Covering Property Axiom CPA

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Covering Property Axiom CPA"

Transcription

1 Covering Property Axiom CPA Krzysztof Ciesielski Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Morgantown, WV , USA K Cies@math.wvu.edu web page: Janusz Pawlikowski 1 Department of Mathematics, University of Wroc law pl. Grunwaldzki 2/4, Wroc law, Poland pawlikow@math.uni.wroc.pl and Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Morgantown, WV , USA pawlikow@math.wvu.edu Draft of March 11, We still plan to make considerable changes to this manuscript. Comments andlist of typos are welcome! 1 The work of the second author was partially supported by KBN Grant number 2 P03A

2 2 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001

3 Contents I CPA for Sacks forcing: a combinatorial core of the iterated perfect set model 5 Preface to Part I 7 Overview of Part I Preliminaries Axiom CPA cube and its consequences: properties (A) (E) Perfectly meager sets, universally null sets, and continuous images of sets of cardinality continuum cof(n )=ω 1 and total failure of Martin s Axiom Some consequences of cof(n )=ω 1 : Blumberg theorem, strong measure zero sets, magic set, and cofinality of Boolean algebras Selective ultrafilters and the reaping numbers r and r σ On a convergence of subsequences of real-valued functions Remarks on a form and consistency of the axiom CPA cube Games and axiom CPA game cube CPA game cube and disjoint coverings MAD families and numbers a and r Remark on a form of CPA game cube Prisms and axioms CPA game prism and CPA prism Fusion for prisms On F-independent prisms CPA prism, additivity of s 0, and more on (A) Multi-games and other remarks on CPA game prism and CPA prism CPA prism and coverings with smooth functions Chapter overview; properties (H )and(q) Proof of Proposition Proposition 4.2.1: a generalization of a theorem of Morayne Theorem 4.1.6: on cov (D n, C n ) < c Examples related to cov operator

4 4 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, Applications of CPA game prism Nice Hamel bases Some additive functions and more on Hamel bases Selective ultrafilters and number u Non-selective P -points and number i Crowded ultrafilters on Q CPA and properties (F ) and (G) cov(s 0 )=c, many ultrafilters, and ω 1 -intersections of open sets Surjections onto nice sets must be continuous on big sets Sums of Darboux and continuous functions Remark on a form of CPA sec cube CPA in the Sacks model Notations and basic forcing facts Consistency of CPA II CPA for other forcings 123 Notation 125 Bibliography 129 Index 135

5 Part I CPA for Sacks forcing: a combinatorial core of the iterated perfect set model 5

6

7 Preface to Part I Many interesting mathematical properties, especially concerning real analysis, are known to be true in the iterated perfect set (Sacks) model, while they are false under the continuum hypothesis. However, the proofs that these facts are indeed true in this model are usually very technical and involve heavy forcing machinery. In this manuscript we extract a combinatorial principle, an axiom similar to the Martin axiom, that is true in the model and show that this axiom implies the above mentioned properties in a simple mathematical way. The proofs are essentially simpler than the original arguments. To follow all but the last chapter of this manuscript only a moderate knowledge of set theory is required. No forcing knowledge is necessary. Overview of Part I The iterated perfect set model, known also as the iterated Sacks model, is a model of the set theory ZFC in which continuum c = ω 2 and many of the consequences of the continuum hypothesis CH fail. In this paper we will describe a combinatorial axiom of the form similar to Martin axiom which holds in the iterated perfect set model and represents a combinatorial core of this model it implies all the general mathematical statements which are known (to us) to be true in this model. It should be mentioned here that our axiom is more an axiom schema with the perfect set forcing being a build-in parameter. A similar axioms hold also for several other forcings and their description will be a subject of Part II of this manuscript. In this text, however, we will concentrate only on the axiom associated with the iterated perfect set model. This is dictated by two reasons: the axiom has the simplest form in this particular model; the iterated perfect set model was the most studied from the class of forcing models we are interested in, we had a good supply of statements against which we could test the power of our axiom. In particular, we used for this purpose the statements listed below as (A) (H). The citations in the parentheses refer to the proofs that a given property holds in the iterated perfect set model. For the definitions see the end next section. 7

8 8 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 (A) (Miller [72]) For every subset S of R of cardinality c there exists a (uniformly) continuous function f: R [0, 1] such that f[s] =[0, 1]. (B) (Miller [72]) Every perfectly meager set S R has cardinality less than c. (C) (Laver [64]) Every universally null set S R has cardinality less than c. (D) (Folklore, see e.g. [74] or [4, p. 339]) The cofinality of the measure ideal N is less than c. (E) (Baumgartner, Laver [6]) There exist selective ultrafilters on ω and any such ultrafilter is generated by less than c many sets. (F) (Balcerzak, Ciesielski, Natkaniec [2]) There is no Darboux Sierpiński- Zygmund function f: R R, that is, for every Darboux function f: R R there is a subset Y of R of cardinality c such that f Y is continuous. (G) (Steprāns [93]) For every Darboux function g: R R there exists a continuous nowhere constant function f: R R such that f + g is Darboux. (H) (Steprāns [94]) The plane R 2 can be covered by less than c many sets each of which is a graph of a partial function defined and differentiable on a perfect subset of either horizontal or vertical axis. The counterexamples, under CH, for (B) and (C) are Luzin and Sierpiński sets. They have been constructed in [67] 1 and [86], respectively. The negation of (A) is witnessed by either Luzin or Sierpiński set, as noticed in [86, 87]. The counterexamples, under CH, for (F) and (G) can be found in [2] and [60], respectively. The fact that (D), (E), and (H) are false under CH is obvious. The manuscript is organized as follows. Since our main axiom, which we call the Covering Property Axiom and denote by CPA, requires some extra definitions which are unnecessary for most of applications, we will introduce the axiom in several approximations, from the easiest to state and use to the most powerful but more complicated. All the versions of the axiom will be formulated and discussed in the main body of the chapters. The sections that follow contain only the consequences of the axioms. In particular, most of the sections can be omitted in the reading without causing the difficulty in following the rest of the material. Thus, we start in Chapter 1 with a formulation of the simplest form of our axiom, CPA cube, which is based on a natural notion of a cube in a Polish space. In Section 1.1 we show that CPA cube implies the properties (A) (C), while Section 1.2 is devoted to the proofs that CPA cube implies the property (D) (i.e., cof(n )=ω 1 ) and the following fact, known as the total failure of Martin s Axiom (I) c >ω 1 and for every non-trivial ccc forcing P there exists ω 1 -many dense sets in P such that no filter intersects all of them. 1 Constructed also a year earlier by Mahlo [68].

9 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, The consistency of (I) was first proved by Baumgartner [5] in a model obtained by adding Sacks reals side-by-side. In Section 1.3 we will present some consequences of cof(n )=ω 1 that seems to be related to the iterated perfect set model. In particular we prove that cof(n )=ω 1 implies that (J) c >ω 1 and there exists a Boolean algebra B of cardinality ω 1 which is not a union of strictly increasing ω-sequence of subalgebras of B. The consistency of (J) was first proved by Just and Koszmider [54] in a model obtained by adding Sacks reals side-by-side, while Koppelberg [61] showed that Martin s Axiom contradicts (J). In Section 1.4 we show that CPA cube implies that every selective ultrafilter is generated by ω 1 sets (i.e., the second part of the property (E)) and that (K) r = ω 1, where r is the reaping (or refinement) number, that is, r = min { W : W [ω] ω & A [ω] ω W W (W A or W ω \ A)}. In Section 1.5 we will prove that CPA cube implies the following version of a theorem of Mazurkiewicz [70]. (L) For each Polish space X and uniformly bounded sequence f n : X R n<ω of Borel measurable functions there are the sequences: P ξ : ξ < ω 1 of compact subsets of X and W ξ [ω] ω : ξ<ω 1 such that X = ξ<ω 1 P ξ and for every ξ<ω 1 : f n P ξ n Wξ is a monotone uniformly convergent sequence of uniformly continuous functions. We will also show that CPA cube + selective ultrafilter on ω implies the following variant of (L): (M) Let X an arbitrary set and f n : X R be a sequence of functions such that the set {f n (x): n<ω} is bounded for every x X. Then there are the sequences: P ξ : ξ<ω 1 of subsets of X and W ξ F: ξ<ω 1 such that X = ξ<ω 1 P ξ and for every ξ<ω 1 : f n P ξ n Wξ is monotone and uniformly convergent. It should be noted here that a result essentially due to Sierpiński (see Example 1.5.2) implies that (M) is false under the Martin s Axiom. The last section of this chapter consists of the remarks on a form and consistency of CPA cube. In particular, we note there that CPA cube is false in a model obtained by adding Sacks reals side-by-side. In Chapter 2 we revise slightly the notion of a cube and introduce a cubegame GAME cube, a covering game of length ω 1 which is a foundation for our next (stronger) variant of the axiom, CPA game cube. In Section 2.1, as its application, we will show that CPA game cube implies that

10 10 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 (N) c >ω 1 and for every Polish space there exists a partition of X into ω 1 disjoint closed nowhere dense measure zero sets. In Section 2.2 we will show that CPA game cube implies that (O) c > ω 1 and there exists a family F [ω] ω of cardinality ω 1 which is simultaneously maximal almost disjoint and reaping. Chapter 3 begins with a definition of a prism, which is a generalization of a notion of cube in a Polish space. This notion, perhaps the most important notion of this text, is then used to our next generation of the axioms, CPA game prism and CPA prism, which are prism (stronger) counterparts of axioms CPA game cube and CPA cube. Since the notion of a prism is rather unknown, in the first two sections of Chapter 3 we develop the tools that will help to deal with them (Section 3.1) and prove for them the main duality property that distinguishes them form cubes (Section 3.2). In the last section of this chapter we discuss some application of CPA prism. In particular, we will prove that CPA prism implies the following generalization of the property (A) (A ) there exists a family G of uniformly continuous functions from R to [0, 1] such that G = ω 1 and for every S [R] c there exists a g G with g[s] =[0, 1]. We will also show that CPA prism implies that (P) add(s 0 ), the additivity of the ideal s 0, is equal to ω 1 < c. We finish Chapter 3 with several remarks on CPA game prism. In particular, we prove that CPA game prism implies axiom CPAgame prism (X ) in which the game is played simultaneously over ω 1 Polish spaces. Chapters 4 and 5 deal with the applications of the axioms CPA prism and CPA game prism, respectively. Chapter 4 contains a deep discussion of a problem of covering R 2 and Borel functions from R to R by continuous functions of different smooth levels. In particular, we show that CPA prism implies the following strengthening of the property (H) (H ) there exists a family F of less then continuum many C 1 functions from R to R (i.e., differentiable functions with continuous derivatives) such that R 2 is covered by functions from F and their inverses as well as the following covering property for the Borel functions (Q) for every Borel function f: R R there exists a family F of less than continuum many C 1 functions (i.e., differentiable functions with continuous derivatives, where derivative can be infinite) whose graphs cover the graph of f. We will also examine which functions can be covered by less than c many C n functions for n>1 and give the examples showing that all covering theorems discussed are the best possible. Chapter 5 concentrates on several specific applications of CPA game prism. Thus in Section 5.1 we will show that CPA game prism implies

11 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, (R) there is a family H of ω 1 pairwise disjoint perfect subsets of R such that H = H is a Hamel basis, that is, a linear basis of R over Q and show that the following two properties are the consequences of (R): (S) there exists a non-measurable subset X of R without the Baire property which is N M-rigid, that is, such that X (r + X) N Mfor every r R; (T) there exists a function f: R R such that for every h R the difference function h (x) =f(x + h) f(x) is Borel; however, for every α<ω 1 there is an h R such that h is not of Borel class α. Implication CPA game prism = (S) answers a question related to the work of Cichoń, Jasiński, Kamburelis, and Szczepaniak [19]. The implication CPA game prism = (T) shows that a recent construction of such a function from CH due to Filipów and Rec law [42] (and answering a question of Laczkovich [63]) can be also repeated with a help of our axiom. In Section 5.2 we show that CPA game prism implies that (U) there is a discontinuous, almost continuous, additive function f: R R whose graph is of measure zero. A first construction of such a function, under Martin s Axiom, was given by Ciesielski in [23]. It is unknown whether it can be constructed in ZFC. We also prove there that, under CPA game prism (V) there exists a Hamel basis H such that E + (H) has measure zero, where E + (A) is a linear combination of A R with non-negative rational coefficients. This relates to work of Erdős [39], H. Miller [75], and Muthuvel [77] who constructed such and similar Hamel bases under different set theoretical assumptions. It is unknown whether (V) holds in ZFC. In Section 5.3 we deduce from CPA game prism that every selective ideal on ω can be extended to a maximal selective ideal. In particular, the first part of the condition (E) holds and u = r σ = ω 1, where u is the smallest cardinality of the base for a non-principal ultrafilter on ω. In Section 5.4 prove that CPA game prism implies that (W) there exist many non-selective P -points as well as a family F [ω] ω of cardinality ω 1 which is simultaneously independent and splitting. In particular i = ω 1, where i is the smallest cardinality of an infinite maximal independent family. We will finish this chapter with the proof that CPA game prism implies that (X) there exists a non-principal ultrafilter on Q which is crowded. In Chapter 6 we formulate the most general form of our axiom, CPA, and show that it implies all the other versions of the axiom. In Section 6.1 we will conclude from CPA that

12 12 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 (Y) cov(s 0 )=c and (Z) if U = {U ξ : ξ<ω 1 } is a family of open sets in C and U = c then U contains a perfect set. In Section 6.2 we show that CPA implies the following two generalizations of the property (F): (F ) for an arbitrary function h from a subset S of a Polish space X onto a Polish space Y there exists a uniformly continuous function f from a subset of X into Y such that f h = c and (F ) for any function h from a subset S of R onto a perfect subset of R there exists a function f Cperf such that f h = c and f can be extended to a function f C 1 (R) such that either either f C 1 or f is an autohomeomorphism of R with f 1 C 1. In Section 6.3 that (A)&(F )= (G). In particular, (G) follows from CPA. In Chapter 7 we show that CPA holds in the iterated perfect set model. Preliminaries Our set theoretic terminology is standard and follows that of [4], [21], or [62]. If a, b R and a < b then (b, a) = (a, b) will stand for the open interval {x R: a<x<b}. Similarly [b, a] =[a, b] is an appropriate closed interval. A Cantor set 2 ω will be denoted by a symbol C. In this paper we use term Polish space for a complete separable metric space without isolated points. For a Polish space X symbol Perf(X) will stand for a collection of all subsets of X homeomorphic to a Cantor set C; as usual C(X) will stand for the family of all continuous functions from X into R. A function f: R R is Darboux if a conclusion of the intermediate value theorem holds for f or, equivalently, when f maps every interval onto an interval; f is a Sierpiński-Zygmund function if its restriction f Y is discontinuous for every subset Y of R of cardinality c; f is nowhere constant if it is not constant on any non-trivial interval. A set S R is perfectly meager if S P is meager in P for every perfect set P R, and S is universally null provided for every perfect set P R the set S P has measure zero with respect to every probability measure on P. For an ideal I on a set X its cofinality is defined by and its covering as cof(i) = min{ B : B generates I} cov(i) = min{ B : B I& B = X}.

13 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, Symbol N will stand for the ideal of Lebesgue measure zero subsets of R. For a fixed Polish space X the ideal of its meager subsets will be denoted by M, and we will use the symbol s 0 (or s 0 (X)) to denote the σ-ideal of Marczewski s s 0 -sets, that is, s 0 = {S X:( P Perf(X))( Q Perf(X)) Q P \ S}. For an ideal I on a set X we use the symbol I + to denote its coideal, that is, I + = P(X) \I. For an ideal I on ω containing all finite subsets of ω we will use the following generalized selectivity terminology. We say (see Farah [40]) that an ideal I is selective provided for every sequence F 0 F 1 of sets from I + there exists an F I + (called a diagonalization of this sequence) with the property that F \{0,...,n} F n for all n F. Notice that this definition agrees with the definition of selectivity given by Grigorieff in [47, p. 365]. (The ideals selective in the above sense Grigorieff calls inductive but he also proves [47, cor. 1.15] that the inductive ideals and the ideals selective in his sense are the same notions.) For A, B ω we will write A B when A\B <ω. A set D I + is dense in I + provided for every B I + there exists an A Dsuch that A B; set D is open in I + if B Dprovided there is an A Dsuch that B A. For D = D n I + : n<ω we say that F I + is a diagonalization of D provided F \{0,...,n} D n for every n<ω. Following Farah [40] we say that an ideal I on ω is semiselective provided for every sequence D = D n I + : n<ω of dense and open subsets of I + the family of all diagonalizations of D is dense in I +. Following Grigorieff [47, p. 390] we say that I is weakly selective (or weak selective) provided for every A I + and f: A ω there exists a B I + such that f B is either one-to-one or constant. (Farah in [40, sec. 2] terms such ideals as having Q + -property. Note also that Baumgartner and Laver in [6] call such ideals selective, despite the fact that they claim to use Grigorieff s terminology from [47].) We have the following implications between these notions. (See Farah [40, sec. 2].) I is selective = I is semiselective = I is weakly selective All these notions represent different generalizations of the properties of the ideal [ω] <ω. In particular, it is easy to see that [ω] <ω is selective. We say that an ideal I on a countable set X is selective (weakly selective) provided it is such upon an identification of X with ω via an arbitrary bijection. A filter F on a countable set X is selective (semiselective, weakly selective) provided so is its dual ideal I = P(X) \F. It is important to note that a maximal ideal (or an ultrafilter) is selective if and only if it is weakly selective. This follows, for example, directly from the definitions of these notions as in Grigorieff [47]. Recall also that the existence of selective ultrafilters cannot be proved in ZFC. (This is the case since every selective ultrafilter is a P -point, while Shelah proved that there are models with no P -points, see e.g. [4, thm ].)

14 14 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001

15 Chapter 1 Axiom CPA cube and its consequences: properties (A) (E) For a Polish space X we will consider Perf(X), the family of all subsets of X homeomorphic to a Cantor set C, as ordered by inclusion. Thus, a family E Perf(X) is dense in Perf(X) provided for every P Perf(X) there exists a Q E such that Q P. All different versions of our axiom will be more or less of the form if E Perf(X) is appropriately dense in Perf(X) then some portion E 0 of E covers almost all of X in a sense that X \ E 0 < c. If the word appropriately in the above is ignored, then it implies the following statement. Naïve-CPA: If E is dense in Perf(X) then X \ E < c. It is a very good candidate for our axiom in a sense that it implies all the properties we are interested in. It has, however, one major flaw it is false! This is the case since S X \ E for some dense set E in Perf(X) provided for each P Perf(X) there is a Q Perf(X) such that Q P \ S. This means that the family G of all sets of the form X \ E, where E is dense in Perf(X), coincides with the σ-ideal s 0 of Marczewski s sets, since G is clearly hereditary. Thus we have { s 0 = X \ } E: E is dense in Perf(X). (1.1) However, it is well known (see e.g. [73, thm. 5.10]) that there are s 0 -sets of cardinality c. Thus, our Naïve-CPA axiom cannot be consistent with ZFC. 15

16 16 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 In order to formulate the real axiom CPA cube we need the following terminology and notation. A subset C of a product C η of the Cantor set is said to be a perfect cube (or just cube) ifc = n η C n, where C n Perf(C) for each n. For a fixed Polish space X let F cube stand for the family of all continuous injections from a perfect cube C C ω onto a set P from Perf(X). We consider each function f F cube from C onto P as a coordinate system imposed on P. We say that P Perf(X) is a cube if we consider it with (implicitly given) witness function f F cube onto P, and Q is a subcube of a cube P Perf(X) provided Q = f[c], where f F cube is a witness function for P and C is a subcube of the domain of f. We say that a family E Perf(X) isf cube -dense (or cube-dense) inperf(x) provided every cube P Perf(X) contains a subcube Q E. More formally, E Perf(X) isf cube -dense provided f F cube g F cube (g f & range(g) E). (1.2) It is easy to see that the notion of F cube -density is a generalization of a notion of density as defined in the first paragraph of this chapter: if E is F cube -dense in Perf(X) then E is dense in Perf(X). (1.3) On the other hand, the converse implication is not true, as shown by the following simple example. Example Let X = C C and let E be the family of all P Perf(X) such that either all vertical sections P x = {y C: x, y P } of P are countable, or all horizontal sections P y = {x C: x, y P } of P are countable. Then E is dense in Perf(X), but it is not F cube -dense in Perf(X). With these notions in hand we are ready to formulate our axiom CPA cube. CPA cube : c = ω 2 and for every Polish space X and every F cube -dense family E Perf(X) there is an E 0 E such that E 0 ω 1 and X \ E 0 ω 1. The proof that CPA cube is consistent with ZFC (it holds in the iterated perfect set model) will be presented in the next chapters. In the reminder of this chapter we will take a closer look at CPA cube and its consequences. In what follows we consider F cube as ordered by the inclusion. Therefore F F cube is dense in F cube provided for every f F cube there exists a g F with g f. Proposition CPA cube is equivalent to the following. CPA 0 cube : c = ω 2 and for every Polish space X and every dense subfamily F of F cube there is an F 0 [F] ω1 such that X \ g F 0 range(g) ω 1.

17 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, Proof. First notice that E Perf(X) isf cube -dense if and only if F cube (E) is dense in F cube, (1.4) where F cube (E) ={g F cube : range(g) E}. Now, to see that CPA 0 cube implies CPA cube take an F cube -dense family E Perf(X). Then, using CPA 0 cube with F = F cube(e), we can find an appropriate F 0 [F] ω1. Clearly E 0 = {range(g): g F 0 } satisfies the conclusion of CPA cube. To see the other implication, take a dense subfamily F of F cube and let E = {range(g): g F}. Then, by (1.4), E is F cube -dense in Perf(X), since F F cube (E). By CPA cube we can find an E 0 [E] ω1 such that X \ E 0 < c. For each E E 0 take an f E Fsuch that range(f E )=E. Then F 0 = {f E : E E 0 } satisfies the conclusion of CPA 0 cube. Condition CPA 0 cube has a form which closer to our main axiom CPA than CPA cube. Also CPA 0 cube does not require a new notion of F cube-density. So why bother with CPA cube at all? The reason is that the consequences presented in this chapter follows more naturally from CPA cube than from CPA 0 cube. Moreover, from CPA cube it is also clearer that the axiom describes, in fact, a property of perfect subsets of X, rather than of some coordinate functions. Note that if F all stands for the family of all injections from perfect subsets of C ω into X then we can use schema (1.2) to define a notion of F-density of E Perf(X) for any family F F all : E Perf(X) isf-dense provided f F g F (g f & range(g) E). (1.5) In particular, it is easy to see that a family E Perf(X) is dense in Perf(X) if and only if E is F all -dense in Perf(X). It is also worth to notice that in order to check that E is F cube -dense it is enough to consider in condition (1.2) only functions f defined on the entire space C ω, that is Fact E Perf(X) is F cube -dense if and only if f F cube, dom(f) =C ω, g F cube (g f & range(g) E). (1.6) Proof. To see this, let Φ be the family of all bijections h = h n n<ω between perfect subcubes n ω D n and n ω C n of C ω such that each h n is a homeomorphism between D n and C n. Then f h F cube for every f F cube and h Φ with range(h) dom(f). (1.7) Now take an arbitrary f: C X from F cube and choose an h Φ mapping C ω onto C. Then ˆf = f h F cube maps C ω into X and, using (1.6), we can find ĝ F cube such that ĝ ˆf and range(ĝ) E. Then g = f h[dom(ĝ)] satisfies (1.2).

18 18 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 Next, let us consider s cube 0 = { X \ } E: E is F cube -dense in Perf(X) = {S X: cube P Perf(X) subcube Q P \ S}. (1.8) It can be easily shown, in ZFC, that s cube 0 forms a σ-ideal. However, we will not use this fact in this text in that general form. This is the case, since we will usually assume that CPA cube holds while CPA cube implies the following stronger fact. Proposition If CPA cube holds then s cube 0 =[X] ω1. Proof. It is obvious that CPA cube implies s cube 0 [X] <c. The other inclusion is always true and it follows from the following simple fact. Fact [X] <c s cube 0 s 0 for every Polish space X. Proof. Choose S [X] <c. In order to see that S s cube 0 note that the family E = {P Perf(X): P S = } is F cube -dense in Perf(X). Indeed, if function f: C ω X is from F cube then there is a perfect subset P 0 of C which is disjoint with the projection π 0 (f 1 (S)) of f 1 (S) into the first coordinate. Then f [ i<ω P i] S =, where Pi = C for all 0 <i<ω. Therefore, f [ i<ω P i] E. Thus, S X \E s cube 0. The inclusion s cube 0 s 0 follows immediately from (1.1), (1.8), and (1.3). 1.1 Perfectly meager sets, universally null sets, and continuous images of sets of cardinality continuum An important quality of the ideal s cube 0, and so the power of the assumption s cube 0 =[X] <c, is well depicted by the following fact. Proposition If X is a Polish space and S X does not belong to s cube 0 then there exist a T [S] c and a uniformly continuous function h from T onto C. Proof. Take an S as above and let f: C ω X be a continuous injection such that f[c] S for every cube C. Let g: C C be a continuous function such that g 1 (y) is perfect for every y C. Then h 0 = g π 0 f 1 : f[c ω ] C is uniformly continuous. Moreover, if T = S f[c ω ] then h 0 [T ]=C since T h 1 0 (y) =T f[π 1 0 (g 1 (y))] = S f[g 1 (y) C C ] for every y C.

19 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, Corollary Assume s cube 0 =[X] <c for a Polish space X. If S X has cardinality c then there exists a uniformly continuous function f: X [0, 1] such that f[s] =[0, 1]. In particular, CPA cube implies property (A). Proof. If S is as above then, by CPA cube, S / s cube 0. Thus, by Proposition there exists a uniformly continuous function h from a subset of S onto C. Let ĥ: X [0, 1] be an uniformly continuous extension of h and let g maps continuously C onto [0, 1]. Then f = ĥ g is as desired. For more on the property (A) see also Corollary It is worth to note here that the function f in Corollary cannot be required to be either monotone or in the class D 1 of all functions having finite or infinite derivative at every point. This follows immediately from the following proposition, since each function which is either monotone or D 1 belongs to the Banach class (See [43] or [84, p. 278].) (T 2 )= { f C(R): {y R: f 1 (y) >ω} N }. Proposition There exists, in ZFC, an S [R] c such that [0, 1] f[s] for every f (T 2 ). Proof. Let {f ξ : ξ<c} be an enumeration of all functions from (T 2 ) which range contains [0, 1]. Construct by induction a sequence s ξ,y ξ : ξ<c such that for every ξ<c (i) y ξ [0, 1] \ f ξ [{s ζ : ζ<ξ}] and f 1 ξ (y ξ ) ω. ( (ii) s ξ R \ {s ζ : ζ<ξ} ) ζ ξ f 1 ζ (y ζ ). Then the set S = {s ξ : ξ<c} is as required since y ξ [0, 1] \ f ξ [S] for every ξ<c. Theorem If S R is either perfectly meager or universally null then S s cube 0. In particular, CPA cube = s cube 0 =[R] <c = (B) & (C). Proof. Take an S R which is either perfectly meager or universally null and let f: C ω R be a continuous injection. Then S f[c ω ] is either meager or null in f[c ω ]. Thus G = C ω \ f 1 (S) is either comeager or of full measure in C ω. Hence the theorem follows immediately from the following fact. Claim If G C ω is either comeager or of full measure in C ω then it contains a perfect cube i<ω P i. Claim follows easily, by induction on coordinates, from the following well known fact.

20 20 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 For every comeager (full measure) subset H of C C there are perfect set P C and a comeager (full measure) subset Ĥ of C such that P Ĥ H. The category version is easy and can be found in [56, Exercise 19.3]. (Its version for R 2 is also proved, for example, in [33, condition ( ), p. 416].) The measure version follows easily form the fact that for every full measure subset H of [0, 1] [0, 1] there are perfect set P C and a positive inner measure subset Ĥ of [0, 1] such that P Ĥ H which is proved by Eggleston [38] and, independently, by Brodskiǐ [10]. 1.2 cof(n )=ω 1 and total failure of Martin s Axiom We will start with the proof that CPA cube implies that for every non-trivial ccc forcing P there exists ω 1 -many dense sets in P such that no filter intersects all of them. This follows immediately from the theorem below. The consistency of this fact with c >ω 1 was first proved by Baumgartner [5] in a model obtained by adding Sacks reals side-by-side. Theorem If CPA cube holds then every compact ccc topological space is a union of ω 1 nowhere dense sets. Proof. Let cba stand for complete Boolean algebra. First notice that in order to prove the theorem it is enough to show that for every ccc cba B there is a family of ω 1 -many maximal antichains in B such that no filter in B intersects all of them. Next notice that it is enough to prove this fact only for countable generated ccc cba s. Indeed, every ccc cba B contains a complete countably generated Boolean subalgebra B 0, which is still ccc. Now, every maximal antichain in B 0 is also a maximal antichain in B. So, if A = {A ξ : ξ<ω 1 } is a family of maximal antichains in B 0 such that no filter in B 0 intersects all of them, then A witness the same fact for B. Next let B be the algebra of Borel subsets of C =2 ω and note that it is a free countably generated cba, with free generators A i = {s C: s(i) =0}. Thus, by Loomis-Sikorski theorem (see [91, p. 117] or [66]), every countably generated ccc cba B 0 (which is just a ccc sigma complete Boolean algebra) is isomorphic to the quotient algebra B/I, where I is some σ-ideal of Borel sets. It follows that we need only to consider cba s of the form B/I, where I is some σ-ideal of Borel sets containing all singletons. To prove that such algebra has ω 1 maximal antichains as desired, it is enough to prove that C is a union of ω 1 sets from I.

21 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, But this follows easily from CPA cube, since any cube P in C contains a subcube Q I: any cube P can be partitioned into c-many disjoint subcubes and, by the ccc property of I, only countable many of them can be outside I. Next we show that CPA cube implies that cof(n )=ω 1. So, under CPA cube, all cardinals from Cichoń s diagram (see e.g. [4]) are equal to ω 1. Let C H be the family of all subsets n<ω T n of ω ω such that T n [ω] n+1 for all n<ω. We will use the following characterization. Proposition (Bartoszyński [4, thm ]) { cof(n ) = min F : F C H & F = ω ω}. Lemma Family C H is F cube -dense in Perf(ω ω ). Proof. Let f: C ω ω ω be a continuous injection. By (1.6) it is enough to find a cube C in C ω such that f[c] C H. So, let { n i,m i : i<ω} be an enumeration of ω ω and for i<ωlet S i = {s C ω : s(n j )(m j ) = 0 for all i j<ω}. Notice that S i =2 i for every i<ω. By induction on i<ωwe will define sets X i = {x s C ω : s S i }. For the unique s S 0 we choose x s C ω arbitrarily. Now, if X i 1 is constructed for some 0 <i<ωwe extend it to X i as follows. For s S i \ S i 1 let s S i 1 be such that s(n j )(m j )=s (n j )(m j ) for all j i. We choose x s x s such that (i) x s (n) =x s (n) for all n n i, and (ii) f(x s ) 2 i = f(x s ) 2 i. The choice satisfying (ii) can be made since f is continuous. Note that we have defined a uniformly continuous mapping g, s x s, from S = i<ω S i onto X = {x s : s S}. So g can be extended continuously to a function ḡ from C ω =cl(s) ontoc = cl(x). Note that, by (i), C is a cube since s(n) =s (n) implies ḡ(s)(n) =ḡ(s )(n) for all s, s C ω and n<ω. Also, by (ii), f(x)(k) T k = {f(x s )(k): s S i } for all x C and 2 i k<2 i+1. So, f[c] n<ω T n C H. Corollary If CPA cube holds then cof(n )=ω 1. Proof. By CPA cube and Lemma there exists an F [C H ] ω1 such that ω ω \ F ω 1. This and Proposition imply cof(n )=ω 1. As a last application in this section let us consider the following covering number connected to a Blumberg s theorem (see next section) and studied by F. Jordan in [52]. Here B 1 stands for the class of all Baire class 1 functions f: R R.

22 22 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 cov(b 1, Perf(R)) is the smallest cardinality of F B 1 such that for each P Perf(R) there is an f F with f P not continuous. Jordan proves also [52, thm. 7(a)] that cov(b 1, Perf(R)) is equal to the covering number of the space Perf(R) (considered with the Hausdorff metric) by the elements of some σ-ideal Z p and notices [52, thm. 17(a)] that every compact set C Perf(R) contains a dense G δ subset which belongs to Z p. So, by Claim 1.1.5, the elements of Perf(R) Z p are F cube -dense in Perf(R). Thus Corollary CPA cube implies that cov(b 1, Perf(R)) = cov(z p )=ω Some consequences of cof(n )=ω 1 : Blumberg theorem, strong measure zero sets, magic set, and cofinality of Boolean algebras In this section we will show some consequences of cof(n ) = ω 1 (so also of CPA cube ) which are related to the Sacks model. In 1922 Blumberg [9] proved that for every f: R R there exists a dense subset D of R such that f D is continuous. This theorem sparked a lot of discussion and generalizations, see e.g. [22, pp ]. In particular, Shelah [85] showed that there is a model of ZFC in which for every f: R R there is a nowhere meager subset D of R such that f D is continuous. The dual measure result, that is the consistency of a statement for every f: R R there is a subset D of R of positive outer Lebesgue measure such that f D is continuous, has been also recently established by Ros lanowski and Shelah [82]. Below we note that each of these properties contradicts CPA cube. (See also in [29].) Theorem Let I {N, M}. Ifcof(I) =ω 1 then there exists an f: R R such that f D is discontinuous for every D P(R) \I. Proof. We will assume that I = N, the proof for I = M being essentially identical. Let {N ξ R 2 : ξ<ω 1 } be a family cofinal in the ideal of null subsets of R 2 and for each ξ<ω 1 let N ξ = {x R:(N ξ ) x / N}, where (N ξ ) x = {y R: x, y N ξ }. By Fubini theorem each Nξ each x Nξ \ ζ<ξ N ζ we choose f(x) so that f(x) / ζ<ξ(n ζ ) x. is null. For Then function f is as desired. Indeed, if f D is continuous for some D R then f D is null in R 2. In particular, there exists a ξ<ω 1 such that f D N ξ. But this means that D ζ ξ N ζ.

23 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, Note that essentially the same proof works if we assume only that cof(i) is equal to the additivity number add(i) of I. Corollary Assume CPA cube. Then there exists an f: R R such that if f D is continuous then D N M. Proof. By CPA cube we have cof(n ) = cof(m) =ω 1. Let f N and f M be from Theorem constructed for the ideals N and M, respectively. Let G R be a dense G δ of measure zero and put f =[f M G] [f N (R \ G)]. Then this f is as desired. Although CPA cube implies that all cardinals from Cichoń s diagram are as small as possible, this does not extend to all possible cardinal invariants. For example we note that CPA cube refutes Borel conjecture. Corollary If CPA cube holds then there exists an uncountable strong measure zero set. Proof. This follows from the fact (see e.g. [4, thm ]) that cof(n )=ω 1 implies the existence of an uncountable strong measure zero set. Recall that a set M R is a magic set (or set of range uniqueness) iffor every different nowhere constant functions f,g C(R) wehavef[m] g[m]. It has been proved by Berarducci and Dikranjan [7, thm. 8.5] that a magic set exists under CH, while Ciesielski and Shelah [32] constructed a model with no magic set. It is relatively easy to see that if M is magic then M is not meager and f[m] [0, 1] for every f C(R). (See [17, cor and thm. 5.6(5)].) So CPA cube implies there is no magic set of cardinality c. On the other hand it was noticed by Todorcevic (see [17, p. 1097]) that in the iterated perfect set model there is a magic set (clearly of cardinality ω 1 ). We like to note here that the same is implied by CPA cube. (See also in [29].) Proposition If the cofinality cof(m) of the ideal M of meager sets is equal ω 1 then there exists a magic set. In particular, CPA cube implies that there exists a magic set. Proof. An uncountable set L R is a 2-Lusin set provided for every disjoint subsets {x ξ : ξ<ω 1 } and {y ξ : ξ<ω 1 } of L, where the enumerations are one-toone, the set of pairs { x ξ,y ξ : ξ<ω 1 } is not a meager subset of R 2. In [17, prop. 4.8] it was noticed that every ω 1 -dense 2-Lusin set is a magic set. It is also a standard and easy diagonal argument that cof(m) =ω 1 implies the existence of a ω 1 -dense 2-Lusin set. (The proof presented in [95, prop. 6.0] works also under the assumption cof(m) =ω 1.) So, CPA cube = cof(n )=ω 1 = cof(m) =ω 1 = there is a magic set.

24 24 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 Recall also that the existence of a magic set for the class D 1 can be proved in ZFC. This follows from [18, thm. 3.1], since every function from D 1 belongs to the class (T 2 ). (Compare also [18, cor. 3.3 and 3.4].) For an infinite Boolean algebra B its cofinality cof(b) is defined as the least infinite cardinal number κ such that B is a union of strictly increasing sequence of type κ of subalgebras of B. Koppelberg [61] proved that Martin s Axiom implies that cof(b) =ω for every Boolean algebra B with B < c while Just and Koszmider [54] proved that in the model obtained by adding at least ω 2 Sacks reals side-by-side there exists a Boolean algebra B of cardinality ω 1 such that cof(b) =ω 1 < c. (See also [37].) We like to notice here that this follows also form CPA cube, since we have: Theorem cof(n )=ω 1 implies that there exists a Boolean algebra B of cardinality ω 1 such that cof(b) =ω 1. The proof of Theorem presented below follows the argument given in [28]. It will be based on the following lemma. Lemma If cof(n )=ω 1 then for every infinite countable Boolean algebra A there exists a family {a ξ n A: n<ω& ξ<ω 1 } with the following properties. (i) a ξ n a ξ m = 0 for every n<m<ωand ξ<ω 1. (ii) For every increasing sequence A n : n<ω of proper subalgebras of A with A = n<ω A n there exists a ξ<ω 1 such that a ξ n / A n for all n<ω. Proof. In the argument that follows every sequence Ā = A n: n<ω as in (ii) will be identified with a function f Ā = f ω A for which f 1 (n) =A n \ i<n A i. We will denote the set of all such functions by X. Also, let {b n : n<ω} be an enumeration of A and for each n<ωlet B n be a finite algebra generated by {b i : i<n}. Thus, A = i<n B i. Since cof(n )=ω 1, the dominating number d = min { K : K ω ω &( f ω ω )( g K)( n <ω) f(n) <g(n)} is equal to ω 1. (See e.g. [4].) So, there exists a dominating family K ω ω of cardinality ω 1. We can also assume that the sequences in K are strictly increasing and that for every g Kfunction ḡ defined by ḡ(n) = i n g(i) also belongs to K. Next notice that for every f X there exist d = d k : k < ω Kand r = r k : k<ω Ksuch that for every k<ω (a) f(b) <r k for all b B k ; and (b) there are disjoint b 0,...,b 2k B dk with r dk 1 <f(b 0 ) < <f(b 2k ). Indeed, the existence of r satisfying (a) follows directly from the definition of a dominating family. Moreover, since all algebras A n = f 1 ({0,...,n}) are

25 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, proper, for every number d<ωthere exist disjoint b 0,...,b 2d Asuch that r d <f(b 0 ) < <f(b 2d ). Let h ω ω be such that b 0,...,b 2d B d+h(d) for every d<ωand let g Kbe a function dominating h. Then d =ḡ is as required. The above implies, in particular, that for every f X there are d, r Ksuch that f satisfies (b) and the sequence f r = f (B dk \ B dk 1 ): k<ω belongs to X( d, r) = k<ω(r dk ) B d k \B dk 1. Now, since cof(n )=ω 1, by Proposition (applied to k<ω ωb d k \B dk 1 in place of ω ω ) we can find an ω 1 -covering of X( d, r) by sets T of the form [ ] k+1 k<ω T k, where T k ω B d k \B dk 1 for all k<ω. Since the total number of these sets T (for different d, r K) is equal to ω 1, to finish the proof it is enough to show that for any such T there is one sequence a n : n<ω satisfying (i) and such that (ii) holds for every for every Ā = A n: n<ω for which f r Ā belongs to T and f Ā satisfies (b). So, let T be as above and let T be the set of all functions f Ā satisfying (b) for which f r T. By induction on k<ωwe will construct a sequence Ā c k B dk \ B dk 1 : k<ω such that ( ) f(c k ) >r dk k for every k<ωand f T. So fix a k<ωand let {f i : i<k} be such that {f i B dk \ B dk 1 : i<k} = {f B dk \ B dk 1 : f T } T k. We show inductively that for every m<k there is a c B dk such that f j (c) >r dk for all j m. (1.9) So, fix an m<kand let a B dk such that f j (a c )=f j (a) >r dk for all j < m. If f m (a) > r dk then c = a satisfies property (1.9). Thus, assume that f m (a c )=f m (a) r dk. By (b) we can find b 0,...,b 2k B dk such that r dk 1 <f m (b 0 ) < <f m (b 2k ). By Pigeon Hole Principle we can find an I [{0,...,2k}] k+1 and a b {a, a c } such that f m (b b i )=f m (b i ) for all i I. Without loss of generality we can assume that I = {0,...,k} and b b i = b i for all i k. Then f m (b c b i ) >r dk for all i k. Moreover, for every j<mthere is at most one i j k for which f j (b c b ij ) r dk since for different i, i k we have f j ((b c b i ) (b c b i )) = f j (b c ) >r dk. Thus, by Pigeon Hole Principle, there is an i k such that c = b c b i satisfies (1.9). This finishes the proof of ( ). Clearly the sequence c k B dk \ B dk 1 : k<ω satisfies (ii) for every Ā with f Ā T. Thus, we need only to modify it to get also the condition (i). To do it, use the fact that

26 26 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 r dk <f(c k ) <r dk+1 for every k<ωand f T to construct the sequences: ω = I 0 I 1 of infinite subsets of ω, increasing k j I j : j<ω, and c k j {c kj,c c k j }: j<ω such that for every j<ω f(ā kj c l ) >r dl for every f T and l>k j with l I j, where ā kj = c k 0 c k j. Then the sequence ā kj : j<ω is a strictly decreasing sequence satisfying (ii) and it is now easy to see that by putting a j =ā kj ā c k j+1 we obtain the desired sequence. Proof of Theorem Algebra B we construct will be a subalgebra of the algebra P(ω) of all subsets of ω. First, let K ω ω be a dominating family with K = ω 1 and fix a partition {D k : k<ω} of ω into infinite subsets. For every sequence ā = a n : n<ω of pairwise disjoint subsets of ω and k<ωput a k = {a n : n D k }. In addition, for every h Kwe put a h = {a nh (k): k<ω} where n h (k) = min{n D k : n>max{h(k),k}}. We also put F (ā) ={a k: k<ω} {a h : h K} [P(ω)] ω1. Next, we will construct an increasing sequence B ξ [P(ω)] ω1 : ξ ω 1 of subalgebras of P(ω) aiming for B = B ω1. Thus, we choose B 0 as an arbitrary subalgebra of P(ω) with B 0 = ω 1 and for limit ordinal numbers λ ω 1 we put B λ = ξ<λ B ξ. The algebra B ξ+1 is formed from B ξ in the following way. Let {b η : η < ω 1 } be an enumeration of B ξ and for η < ω let A ξ η be a subalgebra of B ξ generated by {b ζ : ζ < η}. For each such algebra we apply Lemma to find the sequences ā γ = a γ n: n<ω, γ<ω 1, satisfying (i) and (ii) and let G(A ξ η)= F (ā γ ). γ<ω 1 B ξ+1 is defined as the algebra generated by B ξ η<ω 1 G(A ξ η). This finishes the construction of B. Clearly, B = ω 1. To prove that cof(b) =ω 1 it is enough to show that B is not a union of an increasing sequence B = B n : n<ω of proper subalgebras. So, by way of contradiction, assume that such a sequence B exists. For every n<ωchoose b n B \ B n and find ξ,η < ω 1 such that {b n : n<ω} A ξ η. Then the algebras A n = B n A ξ η form an increasing sequence of proper subalgebras of A = A ξ η. Thus, one of the sequences ā γ satisfies (ii) for Ā. So, if we put ā γ =ā = a n : n<ω we conclude that {a k : k<ω} {ah : h K} B. Let f(k) = min{n <ω: a k B n} and let h Kbe such that f(k) <h(k) for all k<ω. The final contradiction is obtained by noticing that a h cannot belong to any B k. Indeed, if a h B k for some k, then a h a k = a n h (k) belongs to

27 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, B max{f(k),k}, since a k B f(k). But max{f(k),k} max{h(k),k} <n h (k) so we get a nh (k) B nh (k) contradicting the fact that a nh (k) belongs to Ā\A n h (k), which is disjoint with B nh (k). 1.4 Selective ultrafilters and the reaping numbers r and r σ In this section, which in part is based on [30], we will show that CPA cube implies that every selective ultrafilter is generated by ω 1 sets and that the reaping number r is equal to ω 1. The actual construction of a selective ultrafilter will require a stronger version of the axiom and will be done in Theorem We will use here the terminology introduced in the Preliminaries Section. In particular, recall that the ideal [ω] <ω of finite subsets of ω is semiselective. The most important combinatorial fact for us concerning semiselective ideals is the following property. (See theorem 2.1 and remark 4.1 in [40].) This is a generalization of a theorem of Laver [65] who proved this fact for the ideal I =[ω] <ω. Proposition (Farah [40]) Let I be a semiselective ideal on ω. For every analytic set S C ω [ω] ω and every A I + there exist a B I + P(A) and a perfect cube C in C ω such that C [B] ω is either contained in or disjoint with S. With this fact in hand we can prove the following theorem. Theorem Assume that CPA cube holds. If I is a semiselective ideal then there is a family W I +, W ω 1, such that for every analytic set A [ω] ω there is a W W for which either [W ] ω A or [W ] ω A =. Proof. Let S C [ω] ω be a universal analytic set, that is such that the family {S x : x C} (where S x = {y [ω] ω : x, y S}) contains all analytic subsets of [ω] ω. (See e.g. [51, lemma 39.4].) In fact, we will take S such that for any analytic set A in [ω] ω {x C: S x = A} = c. (1.10) For this particular set S consider the family E of all Q Perf(C) for which there exists a W Q I + such that Q [W Q ] ω is either contained in or disjoint with S. (1.11) Note that, by Proposition 1.4.1, family E is F cube -dense in Perf(C). So, by CPA cube, there exists an E 0 E, E 0 ω 1, such that C \ E 0 < c. Let W = {W Q : Q E 0 }. It is enough to see that this W is as required.

28 28 Covering Property Axiom CPA March 12, 2001 Clearly W ω 1. Also, by (1.10), for an analytic set A [ω] ω there exist a Q E 0 and an x Q such that A = S x. So, by (1.11), {x} [W Q ] ω is either contained in or disjoint with {x} S x = {x} A. Recall (see e.g. [4] or [98]) that a family W [ω] ω is a reaping family provided A [ω] ω W W (W A or W ω \ A). The reaping (or refinement) number r is defined as r = min { W : W [ω] ω & A [ω] ω W W (W A or W ω \ A)}. Also, a number r σ is defined as the smallest cardinality of a family W [ω] ω such that for every sequence A n [ω] ω : n<ω there exists a W Wsuch that for every n<ωeither W A n or W ω \ A n. (See [15] or [98].) Clearly r r σ. Corollary If CPA cube holds then for every semiselective ideal I there exists a family W I +, W ω 1, such that for every A [ω] ω there is a W W for which either W A or W ω \ A. In particular, CPA cube implies that r = ω 1 < c. Proof. Family W from Theorem works: since [A] ω is analytic in [ω] ω there exists a W W such that either [W ] ω [A] ω or [W ] ω [A] ω =. Note also that CPA cube implies the second of the property (E). Corollary If CPA cube holds then every selective ultrafilter F on ω is generated by a family of size ω 1 < c. Proof. If F is a selective ultrafilter on ω then I = P(ω) \F is a selective ideal and I + = F. Let W I + = F be as in Corollary Then W generates F. Indeed, if A Fthen there exists a W Wsuch that either W A or W ω \ A. But it is impossible that W ω \ A since then we would have = A W F. As mentioned above, in Theorem we will prove that some version of our axiom implies that there exists a selective ultrafilter on ω. In particular, the assumption of the next corollary are implied by such a version of our axiom. Corollary If CPA cube holds and there exists a selective ultrafilter F on ω then r σ = ω 1 < c. Proof. Let W [F] ω1 be a generating family for F. We will show that it justifies r σ = ω 1. Indeed, take a sequence A n [ω] ω : n<ω. For every n<ω let A n belongs to F {A n,ω\ A n }. Since F is selective, there exists an A F such that A A n for every n<ω. Let W Wbe such that W A. Then for every n<ωeither W A n or W ω \ A n. We got some special interest in number r σ since it is related to different variants of sets of uniqueness coming from harmonic analysis, as described in a survey paper [15]. In particular, from [15, thm. 12.6] it follows that an appropriate version of our axiom implies that all covering numbers described in the paper are equal to ω 1.

SMALL COMBINATORIAL CARDINAL CHARACTERISTICS AND THEOREMS OF EGOROV AND BLUMBERG

SMALL COMBINATORIAL CARDINAL CHARACTERISTICS AND THEOREMS OF EGOROV AND BLUMBERG Real Analysis Exchange Vol. 26(2), 2000/2001, pp. 905 911 Krzysztof Ciesielski, Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, USA, email: K Cies@math.wvu.edu, internet:

More information

Covering Property Axiom CPA cube and its consequences

Covering Property Axiom CPA cube and its consequences Covering Property Axiom CPA cube and its consequences Krzysztof Ciesielski Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, USA e-mail: K Cies@math.wvu.edu; web page: http://www.math.wvu.edu/~kcies

More information

Uncountable γ-sets under axiom CPA game

Uncountable γ-sets under axiom CPA game F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 176 (2003) Uncountable γ-sets under axiom CPA game by Krzysztof Ciesielski (Morgantown, WV), Andrés Millán (Morgantown, WV) and Janusz Pawlikowski (Wrocław) Abstract. We

More information

On sums of Darboux and nowhere constant continuous functions

On sums of Darboux and nowhere constant continuous functions On sums of Darboux and nowhere constant continuous functions Krzysztof Ciesielski Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, USA e-mail: K Cies@math.wvu.edu; web page:

More information

SOME ADDITIVE DARBOUX LIKE FUNCTIONS

SOME ADDITIVE DARBOUX LIKE FUNCTIONS Journal of Applied Analysis Vol. 4, No. 1 (1998), pp. 43 51 SOME ADDITIVE DARBOUX LIKE FUNCTIONS K. CIESIELSKI Received June 11, 1997 and, in revised form, September 16, 1997 Abstract. In this note we

More information

The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane

The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane Krzysztof P lotka Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, USA kplotka@math.wvu.edu and Institute of Mathematics,

More information

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS MARCIN KYSIAK AND TOMASZ WEISS Abstract. We discuss the question which properties of smallness in the sense of measure and category (e.g. being a universally

More information

Covering Property Axiom CPA

Covering Property Axiom CPA Covering Property Axiom CPA A combinatorial core of the iterated perfect set model Krzysztof Ciesielski Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, USA e-mail: K Cies@math.wvu.edu

More information

arxiv:math.gn/ v1 6 Dec 2003

arxiv:math.gn/ v1 6 Dec 2003 SPM BULLETIN ISSUE NUMBER 6: NOVEMBER 2003 CE arxiv:math.gn/0312140 v1 6 Dec 2003 Contents 1. Editor s note 1 Previous issues 1 Contributions 2 Subscription 2 2. Research announcements 2 2.1. The Topological

More information

Classical Theory of Cardinal Characteristics

Classical Theory of Cardinal Characteristics Classical Theory of Cardinal Characteristics Andreas Blass University of Michigan 22 August, 2018 Andreas Blass (University of Michigan) Classical Theory of Cardinal Characteristics 22 August, 2018 1 /

More information

Differentiability on perfect subsets P of R; Smooth Peano functions from P onto P 2

Differentiability on perfect subsets P of R; Smooth Peano functions from P onto P 2 Differentiability on perfect subsets P of R; Smooth Peano functions from P onto P 2 Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University and MIPG, Departmentof Radiology, University

More information

Ultrafilters with property (s)

Ultrafilters with property (s) Ultrafilters with property (s) Arnold W. Miller 1 Abstract A set X 2 ω has property (s) (Marczewski (Szpilrajn)) iff for every perfect set P 2 ω there exists a perfect set Q P such that Q X or Q X =. Suppose

More information

A model with no magic set

A model with no magic set A model with no magic set Krzysztof Ciesielski Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, USA KCies@wvnvms.wvnet.edu Saharon Shelah Institute of Mathematics, the Hebrew

More information

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d Fields October 24, 2012 Notation If A and B are subsets of N let denote the equivalence relation defined by A B if and only if A B is finite. Let [A]

More information

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS NATHAN BOWLER AND STEFAN GESCHKE Abstract. We extend the notion of a uniform matroid to the infinitary case and construct, using weak fragments of Martin s Axiom,

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

Adam Kwela. Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS. Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12)

Adam Kwela. Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS. Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12) Adam Kwela Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12) Opiekun pracy: Piotr Zakrzewski 1. Introduction We study property (S),

More information

Notation 163. (X) 31. Perf (X) 31. GAME cube (X) 31. CPA game

Notation 163. (X) 31. Perf (X) 31. GAME cube (X) 31. CPA game Notation r the reaping number, xiii. G ω1 the family of intersections of ω 1 open subsets of a Polish space, xv. E + (A) linear combinations of A R with nonnegative rational coefficients, xvii. u xvii.

More information

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions vanrooijschikhof.tex April 25, 2018 van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions Notes from [vrs]. Introduction A monotone function is Riemann integrable. A continuous function is Riemann integrable.

More information

SET THEORETIC REAL ANALYSIS

SET THEORETIC REAL ANALYSIS Journal of Applied Analysis Vol. 3, No. 2 (1997), pp. 143 190 Special invited paper SET THEORETIC REAL ANALYSIS K. CIESIELSKI Received February 25, 1997 and, in revised form, September 8, 1997 Abstract.

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies University of Wisconsin, Madison July 2016 The Borel hierachy is described as follows: open = Σ 0 1 = G closed = Π 0 1 = F Π 0 2 = G δ = countable intersections of open sets Σ 0 2 = F σ = countable unions

More information

ON FUNCTIONS WHOSE GRAPH IS A HAMEL BASIS II

ON FUNCTIONS WHOSE GRAPH IS A HAMEL BASIS II To the memory of my Mother ON FUNCTIONS WHOSE GRAPH IS A HAMEL BASIS II KRZYSZTOF P LOTKA Abstract. We say that a function h: R R is a Hamel function (h HF) if h, considered as a subset of R 2, is a Hamel

More information

FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES

FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES ALAN DOW AND RODRIGO HERNÁNDEZ-GUTIÉRREZ Abstract. We give a partial solution to a question by Alas, Junqueria and Wilson by proving that under PFA the one-point

More information

Measures and Measure Spaces

Measures and Measure Spaces Chapter 2 Measures and Measure Spaces In summarizing the flaws of the Riemann integral we can focus on two main points: 1) Many nice functions are not Riemann integrable. 2) The Riemann integral does not

More information

ALGEBRAIC SUMS OF SETS IN MARCZEWSKI BURSTIN ALGEBRAS

ALGEBRAIC SUMS OF SETS IN MARCZEWSKI BURSTIN ALGEBRAS François G. Dorais, Department of Mathematics, Dartmouth College, 6188 Bradley Hall, Hanover, NH 03755, USA (e-mail: francois.g.dorais@dartmouth.edu) Rafa l Filipów, Institute of Mathematics, University

More information

Homogeneous spaces and Wadge theory

Homogeneous spaces and Wadge theory Homogeneous spaces and Wadge theory Andrea Medini Kurt Gödel Research Center University of Vienna July 18, 2018 Everybody loves homogeneous stuff! Topological homogeneity A space is homogeneous if all

More information

CARDINAL INVARIANTS CONCERNING EXTENDABLE AND PERIPHERALLY CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS

CARDINAL INVARIANTS CONCERNING EXTENDABLE AND PERIPHERALLY CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS RESEARCH Real Analysis Exchange Vol. 21(2), 1995 96, pp. 459 472 Krzysztof Ciesielski, Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, e-mail: kcies@@wvnvms.wvnet.edu Ireneusz

More information

Every Lusin set is undetermined in the point-open game

Every Lusin set is undetermined in the point-open game F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 144 (1994) Every Lusin set is undetermined in the point-open game by Ireneusz Recław (Gdańsk) Abstract. We show that some classes of small sets are topological versions

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

ON FUNCTIONS WHOSE GRAPH IS A HAMEL BASIS

ON FUNCTIONS WHOSE GRAPH IS A HAMEL BASIS ON FUNCTIONS WHOSE GRAPH IS A HAMEL BASIS KRZYSZTOF P LOTKA Abstract. We say that a function h: R R is a Hamel function (h HF) if h, considered as a subset of R 2, is a Hamel basis for R 2. We prove that

More information

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies On the Length of Borel Hierarchies Arnold W. Miller November 7, 2016 This is a survey paper on the lengths of Borel hierarchies and related hierarchies. It consists of lecture notes of a lecture given

More information

PRODUCTS OF SPECIAL SETS OF REAL NUMBERS

PRODUCTS OF SPECIAL SETS OF REAL NUMBERS Real Analysis Exchange Vol. 30(2), 2004/2005, pp. 819 836 Boaz Tsaban, Department of Applied Mathematics and Computer Science, The Weizmann Institute of Science, Rehovot 76100, Israel. email: boaz.tsaban@weizmann.ac.il

More information

The topology of ultrafilters as subspaces of 2 ω

The topology of ultrafilters as subspaces of 2 ω Many non-homeomorphic ultrafilters Basic properties Overview of the results Andrea Medini 1 David Milovich 2 1 Department of Mathematics University of Wisconsin - Madison 2 Department of Engineering, Mathematics,

More information

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Rend. Istit. Mat. Univ. Trieste Volume 41 (2009), 27 33. Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Fernando Hernández-Hernández Abstract. We compute the distributivity numbers

More information

int cl int cl A = int cl A.

int cl int cl A = int cl A. BAIRE CATEGORY CHRISTIAN ROSENDAL 1. THE BAIRE CATEGORY THEOREM Theorem 1 (The Baire category theorem. Let (D n n N be a countable family of dense open subsets of a Polish space X. Then n N D n is dense

More information

Strong Fubini properties of ideals

Strong Fubini properties of ideals F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 159 (1999) Strong Fubini properties of ideals by Ireneusz R e c ł a w (Gdańsk) and Piotr Z a k r z e w s k i (Warszawa) Abstract. Let I and J be σ-ideals on Polish spaces

More information

MONOTONE BOREL HULLS FOR BAIRE PROPERTY ANDRZEJ ROS LANOWSKI AND SAHARON SHELAH

MONOTONE BOREL HULLS FOR BAIRE PROPERTY ANDRZEJ ROS LANOWSKI AND SAHARON SHELAH MONOTONE BOREL HULLS FOR BAIRE PROPERTY ANDRZEJ ROS LANOWSKI AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We show that if the meager ideal admits a monotone Borel hull operation, then there is also a monotone Borel hull

More information

Uniquely Universal Sets

Uniquely Universal Sets Uniquely Universal Sets 1 Uniquely Universal Sets Abstract 1 Arnold W. Miller We say that X Y satisfies the Uniquely Universal property (UU) iff there exists an open set U X Y such that for every open

More information

Compact subsets of the Baire space

Compact subsets of the Baire space Compact subsets of the Baire space Arnold W. Miller Nov 2012 Results in this note were obtained in 1994 and reported on at a meeting on Real Analysis in Lodz, Poland, July 1994. Let ω ω be the Baire space,

More information

G δ ideals of compact sets

G δ ideals of compact sets J. Eur. Math. Soc. 13, 853 882 c European Mathematical Society 2011 DOI 10.4171/JEMS/268 Sławomir Solecki G δ ideals of compact sets Received January 1, 2008 and in revised form January 2, 2009 Abstract.

More information

ON THE LACZKOVICH-KOMJÁTH PROPERTY OF SIGMA-IDEALS. 1. Introduction

ON THE LACZKOVICH-KOMJÁTH PROPERTY OF SIGMA-IDEALS. 1. Introduction ON THE LACZKOVICH-KOMJÁTH PROPERTY OF SIGMA-IDEALS MAREK BALCERZAK AND SZYMON G LA B Abstract. Komjáth in 984 proved that, for each sequence (A n) of analytic subsets of a Polish apace X, if lim sup n

More information

TIE-POINTS, REGULAR CLOSED SETS, AND COPIES OF N

TIE-POINTS, REGULAR CLOSED SETS, AND COPIES OF N TIE-POINTS, REGULAR CLOSED SETS, AND COPIES OF N ALAN DOW Abstract. We show that it is consistent to have a non-trivial embedding of N into itself even if all autohomeomorphisms of N are trivial. 1. Introduction

More information

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, 2017 1 Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski Class of August 17: Course and syllabus overview. Topology

More information

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France Maharam Algebras Boban Veličković Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France Abstract Maharam algebras are complete Boolean algebras carrying a positive continuous submeasure.

More information

Title Covering a bounded set of functions by Author(s) Kada, Masaru Editor(s) Citation Topology and its Applications. 2007, 1 Issue Date 2007-01 URL http://hdl.handle.net/10466/12488 Rights c2007 Elsevier

More information

Cofinalities of Marczewski-like ideals

Cofinalities of Marczewski-like ideals Cofinalities of Marczewski-like ideals Jörg Brendle Graduate School of System Informatics Kobe University Rokko-dai 1-1, Nada-ku Kobe 657-8501, Japan email: brendle@kobe-u.ac.jp and Yurii Khomskii Hamburg

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS LAJOS SOUKUP Abstract. The additivity spectrum ADD(I) of an ideal I P(I) is the set of all regular cardinals κ such that there is an increasing chain {A

More information

Template iterations with non-definable ccc forcing notions

Template iterations with non-definable ccc forcing notions Template iterations with non-definable ccc forcing notions Diego Alejandro Mejía Graduate School of System Informatics, Kobe University, Kobe, Japan. damejiag@kurt.scitec.kobe-u.ac.jp arxiv:1305.4740v4

More information

Solutions to Homework Assignment 2

Solutions to Homework Assignment 2 Solutions to Homework Assignment Real Analysis I February, 03 Notes: (a) Be aware that there maybe some typos in the solutions. If you find any, please let me know. (b) As is usual in proofs, most problems

More information

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE ALAN DOW AND ISTVÁN JUHÁSZ Abstract. A space has σ-compact tightness if the closures of σ-compact subsets determines the topology. We consider a dense

More information

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals Boban Velickovic Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France Abstract Prikry asked if it is relatively consistent with the usual axioms

More information

ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS. Tomek Bartoszyński

ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS. Tomek Bartoszyński ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS Tomek Bartoszyński Department of Mathematics, Boise State University Boise, ID 83725 (U.S.A.) Email: tomek@diamond.boisestate.edu Lorenz Halbeisen

More information

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS 1. Cardinal number of a set The cardinal number (or simply cardinal) of a set is a generalization of the concept of the number of elements

More information

Infinite Combinatorics, Definability, and Forcing

Infinite Combinatorics, Definability, and Forcing Infinite Combinatorics, Definability, and Forcing David Schrittesser University of Copenhagen (Denmark) RIMS Workshop on Infinite Combinatorics and Forcing Theory Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Combinatorics,

More information

WHEN AN ATOMIC AND COMPLETE ALGEBRA OF SETS IS A FIELD OF SETS WITH NOWHERE DENSE BOUNDARY

WHEN AN ATOMIC AND COMPLETE ALGEBRA OF SETS IS A FIELD OF SETS WITH NOWHERE DENSE BOUNDARY WHEN AN ATOMIC AND COMPLETE ALGEBRA OF SETS IS A FIELD OF SETS WITH NOWHERE DENSE BOUNDARY ARTUR BARTOSZEWICZ AND PIOTR KOSZMIDER Abstract. We consider pairs A, H(A) where A is an algebra of sets from

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

Measurable Envelopes, Hausdorff Measures and Sierpiński Sets

Measurable Envelopes, Hausdorff Measures and Sierpiński Sets arxiv:1109.5305v1 [math.ca] 24 Sep 2011 Measurable Envelopes, Hausdorff Measures and Sierpiński Sets Márton Elekes Department of Analysis, Eötvös Loránd University Budapest, Pázmány Péter sétány 1/c, 1117,

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Hongtaek Jung December 27, 2017 Abstract This is a part of a supplementary note for a Logic and Set Theory course. The main goal is to

More information

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then MH 7500 THEOREMS Definition. A topological space is an ordered pair (X, T ), where X is a set and T is a collection of subsets of X such that (i) T and X T ; (ii) U V T whenever U, V T ; (iii) U T whenever

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski The onto mapping property of Sierpinski A. Miller July 2014 revised May 2016 (*) There exists (φ n : ω 1 ω 1 : n < ω) such that for every I [ω 1 ] ω 1 there exists n such that φ n (I) = ω 1. This is roughly

More information

ON DENSITY TOPOLOGIES WITH RESPECT

ON DENSITY TOPOLOGIES WITH RESPECT Journal of Applied Analysis Vol. 8, No. 2 (2002), pp. 201 219 ON DENSITY TOPOLOGIES WITH RESPECT TO INVARIANT σ-ideals J. HEJDUK Received June 13, 2001 and, in revised form, December 17, 2001 Abstract.

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries Chapter 1 Measure Spaces 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets 1.1.1 Notation and preliminaries We shall denote by X a nonempty set, by P(X) the set of all parts (i.e., subsets) of X, and by the empty set.

More information

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY THOMAS GILTON AND JOHN KRUEGER Abstract. Assuming the existence of a Mahlo cardinal, we construct a model in which there exists an ω 2 -Aronszajn tree, the ω 1 -approachability

More information

Measure and Integration: Concepts, Examples and Exercises. INDER K. RANA Indian Institute of Technology Bombay India

Measure and Integration: Concepts, Examples and Exercises. INDER K. RANA Indian Institute of Technology Bombay India Measure and Integration: Concepts, Examples and Exercises INDER K. RANA Indian Institute of Technology Bombay India Department of Mathematics, Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay, Powai, Mumbai 400076,

More information

Slow P -point Ultrafilters

Slow P -point Ultrafilters Slow P -point Ultrafilters Renling Jin College of Charleston jinr@cofc.edu Abstract We answer a question of Blass, Di Nasso, and Forti [2, 7] by proving, assuming Continuum Hypothesis or Martin s Axiom,

More information

Irredundant Generators

Irredundant Generators rredundant Generators Jonathan Cancino, Osvaldo Guzmán, Arnold W. Miller May 21, 2014 Abstract We say that is an irredundant family if no element of is a subset mod finite of a union of finitely many other

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n 8 CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Wojciech Stadnicki. On Laver extension. Uniwersytet Wrocławski. Praca semestralna nr 2 (semestr letni 2010/11) Opiekun pracy: Janusz Pawlikowski

Wojciech Stadnicki. On Laver extension. Uniwersytet Wrocławski. Praca semestralna nr 2 (semestr letni 2010/11) Opiekun pracy: Janusz Pawlikowski Wojciech Stadnicki Uniwersytet Wrocławski On Laver extension Praca semestralna nr 2 (semestr letni 2010/11) Opiekun pracy: Janusz Pawlikowski On Laver extension Wojciech Stadnicki Abstract We prove that

More information

IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS

IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS CARLOS DI PRISCO, JOSÉ G. MIJARES, AND CARLOS UZCÁTEGUI Abstract. It is shown that Matet s characterization ([9]) of the Ramsey property relative to a selective co-ideal H,

More information

1/12/05: sec 3.1 and my article: How good is the Lebesgue measure?, Math. Intelligencer 11(2) (1989),

1/12/05: sec 3.1 and my article: How good is the Lebesgue measure?, Math. Intelligencer 11(2) (1989), Real Analysis 2, Math 651, Spring 2005 April 26, 2005 1 Real Analysis 2, Math 651, Spring 2005 Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski 1/12/05: sec 3.1 and my article: How good is the Lebesgue measure?, Math. Intelligencer

More information

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets Countable and Uncountable Sets The concept of countability will be important in this course

More information

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED PROPER FORCING REMASTERED BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ AND GIORGIO VENTURI Abstract. We present the method introduced by Neeman of generalized side conditions with two types of models. We then discuss some applications:

More information

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski Stevo Todorcevic Berkeley, April 2, 2014 Outline 1. Global Chain Conditions 2. The Countable Chain Condition 3. Chain Conditions of Knaster, Shanin and Szpilrajn 4.

More information

Abstract Measure Theory

Abstract Measure Theory 2 Abstract Measure Theory Lebesgue measure is one of the premier examples of a measure on R d, but it is not the only measure and certainly not the only important measure on R d. Further, R d is not the

More information

Measure and Category. Marianna Csörnyei. ucahmcs

Measure and Category. Marianna Csörnyei.   ucahmcs Measure and Category Marianna Csörnyei mari@math.ucl.ac.uk http:/www.ucl.ac.uk/ ucahmcs 1 / 96 A (very short) Introduction to Cardinals The cardinality of a set A is equal to the cardinality of a set B,

More information

TUKEY QUOTIENTS, PRE-IDEALS, AND NEIGHBORHOOD FILTERS WITH CALIBRE (OMEGA 1, OMEGA) by Jeremiah Morgan BS, York College of Pennsylvania, 2010

TUKEY QUOTIENTS, PRE-IDEALS, AND NEIGHBORHOOD FILTERS WITH CALIBRE (OMEGA 1, OMEGA) by Jeremiah Morgan BS, York College of Pennsylvania, 2010 TUKEY QUOTIENTS, PRE-IDEALS, AND NEIGHBORHOOD FILTERS WITH CALIBRE (OMEGA 1, OMEGA) by Jeremiah Morgan BS, York College of Pennsylvania, 2010 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 4 Sep 2010

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 4 Sep 2010 BERNSTEIN SETS AND κ-coverings arxiv:1009.0818v1 [math.lo] 4 Sep 2010 JAN KRASZEWSKI, ROBERT RA LOWSKI, PRZEMYS LAW SZCZEPANIAK AND SZYMON ŻEBERSKI Abstract. In this paper we study a notion of a κ-covering

More information

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University January 9, 2017 V : The Universe of Sets The power set Suppose X is a set. The powerset of X

More information

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) VI.1 : Indexed families and set theoretic operations (Halmos, 4, 8 9; Lipschutz, 5.3 5.4) Lipschutz : 5.3 5.6, 5.29 5.32, 9.14 1. Generalize

More information

Models in which every nonmeager set is nonmeager in a nowhere dense Cantor set arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 25 Nov 2003

Models in which every nonmeager set is nonmeager in a nowhere dense Cantor set arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 25 Nov 2003 Models in which every nonmeager set is nonmeager in a nowhere dense Cantor set arxiv:math/0311443v1 [math.lo] 25 Nov 2003 Maxim R. Burke Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Prince Edward

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

Souslin s Hypothesis

Souslin s Hypothesis Michiel Jespers Souslin s Hypothesis Bachelor thesis, August 15, 2013 Supervisor: dr. K.P. Hart Mathematical Institute, Leiden University Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Trees 2 3 The -Principle 7 4 Martin

More information

A NEW CLASS OF RAMSEY-CLASSIFICATION THEOREMS AND THEIR APPLICATION IN THE TUKEY THEORY OF ULTRAFILTERS, PART 1

A NEW CLASS OF RAMSEY-CLASSIFICATION THEOREMS AND THEIR APPLICATION IN THE TUKEY THEORY OF ULTRAFILTERS, PART 1 TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 00, Number 0, Pages 000 000 S 0002-9947(XX)0000-0 A NEW CLASS OF RAMSEY-CLASSIFICATION THEOREMS AND THEIR APPLICATION IN THE TUKEY THEORY OF ULTRAFILTERS,

More information

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id: Name: Student Id: There are nine problems (check that you have 9 pages). Solutions are expected to be short. In the case of proofs, one or two short paragraphs should be the average length. Write your

More information

CHAPTER 5. The Topology of R. 1. Open and Closed Sets

CHAPTER 5. The Topology of R. 1. Open and Closed Sets CHAPTER 5 The Topology of R 1. Open and Closed Sets DEFINITION 5.1. A set G Ω R is open if for every x 2 G there is an " > 0 such that (x ", x + ") Ω G. A set F Ω R is closed if F c is open. The idea is

More information

MATS113 ADVANCED MEASURE THEORY SPRING 2016

MATS113 ADVANCED MEASURE THEORY SPRING 2016 MATS113 ADVANCED MEASURE THEORY SPRING 2016 Foreword These are the lecture notes for the course Advanced Measure Theory given at the University of Jyväskylä in the Spring of 2016. The lecture notes can

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Topological homogeneity and infinite powers

Topological homogeneity and infinite powers Kurt Gödel Research Center University of Vienna June 24, 2015 Homogeneity an ubiquitous notion in mathematics is... Topological homogeneity Let H(X) denote the group of homeomorphisms of X. A space is

More information

TOPOLOGICAL RAMSEY SPACES DENSE IN FORCINGS

TOPOLOGICAL RAMSEY SPACES DENSE IN FORCINGS TOPOLOGICAL RAMSEY SPACES DENSE IN FORCINGS NATASHA DOBRINEN Abstract. Topological Ramsey spaces are spaces which support infinite dimensional Ramsey theory similarly to the Ellentuck space. Each topological

More information

Author s review of his research, achievements and publications

Author s review of his research, achievements and publications Appendix 4 Author s review of his research, achievements and publications 1. Name: Robert Rałowski 2. Obtained diplomas and academic degrees: M. Sc. in Physics, Wrocław University of Technology, 1989,

More information

Playing with forcing

Playing with forcing Winterschool, 2 February 2009 Idealized forcings Many forcing notions arise as quotient Boolean algebras of the form P I = Bor(X )/I, where X is a Polish space and I is an ideal of Borel sets. Idealized

More information

COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS TODD EISWORTH Abstract. We prove that the Continuum Hypothesis is consistent with the statement that countably compact regular

More information

Hypergraphs and proper forcing

Hypergraphs and proper forcing Hypergraphs and proper forcing Jindřich Zapletal University of Florida November 23, 2017 Abstract Given a Polish space X and a countable collection of analytic hypergraphs on X, I consider the σ-ideal

More information

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS Chapter 6 MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS This chapter can be considered enrichment material containing also several more advanced topics and may be skipped in its entirety. You can proceed directly

More information