WHAT FINITE-ADDITIVITY CAN ADD TO DECISION THEORY

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "WHAT FINITE-ADDITIVITY CAN ADD TO DECISION THEORY"

Transcription

1 Submitted to the Annals of Statistics WHAT FINITE-ADDITIVITY CAN ADD TO DECISION THEORY By Mark J. Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, Rafael Stern, and Joseph B. Kadane Carnegie Mellon University and Federal University of São Carlos We examine general decision problems with loss functions that are bounded below. We allow the loss function to assume the value. No other assumptions are made about the action space, the types of data available, the types of non-randomized decision rules allowed, or the parameter space. By allowing prior distributions and the randomizations in randomized rules to be finitely-additive, we prove very general complete class and minimax theorems. Specifically, under the sole assumption that the loss function is bounded below, we show that every decision problem has a minimal complete class and all admissible rules are Bayes rules. We also show that every decision problem has a minimax rule and a least-favorable distribution and that every minimax rule is Bayes with respect to the least-favorable distribution. Some special care is required to deal properly with infinite-valued risk functions and integrals taking infinite values. 1. Introduction. The following example, adapted from Example 3 of Schervish, Seidenfeld and Kadane (2009), is a case in which countablyadditive randomized rules do not contain a minimal complete class. It involves a discontinuous version of squared-error loss in which a penalty is added if the prediction and the event being predicted are on opposite sides of a critical cutoff. Example 1. A decision maker is going to offer predictions for an event B and its complement. The parameter space is Θ = {B, B C } while the action space is A = [0, 1] 2, pairs of probability predictions. The decision maker suffers the sum of two losses (one for each prediction) each of which equals the usual squared-error loss (square of the difference between indicator of event and corresponding prediction) plus a penalty of 0.5 if the prediction is on the opposite side of 1/2 from the indicator of the event. In symbols, AMS 2000 subject classifications: Primary 62C07; secondary 62C20 Keywords and phrases: admissible rule, Bayes rule, complete class, least-favorable distribution, minimax rule 1

2 2 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE the loss function equals L(θ, (a 1, a 2 )) = (I B a 1 ) 2 +(I B C a 2 ) { I[0,1/2] (a 1 ) + I (1/2,1] (a 2 ) if θ = B, I (1/2,1] (a 1 ) + I [0,1/2] (a 2 ) if θ = B C. To keep matters simple, we assume that no data are available, but one could rework the example with potential data at the cost of more complicated calculations. Figure 1 is a plot of all of the pairs (L(B, (a 1, a 2 )), L(B C, (a 1, a 2 ))), which shows all of the possible risk functions of non-randomized rules (pure strategies when there are no data available.) The admissible non-randomized Risks of Pure Strategies Risk at B complement Risk at B Fig 1. The risk functions of non-randomized rules in Example 1 strategies are the pairs (p, 1 p) for p [0, 1]. The corresponding points in Figure 1 are (i) from (0,3) up to but not including (0.5,1.5) in the upper left, corresponding to p [0, 1/2), (ii) (1,1) in the middle section, corresponding to p = 1/2, and (iii) from but not including (1.5,0.5) to (3,0) in the lower right, corresponding to p (1/2, 1]. The countably-additive randomized rules have risk functions in the convex hull of the set plotted in Figure 1. The resulting set is not closed, and its lower boundary is missing all points on the closed line segment from (0.5, 1.5) to (1.5, 0.5) except (1, 1). One consequence of these points being missing is

3 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 3 that there are many inadmissible rules, corresponding to points just above that line segment, that are dominated by other inadmissible rules, but not dominated by an admissible rule. In other words, the admissible rules do not form a complete class in this problem. If, however, one is willing to introduce finitely-additive randomizations, all of the missing risk functions of admissible rules become available. For example, there are finitely-additive probabilities P and P + on [0, 1] such that P (A) = 1 for every set of the form A = (1/2 ɛ, 1/2) and P + (C) = 1 for every set of the form C = (1/2, 1/2 + ɛ). Every missing point on the line segment between (0.5, 1.5) and (1.5, 0.5) is the risk function of a randomized rule that gives a 1 the distribution αp + (1 α)p + for some α [0, 1/2) (1/2, 1] and sets a 2 = 1 a 1. For example, the risk function for α = 0 is the point (0.5, 1.5) while the risk function for α = 1 is the point (1.5, 0.5). One result (Theorem 1) that we prove in this paper is that every decision problem with a loss function bounded below has a minimal complete class consisting of Bayes rules if finitely-additive randomizations are allowed. There are several complete class theorems in the countably-additive literature that make additional assumptions about the loss function (e.g., continuous, convex) and about the distributions of the available data (e.g., exponential family distributions). Some of these results can be found in Berger and Srinivasan (1978); Brown (1971) and Section 5.7 of Lehmann and Casella (1998). Another of our theorems is a general minimax theorem (Theorem 2) stating that every decision problem with a loss function bounded below has a minimax rule and least-favorable distribution such that all minimax rules are Bayes with respect to that least-favorable distribution. Heath and Sudderth (1972) prove a finitely-additive minimax theorem when risk functions are bounded. Heath and Sudderth (1978) consider cases in which a Bayesian analysis will be performed and the joint distribution of data and parameter can be computed by integration in both orders (a property not possessed by all finitely-additive distributions.) In these situations they present results about Bayes rules and extended admissible rules. Our results also cover cases in which the loss function is allowed to assume the value. An example of such a loss function is the logarithmic loss for predicting events. In the notation of Example 1, replace (I B a 1 ) 2 + (I B C a 2 ) 2 by log(a 1 [1 a 2 ])I B log(a 2 [1 a 1 ])I B C. Dealing with loss functions that assume the value requires special care. In particular, the set of functions that need to be integrated is not a linear space. The paper is organized as follows. We start with a general overview of

4 4 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE decision theory in Section 2. The next three sections give mathematical background needed to prove the main theorems. The background begins with topology and convergence in Section 3. At that point, we have enough tools to give an overview of the theory of integration with respect to finitelyadditive probabilities in Section 4. Because risk functions are integrals of loss functions with respect to various probability distributions, it is necessary to understand what it means to integrate a function with respect to a finitelyadditive probability. The final bit of background includes some results on separation of convex sets of unbounded functions in Section 5. After the mathematical background, we return to results specific to decision theory. Throughout the paper, we assume that the loss function is bounded below. No other assumption is made about the structural parts of the decision problem. Section 6 gives properties of the risk sets of general decision problems involving finitely-additive probabilities and randomizations with loss functions that are bounded below. The first of the main theorems is the complete class theorem (Theorem 1) that appears in Section 7. It states that every decision problem has a minimal complete class of rules consisting of admissible Bayes rules. The second theorem is Theorem 2 in Section 8, which says that every decision problem has a minimax rule and a least-favorable distribution. Also, each minimax rule is Bayes with respect to the least-favorable distribution. Section 9 gives some results on the existence and non-existence of Bayes rules with respect to specific types of priors. 2. General Decision Theory. Table 1 contains some notation that gets used frequently Decision Rules. Definition 1. A non-randomized rule is a function γ : X A. We denote by H 0 the set of all non-randomized rules that the decision maker has available. The risk function of a non-randomized rule δ is the function R(, γ) : Θ IR defined by (1) R(θ, γ) = L(θ, γ(x))p θ (dx). X A randomized rule δ is a coherent prevision on M H0. Its risk function is the function is (2) R(θ, δ) = R(θ, γ)δ(dγ). H 0 A randomized rule δ S M is called simple.

5 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 5 Table 1 Notation used throughout this document. The subscript Z on symbols like M Z, Λ Z, etc. will vary when referring to a specific set like Θ or H 0. Symbol Meaning A The action space X The space where available data take their values Θ The parameter space that indexes the set of data distributions P θ For each θ Θ, P θ is a probability measure on X IR IR { } endowed with the topology consisting of all open subsets of IR together with all sets of the form (c, ) { }. Z A generic set that serves as the domain of a class of IR-valued functions M Z The subset of IR Z consisting of those elements that are bounded below L(, ) The loss function mapping Θ A to IR and bounded below P Z The set of all coherent previsions (see Section 4) on M Z Λ Z The subset of P Z consisting of those coherent previsions that are minimum extensions (see Definition 12) of their restrictions to the bounded functions S Z The subset of Λ Z consisting of the minimum extensions (see Definition 12) of all simple probability measures on M Z, i.e., those supported on a finite set H 0 The subset of A X consisting of all non-randomized rules availble to the decision maker R(, δ) The risk function of a rule δ as defined in (2) R The set of risk functions for all finitely-additive randomized rules R 1 The subset of R whose randomizations are minimum extensions (see Definition 12) Each risk function is an element of M Θ. We can think of a non-randomized rule γ as the special case of a randomized rule δ with δ(a) = I A (γ), for A H 0. With this understanding, (2) is a generalization of (1). The operational understanding of a randomized rule δ is that a decision maker can select a γ from H 0 using an auxiliary randomization with distribution δ. We are deliberately vague about which elements of A X constitute the set H 0. The reason is that our results are general enough to cover whatever set H 0 one wishes to contemplate. One could choose all of A X, or just those rules that are formal Bayes rules with respect to various priors, or whatever subset of A X one wishes. The rules can arise from fixed-sample-size experiments or from sequential experiments. The only structure we assume for the decision problem is that the loss L is bounded below and that all finitely-additive randomizations (as defined in Definition 1) are allowed. Wald and Wolfowitz (1951) described two types of randomized rules. They refer to the randomizations we defined in Defintion 1, leading to risk functions of the form (2), as special randomizatons. They refer to a different kind of randomization, that is common in countably-additive decision the-

6 6 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE ory, as a general randomization. A general randomization is a mapping from X to probability distributions over A. In this manner, the randomization performed after observing a particular x can be virtually unrelated to the randomization that is performed after observing each other x. The theory proceeds by defining (3) L(θ, δ(x)) = L(θ, a)δ(x)(da), A and then inserting (3) directly into (1) to define the risk function of a general randomization δ as (4) R(θ, δ) = L(θ, a)δ(x)(da)p θ (dx). X A Special randomizations are special cases of general randomizations. For the case in which all of the P θ probabilities and all of the general randomizations are countably additive, we prove Lemma 29 (in Appendix A), that states that the risk functions that result from general randomizations are included in the set of risk functions that result from special randomizations. Aside from the restriction to countably additive probabilites, the major difference general and special randomizations involves the orders in which the integrals are performed. For general randomizations, the inner integral is over the randomization with the outer integral over the data distribution P θ. For special randomizations, the integral over the data distribution is inside, and the outer integral is over the randomization. For finitely-additive integrals, the order of integration matters to a larger extent than it does for countably-additve integrals Admissibility, Risk Sets, and Bayes Rules. Definition 2. Let Z be a set, and let f, g IR Z. We say that g dominates f if (i) g(z) f(z) for all z Z and (ii) there is z such that g(z) < f(z). The lower boundary of a subset A of IR Z, denoted L A, is the set of all functions f A such that there is no g A that dominates f. The lower boundary of a set A of functions is defined in terms of the closure of A. If more than one topology is available, one needs to be clear about which closure one is using. The topology of pointwise convergence of functions is always available for a function space since it is the product topology obtained by identifying each function from a space S 1 to S 2 as an element of S S 1 2. If the functions are all bounded, the topology of uniform convergence is also available. Since our results will apply to general function spaces, we will use only the topology of pointwise convergence.

7 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 7 Definition 3. The risk set R is the set of all risk functions of decision rules. A decision rule δ dominates another decision rule δ if R(, δ) dominates R(, δ ). A rule δ is admissible if no other rule dominates δ. A subset C of the set of all decision rules is called a complete class if, for every δ C, there exists a δ C such that δ dominates δ. A set C is an essentially complete class if, for every δ C, there exisits δ C such that R(θ, δ) R(θ, δ ) for all θ. A(n essentially) complete class is minimal if no proper subset is (essentially) complete. For the remainder of this paper, the risk set R is the set of all risk functions of randomized rules as defined in Definition 1. In addition to (as well as related to) the risk function, the Bayes risk of a decision rule with respect to one or several prior distributions is important to decision making. A prior distribution λ over Θ can also be interpreted (as in Section 4) as a coherent prevision on M Θ, hence as an element of P Θ. Definition 4. If δ is a randomized rule, the Bayes risk of δ with respect to λ is the value (5) r(λ, δ) = R(θ, δ)λ(dθ). Let r 0 (λ) = inf δ r(λ, δ). If (6) r(λ, δ 0 ) = r 0 (λ), then δ 0 is called a Bayes rule with respect to λ. Θ 3. Topology Background. Our results rely on the theory of product sets, nets, compact sets, and ultrafilters Product Sets. Definition 5. Let {Z α } α ℵ be a collection of sets, each of which has a topology. The product topology on the product set α ℵ Z α is the topology that has as a sub-base the collection of all sets of the form α ℵ Y α where Y α = Z α for all but at most one α, and for that one α, Y α is an open subset of Z α. If we let Z = α ℵ Z α, then the product set α ℵ Z α can be thought of as the set of all functions f : ℵ Z such that f(α) Z α for all α. If all Z α are the same set Z, then the product set is often written Z ℵ.

8 8 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE Definition 6. Let {Z α } α ℵ be a collection of sets. For each β ℵ, the function f β : α ℵ Z α Z β defined by f β (g) = g(β) is called an evaluation functional or a coordinate-projection function. It is not difficult to show that the product topology has two other equivalent characterizations: (i) the smallest topology such that all of the evaluation functionals are continuous, and (ii) the topology of pointwise convergence of the functions in the product set. Every open set in a topological space is the union of arbitrarily many basic open sets. Each basic open set is the intersection of finitely many sub-basic open sets. Hence, the following result is straightforward. Proposition 1. For every open set N in a product space, there exist a finite integer n, points α 1,..., α n ℵ, and open sets N j Z αj for j = 1,..., n such that N contains (7) {f : f(α j ) N j, for j = 1,..., n}. In particular, every neighborhood of a function g in the product space must contain a set of the form (7) such that g(α j ) N j for j = 1,..., n Nets. Our main use for nets is to identify the closure of a set. Definition 7. A partial order on a set D is a binary relation D with the following properties: (i) for all η D, η D η (reflexive), and (ii) if η D β and β D γ, then η D γ (transitive). A directed set is a set D with a partial order D that has the following additional property: (iii) for all η, β D, there exists γ D such that η D γ and β D γ. Definition 8. Let D be a directed set with partial order D. A function r : D T is called a net on D in T. Such a net is denoted either (D, r) or x = {x η } η D, where x η = r(η) for η D. If {x η } η D is a net, then for each η D, the set A η = {x β : η D β} is called a tail of x. If T is a topological space, we say that the net x converges to x T if every neighborhood of x contains a tail of x. Note that the set ZZ of positive integers is a directed set, and each sequence is a net on ZZ. Every result that holds for all nets holds a fortiori for all sequences. There are nets that are not sequences.

9 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 9 Example 2. Let D be the collection of all finite subsets of an uncountable set X. Create the partial order D on D defined by η 1 D η 2 if η 1 η 2. Notice that η j D (η 1 η 2 ) for j = 1, 2, making D a directed set. Let T be the collection of all indicator functions of subsets of X, and let x η = I η for each η D. It is straightforward to show that {x η } η D converges to I X. It is also easy to see that no sequence of indicators of finite sets can converge to the indicator of an uncountable set. The following results are taken from Dunford and Schwartz (1957). Proposition 2 (I.7.2, p. 27). limits of nets in C that converge. The closure of a set C is the set of all Proposition 3 (I.8.2, p. 32). The product of a collection of Hausdorff spaces is Hausdorff in the product topology. Definition 9. Let x = {x η } η D be a net in a topological space T. We call a net y = {y γ } γ D a subnet of x if there exists a function h : D D with the following properties: (i) y γ = x h(γ) for all γ D, (ii) γ 1 D γ 2 implies h(γ 1 ) D h(γ 2 ) and (iii) for every η D there exists γ D such that h(γ) D η. A cluster point of x is a point p T such that, for every neighborhood N of p and every η D, there exists η D such that η D η and x η N. It is trivial to see that a net is a subnet of itself. If we think of a sequence as a net, then it is also trivial that a subsequence is a subnet. Lemma 1. For a convergent net in a Hausdorff space, there is a unique limit that is also the unique cluster point. Proof. Clearly, the limit of a convergent net is a cluster point. The proof will be complete if we prove that every cluster point equals every limit. Assume to the contrary that there exists a cluster point p that is not equal to a limit p of a convergent net {x η } η D. Let N and N be disjoint neighborhoods of p and p respectively. There exists η 0 D such that x η N for all η D η 0. Because p is a cluster point, there exist η D such that η 0 D η and x η N. But x η N also, which contradicts N N =. Lemma 2. Let x = {x η } η D be a net in a topological space T, and suppose that p is a cluster point. Then there exists a subnet {y γ } γ D of x that converges to p.

10 10 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE Proof. For each neighborhood N of p and each η D, let α N,η D be such that η D α N,η and x αn,η N. Let D = {(N, η) : η D and N is a neighborhood of p}. We show next that D is a directed set. Define D by (N 1, η 1 ) D (N 2, η 2 ) to mean N 2 N 1 and η 1 D η 2, which is clearly transitive and reflexive. If (N 1, η 1 ), (N 2, η 2 ) D, let η D be such that η j D η for j = 1, 2. Then for j = 1, 2 (N j, η j ) D (N 1 N2, η ) D. Let h : D D be h(n, η) = α N,η, which clearly satisfies properties (ii) and (iii) in the definition of subnet. Let y (N,η) = x αn,η for each (N, η) D. To see that {y N,η } (N,η) D converges to p, let N 0 be a neighborhood of p. Then y (N,η) N 0 for all N N 0 and all η D. Lemma 3. same limit. A net converges if and only if every subnet converges to the Proof. The if direction is trivial because the net itself is a subnet. For the only if direction, assume that the net {x η } η D converges to p. Let {y γ } γ D be a subnet with corresponding function h. Let N be a neighborhood of p. Let η N be such that for all η D η N, x η N. Let γ N D be such that h(γ N ) D η N. If γ D γ N, then h(γ) D h(γ n ) η N and y γ = x h(γ) N. The following results are straightforward. Proposition 4. Let x = {x η } η D be a net in a topological space T with a subnet {y γ } γ D. Let f : T V be a function to another topological space V. Then {f(x η )} η D is a net in T with a subnet {f(y γ )} γ D. Proposition 5. Let Z be a set, and let {f η } η D and {g η } η D be convergent nets in IR Z. Let f and g be the respective limits. If f η (z) g η (z) for all z Z and η D, then f(z) g(z) for all z Z Compact Sets. The following results are taken from Dunford and Schwartz (1957). Proposition 6 (I.7.9, p. 29). if every net has a cluster point. A topological space is compact if and only Proposition 7 (I.5.7(a), p. 17). compact. A closed subset of a compact space is

11 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 11 Proposition 8 (I.8.5, p. 32). The product of a collection of compact spaces is compact in the product topology. It is well known that a subset of IR is compact if and only if it is closed and bounded. Lemma 4. subset of IR. For each real number b, set [b, ] is a compact Hausdorff Proof. First, we prove that IR is Hausdorff, hence so is every subset. Let x y IR. If both are finite then the following open intervals (x ɛ, x + ɛ) and (y ɛ, y + ɛ) are disjoint, where ɛ < x y /2. If x < = y, then (x 1, x + 1) and (x + 2, ] are disjoint open intervals. Next, we prove that [a, ] is compact. Let A = {A α } α ℵ be an open cover of [b, ]. Since IR, there exists α 0 ℵ such that A α0 contains a set of the form (c, ]. For the other elements of A, let B α = A α \ { }. Then {B α } α α0 is an open cover of [b, c], which has a finite subcover, because [b, c] is a compact subset of IR. That finite subcover, together with A α0 forms a finite subcover of [b, ] from A. The supremum and infimum are functionals defined on spaces of IR-valued functions. They are not continuous in general, but they do have the following property. Lemma 5. some set Z. Let {f η } η D be a convergent net (with limit f 0 ) in IR Z for If sup z Z f η (z) c η for all η and {c η } η D converges to c 0, then sup z Z f 0 (z) c 0. If inf z Z f η (z) c η for all η and {c η } η D converges to c 0, then inf z Z f 0 (z) c 0. Proof. Consider the claim about the supremum first. The claim is vaccuous if c 0 =. If c 0 <, suppose, to the contrary, that sup z Z f 0 (z) > c 0. Then there exists ɛ > 0 and z 0 Z such that f 0 (z 0 ) > c 0 + ɛ. Because f η converges to f 0, there exists η 0 such that η D η 0 implies that f η (z 0 ) > c 0 +2ɛ/3. Since c η converges to c 0, there exists η 1 such that η D η 1 implies that c η < c 0 +ɛ/3, hence f η (z 0 ) < c 0 +ɛ/3. There exists η 2 such that η j D η 2 for j = 0, 1. Hence, η D η 2 implies both f η (z 0 ) > c 0 + 2ɛ/3 and f η (z 0 ) < c 0 + ɛ/3, a contradiction. A similar argument works for the claim about the infimum.

12 12 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE Lemma 5 has a useful corollary. Corollary 1. Let c IR. Then {f : inf z Z f(z) c} and {f : sup z Z f(z) c} are closed Ultrafilters. Definition 10. Let S be a set and let U be a non-empty collection of subsets of S. We call U an ultrafilter on S if (i) A U and A B implies B U, (ii) A, B U implies A B U, and (iii) for every A S, A U if and only if A C U. An ultrafilter on S is principal if there exists s S such that U consists of all subset of S that contain s. Such an s is called the atom of U. Other ultrafilters are called non-principal. The following result is from Comfort and Negrepontis (1974), and it gives general conditions under which ultrafilters exist. Proposition 9 (Theorem 2.18, p. 39). Let B be a Boolean algebra, and let F B. If F has the finite intersection property, then there is an ultrafilter on B that contains F. Ultrafilters on directed sets are the main ones that we will need. If D is a directed set, then the collection of all tails of D has the finite-intersection property. (Every finite subcollection has non-empty intersection.) By Proposition 9, there is an ultrafilter U D that contains all tails of D. 4. Coherent Previsions Unbounded and Infinite-Valued Functions. De Finetti (1974) laid out the theory of coherent previsions for bounded random variables in great detail. In particular, a finitely-additive probability can be defined on an arbitrary collection of subsets of a general set Z, including the power set. For this reason, measurability conditions are often not included in theorems about finitely-additive probabilities. In this paper, we need an extension of the finitely-addtivie theory from bounded random variables both to unbounded random variables, as was done by Schervish, Seidenfeld and Kadane (2014), and to random variables that assume the value as well. We stop short of defining coherent previsions for random variables that both assume the value and are unbounded below. Definition 11. Let Z be a set, and let F be a subset of IR Z. Let P : F IR { }. An acceptable gamble is a linear combination of the

13 form (8) G(z) = FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 13 n α j [X j (z) c j ], j=1 where each X j F, c j = P (X j ) for each j such that P (X j ) is finite, α j 0 for each j such that either P (X j ) = or there is z such that X j (z) =, and α j 0 for each j such that P (X j ) =. We call P a coherent prevision on F if sup z G(z) 0 for every acceptable gamble G. The conditions involving infinite values are needed to prevent from appearing in the formula for an acceptable gamble. If P is a coherent prevision on F, X F, and X IR Z, then P ( X) = P (X) is coherent with P even if X F and even if P (X) {, }. (Note that such an X could not assume the value.) Indeed, every acceptable gamble that involves P (X j ) = is equal to one with X j replaced by X j, so we could define coherence without allowing previsions in the formula for an acceptable gamble. For a set F containing functions that are all bounded below, a coherent prevision cannot take the value. The following result allows us to extend coherent previsions to sets that are either convex or linear. Proposition 10. Let P be a coherent prevision on a subset F IR Z consisting of functions that are bounded below. Then it is coherent to extend P to the convex hull of F by P (α 1 X α n X n ) = n j=1 α jp (X j ) for all finite n, all X 1,..., X n F and all non-negative α 1,..., α n that add to 1. It is also coherent to extend P to all linear combinations of the form α 1 X α n X n where each X j F satisfies P (X j ) < and α j 0 for each j for which there exists z such that X j (z) =. The extension is P (α 1 X α n X n ) = n j=1 α jp (X j ). For bounded functions, we have the following characterization of coherent previsions. Proposition 11. Let F be a linear space of bounded functions. Then P is a coherent prevision on F if and only if P is a linear functional that satisfies (i) P (1) = 1, and (ii) P (X) 0 for all non-negative X. The following trivial result is useful, but it illustrates the limitations associated with previsions of unbounded functions.

14 14 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE Lemma 6. If F is a set of unbounded functions that are all bounded below, there is a coherent prevision P with P (f) = for all f F. Proof. In (8), every α j 0 is required, hence (8) is unbounded above so long as at least one α j 0. The following result says that a coherent prevision on the set of all bounded random variables can be extended, in one operation, to all random variables bounded below. This is in contrast to the fundamental theorem of prevision, which allows more general extensions, but those more general extensions require that previsions be assigned to new random variables one at a time. Heath and Sudderth (1978, eqn. 1.2) state a similar result without being explicit about the possibility of the extension taking infinite values. Lemma 7. Let J be a linear space of bounded real-valued functions defined on a set Z, and let P be a coherent prevision on J. Let K J be a subset of M Z such that, for each X K and each real m 0, X m J. For each X K, define P (X) = sup P (Y ). Y J, Y X Then P = P on J. Let K 0 be the set of all linear combinations of elements of K J of the form n j=1 α jx j where α j > 0 for each j such that P (X j ) = or such that {z : X j (z) = } =. Define Q(Y ) = n j=1 α jp (X j ) for Y K 0. Then Q is well-defined and is a coherent prevision on K 0. Proof. Because P is coherent, Y X implies P (Y ) P (X) for X, Y J. Hence P (X) = P (X) for X J. Also, P (αx) = αp (X) if α > 0. For this reason, there is no loss of generality in assuming that all α j are 1 or 1. Next, we show that P (X 1 + X 2 ) = P (X 1 ) + P (X 2 ) for X 1, X 2 K. Notice that P (X) = lim m P (X m) because every bounded Y X is bounded above by X m where m = sup z Y (z). Then notice that, for all m, (X 1 m/2) + (X 2 m/2) (X 1 + X 2 ) m (X 1 m) + (X 2 m). The limits of the left-hand and right-hand expressions are both P (X 1 ) + P (X 2 ) while the limit of the middle expression is P (X 1 + X 2 ). Next, we show that Q is well-defined. We need to show that, (i) if X = n j=1 α jx j with α j = 1 for each j such that P (X j ) = or {z : X j (z) = }, (ii) Y = m k=1 β ky k (z) with β k = 1 for each k such that P (Y k ) =

15 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 15 or {z : Y k (z) = }, and (iii) X(z) = Y (z) for all z, then Q(X) = Q(Y ). Rewrite the equation n m α j X j = β k Y k, j=1 by moving all terms with 1 coefficients to the other side. The result has the form Z Z l = W W s, where each Z i is either an X j with α j = 1 or a Y k with β k = 1, and each W i is either a Y k with β k = 1 or an X j with α j = 1. Also, all of the Z i and W i are in K. We just proved that P is additive on K, so k=1 P (Z 1 ) + + P (Z l ) = P (W 1 ) + + P (W s ). Now, move the terms that corresponded to negative coefficients (all of which are finite) back to their original sides of the equation, and we get that Q(X) = Q(Y ). Finally, we prove that Q is coherent. Let K 1 be that part of K 0 where Q is finite and each element of K 1 is real-valued. From what we ve already shown, it follows that, on K 1 (i) Q is a linear functional, (ii) Q(1) = 1, and (iii) Q(X) 0 if X 0. It follows that Q is a coherent prevision on K 1. The only case of gambles not yet covered is that involving both elements of K 1 and functions with infinite prevision and/or functions that take the value. Let Q(X 1 ) =, let Q(X 2 ) be finite, and let X 3 take the value with Q(X 3 ) finite. We need to show that sup z [X 1 (z) c + X 2 (z) Q(X 2 ) + X 3 (z) Q(X 3 )] 0 and sup z [X 1 (z) c + X 2 (z) Q(X 2 )] 0. First, note that sup[x 1 (z) c + X 2 (z) Q(X 2 ) + X 3 (z) Q(X 3 )] = > 0. z Finally, let Y J be such that Y X 1 and > P (Y ) > c. Then, sup[x 1 (z) c + X 2 (z) Q(X 2 )] sup[y (z) P (Y ) + X 2 (z) Q(X 2 )] z z = sup[y (z) Q(Y ) + X 2 (z) Q(X 2 )], z which is non-negative because Y and X 2 are in K 1. Definition 12. We refer to Q in Lemma 7 as the minimum extension of P. If a prevision Q is the minimum extension of its restriction to the bounded random variables, then we say that Q is a minimum extension.

16 16 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE The term minimum extension is used because it assigns the minimum of all possible coherent previsions that are consistent with P to all functions that are bounded below. It is straightforward to see that the measuretheoretic definition of expectation with respect to a countably-additive probability is a minimum extension. Lemma 8. Let X be bounded below. Let P be a minimum extension such that P (X) <. Then P (X) = lim m P [XI {X m} ]. Proof. Since P [XI {X m} ] is non-decreasing in m, it converges to some number c 1 P (X). Hence mp (X > m) converges to c 2 = P (X) c 1 0. We need to prove that c 2 = 0. Assume, to the contrary, that c 2 > 0. Then Also, lim n (9) P (X) 2 n P (X > 2 n ) 2 n 1 P (X > 2 n 1 ) = 1. 2 n 1 P (2 n 1 < X 2 n ). n=1 For each n 1, let d n = 2P (X > 2 n )/P (X > 2 n 1 ). We ve assumed that lim n d n = 1. So P (2 n 1 < X 2 n ) = P (X > 2 n )(1 + ɛ n ) where lim n ɛ n = 0. It follows from (9) that P (X) 2 n 1 P (X > 2 n 1 )(1 + ɛ n ) =, n=1 which contradicts P (X) <. Lemma 9. Let X be bounded below. Let P be a minimum extension such that P (X) <. Let A = {X = }. Then P (XI A ) = 0 and P (A) = 0. Proof. Lemma 8 tells us that P (XI A ) = lim m P (XI A I {X m} ), but I A I {X m} = 0, so P (XI A I {X m} ) = 0 for all m and P (XI A ) = 0. If P (A) > 0, then P ([X m]i {X>0} ) P ([X m]i A ) mp (A), which goes to infinity as m, contradicting P (X) <. Since we make use of Lemma 6 in the proof of Theorem 2, we should note that the coherent prevision in Lemma 6 will not in general be a minimum extension.

17 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 17 Example 3. Let Z be an uncountable set. Then Z contains uncountably many disjoint countable subsets. Let B be an uncountable collection of countable disjoint subsets of Z. For each B B, define the unbounded function f B (z) = j=1 ni B(z n ), where B = {z 1, z 2,...} of Z. The minimum extension of a probability λ on Z assigns positive prevision to f B if and only if λ(b) > 0. At most countably many elements of B can have positive probability, hence at most countably many of the functions f B can have positive (let alone infinite) prevision under the minimum extension of λ Ultrafilter Probabilities. There is a correspondence between ultrafilters and 0-1-valued probabilities. Lemma 10. Let Z be a set, and let F be a field of subsets of Z. A finitely-additive probability P defined on F takes only the values 0 and 1 if and only if (i) P can be extended to P defined on 2 Z and (ii) there is an ultrafilter U of subsets of Z such that P (E) = 1 if and only if E U. Proof. For the if direction, the restriction of P to F takes only the values 0 and 1. For the only if direction, V = {E F : P (E) = 1} has the finite-intersection property, hence there is an ultrafilter U of subsets of Z such V U. Define P (E) = 1 if E U and P (E) = 0 if E U. It is clear that P is finitely-additive on 2 Z. Definition 13. Let U be an ultrafilter of subsets of some set Z. We call the probability P defined by P (E) = 1 if E U and P (E) = 0 if E U the probability corresponding to U. Lemma 11. Let D be a set. Let U be an ultrafilter of subsets of D. Let P be the minimum extension of the probability on D that corresponds to U. Then, for each f M D, f(η)p (dη) = sup inf f(η) = inf sup f(η). B U η B B U η B D Proof. Let k 0 = D f(η)p (dη). Since P (B) = 1 for all B U, Lemma 9 implies that k 0 sup η B f(η), for all B U. Similarly, k 0 inf η B f(η), for all B U. It follows that (10) sup inf f(η) k 0 inf B U η B sup B U η B f(η). If the two endpoints, call them a b, of (10) are not equal, then for each c (a, b) precisely one of {η : f(η) c} or {η : f(η) > c} is in U. If it is the

18 18 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE first of these, it contradicts b = inf B U sup η B f(η). If it the second one, it contradicts a = sup B U inf η B f(η). Hence a = b, and both inequalities in (10) are equality. An alternative expression for D f(η)p (dη) is f(η)p (dη) = sup{x : f 1 ([x, ]) U} = inf{x : f 1 ((, x]) U}. D The proof is similar to the proof of Lemma 11. Lemma 12. Let Z be a set. Let D be a directed set and let f = {f η } η D be a net in M Z. An element g of IR Z is a cluster point of f if and only if there is an ultrafilter U that contains all tails of D whose corresponding probability on D has minimum extension P such that g(z) = D f η(z)p (dη) for all z Z. Proof. For the only if direction, assume first that f converges to g. Let U be any ultrafilter that contains all tails of D, and let P be the minimum extension of the corresponding probability on D. Let h(z) = D f η(z)p (dη) for each z Z. We need to show that, for each z Z and each neighborhood N of g(z), h(z) N. Let z Z. Lemma 11, applied to ultrafilters of subsets of D, says that (11) sup{η : f η (z) B U inf η B f η(z) = h(z) = inf sup B U η B f η (z). If g(z) is finite, let ɛ > 0, and let N be the interval (g(z) ɛ, g(z) + ɛ). Because f converges to g, there exists η D such that f β (z) N for all β D η. Let B = A η = {β D : η D β}, which is in U. It follows that the left and right sides of (11) are respectively at least g(z) ɛ and at most g(z) + ɛ. Hence h(z) N. If g(z) =, let N = (c, ]. Then there exists η D such that f β (z) > c for all β D η. Let B = A η, which is in U. It follows that the left side of (11) is at least c, so that h(z) N. Next, assume that g is merely a cluster point of f. Then there exists a subnet f = {r τ } τ D that converges to g. The previous argument shows that for every ultrafilter U on D that contains all tails of D, g(z) = D r τ (z)p (dτ), where P is the probability that corresponds to U. Let h : D D be the cofinal function that embeds D in D, preserving order. Then r τ = f h(τ), so that g(z) = D f h(τ) (z)p (dτ). Let P be the probability on D induced by h from P. Then f η (z)p (dη) = f h(τ) (z)p (dτ). D D

19 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 19 For the if direction, let U be an ultrafilter that contains all tails of D such that g(z) = D f η(z)p (dη) for all z Z, where P is the minimum extension of the probability on D that corresponds to U. We need to show that g is a cluster point of f. Specifically, we need to show that, for every neighborhood N of g and η D, there exists β D η such that f β N. It suffices to prove this claim for all neighborhoods of the form N = {h : h(z j ) N j, for j = 1,..., n}, for arbitrary positive integer n, distinct z 1,..., z n Z and neighborhoods N 1,..., N n of the form N j = (g(z j ) ɛ, g(z j ) + ɛ) for ɛ > 0 if g(z j ) is finite and N j = (c, ] if g(z j ) =. So, let N be of the form just described, and let η D. We need to find β D such that η D β and f β (z j ) N j for j = 1,..., n. We know that, for all z Z, sup B U inf f β(z) = g(z) = inf β B sup B U β B f β (z). For each j such that g(z j ) is finite, let B j U be such that such that inf f β (z j ) > g(z j ) ɛ, η B j sup f β (z j ) < g(z j ) + ɛ. η B j For each j such that g(z j ) =, let B j U be such that such that inf f β (z j ) > c. β B j If we replace B j by B j A η, all of the last three inequalities above continue to hold. For each j, let β j B j, and let β D β j for all j. Then η D β and f β (z j ) N j for all j. Corollary 2. Let Z be a set. Let D be a directed set and let f = {f η } η D be a net in IR Z. The net f converges to g if and only if for every ultrafilter U that contains all tails of D with corresponding probability on D having minimum extension P, g(z) = D f η(z)p (dη) for all z Z Topology of Coherent Previsions. The set of coherent previsions is a set of functions defined on the space of random variables (functions) under consideration. In general, if Z is a space and we think of M Z as the set of all IR-valued functions that are bounded below, we can think of P Z as a set of functions from M Z to IR. As such, P Z has a product topology, which is also the topology of pointwise convergence. That is, a net {Q η } η D in P Z converges to R if and only if {Q η (f)} η D converges to R(f) for all f M Z.

20 20 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE Lemma 13. Let Z be a set. Let Q = {Q η } η D be a net of coherent previsions on a subset J of M Z. Every cluster point of Q is a coherent prevision on J. Proof. Since every cluster point of every net is the limit of some (possibly different) convergent net, it sufficies to prove the result for limits of convergent nets. Let R be the limit of Q so that, for each J J, lim η Q η (J) = R(J). We show that R is a coherent prevision indirectly. Suppose to the contrary that there are J 1,..., J n J and non-zero real numbers α 1,..., α n and c 1,..., c n and ɛ > 0 such that n α j [J j (z) c j ] ɛ, j=1 for all z Z and such that α j 0 for each j such that R(J j ) = or J j (y) = for some y, and c j = R(J j ) for each j such that R(J j ) <. Since Q η (J j ) converges to R(J j ) for each j, there exists η 0 D such that Q η0 (J j ) R(J j ) ɛ/(n α j ) for all j such that R(J j ) < and Q η0 (J j ) c j for each j such that R(J j ) =. It follows that (12) n α j [J j (z) d j ] ɛ 2, j=1 where d j = Q η0 (J j ) for each j such that R(J j ) < and d j = c j for each j such that R(J j ) =. Since Q η0 (J j ) d j for each j such that Q η0 (J j ) <, the left-hand side of (12) becomes even more negative if we replace each d j by Q η0 (J j ) when R(J j ) = but Q η0 (J j ) <. The resulting inequality implies that Q η0 is incoherent as a prevision for elements of J, a contradiction. Lemma 14. Let Z be a set. Then S Z is dense in Λ Z. Proof. Let λ 0 Λ Z. Let N be a neighborhood of λ 0. Then N contains a basic open set of the form (13) N = {λ Λ Z : λ(f j ) N j, for j = 1,..., n}, where each f j IR Z is bounded below and each N j is a neighborhood of P (f j ) in IR. Define J 1 = {j : λ 0 (f j ) < }, J 2 = {j : λ 0 (f j ) = }.

21 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 21 Without loss of generality, we can assume that there exist ɛ j > 0 for each j J 1 and c j for each j J 2 such that N j = (P (f j ) ɛ j, P (f j ) + ɛ j ) for each j J 1, and N j = (c j, ] for each j J 2. Let ɛ = min j J1 ɛ j and c = max j J2 c j. For each j J 2, there exists m j, such that λ 0 (f j m j ) > c + ɛ. Let a = min j inf z f j (z). Let g j = f j a for j J 1 and g j = (f j m j ) a for j J 2. This makes each g j non-negative. We will find a simple probability measure λ N such that λ 0 (g j ) λ N (g j ) < ɛ for all j J 1 and λ N (g j ) > c a for all j J 2. Since f j g j + a, for j J 2, the above clearly implies that λ N N. Let g = n j=1 g j. Note that λ 0 (g) <. Let m be large enough so that λ 0 (g) < λ 0 (gi {g m} ) + ɛ/3, which exists by Lemma 8. Note that Hence n λ 0 (g j I {g m} ) = λ 0 (gi {g m} ) j=1 ɛ 3 > j J 1 > λ 0 (g) ɛ 3, = n λ 0 (g j ) ɛ 3. j=1 [ λ0 (g j ) λ 0 (g j I {g m} ) ]. Since each λ 0 (g j ) λ 0 (g j I {g m} ), we have λ 0 (g j ) < λ 0 (g j I {g m} ) + ɛ/3 for each j. Let A = {z : g(z) m}. Let l = 3m/ɛ. For each j J 1 and k = 1,..., l, let A j,k = A {z : (k 1)ɛ g j (z) < kɛ}. Then, for each j J 1, A j,1,..., A j,l partitions A. Let B 1,..., B r be the elements of the common refinement of these partitions that satisfy λ 0 (B k ) > 0 for each k. If z k B k for all k, then r λ 0 (B k )g j (z k ) λ 0 (g j I A ) < 2ɛ 3, k=1 for all j. Let z 0 A and B 0 = A C. For E Z, define r λ N (E) = λ 0 (B k )I E (z k ). Then λ N (g j ) = k=0 r λ 0 (B k )g j (z k ) + λ 0 (A C )g j (z 0 ). k=1

22 22 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE Since g j (z 0 ) 0, for each j J 2, we have λ N (g j ) λ 0 (g j I A ) 2ɛ 3 > λ 0(g j ) ɛ > c + ɛ a c a. Because z 0 A, we have 0 g j (z 0 ) g(z 0 ) m. Hence, for j J 1, It follows that, for j J 1, g j (z 0 )λ 0 (A C ) λ 0 (gi A C ) ɛ 3. λ 0 (g j ) ɛ < λ 0 (g j I A ) 2ɛ 3 λ N(g j ) λ 0 (g j I A )+ 2ɛ 3 +g j(z 0 )λ 0 (A C ) λ 0 (g j )+ 2ɛ 3. So λ N (g j ) λ 0 (g j ) < ɛ for all j J 1 and λ N (g j ) > c a for all j J 2 and λ N N. Corollary 2 and Lemma 14 combine to provide the following representation. Corollary 3. Let Z be a set. A coherent prevision λ is in Λ Z if and only if there exists a net {λ η } η D in S Z of simple previsions and a coherent prevision P Λ D corresponding to an ultrafilter on D containing all tails of D such that λ(f) = λ η (f)p (dη), for all f M Z. D 4.4. Order Matters. The following is as close as we come to a Fubini/Tonelli theorem involving finitely-additive integrals. Lemma 15. Let X and Y be sets. Let P be the finitely-additive probability corresponding to an ultrafilter U of subsets of Y. Let Q be a countablyadditive discrete probability on X. Then P [Q] = Q[P ] for bounded functions. Proof. Let A X Y. For each x X, let A x = {y Y : (x, y) A}. For each y Y, let A y = {x X : (x, y) A}. For each x X, P (A x ) = 1 or 0 according as A x U or A x U. Let C A = {x : A x U}. Then Q[P ](A) = Q(C A ). For each y Y, let f A (y) = Q(A y ). Lemma 12 says that P [Q](A) equals the common value of sup B U inf y B f A (y) = inf B U sup y B f A (y). For each ɛ > 0, define D A,ɛ = {y : f A (y) (P [Q](A) ɛ, P [Q](A)+ɛ)}. Note that D A,ɛ U. The preceding analysis applies to every subset A of X Y.

23 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 23 We would like to prove that, for every ɛ > 0, (14) {y : Q(C A ) ɛ f A (y) Q(C A ) + ɛ} U. This would imply that P [Q](A) Q(C A ) ɛ for all ɛ > 0, hence P [Q](A) = Q(C A ) = Q[P ](A). There exists a countable subset {z 1, z 2,...} of X such that j=1 Q({z j}) = 1. Let {x 1,..., x n } be a large enough subset of C A so that n j=1 Q({x j}) > Q(C A ) ɛ. Since each A x U, n A n j=1 A x j U and for each y n A, {x 1,..., x n } A y. It follows that f A (y) Q(A) ɛ for every y n A. Apply the argument immediately above to A C to conclude that f A C (y) Q(CA C) ɛ for all y in an ultrafilter set that we will call n A. Notice that (A C ) x = (A x ) C for all x X. It follows that C A C = CA C and f A C (y) = 1 f A(y) for all y Y. Hence, Q(C A C ) = 1 Q(C A ), and f A (y) Q(C A ) + ɛ for every y n A. The set n A n A U is then a subset of the set defined in (14). Here is an example to show why Lemma 15 has the condition that Q be a discrete countably-additive probability rather than a general countablyadditive probability. Example 4. Let X = {0, 1}, the set of countable binary sequences. Let Q 0 be the distribution a sequence X = {X n } n=1 of independent Bernoulli random variables each with Pr(X n = 1) = 1/2. Let Y be the positive integers, and let P be the finitely-additive probability corresponding to a non-principal ultrafilter U of subsets of the integers. Let E X Y be defined as follows: For each y Y, let E y = {x : x y = 1}, i.e., the set of sequences in which the yth coordinate is 1. Each E y is a measurable set. Set E = y=1 Ey, which is also measurable, and each E y is the y- section of E. For each x X, the x-section of E is E x = {y : x y = 1}, i.e. the subscripts of those terms in the sequence x that equal 1. We will also need to use the set A = {x : E x U}, which is not measurable. To see this, suppose that A is measurable. Then A is in the tail σ-field of the sequence X. By the Kolmogorov 0-1 law, Q 0 (A) {0, 1}. Similarly, A C is in the tail σ-field, so Q 0 (A C ) {0, 1}. But A C = {x : Ex C U} where Ex C = {y : x y = 0}. By the inherent symmetry in the distribution of X, we must have Q 0 (A) = Q 0 (A C ). But we can t have Q 0 (A) = Q 0 (A C ) = 0, and we can t have Q 0 (A) = Q 0 (A C ) = 1, so A is not measurable. It follows that the inner and outer measures of A are not equal, so there is a number c 1/2 that is between the inner and outer measures. By symmetry the interval between the inner and outer measures is symmetric around 1/2, so we can take c > 1/2. Extend Q 0 to the measure Q on the σ-field generated by A and the original domain of Q 0 with Q(A) = c.

24 24 SCHERVISH, SEIDENFELD, STERN AND KADANE The remainder of the example is devoted to showing that P [Q](E) Q[P ](E). First, note that Q(E y ) = Q(X y = 1) = 1/2 for all y Y, hence P [Q](E) = Q(E y )P (dy) = 1 2. Next, note that P (E x ) = I A (x), so Q[P ](E) = P (E x )Q(dx) = X Y X I A (x)q(dx) = Q(A) = c > 1 2. Lemma 16. Under the conditions of Lemma 15, the minimum extension of the common prevision Q[P ] = P [Q] is the iterated integral Q[P ] of the minimum extensions. Proof. The minimum extension of Q[P ] is Q (f) = lim [f(x, y) n]p (dy)q(dx) n X Y = lim [f(x, y) n]p (dy)q(dx) X n Y = f(x, y)p (dy)q(dx), X Y where the second equality follows from monotone convergence and the fact that Q is countably additive. 5. Separation of Convex Sets. The following definition extends some common terms to deal with IR-valued functions. Definition 14. and f IR Z, define Let Z be a set. Let F IR Z be convex. For each p F A p,f,f = {a (0, ) : p + f/a F }. We say that p is an internal point of F if for every bounded f, A p,f,f. If 0 is an internal point of F, define t F (f) = inf A 0,f,F. We call t F the support function of F.

25 FINITELY-ADDITIVE DECISION THEORY 25 Example 5. Let g IR Z and F = {f IR Z : f(z) < g(z), for all z}. Then F is convex and g ɛ is an internal point for each ɛ > 0. In fact, for every ɛ > 0 and every bounded h ɛ, g h is an internal point of F. Functions that get arbitrarily close to g are not internal. Lemma 17. Let g and k be real-valued functions. Let F be a convex set with g as an internal point. Let F be another convex set that contains k. Suppose that f f is well defined for every f F and every f F. Then k g is internal to F F. Proof. Let h be a bounded function. We need to show that there exists a > 0 such that k g + h/a F F. Since g is internal to F and h is bounded, there exists a > 0 such that g + ( h)/a F. Then k [g + ( h)/a] = k g + h/a F F. (Note that none of the arithmetic in this proof involved infinite values.) Lemma 18. Let F be a convex set with 0 as an internal point. Then 1. if f F, t F (f) [0, 1], 2. if f F, t F (f) [1, ], 3. t F (f 1 + f 2 ) t F (f 1 ) + t F (f 2 ) for all f 1, f 2, 4. t F (αf) = αt F (f) for all f and all α > 0, and 5. F F = {f : t F (f) < and t F ( f) < } is a linear space that contains all bounded functions. Proof. Part (i): Let f F. Since f/1 = f, we see that 1 A 0,f,F and t F (f) 1. Part (ii): Let f F. If A 0,f,F =, then t F (f) = > 1. For the rest of the proof of part (ii), suppose that A 0,f,F. Note that f = a(f/a) + (1 a)0 for all a (0, 1]. So f/a F for a (0, 1] and t F (f) 1. Part (iii): The inequality holds if either t F (f 1 ) = or t F (f 2 ) =. For the rest of the proof of part (iii), assume that α j = t F (f j ) < for both j = 1, 2. Let ɛ > 0. Then f j /(α j + ɛ) F for j = 1, 2. Since F is convex α 1 + ɛ f 1 α 1 + α 2 + 2ɛ α 1 + ɛ + α 2 + ɛ f 2 α 1 + α 2 + 2ɛ α 2 + ɛ = f 1 + f 2 α 1 + α 2 + 2ɛ, is in F. Hence t F (f 1 +f 2 ) α 1 +α 2 +2ɛ for all ɛ, which implies t F (f 1 +f 2 ) α 1 + α 2. Part (iv): Let α > 0. For every a > 0 and every f, αf/(αa) F if and only if f/a F, so that A 0,αf,F = αa 0,f,F for all f. Hence t F (αf) = αt F (f).

WHAT FINITE-ADDITIVITY CAN ADD TO DECISION THEORY

WHAT FINITE-ADDITIVITY CAN ADD TO DECISION THEORY WHAT FINITE-ADDITIVITY CAN ADD TO DECISION THEORY By Mark J. Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, Rafael Stern, and Joseph B. Kadane Carnegie Mellon University and Federal University of São Carlos We examine general

More information

ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES

ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES Submitted to the Annals of Probability ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES By Mark J. Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph B. Kadane, Carnegie

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

Metric Spaces and Topology

Metric Spaces and Topology Chapter 2 Metric Spaces and Topology From an engineering perspective, the most important way to construct a topology on a set is to define the topology in terms of a metric on the set. This approach underlies

More information

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi Real Analysis Math 3AH Rudin, Chapter # Dominique Abdi.. If r is rational (r 0) and x is irrational, prove that r + x and rx are irrational. Solution. Assume the contrary, that r+x and rx are rational.

More information

Problem set 1, Real Analysis I, Spring, 2015.

Problem set 1, Real Analysis I, Spring, 2015. Problem set 1, Real Analysis I, Spring, 015. (1) Let f n : D R be a sequence of functions with domain D R n. Recall that f n f uniformly if and only if for all ɛ > 0, there is an N = N(ɛ) so that if n

More information

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 Index Page 1 Topology 2 1.1 Definition of a topology 2 1.2 Basis (Base) of a topology 2 1.3 The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 1.4 Basic topology concepts: limit points, closed sets,

More information

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets 2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets NOTE: AS OF 2008, SOME OF THIS STUFF IS A BIT OUT- DATED AND HAS A FEW TYPOS. I WILL REVISE THIS MATE- RIAL SOMETIME. In this lecture we discuss two

More information

Measure Theory on Topological Spaces. Course: Prof. Tony Dorlas 2010 Typset: Cathal Ormond

Measure Theory on Topological Spaces. Course: Prof. Tony Dorlas 2010 Typset: Cathal Ormond Measure Theory on Topological Spaces Course: Prof. Tony Dorlas 2010 Typset: Cathal Ormond May 22, 2011 Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 The Riemann Integral........................................ 2 1.2 Measurable..............................................

More information

Some Finitely Additive (Statistical) Decision Theory or How Bruno de Finetti might have channeled Abraham Wald

Some Finitely Additive (Statistical) Decision Theory or How Bruno de Finetti might have channeled Abraham Wald Some Finitely Additive (Statistical) Decision Theory or How Bruno de Finetti might have channeled Abraham Wald T.Seidenfeld ------------ Based on our T.R.: What Finite Additivity Can Add to Decision Theory

More information

PROBLEMS. (b) (Polarization Identity) Show that in any inner product space

PROBLEMS. (b) (Polarization Identity) Show that in any inner product space 1 Professor Carl Cowen Math 54600 Fall 09 PROBLEMS 1. (Geometry in Inner Product Spaces) (a) (Parallelogram Law) Show that in any inner product space x + y 2 + x y 2 = 2( x 2 + y 2 ). (b) (Polarization

More information

The weak topology of locally convex spaces and the weak-* topology of their duals

The weak topology of locally convex spaces and the weak-* topology of their duals The weak topology of locally convex spaces and the weak-* topology of their duals Jordan Bell jordan.bell@gmail.com Department of Mathematics, University of Toronto April 3, 2014 1 Introduction These notes

More information

Serena Doria. Department of Sciences, University G.d Annunzio, Via dei Vestini, 31, Chieti, Italy. Received 7 July 2008; Revised 25 December 2008

Serena Doria. Department of Sciences, University G.d Annunzio, Via dei Vestini, 31, Chieti, Italy. Received 7 July 2008; Revised 25 December 2008 Journal of Uncertain Systems Vol.4, No.1, pp.73-80, 2010 Online at: www.jus.org.uk Different Types of Convergence for Random Variables with Respect to Separately Coherent Upper Conditional Probabilities

More information

REVIEW OF ESSENTIAL MATH 346 TOPICS

REVIEW OF ESSENTIAL MATH 346 TOPICS REVIEW OF ESSENTIAL MATH 346 TOPICS 1. AXIOMATIC STRUCTURE OF R Doğan Çömez The real number system is a complete ordered field, i.e., it is a set R which is endowed with addition and multiplication operations

More information

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers Page 1 Theorems Wednesday, May 9, 2018 12:53 AM Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property Suppose is an ordered set with the least-upper-bound property Suppose, and is bounded below be the set of lower

More information

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M.

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M. COMPACTNESS If C R n is closed and bounded, then by B-W it is sequentially compact: any sequence of points in C has a subsequence converging to a point in C Conversely, any sequentially compact C R n is

More information

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then MH 7500 THEOREMS Definition. A topological space is an ordered pair (X, T ), where X is a set and T is a collection of subsets of X such that (i) T and X T ; (ii) U V T whenever U, V T ; (iii) U T whenever

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han Set, functions and Euclidean space Seungjin Han September, 2018 1 Some Basics LOGIC A is necessary for B : If B holds, then A holds. B A A B is the contraposition of B A. A is sufficient for B: If A holds,

More information

The Lebesgue Integral

The Lebesgue Integral The Lebesgue Integral Brent Nelson In these notes we give an introduction to the Lebesgue integral, assuming only a knowledge of metric spaces and the iemann integral. For more details see [1, Chapters

More information

Topology Part of the Qualify Exams of Department of Mathematics, Texas A&M University Prepared by Zhang, Zecheng

Topology Part of the Qualify Exams of Department of Mathematics, Texas A&M University Prepared by Zhang, Zecheng Topology Part of the Qualify Exams of Department of Mathematics, Texas A&M University Prepared by Zhang, Zecheng Remark 0.1. This is a solution Manuel to the topology questions of the Topology Geometry

More information

Extensions of Expected Utility Theory and some Limitations of Pairwise Comparisons

Extensions of Expected Utility Theory and some Limitations of Pairwise Comparisons Extensions of Expected Utility Theory and some Limitations of Pairwise Comparisons M. J. SCHERVISH Carnegie Mellon University, USA T. SEIDENFELD Carnegie Mellon University, USA J. B. KADANE Carnegie Mellon

More information

Metric Space Topology (Spring 2016) Selected Homework Solutions. HW1 Q1.2. Suppose that d is a metric on a set X. Prove that the inequality d(x, y)

Metric Space Topology (Spring 2016) Selected Homework Solutions. HW1 Q1.2. Suppose that d is a metric on a set X. Prove that the inequality d(x, y) Metric Space Topology (Spring 2016) Selected Homework Solutions HW1 Q1.2. Suppose that d is a metric on a set X. Prove that the inequality d(x, y) d(z, w) d(x, z) + d(y, w) holds for all w, x, y, z X.

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.fa] 14 Jul 2018

arxiv: v1 [math.fa] 14 Jul 2018 Construction of Regular Non-Atomic arxiv:180705437v1 [mathfa] 14 Jul 2018 Strictly-Positive Measures in Second-Countable Locally Compact Non-Atomic Hausdorff Spaces Abstract Jason Bentley Department of

More information

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller Real Analysis Notes Thomas Goller September 4, 2011 Contents 1 Abstract Measure Spaces 2 1.1 Basic Definitions........................... 2 1.2 Measurable Functions........................ 2 1.3 Integration..............................

More information

Week 2: Sequences and Series

Week 2: Sequences and Series QF0: Quantitative Finance August 29, 207 Week 2: Sequences and Series Facilitator: Christopher Ting AY 207/208 Mathematicians have tried in vain to this day to discover some order in the sequence of prime

More information

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem Set 2: s Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem 1. (a) Prove that a closed subset of a complete metric space is complete. (b) Prove that a closed subset of a compact metric space is compact. (c) Prove that

More information

4 Countability axioms

4 Countability axioms 4 COUNTABILITY AXIOMS 4 Countability axioms Definition 4.1. Let X be a topological space X is said to be first countable if for any x X, there is a countable basis for the neighborhoods of x. X is said

More information

On maxitive integration

On maxitive integration On maxitive integration Marco E. G. V. Cattaneo Department of Mathematics, University of Hull m.cattaneo@hull.ac.uk Abstract A functional is said to be maxitive if it commutes with the (pointwise supremum

More information

DRAFT MAA6616 COURSE NOTES FALL 2015

DRAFT MAA6616 COURSE NOTES FALL 2015 Contents 1. σ-algebras 2 1.1. The Borel σ-algebra over R 5 1.2. Product σ-algebras 7 2. Measures 8 3. Outer measures and the Caratheodory Extension Theorem 11 4. Construction of Lebesgue measure 15 5.

More information

Quick Tour of the Topology of R. Steven Hurder, Dave Marker, & John Wood 1

Quick Tour of the Topology of R. Steven Hurder, Dave Marker, & John Wood 1 Quick Tour of the Topology of R Steven Hurder, Dave Marker, & John Wood 1 1 Department of Mathematics, University of Illinois at Chicago April 17, 2003 Preface i Chapter 1. The Topology of R 1 1. Open

More information

Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9)

Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9) The University of Sydney School of Mathematics and Statistics Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9) MATH3961: Metric Spaces (Advanced) Semester 1, 2018 Web Page: http://www.maths.usyd.edu.au/u/ug/sm/math3961/

More information

Analysis Finite and Infinite Sets The Real Numbers The Cantor Set

Analysis Finite and Infinite Sets The Real Numbers The Cantor Set Analysis Finite and Infinite Sets Definition. An initial segment is {n N n n 0 }. Definition. A finite set can be put into one-to-one correspondence with an initial segment. The empty set is also considered

More information

Some Background Material

Some Background Material Chapter 1 Some Background Material In the first chapter, we present a quick review of elementary - but important - material as a way of dipping our toes in the water. This chapter also introduces important

More information

S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the. natural numbers together with an infinite maximal almost disjoint family(madf)

S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the. natural numbers together with an infinite maximal almost disjoint family(madf) PAYNE, CATHERINE ANN, M.A. On ψ (κ, M) spaces with κ = ω 1. (2010) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 30pp. S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the natural numbers together with

More information

U e = E (U\E) e E e + U\E e. (1.6)

U e = E (U\E) e E e + U\E e. (1.6) 12 1 Lebesgue Measure 1.2 Lebesgue Measure In Section 1.1 we defined the exterior Lebesgue measure of every subset of R d. Unfortunately, a major disadvantage of exterior measure is that it does not satisfy

More information

Topological properties

Topological properties CHAPTER 4 Topological properties 1. Connectedness Definitions and examples Basic properties Connected components Connected versus path connected, again 2. Compactness Definition and first examples Topological

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

A SECOND COURSE IN GENERAL TOPOLOGY

A SECOND COURSE IN GENERAL TOPOLOGY Heikki Junnila, 2007-8/2014 A SECOND COURSE IN GENERAL TOPOLOGY CHAPTER I COMPLETE REGULARITY 1. Definitions and basic properties..... 3 2. Some examples..... 7 Exercises....9 CHAPTER II CONVERGENCE AND

More information

Spring 2014 Advanced Probability Overview. Lecture Notes Set 1: Course Overview, σ-fields, and Measures

Spring 2014 Advanced Probability Overview. Lecture Notes Set 1: Course Overview, σ-fields, and Measures 36-752 Spring 2014 Advanced Probability Overview Lecture Notes Set 1: Course Overview, σ-fields, and Measures Instructor: Jing Lei Associated reading: Sec 1.1-1.4 of Ash and Doléans-Dade; Sec 1.1 and A.1

More information

JORDAN CONTENT. J(P, A) = {m(i k ); I k an interval of P contained in int(a)} J(P, A) = {m(i k ); I k an interval of P intersecting cl(a)}.

JORDAN CONTENT. J(P, A) = {m(i k ); I k an interval of P contained in int(a)} J(P, A) = {m(i k ); I k an interval of P intersecting cl(a)}. JORDAN CONTENT Definition. Let A R n be a bounded set. Given a rectangle (cartesian product of compact intervals) R R n containing A, denote by P the set of finite partitions of R by sub-rectangles ( intervals

More information

CHAPTER II THE HAHN-BANACH EXTENSION THEOREMS AND EXISTENCE OF LINEAR FUNCTIONALS

CHAPTER II THE HAHN-BANACH EXTENSION THEOREMS AND EXISTENCE OF LINEAR FUNCTIONALS CHAPTER II THE HAHN-BANACH EXTENSION THEOREMS AND EXISTENCE OF LINEAR FUNCTIONALS In this chapter we deal with the problem of extending a linear functional on a subspace Y to a linear functional on the

More information

Indeed, if we want m to be compatible with taking limits, it should be countably additive, meaning that ( )

Indeed, if we want m to be compatible with taking limits, it should be countably additive, meaning that ( ) Lebesgue Measure The idea of the Lebesgue integral is to first define a measure on subsets of R. That is, we wish to assign a number m(s to each subset S of R, representing the total length that S takes

More information

Stone-Čech compactification of Tychonoff spaces

Stone-Čech compactification of Tychonoff spaces The Stone-Čech compactification of Tychonoff spaces Jordan Bell jordan.bell@gmail.com Department of Mathematics, University of Toronto June 27, 2014 1 Completely regular spaces and Tychonoff spaces A topological

More information

A LITTLE REAL ANALYSIS AND TOPOLOGY

A LITTLE REAL ANALYSIS AND TOPOLOGY A LITTLE REAL ANALYSIS AND TOPOLOGY 1. NOTATION Before we begin some notational definitions are useful. (1) Z = {, 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, }is the set of integers. (2) Q = { a b : aεz, bεz {0}} is the set

More information

Notes on Complex Analysis

Notes on Complex Analysis Michael Papadimitrakis Notes on Complex Analysis Department of Mathematics University of Crete Contents The complex plane.. The complex plane...................................2 Argument and polar representation.........................

More information

CHAPTER 9. Embedding theorems

CHAPTER 9. Embedding theorems CHAPTER 9 Embedding theorems In this chapter we will describe a general method for attacking embedding problems. We will establish several results but, as the main final result, we state here the following:

More information

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces Course 212: Academic Year 1991-2 Section 1: Metric Spaces D. R. Wilkins Contents 1 Metric Spaces 3 1.1 Distance Functions and Metric Spaces............. 3 1.2 Convergence and Continuity in Metric Spaces.........

More information

MAT1000 ASSIGNMENT 1. a k 3 k. x =

MAT1000 ASSIGNMENT 1. a k 3 k. x = MAT1000 ASSIGNMENT 1 VITALY KUZNETSOV Question 1 (Exercise 2 on page 37). Tne Cantor set C can also be described in terms of ternary expansions. (a) Every number in [0, 1] has a ternary expansion x = a

More information

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION Introduction to Proofs in Analysis updated December 5, 2016 By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION Purpose. These notes intend to introduce four main notions from

More information

REAL VARIABLES: PROBLEM SET 1. = x limsup E k

REAL VARIABLES: PROBLEM SET 1. = x limsup E k REAL VARIABLES: PROBLEM SET 1 BEN ELDER 1. Problem 1.1a First let s prove that limsup E k consists of those points which belong to infinitely many E k. From equation 1.1: limsup E k = E k For limsup E

More information

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination Answer Key 1 1. [25 points] Let X be a set with 2 or more elements. Show that there are topologies U and V on X such that the identity map J : (X, U)

More information

Supplementary Notes for W. Rudin: Principles of Mathematical Analysis

Supplementary Notes for W. Rudin: Principles of Mathematical Analysis Supplementary Notes for W. Rudin: Principles of Mathematical Analysis SIGURDUR HELGASON In 8.00B it is customary to cover Chapters 7 in Rudin s book. Experience shows that this requires careful planning

More information

CHAPTER I THE RIESZ REPRESENTATION THEOREM

CHAPTER I THE RIESZ REPRESENTATION THEOREM CHAPTER I THE RIESZ REPRESENTATION THEOREM We begin our study by identifying certain special kinds of linear functionals on certain special vector spaces of functions. We describe these linear functionals

More information

Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008

Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008 Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008 October 29, 2008 1 Introduction into proof August 20, 2008 First we will go through some simple proofs to learn how one writes a rigorous proof. Let start

More information

Functional Analysis. Franck Sueur Metric spaces Definitions Completeness Compactness Separability...

Functional Analysis. Franck Sueur Metric spaces Definitions Completeness Compactness Separability... Functional Analysis Franck Sueur 2018-2019 Contents 1 Metric spaces 1 1.1 Definitions........................................ 1 1.2 Completeness...................................... 3 1.3 Compactness......................................

More information

MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction

MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction 1 INTRODUCTION MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, 2014 1 Introduction Definition. If A, B are sets and there exists a bijection A B, they have the same cardinality, which we write as A, #A. If there exists

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Lecture 5 - Hausdorff and Gromov-Hausdorff Distance

Lecture 5 - Hausdorff and Gromov-Hausdorff Distance Lecture 5 - Hausdorff and Gromov-Hausdorff Distance August 1, 2011 1 Definition and Basic Properties Given a metric space X, the set of closed sets of X supports a metric, the Hausdorff metric. If A is

More information

Class Notes for MATH 255.

Class Notes for MATH 255. Class Notes for MATH 255. by S. W. Drury Copyright c 2006, by S. W. Drury. Contents 0 LimSup and LimInf Metric Spaces and Analysis in Several Variables 6. Metric Spaces........................... 6.2 Normed

More information

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS 3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS Definition 3.1 Let X be a topological space. A subset D of X is dense in X iff D = X. X is separable iff it contains a countable dense subset. X satisfies the first

More information

Coherence with Proper Scoring Rules

Coherence with Proper Scoring Rules Coherence with Proper Scoring Rules Mark Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph (Jay) Kadane Mark Schervish Joseph ( Jay ) Kadane Coherence with Proper Scoring Rules ILC, Sun Yat-Sen University June 2010

More information

Non-conglomerability for countably additive measures that are not -additive* Mark Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph Kadane CMU

Non-conglomerability for countably additive measures that are not -additive* Mark Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph Kadane CMU Non-conglomerability for countably additive measures that are not -additive* Mark Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph Kadane CMU Abstract Let be an uncountable cardinal. Using the theory of conditional

More information

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals MATH 02 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS Properties of Real Numbers Some Fundamentals The whole course will be based entirely on the study of sequence of numbers and functions defined on the real

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n 8 CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

MATH 202B - Problem Set 5

MATH 202B - Problem Set 5 MATH 202B - Problem Set 5 Walid Krichene (23265217) March 6, 2013 (5.1) Show that there exists a continuous function F : [0, 1] R which is monotonic on no interval of positive length. proof We know there

More information

Math 118B Solutions. Charles Martin. March 6, d i (x i, y i ) + d i (y i, z i ) = d(x, y) + d(y, z). i=1

Math 118B Solutions. Charles Martin. March 6, d i (x i, y i ) + d i (y i, z i ) = d(x, y) + d(y, z). i=1 Math 8B Solutions Charles Martin March 6, Homework Problems. Let (X i, d i ), i n, be finitely many metric spaces. Construct a metric on the product space X = X X n. Proof. Denote points in X as x = (x,

More information

Chapter 4. Measure Theory. 1. Measure Spaces

Chapter 4. Measure Theory. 1. Measure Spaces Chapter 4. Measure Theory 1. Measure Spaces Let X be a nonempty set. A collection S of subsets of X is said to be an algebra on X if S has the following properties: 1. X S; 2. if A S, then A c S; 3. if

More information

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3 Analysis Math Notes Study Guide Real Analysis Contents Ordered Fields 2 Ordered sets and fields 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts 2 Metric Spaces 3 Metric Spaces 3 Definitions 4 Separability

More information

Suppose R is an ordered ring with positive elements P.

Suppose R is an ordered ring with positive elements P. 1. The real numbers. 1.1. Ordered rings. Definition 1.1. By an ordered commutative ring with unity we mean an ordered sextuple (R, +, 0,, 1, P ) such that (R, +, 0,, 1) is a commutative ring with unity

More information

Based on the Appendix to B. Hasselblatt and A. Katok, A First Course in Dynamics, Cambridge University press,

Based on the Appendix to B. Hasselblatt and A. Katok, A First Course in Dynamics, Cambridge University press, NOTE ON ABSTRACT RIEMANN INTEGRAL Based on the Appendix to B. Hasselblatt and A. Katok, A First Course in Dynamics, Cambridge University press, 2003. a. Definitions. 1. Metric spaces DEFINITION 1.1. If

More information

Maths 212: Homework Solutions

Maths 212: Homework Solutions Maths 212: Homework Solutions 1. The definition of A ensures that x π for all x A, so π is an upper bound of A. To show it is the least upper bound, suppose x < π and consider two cases. If x < 1, then

More information

INTRODUCTION TO REAL ANALYTIC GEOMETRY

INTRODUCTION TO REAL ANALYTIC GEOMETRY INTRODUCTION TO REAL ANALYTIC GEOMETRY KRZYSZTOF KURDYKA 1. Analytic functions in several variables 1.1. Summable families. Let (E, ) be a normed space over the field R or C, dim E

More information

106 CHAPTER 3. TOPOLOGY OF THE REAL LINE. 2. The set of limit points of a set S is denoted L (S)

106 CHAPTER 3. TOPOLOGY OF THE REAL LINE. 2. The set of limit points of a set S is denoted L (S) 106 CHAPTER 3. TOPOLOGY OF THE REAL LINE 3.3 Limit Points 3.3.1 Main Definitions Intuitively speaking, a limit point of a set S in a space X is a point of X which can be approximated by points of S other

More information

Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces

Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces T. C. Dorlas Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies School of Theoretical Physics 10 Burlington Road, Dublin 4, Ireland. Email: dorlas@stp.dias.ie

More information

Exercise Solutions to Functional Analysis

Exercise Solutions to Functional Analysis Exercise Solutions to Functional Analysis Note: References refer to M. Schechter, Principles of Functional Analysis Exersize that. Let φ,..., φ n be an orthonormal set in a Hilbert space H. Show n f n

More information

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University

Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University Lecture Notes in Advanced Calculus 1 (80315) Raz Kupferman Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University February 7, 2007 2 Contents 1 Metric Spaces 1 1.1 Basic definitions...........................

More information

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED PROPER FORCING REMASTERED BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ AND GIORGIO VENTURI Abstract. We present the method introduced by Neeman of generalized side conditions with two types of models. We then discuss some applications:

More information

Convex Optimization Notes

Convex Optimization Notes Convex Optimization Notes Jonathan Siegel January 2017 1 Convex Analysis This section is devoted to the study of convex functions f : B R {+ } and convex sets U B, for B a Banach space. The case of B =

More information

Introduction to Dynamical Systems

Introduction to Dynamical Systems Introduction to Dynamical Systems France-Kosovo Undergraduate Research School of Mathematics March 2017 This introduction to dynamical systems was a course given at the march 2017 edition of the France

More information

EC 521 MATHEMATICAL METHODS FOR ECONOMICS. Lecture 1: Preliminaries

EC 521 MATHEMATICAL METHODS FOR ECONOMICS. Lecture 1: Preliminaries EC 521 MATHEMATICAL METHODS FOR ECONOMICS Lecture 1: Preliminaries Murat YILMAZ Boğaziçi University In this lecture we provide some basic facts from both Linear Algebra and Real Analysis, which are going

More information

Continuous Functions on Metric Spaces

Continuous Functions on Metric Spaces Continuous Functions on Metric Spaces Math 201A, Fall 2016 1 Continuous functions Definition 1. Let (X, d X ) and (Y, d Y ) be metric spaces. A function f : X Y is continuous at a X if for every ɛ > 0

More information

MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER SERIES AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Extra Reading Material for Level 4 and Level 6

MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER SERIES AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Extra Reading Material for Level 4 and Level 6 MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER SERIES AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION Extra Reading Material for Level 4 and Level 6 Part A: Construction of Lebesgue Measure The first part the extra material consists of the construction

More information

s P = f(ξ n )(x i x i 1 ). i=1

s P = f(ξ n )(x i x i 1 ). i=1 Compactness and total boundedness via nets The aim of this chapter is to define the notion of a net (generalized sequence) and to characterize compactness and total boundedness by this important topological

More information

1 Measurable Functions

1 Measurable Functions 36-752 Advanced Probability Overview Spring 2018 2. Measurable Functions, Random Variables, and Integration Instructor: Alessandro Rinaldo Associated reading: Sec 1.5 of Ash and Doléans-Dade; Sec 1.3 and

More information

Def. A topological space X is disconnected if it admits a non-trivial splitting: (We ll abbreviate disjoint union of two subsets A and B meaning A B =

Def. A topological space X is disconnected if it admits a non-trivial splitting: (We ll abbreviate disjoint union of two subsets A and B meaning A B = CONNECTEDNESS-Notes Def. A topological space X is disconnected if it admits a non-trivial splitting: X = A B, A B =, A, B open in X, and non-empty. (We ll abbreviate disjoint union of two subsets A and

More information

7 Complete metric spaces and function spaces

7 Complete metric spaces and function spaces 7 Complete metric spaces and function spaces 7.1 Completeness Let (X, d) be a metric space. Definition 7.1. A sequence (x n ) n N in X is a Cauchy sequence if for any ɛ > 0, there is N N such that n, m

More information

3 Hausdorff and Connected Spaces

3 Hausdorff and Connected Spaces 3 Hausdorff and Connected Spaces In this chapter we address the question of when two spaces are homeomorphic. This is done by examining two properties that are shared by any pair of homeomorphic spaces.

More information

(1) Consider the space S consisting of all continuous real-valued functions on the closed interval [0, 1]. For f, g S, define

(1) Consider the space S consisting of all continuous real-valued functions on the closed interval [0, 1]. For f, g S, define Homework, Real Analysis I, Fall, 2010. (1) Consider the space S consisting of all continuous real-valued functions on the closed interval [0, 1]. For f, g S, define ρ(f, g) = 1 0 f(x) g(x) dx. Show that

More information

Measurable Choice Functions

Measurable Choice Functions (January 19, 2013) Measurable Choice Functions Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ [This document is http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/m/fun/choice functions.pdf] This note

More information

Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018

Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018 Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Ec 181 KC Border Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018 Supplement A: Mathematical background A.1 Extended real numbers The extended real number

More information

Semicontinuous functions and convexity

Semicontinuous functions and convexity Semicontinuous functions and convexity Jordan Bell jordan.bell@gmail.com Department of Mathematics, University of Toronto April 3, 2014 1 Lattices If (A, ) is a partially ordered set and S is a subset

More information

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions Economics 24 Fall 211 Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions 1. Determine whether the following sets are open, closed, both or neither under the topology induced by the usual metric. (Hint: think about limit

More information

LECTURE 6. CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND BASIC TOPOLOGICAL NOTIONS

LECTURE 6. CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND BASIC TOPOLOGICAL NOTIONS ANALYSIS FOR HIGH SCHOOL TEACHERS LECTURE 6. CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND BASIC TOPOLOGICAL NOTIONS ROTHSCHILD CAESARIA COURSE, 2011/2 1. The idea of approximation revisited When discussing the notion of the

More information

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Chapter : Logic Topics:. Statements, Negation, and Compound Statements.2 Truth Tables and Logical Equivalences.3

More information

Annalee Gomm Math 714: Assignment #2

Annalee Gomm Math 714: Assignment #2 Annalee Gomm Math 714: Assignment #2 3.32. Verify that if A M, λ(a = 0, and B A, then B M and λ(b = 0. Suppose that A M with λ(a = 0, and let B be any subset of A. By the nonnegativity and monotonicity

More information

ORBITAL SHADOWING, INTERNAL CHAIN TRANSITIVITY

ORBITAL SHADOWING, INTERNAL CHAIN TRANSITIVITY ORBITAL SHADOWING, INTERNAL CHAIN TRANSITIVITY AND ω-limit SETS CHRIS GOOD AND JONATHAN MEDDAUGH Abstract. Let f : X X be a continuous map on a compact metric space, let ω f be the collection of ω-limit

More information

Math 5210, Definitions and Theorems on Metric Spaces

Math 5210, Definitions and Theorems on Metric Spaces Math 5210, Definitions and Theorems on Metric Spaces Let (X, d) be a metric space. We will use the following definitions (see Rudin, chap 2, particularly 2.18) 1. Let p X and r R, r > 0, The ball of radius

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models

Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models Samuel Trautwein, Esther Röder, Giorgio Barozzi November 3, 20 Topology of Q p vs Topology of R Both R and Q p are normed fields and complete

More information