The cardinal comparison of sets

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The cardinal comparison of sets"

Transcription

1 (B) The cardinal comparison of sets I think we can agree that there is some kind of fundamental difference between finite sets and infinite sets. For a finite set we can count its members and so give it a size 0, 1, 2, 3,... a unique natural number. In this way we see how two finite sets can be equivalent if we don t worry about which members it has. Two finite sets are equivalent, in this sense, if they have the same number of members. It is also obvious that all infinite sets are somehow equivalent. This was an accepted fact 150 years ago (and it still is by many non-mathematicians). For several years Cantor tried to set up an enumeration of R, a bijection N R. Around 1875, after some correspondence with Dedekind and so more thought, Cantor showed that N and R are not equivalent. There are different sizes of infinite sets. After that all hell broke out, although this time I don t think the Pope got involved. In this document we look at the way sets, finite and infinite, can be given a size. Contents 1 The comparison relations Exercises: The comparison relations Problems: The comparison relations The diagonal argument Exercises: The diagonal argument Problems: The diagonal argument The Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem Exercises: The CSB theorem Problems: The CSB theorem The comparison relations A set A is something with elements or members. It also has a family of subsets a A X A and the whole family of these is the power set PA of A. Often a set carries more gadgets to form an algebraic structure, or a geometric structure, or a topological structure, or several other kinds of structures. Here we are concerned solely with the set, its elements, and its subsets. We wish to not distinguish between sets that are in some sense equivalent. How can we make that precise? Each finite set has a given size. It is equivalent to precisely one of the sets {0} {0, 1} {0, 1, 2} {0,..., n} 1

2 using the natural numbers n N. Beyond these we have the infinite sets, and as we will see shortly there are different sizes of such sets. To make that precise we set up some notation and terminology. 1.1 DEFINITION. For two sets A, B we write A B A B if there is at least one function f : A B which is an injection a bijection respectively. These are the cardinal comparison cardinal equivalence relations, respectively. Observe that if A, B are finite sets then the following hold. A B A has fewer members than B (or the same number of members) A B A has exactly the same number of members as B We wish to extend this idea to infinite sets. In due course we will write A B for A B A = B for A B but for the time being we stick to the notation given above. The following result is a simple consequence of the behaviour of functions. The proof is left as an exercise. 1.2 LEMMA. Let A, B, C be arbitrary sets. The following hold. (i) A B = A B (ii) A A (iii) A B = B A (iv) A B C = A C (v) A B C = A C Observe that there seems to be one property missing, namely that A B A = A B for arbitrary A, B. This is true be the proof is not immediate. We return to this later in Section 3. What use is this notion of cardinal equivalence? Intuitively it is seems obvious that any two infinite sets are equivalent. Let s look at some examples of this. 2

3 1.3 EXAMPLES. (a) Consider the set N of natural numbers. 0, 1, 2, 3, 4,..., n,... We use this as a template against which we can measure other infinite sets. (b) Consider the set Z of integers. We can match this against N as follows. 0, 1, 1, 2, 2, 3, 3, 4, 4,... This shows that Z N. A simple calculation show that this enumeration is produced by the function ζ : N Z given by ζ(n) = ( 1) n+1 (n + 1)/2 for each n N. Here is the integer part function. (c) Consider Z Z. We can think of this set as the points in the cartesian plane that have integer components. Then the path (0, 0). shows that Z Z N. There are many other paths through Z Z and some of these can be described by a formula. Although, at the moment I can t think of one. Have a look at Problems 1.7, 1.8, 1.9. (d) Consider the set Q of rational numbers. Each such number has a representation n/d in lowest common form. That is with n Z, d N and where n and d have no common factors (which ensures d 0). Thus each rational can be viewed as sitting on some point in the diagram of (c). There will be some points that don t have a rational friend. However, this shows that Q N. (e) There is a neater enumeration of the rationals. Consider the function f : N N given by f(0) = 1 f(2m + 1) = f(m) f(2m + 2) = f(m) + f(m + 1) for each m N. It doesn t take long to see that for each n N the two consecutive outputs f(n), f(n + 1) are relatively prime. With quite a bit more work it can be shown that N Q n f(n)/f(n + 1) is a bijection. We may look at the details of this later. (f) What about the set of algebraic numbers? We can convince ourselves that this set is equivalent to N, but a proper proof needs some background developments. 3

4 An algebraic number is a (real) root of a polynomial a 0 x n + a 1 x n a n 2 x 2 + a n 1 x + a n with integer coefficients and a 0 0. Each such polynomial has just finite many roots (in fact, precisely n root if we allow multiple roots). Since each such polynomial is determined by its finite list of coefficients, there is an enumeration of all such polynomials. This leads to an enumeration of all algebraic numbers. (g) What about the set R of real numbers? Cantor showed that N R, that is R can not be enumerated as an N-sequence. Later, in Section 3, we will see a quite simple proof of this. Notice that by part (f) there must be a lot of transcendental numbers, a real (or complex) number that is not algebraic. However, it wasn t until around 1850 that an explicit example of a transcendental was produced by Liouville. This was 0 (1/10)n! which, if you write this down as a decimal expansion, you will see what is going on. It was Hermite in 1873 who first proved that e is transcendental, and Lindemann in 1882 proved that π is transcendental. There are still many numbers, such as e + π for which we do not know if they are algebraic or transcendental. Around 500 BC one of the Pythagoreans, called Hippasus, produced the first known non-rational number, namely 2. This caused a bit of a splash. The Pythagoreans, lead by Pythagoras, were a pseudo-religious group who investigated the nature of the world, and mathematics in particular. One of their dogmas was that the world is rational, and the comparison of any two like things could be measured by a rational number. When Hippasus proved that 2 is not rational this gave the Pythagoreans a bit of a quandary. They threw Hippasus off a ship into the sea to drown him, and so prevent the awkward result becoming more well-known. This sets up the problem we look at in this document. We know how to measure the size of a finite set, using the natural numbers. How can we measure the size of an infinite set? To help with this make use of a bit of notation. 1.4 DEFINITION. We say a set A has cardinality ℵ 0 if N A. We sometime write A = ℵ 0 to indicate this. We say a set A has cardinality ℶ 1, or 2 ℵ 0, if PN A. We sometime write A = ℶ 1 to indicate this. More generally, we say two sets A, B have the same cardinality and write A = B if A B, that is there is a bijection between them. Here ℵ 0 is a particular cardinal number, the first in an very long increasing chain ℵ 0 < ℵ 1 <... < ℵ n <... < ℵ ω <... of cardinal numbers. We may look at cardinal numbers in more detail later. There is also another chain of cardinals ℶ 0 = ℵ 0 < ℶ 1 = 2 ℶ 0 < ℶ 2 = 2 ℶ 1 <... 4

5 which corresponds to taking powers sets. As indicated, it is known that ℵ 0 < ℶ 1, and we will prove this in Section 2. It is known that ℶ 1 must fit somewhere in the ℵ-series, but it is not known where. It can be proved that ℶ 1 ℵ ω, but it could be anywhere strictly between ℵ 0 and ℵ ω. It could also be beyond ℵ ω. Later we may look at some of the basics of cardinal arithmetic, and we may be able to show ℶ 1 ℵ ω. I should tell you that the symbol ℵ is the first letter of the Hebrew alphabet. It is now standard notation. In fact, the first four letters ℵ (aleph), ℶ (beth), ℸ (daleth), ג (gimel) of the Hebrew alphabet are now standard AMS LaTeX symbols. However, we don t yet use Cyrillic subscripts, very often. If you ask me I can tell you a story of why the letter ℵ was used. However, I don t know if it is true. 1.1 Exercises: The comparison relations 1.1 Prove the five parts of Lemma 1.2 by exhibiting appropriate functions. 1.2 Recall that for a set A a characteristic function on A is a function χ : A 2 where 2 = {0, 1}. Recall also that for each sets A, B we let [A, B] = [A B] be the set of all functions from A to B. Both notations are useful at different times. (a) Show there is a bijection PA [A, 2] for arbitrary A. (b) Show that if A is finite with m members, that PA has 2 m members. 1.3 (a) For arbitrary sets A, X, Y show the following. (i) PA [A, 2] (ii) If X Y then [X, A] [Y, A] and [A, X] [A, Y ] (iii) [X, [Y, A]] [X Y, A] (b) Show that both N N N and [N, PN] PN 1.4 (a) Show that for each pair A, B of countable sets the cartesian product A B is countable. (b) Show that for each countable set A, each of the sets A 0, A 1, A 2,..., A n,... is countable. Here for each n N the power A n is the set of all n-tuples of elements of A. (b) Show that for each countable set A, the set A of all finite sequences from A is countable. 1.5 Consider Example 1.3(e). Start to write down the suggested enumeration, and see if you can sort out a picture of what is happening. 5

6 1.2 Problems: The comparison relations 1.6 Consider a collection X of subsets of N. (a) Suppose X is pairwise disjoint, that is for X, Y X. Show that X is countable. (b) We say X is almost disjoint if X = Y or X Y = X = Y or X Y is finite for X, Y X. Show that there is such a collection in bijection with S = (0, ) the strictly positive reals. To do that you might want to consider the odd numbers for m N, x S. 1.7 Consider the function where, of course, x, y N. (a) Show the following 2 mx + 1 f : N N Q given by f(x, y) = (x + y)2 + 3x + y 2 (i) f(0, z + 1) = f(z, 0) + 1 (ii) f(x + 1, y) = f(x, 1 + y) + 1 (iii) f(x, y) = f(0, x + y) + x (iv) f(z, 0) = f(0, z) + z for all x, y, z N. (b) Show that (i) f(z, 0) N (ii) f(x, y) N for all x, y, z N. (c) Show that each m N is a value of f. (d) Show that f is injective, that is for each m N there are unique x, y N with m = f(x, y). 6

7 1.8 Consider the integral points N N in the upper right hand quadrant of the cartesian plane R R. Suppose we enumerate these by taking longer and longer downward diagonals, as illustrated Each point (x, y) N 2 is given a position f(x, y). Thus f(0, 0) = 0, f(0, 1) = 1, f(1, 0) = 2, f(0, 2) = 3, f(1, 1) = 4, f(2, 0) = 5, f(3, 0) = 6,... are the first few positions. Show that f(x, y) = (x + y)2 + 3x + y 2 gives the position of a general point (x, y). 1.9 (a) Consider the function f : N N N given by f(x, y) = max{x 2, y 2 } + x + (x y) { x y if y x x y = 0 if x y gives the last component. Write out an explicit description of this function for the two cases. (b) Consider the integral points N N in the upper right hand quadrant of the cartesian plane R R. Suppose we enumerate these by taking larger and larger square, as illustrated Each point (x, y) N 2 is given a position f(x, y). Thus f(0, 0) = 0, f(0, 1) = 1, f(1, 1) = 2, f(1, 0) = 3, f(0, 2) = 4, f(1, 2) = 5, f(2, 2) = 6,... are the first few positions. Show that f is the function of part (a). 7

8 2 The diagonal argument The main aim of this section is to show that the set R of reals is not countable, that is there is no bijection between N and R. This along with several related results is given in Theorem 2.4. Before that we develop some preliminary material for arbitrary sets. Each set A has two associate sets PA [A, 2] = [A 2] its power set and the set of characteristic functions on A. Recall that, as on the right hand side, we use alternative notions for the set of functions from A to 2. This can be useful when there are several other functions around. By Exercise 1.2(a) or Exercise 1.3(a)(i) we know that these two associated sets PA and [A, 2] are in bijective correspondence. That ensures that the analysis we carry out here for one of them is easily transferred to the other. However, it is instructive to see both versions done independently. 2.1 LEMMA. Let A be any set. Then that is there is at least one injection A PA A [A, 2] A f PA A φ [A, 2] from A to the associated set. Proof. (f) The following function will do. A a f PA {a} (φ) Consider any a A and let φ(a) : A 2 be the function given by for arbitrary x A. We have φ(a)(x) = { 1 if x = a 0 if x a φ(a) : A 2 and hence φ : A [A, 2] by releasing a. Thus it suffices to show that φ is injective. To this end consider a, b A with φ(a) = φ(b). Thus a = b is required. But φ(b)(a) = φ(a)(a) = 1 so that b = a, as required. Next we come to the crucial result. This proof of this is quite simple, but it has had an enormous impact on certain areas of Mathematics (and has influenced many people who don t know what they are talking about). Again the result is given in two parts, and each part can be deduced from the other. But again it is instructive to see both versions. 8

9 2.2 THEOREM. Let A be any set and consider any pair of functions. A Then neither is surjective. f PA A φ [A, 2] Proof. (f) Given the function f we must produce a subset D A which is not an output of f. For each x A we know that f(x) A, so the construction x D x / f(x) makes sense to produce some D A. By way of contradiction suppose D is an output of f, that is D = f(a) for some a A. Then a D a / f(a) = D a / D which can not be, and so gives the contradiction. (φ) Given the function φ we must produce a function : A 2 which is not an output of φ. For each x A we know that φ(x) : A 2, so we may also evaluate φ(x) at any y A to produce φ(x)(y) 2 = {0, 1}. Thus we may set (x) = 1 φ(x)(x) to produce : A 2. By way of contradiction suppose is an output of φ, that is = φ(a) for some a A. Then which is the contradiction. (a) = φ(a)(a) 1 φ(a)(a) = (a) As mentioned at the beginning of this section, for each set A the two sets PA and [A, 2] have the same cardinality. We now have the following crucial result. 2.3 COROLLARY. For each set A, the cardinal equivalent sets PA and [A, 2] do not have the same cardinality as A. Given two sets A, B we write A < B if there is at least one injection from A to B, but there is no bijection between the two sets. We say B has strictly larger cardinality than A. We have just seen that for each set A. But now A < PA A, PA, P 2 A, P 3 A,... is a chain of larger and larger sets. When does this end? It doesn t! When A = ℵ 0, that is when A is countably infinite, This chain produces the chain of cardinals ℵ 0 = ℶ 0 < ℶ 1 < ℶ 2 < ℶ 3 <... which goes on for ever, and further than you think. As yet we haven t determined the cardinality of the set R of real numbers. Let s do that now, after a fashion. 9

10 2.4 THEOREM. Each non-trivial interval of R has cardinality ℶ 1 = 2 ℵ 0. Proof. Let I be any non-trivial interval of R. We first observe the following. [0, 3/2] I R PQ [Q 2] [N 2] The first comparison is obtained by an appropriate linear function. inclusion. For the third we send each real r to the rational interval The second is an (, r) Q and observe that this is an injection. The fourth is an instance of the remarks at the beginning of this section. The fifth holds since Q N. Observe that this is a place where the notation [A B] is useful, so we don t get [A, B] confused with a real interval. Given these comparisons it is now sufficient to produce an injection f : [N 2] [0, 3/2] and this is where the choice of 3/2 becomes useful. For each f : N 2 consider the following series. x f = {f(r)3 r r < ω} This is a series of positive terms and, since each f(r) {0, 1}, we have 0 {3 r r < ω} = 3/2 to show that the series converges. Thus we have a function [N 2] [0, 3/2] x x f and it suffices to check that this is injective. Consider f, g [N 2] with x f = x g. We require f = g. To this end, for each r N let a r = f(r) g(r) so that a r { 1, 0, 1}, and we require a r = 0. Consider the following series. {ar 3 r r < ω} This has value x f x g which is 0. Since a r 1 the series is absolutely convergent. This gives a 0 = {a r 3 r 0 < r < ω} { a r 3 r 0 < r < ω} {3 r 0 < r < ω} = 1/2 so that to give a 0 = 0. a 0 { 1, 0, 1} 1/2 a 0 1/2 10

11 A repeat of this argument now gives a n = 0 by induction on n. Thus f = g, as required. The crucial results of this and the previous section is that Q is countable, but R is not. We have Q = ℵ 0 R = ℶ 1 where we know that ℵ 0 < ℵ 1 ℶ 1. The standard axioms of Axiomatic Set Theory tell us very little about the size of ℶ 1. Some people, such as Gödel, believe that ℶ 1 = ℵ 1, and it seems that some people now believe that ℶ 1 = ℵ 2. If that is not the case then what is the value of ℶ 1. As we move up the possible values ℵ 1, ℵ 1, ℵ 3,..., ℵ 42,... these seem to get less and less likely. If ℶ 1 ℵ 1 then the next most likely value seems to be ℵ ω. But there is a quite simple proof that this can not be the value. What is going on? Is someone having us on? 2.1 Exercises: The diagonal argument 2.1 Consider the proof of Lemma 2.1. How are the two functions f and φ related? 2.2 Consider the (missing) proof of the last part of Theorem 2.4. Using an induction on n, or otherwise, fill in this missing argument. 2.3 This continues Exercise 1.4 (a) Show that the set of all real algebraic numbers is countable. (b) Show that N (0, 1) and that (0, 1) is not countable. (c) Show that there is at least one transcendental number. (d) Can you exhibit a transcendental number and prove that it is transcendental. 2.2 Problems: The diagonal argument 2.4 Let A be the set of all monotone (increasing) ω-sequences of natural numbers. For we say if a = (a n n < ω) b = (b n n < ω) a is dominated by b or b dominates a a n /b n 0 as n holds. Let f : N A be an arbitrary function. (a) Let d n = max{f(0) n, f(1) n,..., f(n) n } for each n N. Show that d = (d m n < ω) is a member of A. 11

12 (b) Show that for arbitrary m N and a A, if b = f(m) dominates a then we have 2a n < b n d n for almost all n, that is for all sufficiently large n. (c) Show that no sequence f(m) dominates d. (d) Show that there is no countable B A such that each a A is dominated by some b B. 2.5 Calculate the cardinality of each of the following. (i) The set of real sequence, that is the set of ω-sequences of real numbers. (ii) The set of convergent real sequences. (iii) The set of real sequences with a convergent series. (iv) The set of continuous real functions R R. (v) Any set of pairwise disjoint non-trivial real intervals. (vi) The set of discontinuities of any monotone function R R. 2.6 Let {A n n N} be an increasing chain of sets with union A. A 0 A 1 A n A = {A n n N} Suppose also that for each n N there is no surjective function A n A. Now let φ : A [N A] be an arbitrary function. For each n N let to obtain a family of subsets of A. X n = {φ(a)(n) a A n } (i) Show that each X n is a proper subset of A. (ii) Show that if f φ[a] then f(n) X n for at least one n N. (iii) Show that φ is not surjective. 2.7 By making use of Problem 2.6 show that the cardinality of PN can not be ℵ λ for any countable limit ordinal λ. If you are not sure what such a λ is, then take the particular case λ = ω. 3 The Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem We have two comparisons between sets A B A B given by the existence of an injection a bijection respectively. These are designed to capture the informal notions A is no bigger than B A has the same size as B 12

13 where it is the number of elements we are trying to measure. It ought to be the case that A B and B A = A B but this is by no means obvious. In this section we prove that this implication does hold. The result has various names attached to it, usually referring to two of the three people in the title of this section. In Levy Basic set theory page 85 it is stated that the result was proved by Dedekind in 1887, conjectured by Cantor in 1895, and proved by Bernstein in Those dates look a bit dodgy. In Temple 100 years of mathematics page 32 it is stated that the result was proved independently by Schröder in 1896 and Bernstein in I have been told by others that Cantor suggested the idea, Schröder wrote the words, and Bernstein set it to music. But I m not sure I believe that one. The aim of this section is to prove the following. 3.1 THEOREM. Consider a pair of injections f A B g between two sets going in opposite directions. Then there is a bijection h : A B between the sets. Furthermore, such a bijection h can be built from parts of the two given injections f, g. Proof. We partition each set into two parts in a way that the restrictions of f, g become bijections. A = A + A B = B + B A + f + B A g+ B + A = g[b + ] B = f[a + ] f + = f A+ g + = g B + Let h + = f + and let h be the inverse of g +. We thus have two bijections h + : A + B h : A B + between disjoint sets. We let h = h + h to obtain the required bijection between the given sets. Of course, this proof is not complete. How do we know that such a partition exists? In fact, that is probably the more interesting part of the result. In the remainder of this section we show how such a partition can be produced. 13

14 We are given a pair of injections f, g between two sets A, B and we wish to find partitions such that each of the two restrictions is a bijection. One way to achieve that is to use a simple fixed point construction. However, here it is a fixed set construction. We work on the power set PA of A and combine the two given functions f and g into one function H : PA PA on subsets of A. For each subset X A we put H(X) = A g[b f[x]] to produce another subset of A. Observe how H produces the output H(X). For the input X A we take the image of X across f to obtain a subset f[x] B on the other side. We take the complement of that in B to obtain B f[x]. We pass that back to A using g to obtain g[b f[x]] A. We take the complement of that in A to obtain H(X). We want to find some X A which is fixed by H, that is H(X) = X. In general the input X and the output H(X) have no relationship with each other. However, H does track variations of X. 3.2 LEMMA. The function H is monotone, that is for U, X A. U X = H(U) H(X) Proof. Consider U, X A with U X. Then so that by taking complements in B. But now f[u] f[x] B f[x] B f[u] g[b f[x]] g[b f[u]] so that by taking complements in A. H(U) H(X) To find a fixed set we look at those subsets that are inflated by H. 3.3 DEFINITION. Let U be the collections of those sets U A with U H(U). 14

15 Trivially, we have U. In some circumstances this could be the only member of U. The trick is to look for a maximal member of U. To do that we let L = U so that any maximal member of U is a subset of L. In fact, we get more than that. 3.4 LEMMA. We have L H(L), so that L U. Proof. Consider any U U. Then U L, so that since H is monotone. But now to give the required result. U H(U) H(L) L = U H(L) This shows that L is a special member of U. It is the unique maximum member of U. It also has another special relationship with H. 3.5 LEMMA. We have H(L) = L. Proof. We already know that L H(L), so it suffices to verify the converse inclusion. But this known inclusion gives H(L) H ( H(L) ) since H is monotone. This ensures that H(L) U, and hence H(L) L by the definition of L. This show that H has at least one fixed set. To obtain the required partition we can use any fixed set. 3.6 DEFINITION. Let A + be any fixed set of H. We put to obtain partitions of A and B. A = A A = B = f[a + ] B + = B B We could try to carry out this construction starting with any subset A + A. However, it is the fixed set property that gives us the conditions we want. 3.7 LEMMA. Let A + be any fixed set of H. Then holds. f[a + ] = B g[b + ] = A Proof. The left hand equality is given by the construction. We must verify the right hand equality. But so that as required. A + = H(A + ) = A g[b f[a + ]] = A g[b B ] = A g[b + ] A = A A + = g[b + ] This completes the proof of Theorem

16 3.1 Exercises: The CSB theorem 3.1 Consider the first proof of the CSB result. There may be many fixed sets of the function H. (a) Show that the example produced L is the largest fixed set, that is if F is any fixed set then F L. (b) Show there is a smallest fixed set. 3.2 This exercise produces a generalization of the constructions and results of Exercise 3.1. Let (P, ) be any linearly ordered set. Suppose this linear set is complete, that is for each X P the supremum X and the infimum X exist. Recall that the supremum is just the least upper bound, and the infimum is the greatest lower bound. For instance, the real interval [0.1] is an example of such a set. Let h : P P a monotone function on P, that is x y = h(x) h(y) for all x, y P. An element a P is a fixed point (or a fixed element) of h if h(a) = a. (a) Show that h has a largest and a smallest fixed point. (b) Find examples where h has precisely 1,2,3,4,... fixed points. (c) Using P = [0, 1], the real interval, how many fixed points do you think h can have (provided h is not the identity function). 3.2 Problems: The CSB theorem 3.3 (a) Suppose A, B, C are three sets with A B C, A B = and where A, B have cardinality ℵ 0. Show that C A = C. (b) Show that if A R is countably infinite, then R A = ℶ 1. (c) What is the cardinality of the set I of irrationals? 16

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS BJORN POONEN 1 Some terminology of set theory N := {0, 1, 2, 3, } Z := {, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, } Q := the set of rational numbers R := the set of real numbers C := the set of complex

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

1 of 8 7/15/2009 3:43 PM Virtual Laboratories > 1. Foundations > 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 6. Cardinality Definitions and Preliminary Examples Suppose that S is a non-empty collection of sets. We define a relation

More information

(D) Introduction to order types and ordinals

(D) Introduction to order types and ordinals (D) Introduction to order types and ordinals Linear orders are one of the mathematical tools that are used all over the place. Well-ordered sets are a special kind of linear order. At first sight well-orders

More information

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id: Name: Student Id: There are nine problems (check that you have 9 pages). Solutions are expected to be short. In the case of proofs, one or two short paragraphs should be the average length. Write your

More information

Part IA Numbers and Sets

Part IA Numbers and Sets Part IA Numbers and Sets Definitions Based on lectures by A. G. Thomason Notes taken by Dexter Chua Michaelmas 2014 These notes are not endorsed by the lecturers, and I have modified them (often significantly)

More information

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting Countability 1 Motivation In topology as well as other areas of mathematics, we deal with a lot of infinite sets. However, as we will gradually discover, some infinite sets are bigger than others. Countably

More information

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Chapter : Logic Topics:. Statements, Negation, and Compound Statements.2 Truth Tables and Logical Equivalences.3

More information

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. MAT 200, Logic, Language and Proof, Fall 2015 Summary Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. Definition. A proposition is a sentence which is either true or false. Truth table for the connective or :

More information

LECTURE 22: COUNTABLE AND UNCOUNTABLE SETS

LECTURE 22: COUNTABLE AND UNCOUNTABLE SETS LECTURE 22: COUNTABLE AND UNCOUNTABLE SETS 1. Introduction To end the course we will investigate various notions of size associated to subsets of R. The simplest example is that of cardinality - a very

More information

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW 1. Sets As a review, we begin by considering a naive look at set theory. For our purposes, we define a set as a collection of objects. Except for certain sets like N, Z,

More information

Mathematics 220 Workshop Cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality.

Mathematics 220 Workshop Cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality. These are two series of problems with specific goals: the first goal is to prove that the cardinality of the set of irrational numbers is continuum, and the second

More information

Infinite constructions in set theory

Infinite constructions in set theory VI : Infinite constructions in set theory In elementary accounts of set theory, examples of finite collections of objects receive a great deal of attention for several reasons. For example, they provide

More information

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY About the Class Evaluation. Final grade will be based 25%, 25%, 25%, 25%, on homework, midterm 1, midterm 2, final exam. Exam dates. Midterm 1: Oct 4. Midterm 2:

More information

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction (David Ross, UH-Manoa Dept. of Mathematics) 1 Cardinality Recall the following notions: function, relation, one-to-one, onto, on-to-one correspondence,

More information

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 1 Real Numbers In these lectures, we are going to study a branch of mathematics called

More information

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS 1. Cardinal number of a set The cardinal number (or simply cardinal) of a set is a generalization of the concept of the number of elements

More information

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability Highlights What is cardinality? Is it the same as size? Types of cardinality and infinite sets Reading Sections 45 and 81 84 of Mathematics

More information

Basic material. We make use of the standard families of numbers. These now have standard names.

Basic material. We make use of the standard families of numbers. These now have standard names. (A) Basic material In this document we set down all the basic material you should already know, together with some notation and terminology. Of course, there are different terminologies and notations for

More information

Finite and Infinite Sets

Finite and Infinite Sets Chapter 9 Finite and Infinite Sets 9. Finite Sets Preview Activity (Equivalent Sets, Part ). Let A and B be sets and let f be a function from A to B..f W A! B/. Carefully complete each of the following

More information

Meta-logic derivation rules

Meta-logic derivation rules Meta-logic derivation rules Hans Halvorson February 19, 2013 Recall that the goal of this course is to learn how to prove things about (as opposed to by means of ) classical first-order logic. So, we will

More information

What is proof? Lesson 1

What is proof? Lesson 1 What is proof? Lesson The topic for this Math Explorer Club is mathematical proof. In this post we will go over what was covered in the first session. The word proof is a normal English word that you might

More information

Algorithms: Lecture 2

Algorithms: Lecture 2 1 Algorithms: Lecture 2 Basic Structures: Sets, Functions, Sequences, and Sums Jinwoo Kim jwkim@jjay.cuny.edu 2.1 Sets 2 1 2.1 Sets 3 2.1 Sets 4 2 2.1 Sets 5 2.1 Sets 6 3 2.1 Sets 7 2.2 Set Operations

More information

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Chapter One. The Real Number System Chapter One. The Real Number System We shall give a quick introduction to the real number system. It is imperative that we know how the set of real numbers behaves in the way that its completeness and

More information

Introduction to Proofs

Introduction to Proofs Introduction to Proofs Notes by Dr. Lynne H. Walling and Dr. Steffi Zegowitz September 018 The Introduction to Proofs course is organised into the following nine sections. 1. Introduction: sets and functions

More information

A Short Review of Cardinality

A Short Review of Cardinality Christopher Heil A Short Review of Cardinality November 14, 2017 c 2017 Christopher Heil Chapter 1 Cardinality We will give a short review of the definition of cardinality and prove some facts about the

More information

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) VI.1 : Indexed families and set theoretic operations (Halmos, 4, 8 9; Lipschutz, 5.3 5.4) Lipschutz : 5.3 5.6, 5.29 5.32, 9.14 1. Generalize

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. IAN KIMING 1. Motivation. It will not come as a big surprise to anyone when I say that we need the real numbers in mathematics. More to the point, we need to be able to

More information

Notes on counting. James Aspnes. December 13, 2010

Notes on counting. James Aspnes. December 13, 2010 Notes on counting James Aspnes December 13, 2010 1 What counting is Recall that in set theory we formally defined each natural number as the set of all smaller natural numbers, so that n = {0, 1, 2,...,

More information

The Two Faces of Infinity Dr. Bob Gardner Great Ideas in Science (BIOL 3018)

The Two Faces of Infinity Dr. Bob Gardner Great Ideas in Science (BIOL 3018) The Two Faces of Infinity Dr. Bob Gardner Great Ideas in Science (BIOL 3018) From the webpage of Timithy Kohl, Boston University INTRODUCTION Note. We will consider infinity from two different perspectives:

More information

One-to-one functions and onto functions

One-to-one functions and onto functions MA 3362 Lecture 7 - One-to-one and Onto Wednesday, October 22, 2008. Objectives: Formalize definitions of one-to-one and onto One-to-one functions and onto functions At the level of set theory, there are

More information

Cardinality and ordinal numbers

Cardinality and ordinal numbers Cardinality and ordinal numbers The cardinality A of a finite set A is simply the number of elements in it. When it comes to infinite sets, we no longer can speak of the number of elements in such a set.

More information

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant).

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant). Sets and Functions 1. The language of sets Informally, a set is any collection of objects. The objects may be mathematical objects such as numbers, functions and even sets, or letters or symbols of any

More information

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers Chapter The Real Numbers.. Some Preliminaries Discussion: The Irrationality of 2. We begin with the natural numbers N = {, 2, 3, }. In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend

More information

Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases

Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases September 22, 2018 Recall from last week that the purpose of a proof

More information

Definition: Let S and T be sets. A binary relation on SxT is any subset of SxT. A binary relation on S is any subset of SxS.

Definition: Let S and T be sets. A binary relation on SxT is any subset of SxT. A binary relation on S is any subset of SxS. 4 Functions Before studying functions we will first quickly define a more general idea, namely the notion of a relation. A function turns out to be a special type of relation. Definition: Let S and T be

More information

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005 POL502: Foundations Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University October 10, 2005 Our first task is to develop the foundations that are necessary for the materials covered in this course. 1

More information

Discrete Mathematics 2007: Lecture 5 Infinite sets

Discrete Mathematics 2007: Lecture 5 Infinite sets Discrete Mathematics 2007: Lecture 5 Infinite sets Debrup Chakraborty 1 Countability The natural numbers originally arose from counting elements in sets. There are two very different possible sizes for

More information

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014 Functions and cardinality (solutions) 21-127 sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014 What follows is a somewhat hastily written collection of solutions for my review sheet. I have omitted some

More information

(C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets. Contents. 1 The characterizing results

(C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets. Contents. 1 The characterizing results (C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets We know that both Q and R are something special. When we think about about either o these we usually view it as a ield, or at least some kind o

More information

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION Introduction to Proofs in Analysis updated December 5, 2016 By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION Purpose. These notes intend to introduce four main notions from

More information

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES NATHANIEL GALLUP 1. Introduction Number theory begins as the study of the natural numbers the integers N = {1, 2, 3,...}, Z = { 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3,...}, and sometimes

More information

A Readable Introduction to Real Mathematics

A Readable Introduction to Real Mathematics Solutions to selected problems in the book A Readable Introduction to Real Mathematics D. Rosenthal, D. Rosenthal, P. Rosenthal Chapter 10: Sizes of Infinite Sets 1. Show that the set of all polynomials

More information

Sets are one of the basic building blocks for the types of objects considered in discrete mathematics.

Sets are one of the basic building blocks for the types of objects considered in discrete mathematics. Section 2.1 Introduction Sets are one of the basic building blocks for the types of objects considered in discrete mathematics. Important for counting. Programming languages have set operations. Set theory

More information

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers Chapter 1 The Real Numbers 1.1. Some Preliminaries Discussion: The Irrationality of 2. We begin with the natural numbers N = {1, 2, 3, }. In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need

More information

1. A Little Set Theory

1. A Little Set Theory . A Little Set Theory I see it, but I don t believe it. Cantor to Dedekind 29 June 877 Functions are the single most important idea pervading modern mathematics. We will assume the informal definition

More information

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017 MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017 Definition: A set A is finite if there exists a nonnegative integer c such that there exists a bijection from A

More information

Section 0. Sets and Relations

Section 0. Sets and Relations 0. Sets and Relations 1 Section 0. Sets and Relations NOTE. Mathematics is the study of ideas, not of numbers!!! The idea from modern algebra which is the focus of most of this class is that of a group

More information

Basic counting techniques. Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School

Basic counting techniques. Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School Basic counting techniques Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School i LECTURE NOTES IN Elementary counting methods Periklis A. Papakonstantinou MSIS, Rutgers Business School ALL RIGHTS RESERVED

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B).

2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B). 2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B). 2.24 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. Then L(A B) = L(A) L(B). It is worth noting that you can t replace union

More information

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals MATH 02 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS Properties of Real Numbers Some Fundamentals The whole course will be based entirely on the study of sequence of numbers and functions defined on the real

More information

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u.

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u. 5. Fields 5.1. Field extensions. Let F E be a subfield of the field E. We also describe this situation by saying that E is an extension field of F, and we write E/F to express this fact. If E/F is a field

More information

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero Chapter Limits of Sequences Calculus Student: lim s n = 0 means the s n are getting closer and closer to zero but never gets there. Instructor: ARGHHHHH! Exercise. Think of a better response for the instructor.

More information

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted Chapter 2 The Structure of R The purpose of this chapter is to explain to the reader why the set of real numbers is so special. By the end of this chapter, the reader should understand the difference between

More information

Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008

Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008 Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008 October 29, 2008 1 Introduction into proof August 20, 2008 First we will go through some simple proofs to learn how one writes a rigorous proof. Let start

More information

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity Math/CS 20: Intro. to Math Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity Week 2 UCSB 204 Sizes of Infinity On one hand, we know that the real numbers contain more elements than the rational

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS Article A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS Juan Pablo Ramírez 0000-0002-4912-2952 Abstract: We present the real number system as a generalization of the natural numbers. First, we prove the co-finite topology,

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

586 Index. vertex, 369 disjoint, 236 pairwise, 272, 395 disjoint sets, 236 disjunction, 33, 36 distributive laws

586 Index. vertex, 369 disjoint, 236 pairwise, 272, 395 disjoint sets, 236 disjunction, 33, 36 distributive laws Index absolute value, 135 141 additive identity, 254 additive inverse, 254 aleph, 465 algebra of sets, 245, 278 antisymmetric relation, 387 arcsine function, 349 arithmetic sequence, 208 arrow diagram,

More information

Chapter 20. Countability The rationals and the reals. This chapter covers infinite sets and countability.

Chapter 20. Countability The rationals and the reals. This chapter covers infinite sets and countability. Chapter 20 Countability This chapter covers infinite sets and countability. 20.1 The rationals and the reals You re familiar with three basic sets of numbers: the integers, the rationals, and the reals.

More information

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations D. R. Wilkins Academic Year 1996-7 1 Number Systems and Matrix Algebra Integers The whole numbers 0, ±1, ±2, ±3, ±4,...

More information

Prof. Ila Varma HW 8 Solutions MATH 109. A B, h(i) := g(i n) if i > n. h : Z + f((i + 1)/2) if i is odd, g(i/2) if i is even.

Prof. Ila Varma HW 8 Solutions MATH 109. A B, h(i) := g(i n) if i > n. h : Z + f((i + 1)/2) if i is odd, g(i/2) if i is even. 1. Show that if A and B are countable, then A B is also countable. Hence, prove by contradiction, that if X is uncountable and a subset A is countable, then X A is uncountable. Solution: Suppose A and

More information

X = { X f X i A i : (œx, y 0 X)[x /= y œi[ x i /= y i ]]}.

X = { X f X i A i : (œx, y 0 X)[x /= y œi[ x i /= y i ]]}. CARDINALS II James T. Smith San Francisco State University These notes develop the part of cardinal arithmetic that depends on the axiom of choice. The first result is the comparability theorem: every

More information

Foundations of Mathematics

Foundations of Mathematics Foundations of Mathematics L. Pedro Poitevin 1. Preliminaries 1.1. Sets We will naively think of a set as a collection of mathematical objects, called its elements or members. To indicate that an object

More information

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University Sets, Models and Proofs I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University 2000; revised, 2006 Contents 1 Sets 1 1.1 Cardinal Numbers........................ 2 1.1.1 The Continuum

More information

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009 Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009 Our main goal is here is to do counting using functions. For that, we

More information

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability 1 Motivation Up to now we have been mentioning the notion of sequence convergence without actually defining it. So in this section we will

More information

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets Introduction In this short article, we will describe some basic notions on cardinality of sets. Given two

More information

Extended Essay - Mathematics

Extended Essay - Mathematics Extended Essay - Mathematics Creating a Model to Separate or Group Number Sets by their Cardinalities Pope John Paul II C.S.S. September 2009 Candidate Number: 001363-012 The conquest of the actual infinite

More information

Part IA Numbers and Sets

Part IA Numbers and Sets Part IA Numbers and Sets Theorems Based on lectures by A. G. Thomason Notes taken by Dexter Chua Michaelmas 2014 These notes are not endorsed by the lecturers, and I have modified them (often significantly)

More information

Math 300: Final Exam Practice Solutions

Math 300: Final Exam Practice Solutions Math 300: Final Exam Practice Solutions 1 Let A be the set of all real numbers which are zeros of polynomials with integer coefficients: A := {α R there exists p(x) = a n x n + + a 1 x + a 0 with all a

More information

Solutions Manual for: Understanding Analysis, Second Edition. Stephen Abbott Middlebury College

Solutions Manual for: Understanding Analysis, Second Edition. Stephen Abbott Middlebury College Solutions Manual for: Understanding Analysis, Second Edition Stephen Abbott Middlebury College June 25, 2015 Author s note What began as a desire to sketch out a simple answer key for the problems in Understanding

More information

Some Background Material

Some Background Material Chapter 1 Some Background Material In the first chapter, we present a quick review of elementary - but important - material as a way of dipping our toes in the water. This chapter also introduces important

More information

Cantor and Infinite Sets

Cantor and Infinite Sets Cantor and Infinite Sets Galileo and the Infinite There are many whole numbers that are not perfect squares: 2, 3, 5, 6, 7, 8, 10, 11, and so it would seem that all numbers, including both squares and

More information

Theorem. For every positive integer n, the sum of the positive integers from 1 to n is n(n+1)

Theorem. For every positive integer n, the sum of the positive integers from 1 to n is n(n+1) Week 1: Logic Lecture 1, 8/1 (Sections 1.1 and 1.3) Examples of theorems and proofs Theorem (Pythagoras). Let ABC be a right triangle, with legs of lengths a and b, and hypotenuse of length c. Then a +

More information

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SYLVIA DURIAN Abstract. This paper develops the ordinal numbers and transfinite induction, then demonstrates some interesting applications of transfinite induction.

More information

Study skills for mathematicians

Study skills for mathematicians PART I Study skills for mathematicians CHAPTER 1 Sets and functions Everything starts somewhere, although many physicists disagree. Terry Pratchett, Hogfather, 1996 To think like a mathematician requires

More information

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31 Contents 1 Lecture 1: Introduction 2 2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction 7 3 Lecture 3: Induction and Well-Ordering Principle 11 4 Lecture 4: Definition of a Group and examples 15

More information

Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 2007 Luca Trevisan Lecture 27

Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 2007 Luca Trevisan Lecture 27 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 007 Luca Trevisan Lecture 7 Infinity and Countability Consider a function f that maps elements of a set A (called the domain of f ) to elements of set B (called

More information

An Introduction to Real Analysis. John K. Hunter 1

An Introduction to Real Analysis. John K. Hunter 1 An Introduction to Real Analysis John K. Hunter Department of Mathematics, University of California at Davis The author was supported in part by the NSF. Thanks to Janko Gravner for a number of corrections

More information

A Logician s Toolbox

A Logician s Toolbox A Logician s Toolbox 461: An Introduction to Mathematical Logic Spring 2009 We recast/introduce notions which arise everywhere in mathematics. All proofs are left as exercises. 0 Notations from set theory

More information

6 Cosets & Factor Groups

6 Cosets & Factor Groups 6 Cosets & Factor Groups The course becomes markedly more abstract at this point. Our primary goal is to break apart a group into subsets such that the set of subsets inherits a natural group structure.

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

Basics on Sets and Functions

Basics on Sets and Functions HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS Spring 2005 Basics on Sets and Functions Introduction to the work of Georg Cantor #10 in the series. Some dictionaries define a set as a collection or aggregate of objects. However,

More information

Analysis I. Classroom Notes. H.-D. Alber

Analysis I. Classroom Notes. H.-D. Alber Analysis I Classroom Notes H-D Alber Contents 1 Fundamental notions 1 11 Sets 1 12 Product sets, relations 5 13 Composition of statements 7 14 Quantifiers, negation of statements 9 2 Real numbers 11 21

More information

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET 1. THE AXIOM OF FOUNDATION Early on in the book (page 6) it is indicated that throughout the formal development set is going to mean pure set, or set whose elements,

More information

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions Sect. 1.1.3: # 2, 3 (Page 7-8 Math 105A HW 1 Solutions 2(a ( Statement: Each positive integers has a unique prime factorization. n N: n = 1 or ( R N, p 1,..., p R P such that n = p 1 p R and ( n, R, S

More information

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS AARON LANDESMAN CONTENTS 1. Introduction to finite fields 2 2. Definition and constructions of fields 3 2.1. The definition of a field 3 2.2. Constructing field extensions by adjoining

More information

Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1

Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1 22M:132 Fall 07 J. Simon Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1 Chapter 1 contains material on sets, functions, relations, and cardinality that

More information

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS WINTER 2014 Problem 1 (15 points). For each statement below, circle T or F according to whether the statement is true or false. You do NOT need to justify your answers. T F

More information

Topology Math Conrad Plaut

Topology Math Conrad Plaut Topology Math 467 2010 Conrad Plaut Contents Chapter 1. Background 1 1. Set Theory 1 2. Finite and Infinite Sets 3 3. Indexed Collections of Sets 4 Chapter 2. Topology of R and Beyond 7 1. The Topology

More information

Foundations Revision Notes

Foundations Revision Notes oundations Revision Notes hese notes are designed as an aid not a substitute for revision. A lot of proofs have not been included because you should have them in your notes, should you need them. Also,

More information

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1. I. Foundational material

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1. I. Foundational material SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1 Fall 2014 I. Foundational material I.1 : Basic set theory Problems from Munkres, 9, p. 64 2. (a (c For each of the first three parts, choose a 1 1 correspondence

More information

Introduction: Pythagorean Triplets

Introduction: Pythagorean Triplets Introduction: Pythagorean Triplets On this first day I want to give you an idea of what sorts of things we talk about in number theory. In number theory we want to study the natural numbers, and in particular

More information

Examples of the Cantor-Bendixson process on the reals Harold Simmons

Examples of the Cantor-Bendixson process on the reals Harold Simmons Examples of the Cantor-Bendixson process on the reals Harold Simmons Mathematical Foundations Group, The University, Manchester, England hsimmons @ manchester.ac.uk A few months ago I was introducing some

More information