling

More information

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4 1 Hotelling s model 1.1 Two vendors Game Theory Solutions to Problem Set 4 Consider a strategy pro le (s 1 s ) with s 1 6= s Suppose s 1 < s In this case, it is pro table to for player 1 to deviate and

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key EconS 503 - Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key 1. WEAs with market power. Consider an exchange economy with two consumers, A and B, whose utility functions are u A (x A 1 ; x A 2 ) = x A

More information

An Experiment on Forward versus Backward Induction: How Fairness and Levels of Reasoning Matter.

An Experiment on Forward versus Backward Induction: How Fairness and Levels of Reasoning Matter. An Experiment on Forward versus Backward Induction: How Fairness and Levels of Reasoning Matter. Dieter Balkenborg y and Rosemarie Nagel z The University of Exeter and Universitat Pompeiu Fabra 9.5.28

More information

Subgame Perfect Implementation With Almost Perfect. Information

Subgame Perfect Implementation With Almost Perfect. Information Subgame Perfect Implementation With Almost Perfect Information Philippe Aghion, Drew Fudenberg and Richard Holden December 6, 007 Abstract The theory of incomplete contracts has been recently questioned

More information

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis Natalia Lazzati y November 09, 2013 Abstract We study collective choice models from a revealed preference approach given limited

More information

A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon

A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon Chantal Marlats January 2010 Chantal Marlats () A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon January 2010 1 / 14 Introduction: A story

More information

Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge

Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge Christoph Schottmüller University of Copenhagen November 13 and 20, 2014 1 / 36 Outline 1 (Common) Knowledge The hat game A model of knowledge Common knowledge Agree

More information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information joint with Stephen Morris (Princeton University) November 2010 Payoff Environment in games with incomplete information, the agents are uncertain

More information

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No. 1846 EFFICIENT AUCTIONS AND INTERDEPENDENT TYPES Dirk Bergemann, Stephen Morris, and Satoru Takahashi

More information

Direct Tests of Models of Social Preferences and a New Model. By James C. Cox and Vjollca Sadiraj

Direct Tests of Models of Social Preferences and a New Model. By James C. Cox and Vjollca Sadiraj Direct Tests of Models of Social Preferences and a New Model By James C. Cox and Vjollca Sadiraj Abstract: Departures from economic man behavior in many games in which fairness is a salient characteristic

More information

Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan

Discussion of Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan Stephen Morris IUB Stern Workshop March 2017 Basic Question Some policy ingredients:

More information

How to Characterize Solutions to Constrained Optimization Problems

How to Characterize Solutions to Constrained Optimization Problems How to Characterize Solutions to Constrained Optimization Problems Michael Peters September 25, 2005 1 Introduction A common technique for characterizing maximum and minimum points in math is to use first

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium EconS 50 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium. Based on MWG 9.C.4 A plainti, Ms. P, les a suit against Ms. D (the defendant). If Ms. P wins, she will collect dollars in

More information

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 18 To recap Tuesday: We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Two finite populations, call them Men and Women, who want to

More information

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Spring 2013: 521 B Introduction game theoretic predictions are very sensitive to "information structure"

More information

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) Game Theory Bargaining Theory J International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) (International Game Theory: Doctorate Bargainingin Theory Economic Analysis (IDEA)

More information

OTHER-REGARDING PREFERENCES: OUTCOMES, INTENTIONS OR INTERDEPENDENCE?

OTHER-REGARDING PREFERENCES: OUTCOMES, INTENTIONS OR INTERDEPENDENCE? OTHER-REGARDING PREFERENCES: OUTCOMES, INTENTIONS OR INTERDEPENDENCE? YORAM HALEVY AND MICHAEL PETERS Abstract. If preferences and beliefs are appropriately parametrized, different theories of other-regarding

More information

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Course Overview 1. Bargaining 2. Hidden information and self-selection Optimal contracting with hidden information

More information

Module 16: Signaling

Module 16: Signaling Module 16: Signaling Information Economics (Ec 515) George Georgiadis Players with private information can take some action to signal their type. Taking this action would distinguish them from other types.

More information

Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize

Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize Dov Monderer and Moshe Tennenholtz Faculty of Industrial Engineering and Management Technion Israel Institute of Technology Haifa 32000,

More information

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Econometric Society Summer Meeting June 2012 Robust Predictions Agenda game theoretic predictions are very

More information

Bayesian Nash equilibrium

Bayesian Nash equilibrium Bayesian Nash equilibrium Felix Munoz-Garcia EconS 503 - Washington State University So far we assumed that all players knew all the relevant details in a game. Hence, we analyzed complete-information

More information

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action Moral Hazard: Hidden Action Part of these Notes were taken (almost literally) from Rasmusen, 2007 UIB Course 2013-14 (UIB) MH-Hidden Actions Course 2013-14 1 / 29 A Principal-agent Model. The Production

More information

Mechanism Design: Implementation. Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham

Mechanism Design: Implementation. Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham Bayesian Game Setting Extend the social choice setting to a new setting where agents can t be relied upon to disclose their preferences honestly Start

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design 1. Public Good Provision Imagine that you and your colleagues want to buy a co ee machine for your o ce. Suppose that some of you may

More information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Levent Koçkesen 1 Extensive Form Games The strategies in strategic form games are speci ed so that each player chooses an action (or a mixture of actions)

More information

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Game Theory Wolfgang Frimmel Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium / 22 Bayesian Nash equilibrium and dynamic games L M R 3 2 L R L R 2 2 L R L 2,, M,2, R,3,3 2 NE and 2 SPNE (only subgame!) 2 / 22 Non-credible

More information

Some forgotten equilibria of the Bertrand duopoly!?

Some forgotten equilibria of the Bertrand duopoly!? Some forgotten equilibria of the Bertrand duopoly!? Mathias Erlei Clausthal University of Technology Julius-Albert-Str. 2, 38678 Clausthal-Zellerfeld, Germany email: m.erlei@tu-clausthal.de Abstract This

More information

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers joint work with Frederic Murphy Climate Policy and Long Term Decisions-Investment and R&D, Bocconi University, Milan,

More information

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search Labor Economics, 14.661. Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search Daron Acemoglu MIT December 6, 2011. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Sequential Search December 6, 2011. 1 / 43 Introduction Introduction

More information

Pre-Communication in a Coordination Game with Incomplete Information

Pre-Communication in a Coordination Game with Incomplete Information Pre-Communication in a Coordination Game with Incomplete Information Zhuozheng Li, Huanxing Yang, and Lan Zhang y JEL Classi cation: D3, D74, D8 Keywords: Cheap talk, Coordination game, Centralization,

More information

ECO421: Reputation. Marcin P ski. March 29, 2018

ECO421: Reputation. Marcin P ski. March 29, 2018 ECO421: Reputation Marcin P ski March 29, 2018 Plan Chain store game Model of reputation Reputations in innite games Applications Model No pure strategy equilibria Mixed strategy equilibrium Basic model

More information

A Solution to the Problem of Externalities When Agents Are Well-Informed

A Solution to the Problem of Externalities When Agents Are Well-Informed A Solution to the Problem of Externalities When Agents Are Well-Informed Hal R. Varian. The American Economic Review, Vol. 84, No. 5 (Dec., 1994), pp. 1278-1293 Introduction There is a unilateral externality

More information

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals Liping Tang Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh PA 15213, USA Abstract. Crawford and Sobel s Cheap Talk model [1] describes an information

More information

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection Geethanjali Selvaretnam Abstract This model takes into consideration the fact that depositors

More information

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo Game Theory Giorgio Fagiolo giorgio.fagiolo@univr.it https://mail.sssup.it/ fagiolo/welcome.html Academic Year 2005-2006 University of Verona Summary 1. Why Game Theory? 2. Cooperative vs. Noncooperative

More information

Asymmetric Information and Bank Runs

Asymmetric Information and Bank Runs Asymmetric Information and Bank uns Chao Gu Cornell University Draft, March, 2006 Abstract This paper extends Peck and Shell s (2003) bank run model to the environment in which the sunspot coordination

More information

Mutual Optimism in the Bargaining Model of War

Mutual Optimism in the Bargaining Model of War Mutual Optimism in the Bargaining Model of War Mark Fey Kristopher W. Ramsay December 19, 2016 Abstract Mutual optimism is often considered an explanation for war, but recent research has challenged that

More information

Altruism, Spite and Competition in Bargaining Games

Altruism, Spite and Competition in Bargaining Games Altruism, Spite and Competition in Bargaining Games Maria Montero December 005 Abstract This paper shows that altruism may be beneficial in bargaining when there is competition for bargaining partners.

More information

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Nicolas Schutz Nicolas Schutz Game Theory 1 / 43 Introduction Why game theory? In the introductory lecture, we defined Industrial Organization as the economics

More information

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No. 772 INTERDEPENDENT PREFERENCES AND STRATEGIC DISTINGUISHABILITY Dirk Bergemann, Stephen Morris and

More information

Chapter 7. Evolutionary Game Theory

Chapter 7. Evolutionary Game Theory From the book Networks, Crowds, and Markets: Reasoning about a Highly Connected World. By David Easley and Jon Kleinberg. Cambridge University Press, 2010. Complete preprint on-line at http://www.cs.cornell.edu/home/kleinber/networks-book/

More information

Spence s labor market signaling model

Spence s labor market signaling model Spence s labor market signaling model Felix Munoz-Garcia EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II - Washington State University Readings MWG 13.C (You can also read 13.B) Macho-Stadler and Perez-Castrillo,

More information

ROBUST PREDICTIONS IN INFINITE-HORIZON GAMES AN UNREFINABLE FOLK THEOREM

ROBUST PREDICTIONS IN INFINITE-HORIZON GAMES AN UNREFINABLE FOLK THEOREM ROBUST PREDICTIONS IN INFINITE-HORIZON GAMES AN UNREFINABLE FOLK THEOREM JONATHAN WEINSTEIN AND MUHAMET YILDIZ Abstract. We show that in any game that is continuous at in nity, if a plan of action a i

More information

ECO 199 GAMES OF STRATEGY Spring Term 2004 Precepts Week 7 March Questions GAMES WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION QUESTIONS

ECO 199 GAMES OF STRATEGY Spring Term 2004 Precepts Week 7 March Questions GAMES WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION QUESTIONS ECO 199 GAMES OF STRATEGY Spring Term 2004 Precepts Week 7 March 22-23 Questions GAMES WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION QUESTIONS Question 1: In the final stages of the printing of Games of Strategy, Sue Skeath

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Leonardo Felli EC441: Room D.106, Z.332, D.109 Lecture 8 bis: 24 November 2004 Monopoly Consider now the pricing behavior of a profit maximizing monopolist: a firm that is the only

More information

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

1 Uncertainty and Insurance Uncertainty and Insurance Reading: Some fundamental basics are in Varians intermediate micro textbook (Chapter 2). A good (advanced, but still rather accessible) treatment is in Kreps A Course in Microeconomic

More information

Bargaining with Periodic Participation Costs

Bargaining with Periodic Participation Costs Bargaining with Periodic Participation Costs Emin Karagözoğlu Shiran Rachmilevitch July 4, 017 Abstract We study a bargaining game in which a player needs to pay a fixed cost in the beginning of every

More information

EconS Sequential Competition

EconS Sequential Competition EconS 425 - Sequential Competition Eric Dunaway Washington State University eric.dunaway@wsu.edu Industrial Organization Eric Dunaway (WSU) EconS 425 Industrial Organization 1 / 47 A Warmup 1 x i x j (x

More information

Basics of Game Theory

Basics of Game Theory Basics of Game Theory Giacomo Bacci and Luca Sanguinetti Department of Information Engineering University of Pisa, Pisa, Italy {giacomo.bacci,luca.sanguinetti}@iet.unipi.it April - May, 2010 G. Bacci and

More information

Are Obstinacy and Threat of Leaving the Bargaining Table Wise Tactics in Negotiations?

Are Obstinacy and Threat of Leaving the Bargaining Table Wise Tactics in Negotiations? Are Obstinacy and Threat of Leaving the Bargaining Table Wise Tactics in Negotiations? Selçuk Özyurt Sabancı University Very early draft. Please do not circulate or cite. Abstract Tactics that bargainers

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Summer 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the four areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory A, (III) game theory B, and (IV) psychology & economics). Be sure

More information

DYNAMIC LIMIT PRICING: ONLINE APPENDIX Flavio Toxvaerd. March 8, 2018

DYNAMIC LIMIT PRICING: ONLINE APPENDIX Flavio Toxvaerd. March 8, 2018 DYNAMIC LIMIT PRICING: ONLINE APPENDIX Flavio Toxvaerd March 8, 2018 Abstract. This appendix o ers a detailed and self-contained analysis of the benchmark single-round version of the dynamic model presented

More information

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden 1 Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning Jason R. Marden Abstract A learning rule is completely uncoupled if each player s behavior is conditioned only on his own realized

More information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information Contracts under Asymmetric Information 1 I Aristotle, economy (oiko and nemo) and the idea of exchange values, subsequently adapted by Ricardo and Marx. Classical economists. An economy consists of a set

More information

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication Work in Progress Ying Chen Johns Hopkins University Atara Oliver Rice University March 19, 2018 Main idea In many communication situations,

More information

Evolutionary Dynamics and Extensive Form Games by Ross Cressman. Reviewed by William H. Sandholm *

Evolutionary Dynamics and Extensive Form Games by Ross Cressman. Reviewed by William H. Sandholm * Evolutionary Dynamics and Extensive Form Games by Ross Cressman Reviewed by William H. Sandholm * Noncooperative game theory is one of a handful of fundamental frameworks used for economic modeling. It

More information

COSTLY BARGAINING AND RENEGOTIATION

COSTLY BARGAINING AND RENEGOTIATION COSTLY BARGAINING AND RENEGOTIATION Luca Anderlini (St. John's College, Cambridge) Leonardo Felli (London School of Economics) October 1998 Abstract. We identify the ine±ciencies that arise when negotiation

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication. National University of Singapore June 5, 2018

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication. National University of Singapore June 5, 2018 When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication Ying Chen Johns Hopkins University Atara Oliver Rice University National University of Singapore June 5, 2018 Main idea In many communication

More information

Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260

Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260 1 Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260 Problem 1 a) What is a public good game? See, for example, Camerer (2003), Fehr and Schmidt (1999) p.836, and/or lecture notes, lecture 1 of Topic 3.

More information

Learning and Risk Aversion

Learning and Risk Aversion Learning and Risk Aversion Carlos Oyarzun Texas A&M University Rajiv Sarin Texas A&M University January 2007 Abstract Learning describes how behavior changes in response to experience. We consider how

More information