Slow P -point Ultrafilters

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Slow P -point Ultrafilters"

Transcription

1 Slow P -point Ultrafilters Renling Jin College of Charleston jinr@cofc.edu Abstract We answer a question of Blass, Di Nasso, and Forti [2, 7] by proving, assuming Continuum Hypothesis or Martin s Axiom, that (1) there exists a P -point which is not interval-to-one and (2) there exists an interval-to-one P -point which is neither quasi-selective nor weakly Ramsey. 1 Introduction Quasi-selective ultrafilter is first introduced in [4] where it is actually called smooth ultrafilter. Quasi-selective ultrafilter is interesting because the existence of such ultrafilters is equivalent to the existence of coherent fine densities [4, Theorem 3.2] and to the existence of asymptotic numerosities [2, Corollary 5.3]. Since a selective ultrafilter is quasi-selective and a quasiselective ultrafilter is a P -point, it is natural to study whether these three classes of ultrafilters are really distinct. It is shown in [2] that, under CH, these three classes of ultrafilters are distinct. In fact, the quasi-selective nonselective ultrafilter F constructed in [2] is also weakly Ramsey. In [7] it is pointed out that both quasi-selective ultrafilters and weakly Ramsey ultrafilters are a special kind of P -points, called interval-to-one P -points. The question whether the class of P -points, the class of interval-to-one P -points, and the class of quasi-selective or weakly Ramsey ultrafilters are distinct is asked in both [2, page 1484] and [7, page 11]. Since by a celebrated result Mathematics Subject Classification 2010 Primary 03E05, 03E65 Keywords: slow ultrafilter, P -point, interval-to-one P -point, quasi-selective ultrafilter, weakly Ramsey ultrafilter Acknowledgment: This work was partially supported by a collaboration grant (ID: ) from Simons Foundation. 1

2 of S. Shelah [10] it is consistent that there exist no P -points, we can only discuss the differences between these ultrafilters under some set theoretical assumptions beyond ZFC such as, for example, CH (Continuum Hypothesis), MA (Martin s Axiom), etc. In this paper we show that these classes of ultrafilters are distinct assuming either CH or MA. Rapid ultrafilters are another class of ultrafilters closely related to selective ultrafilters and P -points. It is shown in [2, Corollary 1.6] that an ultrafilter F is selective if and only if it is rapid and quasi-selective. In [12] it is shown that an ultrafilter F is rapid if and only if the intersection of F with any tall summable ideal is non-empty. Therefore, a non-selective quasi-selective ultrafilter F must have empty intersection with some tall summable ideal I f determined by a non-increasing function f : N [0, 1]. As an antonym for the word rapid we call an ultrafilter f-slow if it is disjoint from I f. In this paper we want to find P -point ultrafilters which are not interval-toone and interval-to-one P -point ultrafilters which are neither quasi-selective nor weakly Ramsey. We look for these ultrafilters among all f-slow ultrafilters for some f. Indeed, we do find them by carefully controlling the speeds of their slow-ness. In Section 2 we state the definitions of various involved ideals and filters. Although many of these definitions are well-known to a set theorist, we include the definitions here to make the paper somewhat self-contained. In Section 3 we prove our results under CH and in Section 4 we do the same under MA 1. Some open problems are in Section 5. 2 Summable ideals and slow ultrafilters By an interval [a, b] we mean an interval of integers {x Z a x b}. Occasionally, we use the interval notation [0, 1] for the unit interval of reals. Hope that won t cause confusion. Let N be the set of all positive integers. Definition 2.1 A family of sets I P(N) is a free ideal if 1. N I, 2. F I for every finite or empty subset F of N, 3. A I and B A imply B I, and 1 In fact, we need only MA for σ-centered partial orders. 2

3 4. A B I for any A, B I. Definition 2.2 A family of sets F P(N) is a free filter if 1. F, 2. N \ F F for every finite or empty subset F of N, 3. A F and B A imply B F, and 4. A B F for any A, B F. A free filter F is called an ultrafilter if A F or N \ A F for any A N. Since all ideals and filters considered in this paper are free, we will omit the word free from now on. Clearly, I is an ideal if and only if F = {N \ A A I} is a filter. In that case, I and F are dual of each other. Definition 2.3 Let f : N [0, 1] be a non-increasing function such that f(n) =. The following set I f is called the summable ideal determined n=1 by f where I f := { A N } f(n) <. n A The summable ideal I f is tall if lim n f(n) = 0. Notice that all non-tall summable ideals are the same which is the ideal of all finite subsets of N. For notational convenience we will frequently use the following expression. S(f, A) := n A f(n). (1) Definition 2.4 Let I f be a summable ideal determined by f. An ultrafilter F is called f-slow if F contains the dual filter of I f. Notice that an ultrafilter F is f-slow if and only if S(f, A) = for all A F. 3

4 Definition 2.5 Let A N be an infinite set and g : A N. The function g is called finite-to-one if g 1 (n) is a finite set for every n N. An ultrafilter F is called a P -point if for every function g : N N there exists an A F such that g A is either a constant function or a finite-to-one function. Notice that a function g : N N can be viewed as a partition {g 1 (n) n N} of N and a partition P = {B n n N} of N can be viewed as a function g P with g P (x) = n if and only if x B n. Definition 2.6 Let A N be an infinite set and g : A N. The function g is called interval-to-one if the intervals in C = {[min(g 1 (n)), sup(g 1 (n))] n N and g 1 (n) } are pairwise disjoint. A P -point F is said to be interval-to-one if for every function g : N N, there is an A F such that g A is interval-to-one. Notice that the collection C above can contain an infinite interval when {n g 1 (n) } is a finite set. If sup S =, the interval [a, sup S] means [a, ). Otherwise, sup(g 1 (n)) = max(g 1 (n)). Definition 2.7 An ultrafilter F is selective if for every function g : N N there is an A F such that g A is either a constant function or a one-to-one function. Definition 2.8 An ultrafilter F is said to be quasi-selective if for every function g : N N with g(n) n for all n N, there exists an A F such that g A is a non-decreasing function. Let X be a set and [X] 2 := {{a, b} a, b X and a b}. Definition 2.9 An ultrafilter F is Ramsey if for every function c : [N] 2 {0, 1} there is an A F such that range(c [A] 2 ) = 1. The set A above is called a c-homogeneous set. Definition 2.10 An ultrafilter F is said to be weakly Ramsey if for every function c : [N] 2 {0, 1, 2} there is an A F such that range(c [A] 2 ) 2. 4

5 It is a well-known fact that an ultrafilter is selective if and only if it is Ramsey. A selective ultrafilter is quasi-selective as well as weakly Ramsey, and a quasi-selective ultrafilter or a weakly Ramsey ultrafilter is an interval-to-one P -point [2, 7]. Definition 2.11 An ultrafilter F is rapid if for every finite-to-one function g : N N, there exists an A F such that g 1 (n) A n for all n N. It is shown in [12] that if F is a rapid ultrafilter and I f is a tall summable ideal determined by f, then F I f. We say that A is almost a subset of B, denoted by A B, if A \ B is a finite set. The reader may find other basic information on ultrafilters in [1, 3] and basic information on set theory, especially Continuum Hypothesis and Martin s Axiom in [8, 9]. 3 Assuming CH deter- Theorem 3.1 Assume that CH holds. For each summable ideal I f mined by f, there exists an f-slow P -point. Proof: By CH we can list all functions from N to N as {g α α < ℵ 1 }. We define sets A α inductively on all ordinals α < ℵ 1 such that for any α < < ℵ 1 1. A α I f, 2. A A α, and 3. either A α+1 gα 1 (n) for some n N or A α+1 gα 1 (n) < for every n N. The theorem follows from the construction because the ultrafilter F generated by {A α α < ℵ 1 } is an f-slow P -point. Indeed, {A α α < ℵ 1 } has FIP (finite intersection property) by 2. Also F is a P -point by 3. For f-slowness, if C I f, then {C, N \ C} is a partition of N, and hence N \ C A α for some α < ℵ 1 by 1. and 3. We start with A 0 = N. Suppose that {A α α < δ} have been constructed for some δ < ℵ 1 to satisfy 1., 2., and 3. when ℵ 1 is replaced by δ. Case 1: δ is a limit ordinal. 5

6 Let {α n < δ n N} be an increasing sequence of ordinals cofinal in δ. m For each m N, we have A αn I f by 1. and 2. For each m N let n=1 B m = {a i n m i < n m+1 } be a finite increasing sequence of elements in m such that S(f, B m ) 1 (S(f, B m ) is defined in (1)). The sequence n=1 A αn B m can be chosen such that a nm 1, the last element in B m 1, is less than a nm, the first element in B m, for every m N. Let A δ := m=1 B m. The existence of B m is guaranteed due to the fact that S(f, m n=1 A α n ) =. Clearly, {A α α < δ + 1} satisfies 1. and 2. when ℵ 1 is replaced by δ + 1. The condition 3. is vacuous. Case 2: δ = + 1. Let h = g A. If there is an n N such that h 1 (n) I f, let A δ = h 1 (n). Clearly, {A α α < δ + 1} satisfies 1., 2., and 3. when ℵ 1 is replaced by δ + 1. Hence we can assume that h 1 (n) I f for every n N. Let n 0 = 1 and A 0 = A. We now construct an increasing sequence {n i } and a decreasing sequence {A i } of sets not in I f by induction such that S(f, D i ) 1 where D i = A i 1 A i = Ai 1 [n i 1, n i 1] and \ {h 1 (n) h 1 (n) D i }. Notice that there are only finitely many n with h 1 (n) D i. Hence A i I f if A i 1 I f. Suppose we have had n k 1 and A k 1 I f. Let n k be large enough such that S(f, A k 1 [n k 1, n k 1]) 1. The number n k exists because A k 1 I f. Let A k = Ak 1 \ {h 1 (n) h 1 (n) D k } where D k = A k 1 [n k 1, n k 1]. This completes the construction. Let A δ := D i. Then A δ I f because S(f, A δ ) = S(f, D i ) = i N. Clearly, A δ A. For each n N, let k be the smallest such that D k g 1 (n) or k = 1 if D k g 1 (n) = for every k N. Hence D i g 1 (n) = D i h 1 (n) = for every i > k. This shows that A δ g 1 (n) i=1 6

7 [1, n k 1]. Therefore, we have that {A α α < δ + 1} satisfies Conditions 1., 2., and 3. when ℵ 1 is replaced by δ + 1. Notice that if lim n f(n) > 0, then f-slow P -point is just the ordinary P -point. Hence Theorem 3.1 is only interesting when I f is tall. Theorem 3.2 Let f(n) = 1/n. There does not exist interval-to-one f-slow P -point. Proof: Assume by contrary that F is an interval-to-one f-slow P -point. Let a 0 = 0, a n+1 = a n + n 2 for any n 0. Notice that [a n, a n+1 1] is an interval of length n 2. Let B m := {a n + m + in i = 0, 1,..., n 1}. n=m Notice that the set {a n + m + in i = 0, 1,..., n 1} is the m-th arithmetic progression of length n and difference n in [a n, a n+1 1]. Therefore, P = {B m m N} is a partition of N. Since a n+1 = n 2 + (n 1) = 1 n(n + 1)(2n + 1), 6 we have that S(f, B m ) = n=m S(f, B m [a n, a n+1 1]) n=m n a n 1 + n=m+1 3 (n 1) 2 <. Hence B m I f for every m N. Since F is an interval-to-one f-slow P - point, there exists a set A F such that intervals [min(a B), max(a B)] for all B P are pairwise disjoint. Claim A [a n, a n+1 1] 2n. Proof of Claim: Notice that B m [a n, a n+1 1] = for all m > n. Suppose there are k sets B m1, B m2,..., B mk P for some k n such that B mi A [a n, a n+1 1] for i = 1, 2,..., k. Let l i = min(b mi A [a n, a n+1 1]) and u i = max(b mi A [a n, a n+1 1]). Notice that [l i, u i ] A 7

8 contains at most e i := 1 + (u i l i )/n elements from B mi and contains no elements from any other B mj for j i. So n 2 k (u i l i + 1) = i=1 k k (n(e i 1) + 1) = n e i kn + k, i=1 i=1 which implies that A [a n, a n+1 1] k e i 1 n (n2 + kn k) 1 n (2n2 k) 2n. i=1 This completes the proof of the claim. Now the theorem follows from the claim because 2n S(f, A) = S(f, A [a n, a n+1 1]) <. a n n=1 n=1 This contradicts the assumption that A I f. Notice that Theorem 3.2 is a consequence of ZFC. Corollary 3.3 Assume that CH holds. There exists a non-interval-to-one P -point. Proof: Let f(n) = 1/n. By Theorem 3.1 there is an f-slow P -point F. By Theorem 3.2 the P -point F cannot be interval-to-one. In the proof of the next theorem we need to use three existing results. The first one is a result in [2, Proposition 1.7] which guarantees that if F is a quasi-selective ultrafilteer and h(n) = 2 n, then for every function h : N N with h (n) h(n) for all n N, there exists a set A F such that h A is non-decreasing. The second result we need is so called Erdős-Szekeres Theorem [6], which says that every finite sequence of real numbers of length n contains a monotonic subsequence of length at least n + 1. In the proof of next theorem we need only a consequence for notational convenience that every sequence of length n 2 contains a monotonic subsequence of length at least n. The third result we need is a lower bound for Ramsey numbers by P. Erdő [5] which is later improved in [11]. Recall that [X] 2 := {{a, b} a, b 8

9 X and a b}. For any r N let R(r) be the smallest positive integer n such that for any c : [X] 2 {0, 1} where X = n there is a set X X such that X r and c [X] 2 is a constant function. It is shown in [11] that for all sufficiently large r. R(r) > Cr2 r 2 where C = 2 e (2) Theorem 3.4 Assume that CH holds. There exists an interval-to-one P - point, which is neither quasi-selective nor weakly Ramsey. Proof: Let a 0 = 1 and a n = 2 n! for n 1. Let p : N N be such that p(x) = n if and only if a n x < a n+1. Let f : N [0, 1] be such that f(x) = 1/2 (n 1)! if x p 1 (n). Notice a n+1 a n that f is non-increasing, lim f(n) = 0, and S(f, N) =. n 2 (n 1)! n=1 Let I f be the tall summmable ideal determined by f. Notice also that if A p 1 (n) 2 (n 1)! for infinitely many n, then A I f. The ultrafilter F that we construct will be f-slow. By CH we can list all functions from N to N as a sequence {g α α < ℵ 1 }. We construct a sequence {A α α < ℵ 1 } of sets by induction such that for any α < < ℵ 1 1. A α I f, 2. A A α, 3. {n N A α p 1 (n) > a k n 1} is infinite for each k N, 4. either A α+1 gα 1 (m) for some m N or intervals in {[min(a α+1 gα 1 (m)), max(a α+1 gα 1 (m))] m N} are pairwise disjoint. Condition 1 is listed for convenience only. It is actually a consequence of Condition 3. We start with A 0 = N. Notice that Condition 3 is true for A 0 because if k 1 is fixed, then a n+1 a n > a k n 1 2 (n 1)! for all sufficiently large n N. Conditions 2. and 4. are vacuous for A 0. 9

10 Assume that we have obtained all sets A α for α < δ for some δ < ℵ 1 such that the four properties above are satisfied when ℵ 1 is replaced by δ. Case 1: δ is a limit ordinal. Let {α m m N} be an increasing sequence of ordinals below δ and cofinal in δ. Without loss of generality we can assume that A αm+1 A αm for every m N. Let n 1 be the smallest positive integer such that A α1 p 1 (n 1 ) > a 1 n 1 1. For each m > 1 let n m > n m 1 be the smallest integer such that A αm p 1 (n m ) > a m n m 1. The existence of n m is guaranteed by Condition 3. Now let A δ := (A αm p 1 (n m )). m=1 Clearly, Condition 2 is true because for a fixed m 0, m=m 0 (A αm p 1 (n m )) A αm0. Hence A δ A α for any α < δ. Condition 3 is true because for each fixed k, A δ p 1 (n m ) > a m n m 1 a k n m 1 for all m > k. Condition 4 is vacuous. Case 2: δ is a successor ordinal + 1. By Erdős Szekeres Theorem we have that every sequence of real numbers with n 2 terms contains a monotonic subsequence with n terms. First we assume that there exists an m N such that for each k N there are infinitely many n with A g 1 (m) p 1 (n) > a k n 1. Then we set A δ := A g 1 (m). It is easy to check that {A α α < δ + 1} satisfies Conditions 1 4 above when ℵ 1 is replaced by δ + 1. Hence we can now assume that for every m, there is a k m and n m such that A g 1 (m) p 1 (n) a km n 1 (3) for every n n m. Let S = {n A p 1 (n) > a n 1 }. We construct an increasing sequence n 1 < n 2 < in S and sets D ni p 1 (n i ) A inductively such that a. D ni > a i n i 1, 10

11 b. g D ni is monotonic, and c. g (x) g (y) for any x D ni and y D nj when i j. Let n 1 = min{n S A p 1 (n) > a 2 n 1}. By Erdős Szekeres Theorem the sequence {g (x) x A p 1 (n 1 )} contains a monotonic subsequence {g (x) x D n1 } with D n1 > a n 1. Notice that g D n1 is interval-to-one because it is monotonic. Suppose we have constructed n 1 < n 2 < < n t and D ni A p 1 (n i ) for i = 1, 2,..., t such that D ni > a i n i 1, g is monotonic on D ni, and g (x) g (y) for any x D ni and y D nj when i j for all 1 i, j t. For constructing n t+1 and D nt+1 let X := {m D ni g 1 (m) for some i t}. Notice that X a nt+1. Let k = max{k m m X} and n = max{n m m X} where k m and n m are defined in (3). Recall that A g 1 (m) p 1 (n) a km n 1 a k n 1 for all m X and all n n. Let k = max{2p + 3, k + 2}. By Condition 3 we can find an n t+1 max{n t + 1, n} + 1 in S such that A p 1 (n t+1 ) > a k n t+1 1. Let Then we have A = (A \ {g 1 (m) m X}) p 1 (n t+1 ). A > a k n t+1 1 a nt+1 a k nt+1 1 a k n t+1 1 a k+1 n t+1 1 a k 1 n t+1 1 a 2(t+1) n t+1 1. By Erdős Szekeres Theorem we can find an D nt+1 A such that D nt+1 > a t+1 n t+1 1 and g is monotonic on D nt+1. Clearly, a. and b. are satisfied. The condition c. is true because all function values of g on D nt+1 are not in X. Now set A δ := D ni. Clearly, A δ A. Hence Condition 2 is true. Since for a fixed k, i=1 A δ p 1 (n i ) = D i > a i n i 1 a k n i 1 for all i k, Condition 3 is true. Condition 4 is true because g is monotonic on each D ni, and the range of g D i and the range of g D j are pairwise disjoint for any i j. 11

12 Let F = {U N A α U for some α < ℵ 1 }. Clearly, F is a filter. For any B N, there must be a function g α such that g α (x) = 1 if x B and g α (x) = 2 if x B. By Condition 4 we have that A α+1 gα 1 (1), which implies B F, or A α+1 gα 1 (2), which implies N \ B F. Hence F is an ultrafilter. Also by Condition 4 F is an interval-to-one P -point. Since A α I f by Condition 1, the ultrafilter F is f-slow. We now show that F is neither quasi-selective nor weakly Ramsey. Suppose that F is a quasi-selective ultrafilter. Let h(n) = 2 n. By [2, Proposition 1.7] any function h : N N with h (n) h(n) for all n N is F-equivalent to a non-decreasing function. For each x [a n, a n+1 1] let h (x) = a n+1 (x a n ). Then h (x) a n+1 = 2 (n+1)! 2 2n! = h(a n ) h(x). Hence there is an A F such that h is non-decreasing on A, which implies that A [a n, a n+1 1] contains at most one element. So we have that S(f, A) n=1 1 2 (n 1)! <, which contradicts that F is f-slow. Now we show that F is not weakly Ramsey. By (2) we have that R(2 (n 2)! ) > C2 (n 2)! 2 2(n 2)!/2 for all sufficiently large n. Let X n = [a n, a n+1 1]. Since C2 (n 2)! 2 2(n 2)!/2 lim =, n 2 (n+1)! 2 n! there is a function c n : [X n ] 2 {0, 1} for all sufficiently large n such that max{ X X X n is c n -homogeneous} < 2 (n 2)!. Assume by the contrary that F is weakly Ramsey. For every {a, b} [N] 2, define 0 if p(a) = p(b) = n and c n (a) = c n (b) c({a, b}) = 1 if p(a) = p(b) = n and c n (a) c n (b) 2 if p(a) p(b). Then there exists a set A F such that c takes only two values among {0, 1, 2}. If the range of c on [A] 2 is {0, 1}, then A p 1 (n) for some n. This 12

13 is impossible because A is infinite. If the range of c on [A] 2 is {1, 2}, then A p 1 (n) 2 because c n can have only two values. Hence S(f, A) < n=1 2 2 (n 1)! <, contradicting that A I f. If the range of c on [A] 2 is {0, 2}, then A p 1 (n) is c n -homogeneous, which implies that there is an n 0 N such that A p 1 (n) < 2 (n 2)! for all n n 0. Hence S(f, A) S(f, A [1, a n0 1]) + 2(n 2)! <, 2 (n 1)! n=n 0 which again contradicts that A I f. This completes the proof of the theorem. 4 Under MA deter- Theorem 4.1 Assume that MA holds. For each summable ideal I f mined by f, there exists an f-slow P -point. Proof: The steps of the proof for this theorem is similar to those of Theorem 3.1. So we borrow notation from there. The main difference is that the list {g α α < 2 ℵ 0 } of all functions from N to N has a length of 2 ℵ 0, which may be greater than ℵ 1 and therefore, our construction of the sequence of sets {A α α < 2 ℵ 0 } must also have a length of 2 ℵ 0. More specifically, we want to construct sets A α inductively on all ordinals α < 2 ℵ 0 such that for any α < < 2 ℵ 0 1. A α I f, where I f is a fixed summable ideal determined by f, 2. A A α, and 3. either A α+1 gα 1 (n) for some n N or A α+1 gα 1 (n) < for every n N. The steps of the construction of A δ for successor ordinals δ = + 1 are identical to the correspondent part in the proof of Theorem 3.1. In the case of δ being a limit ordinal we find A δ by MA. Notice that in this case Condition 3 is vacuous. 13

14 Suppose that δ < 2 ℵ 0 is a limit ordinal and A δ = {A α α < δ} has been constructed so that it satisfies Condition 1, 2, and 3 when 2 ℵ 0 is replaced by δ. In order to find A δ we define a partial order P such that P = {(n, s, F ) n N, s [1, n], F A δ, and F is finite}. For any p = (n p, s p, F p ), q = (n q, s q, F q ) P, define p q (or p is stronger than q) if 1. n p n q, 2. s p [1, n q ] = s q, 3. F q F p, 4. s p [n q + 1, n p ] A for any A F q, 5. S(f, s p [n q + 1, n p ]) 1. If n p = n q and s p = s q, then (n p, s p, F p F q ) is a common lower bound of p and q. Hence (P, ) is σ-centered. So (P, ) has c.c.c. Let D A,n = {p P n p n and A F p } for each n N and A A δ. It is routine to check that D A,n is dense in P. Since D = {D A,n A A δ and n N} has less than 2 ℵ 0 members, there exists, by MA, a D generic filter G P, i.e., a filter G G such that G D for all D D. Let A δ := {s p p G}. Then A δ A α for any α < δ because G D Aα,n, and A δ I f because there are increasing sequence p 1 > p 2 >... in G with n p1 < n p2 < and thus S(f, A δ [n pi + 1, n pj+1 ]) 1 for i = 1, 2,.... Corollary 4.2 Assume MA. There exists a non-interval-to-one P -point. Proof: Notice that Theorem 3.2 is a result of ZFC. Therefore, the existence of a 1/n-slow non-interval-to-one P -point follows from Theorem 4.1 and Theorem 3.2. Theorem 4.3 Assume that MA holds. There exists an interval-to-one P - point, which is neither quasi-selective nor weakly Ramsey. 14

15 Proof: Similar to the proof of Theorem 4.1 the proof of this theorem is parallel to the proof of Theorem 3.4. So we borrow also notation from there. The only step different from that of the proof of Theorem 3.4 is the construction of the set A δ when δ is a limit ordinal. Suppose that δ < 2 ℵ 0 is a limit ordinal and A δ = {A α α < δ} has been constructed. Notice that the letter p is already used for a function defined in the first line of the proof of Theorem 3.4. For obtaining the set A δ let Q = {(s, D, F, k) s N is finite, D n s p 1 (n), F A δ is finite, and k N}. For any q = (s q, D q, F q, k q ), q = (s q, D q, F q, k q ) Q define that q q if 1. s q [1, max s q ] = s q, 2. D q p 1 (n) = D q p 1 (n) for each n s q, 3. D q p 1 (n) A for each n s q \ s q and A F q, 4. k q k q, 5. D q p 1 (n) > a k q n 1 for each n s q \ s q. It is routine to check that (Q, ) is σ-centered. Let D = {D A,n,k A A δ and n, k N} where D A,n,k = {q Q max s q > n, A F q, and k q > k}. It is easy to see that D A,n,k is dense in Q and D has less than 2 ℵ 0 members. By MA there is a D generic filter G Q. Let A δ := {D q q G}. This completes the construction of A δ. It is now routine to check that A δ is the set we want. 5 Open questions An interval-to-one P -point can never be 1/n-slow by Theorem 3.2. The interval-to-one P -point which is neither quasi-selective nor weakly Ramsey in 15

16 Theorem 3.4 is f-slow for a function f with a very slow speed of approaching zero. It may be interesting to characterize the slow-ness of f which allows an f-slow interval-to-one P -point to exist. In particular we don t know the answer to the follwing question. Question 5.1 Assume that CH holds. P -point exist? Can 1/ log(n)-slow interval-to-one It is interesting to explore the relative consistency strength among these ultrafilters. Question 5.2 Is it consistent, relative to ZFC, that there exist P -points but not interval-to-one P -points? Is it consistent, relative to ZFC, that there exist interval-to-one P -points but not quasi-selective ultrafilters? Is it consistent, relative to ZFC, that there exist interval-to-one P -points but not weakly Ramsey ultrafilters? References [1] A. Blass, Combinatorial cardinal characteristics of the continuum, in: M. Foreman, A. Kanamori (Eds.), Handbook of Set Theory, Springer- Verlag, 2010, [2] A. Blass, M. Di Nasso, and M. Forti, Quasi-selective ultrafilters and asymptotic numerosities, Advances in Mathematics, vol. 231 (2012), [3] D. Booth, Ultrafilters on a countable set, Ann. Math. Log. 2 ( ), [4] M. Di Nasso, Fine asymptotic densities for sets of natural numbers, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 138 (2010) [5] P. Erdős, Some remarks on the theory of graphs, Bull. Amer. Math. Sot. 53 (1947), [6] P. Erd s and G. Szekeres, A combinatorial problem in geometry, Compositio Mathematica, 2: , (1935) 16

17 [7] M. Forti, Quasi-selective and weakly Ramsey ultrafilters, arxiv: [8] K. Kunen, Set Theory an introduction to independence proofs, North Holland, Amsterdam, [9] K. Kunen, Set Theory, Mathematical logic and foundations, vol. 34, College Publications, [10] S. Shelah, Proper and Improper Forcing, second ed., Springer-Verlag, [11] J. Spencer, (1975), Ramsey s theorem a new lower bound, Journal of Combinatorial Theory Ser. A, 18, [12] P. Vojtáš, On ω and absolutely divergent series, Topology Proceedings 19, ,

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS NATHAN BOWLER AND STEFAN GESCHKE Abstract. We extend the notion of a uniform matroid to the infinitary case and construct, using weak fragments of Martin s Axiom,

More information

Katětov and Katětov-Blass orders on F σ -ideals

Katětov and Katětov-Blass orders on F σ -ideals Katětov and Katětov-Blass orders on F σ -ideals Hiroaki Minami and Hiroshi Sakai Abstract We study the structures (F σ ideals, K ) and (F σ ideals, KB ), where F σideals is the family of all F σ-ideals

More information

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 169 (2001) Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom by Uri Abraham (Beer-Sheva) and Saharon Shelah (Jerusalem) Abstract. Assuming the continuum hypothesis there

More information

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ ALAN DOW Abstract. We prove that implies there is a zero-dimensional Hausdorff Lindelöf space of cardinality 2 ℵ1 which has points G δ. In addition, this space has

More information

Axioms for Set Theory

Axioms for Set Theory Axioms for Set Theory The following is a subset of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms for set theory. In this setting, all objects are sets which are denoted by letters, e.g. x, y, X, Y. Equality is logical identity:

More information

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS MARCIN KYSIAK AND TOMASZ WEISS Abstract. We discuss the question which properties of smallness in the sense of measure and category (e.g. being a universally

More information

Ultrafilters maximal for finite embeddability

Ultrafilters maximal for finite embeddability 1 16 ISSN 1759-9008 1 Ultrafilters maximal for finite embeddability LORENZO LUPERI BAGLINI Abstract: In this paper we study a notion of preorder that arises in combinatorial number theory, namely the finite

More information

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski The onto mapping property of Sierpinski A. Miller July 2014 revised May 2016 (*) There exists (φ n : ω 1 ω 1 : n < ω) such that for every I [ω 1 ] ω 1 there exists n such that φ n (I) = ω 1. This is roughly

More information

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals Boban Velickovic Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France Abstract Prikry asked if it is relatively consistent with the usual axioms

More information

Ultrafilters with property (s)

Ultrafilters with property (s) Ultrafilters with property (s) Arnold W. Miller 1 Abstract A set X 2 ω has property (s) (Marczewski (Szpilrajn)) iff for every perfect set P 2 ω there exists a perfect set Q P such that Q X or Q X =. Suppose

More information

Ultrafilters and Set Theory. Andreas Blass University of Michigan Ann Arbor, MI

Ultrafilters and Set Theory. Andreas Blass University of Michigan Ann Arbor, MI Ultrafilters and Set Theory Andreas Blass University of Michigan Ann Arbor, MI 48109 ablass@umich.edu Ultrafilters and Set Theory Ultrafilters and Set Theory But not large cardinals (Itay Neeman) Ultrafilters

More information

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Rend. Istit. Mat. Univ. Trieste Volume 41 (2009), 27 33. Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Fernando Hernández-Hernández Abstract. We compute the distributivity numbers

More information

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL ALAN DOW AND OLEG PAVLOV Abstract. Hušek defines a space X to have a small diagonal if each uncountable subset of X 2 disjoint from the diagonal, has an uncountable

More information

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id: Name: Student Id: There are nine problems (check that you have 9 pages). Solutions are expected to be short. In the case of proofs, one or two short paragraphs should be the average length. Write your

More information

FINITE BOREL MEASURES ON SPACES OF CARDINALITY LESS THAN c

FINITE BOREL MEASURES ON SPACES OF CARDINALITY LESS THAN c PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 81, Number 4, April 1981 FINITE BOREL MEASURES ON SPACES OF CARDINALITY LESS THAN c R. J. GARDNER AND G. GRUENHAGE Abstract. Let k < c be uncountable.

More information

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom arxiv:math/9807178v1 [math.lo] 15 Jul 1998 Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom Uri Abraham Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Ben-Gurion University, Beér-Sheva, Israel Saharon

More information

MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY

MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY LINDELÖF SPACES GARY GRUENHAGE Abstract. We answer questions of Bennett, Lutzer, and Matveev by showing that any monotonically compact LOT S is metrizable, and any

More information

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 149 (1996) The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom by Gary G r u e n h a g e and Piotr K o s z m i d e r (Auburn, Ala.) Abstract. We show that MA σ-centered

More information

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011 Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011 I. Generalizing Ramsey s Theorem Our proof of Ramsey s Theorem for pairs was

More information

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies University of Wisconsin, Madison July 2016 The Borel hierachy is described as follows: open = Σ 0 1 = G closed = Π 0 1 = F Π 0 2 = G δ = countable intersections of open sets Σ 0 2 = F σ = countable unions

More information

ALMOST DISJOINT AND INDEPENDENT FAMILIES. 1. introduction. is infinite. Fichtenholz and Kantorovich showed that there is an independent family

ALMOST DISJOINT AND INDEPENDENT FAMILIES. 1. introduction. is infinite. Fichtenholz and Kantorovich showed that there is an independent family ALMOST DISJOINT AND INDEPENDENT FAMILIES STEFAN GESCHKE Abstract. I collect a number of proofs of the existence of large almost disjoint and independent families on the natural numbers. This is mostly

More information

On The Model Of Hyperrational Numbers With Selective Ultrafilter

On The Model Of Hyperrational Numbers With Selective Ultrafilter MSC 03H05 On The Model Of Hyperrational Numbers With Selective Ultrafilter A. Grigoryants Moscow State University Yerevan Branch February 27, 2019 Abstract In standard construction of hyperrational numbers

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Open covers and a polarized partition relation

Open covers and a polarized partition relation Open covers and a polarized partition relation Marion Scheepers 1 Abstract We show that a strengthened form of a property of Rothberger implies that a certain polarized partition relation holds for the

More information

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper.

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper. SARAJEVO JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS Vol.13 (26), No.2, (2017), 141 154 DOI: 10.5644/SJM.13.2.02 PRESERVING OLD ([ω] ℵ0, ) IS PROPER SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We give some sufficient and necessary conditions

More information

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS LAJOS SOUKUP Abstract. The additivity spectrum ADD(I) of an ideal I P(I) is the set of all regular cardinals κ such that there is an increasing chain {A

More information

A UNIVERSAL SEQUENCE OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS

A UNIVERSAL SEQUENCE OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS A UNIVERSAL SEQUENCE OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS STEVO TODORCEVIC Abstract. We show that for each positive integer k there is a sequence F n : R k R of continuous functions which represents via point-wise

More information

ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS. Tomek Bartoszyński

ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS. Tomek Bartoszyński ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS Tomek Bartoszyński Department of Mathematics, Boise State University Boise, ID 83725 (U.S.A.) Email: tomek@diamond.boisestate.edu Lorenz Halbeisen

More information

Combinatorial dichotomies and cardinal invariants

Combinatorial dichotomies and cardinal invariants Dilip Raghavan (Joint with Stevo Todorcevic) National University of Singapore ASL North American annual meeting, University of Waterloo May 9, 2013 Outline 1 The Project 2 3 4 Calibrating some consequences

More information

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1. M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, 10001 100NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE Justin Tatch Moore Abstract. The purpose of this note is to define an Aronszajn line η C and prove

More information

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014 Functions and cardinality (solutions) 21-127 sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014 What follows is a somewhat hastily written collection of solutions for my review sheet. I have omitted some

More information

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS JUSTIN TATCH MOORE Abstract. The purpose of this article is to prove that the forcing axiom for completely

More information

An introduction to OCA

An introduction to OCA An introduction to OCA Gemma Carotenuto January 29, 2013 Introduction These notes are extracted from the lectures on forcing axioms and applications held by professor Matteo Viale at the University of

More information

REU 2007 Transfinite Combinatorics Lecture 9

REU 2007 Transfinite Combinatorics Lecture 9 REU 2007 Transfinite Combinatorics Lecture 9 Instructor: László Babai Scribe: Travis Schedler August 10, 2007. Revised by instructor. Last updated August 11, 3:40pm Note: All (0, 1)-measures will be assumed

More information

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS 1. Cardinal number of a set The cardinal number (or simply cardinal) of a set is a generalization of the concept of the number of elements

More information

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies On the Length of Borel Hierarchies Arnold W. Miller November 7, 2016 This is a survey paper on the lengths of Borel hierarchies and related hierarchies. It consists of lecture notes of a lecture given

More information

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 124 (2003) 179 191 www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing Milos S. Kurilic Department of Mathematics and Informatics, University of Novi

More information

Large Sets in Boolean and Non-Boolean Groups and Topology

Large Sets in Boolean and Non-Boolean Groups and Topology axioms Article Large Sets in Boolean and Non-Boolean Groups and Topology Ol ga V. Sipacheva ID Department of General Topology and Geometry, Lomonosov Moscow State University, Leninskie Gory 1, Moscow 119991,

More information

SMALL COMBINATORIAL CARDINAL CHARACTERISTICS AND THEOREMS OF EGOROV AND BLUMBERG

SMALL COMBINATORIAL CARDINAL CHARACTERISTICS AND THEOREMS OF EGOROV AND BLUMBERG Real Analysis Exchange Vol. 26(2), 2000/2001, pp. 905 911 Krzysztof Ciesielski, Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, USA, email: K Cies@math.wvu.edu, internet:

More information

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017 MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017 Definition: A set A is finite if there exists a nonnegative integer c such that there exists a bijection from A

More information

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS PHILIPP LÜCKE AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. Let L be a finite first-order language and M n n < ω be a sequence of finite L-models containing models

More information

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES P max VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES TETSUYA ISHIU AND PAUL B. LARSON Abstract. In his book on P max [6], Woodin presents a collection of partial orders whose extensions satisfy strong

More information

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics University of Illinois at Chicago Chicago, IL 60680 Rami Grossberg Department of Mathematics Carnegie

More information

A product of γ-sets which is not Menger.

A product of γ-sets which is not Menger. A product of γ-sets which is not Menger. A. Miller Dec 2009 Theorem. Assume CH. Then there exists γ-sets A 0, A 1 2 ω such that A 0 A 1 is not Menger. We use perfect sets determined by Silver forcing (see

More information

D, such that f(u) = f(v) whenever u = v, has a multiplicative refinement g : [λ] <ℵ 0

D, such that f(u) = f(v) whenever u = v, has a multiplicative refinement g : [λ] <ℵ 0 Maryanthe Malliaris and Saharon Shelah. Cofinality spectrum problems in model theory, set theory and general topology. J. Amer. Math. Soc., vol. 29 (2016), pp. 237-297. Maryanthe Malliaris and Saharon

More information

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory Boban Veličković Equipe de Logique Université de Paris 7 http://www.logique.jussieu.fr/ boban 15th Boise Extravaganza in Set Theory Boise State University,

More information

SET MAPPING REFLECTION

SET MAPPING REFLECTION SET MAPPING REFLECTION JUSTIN TATCH MOORE Abstract. In this note we will discuss a new reflection principle which follows from the Proper Forcing Axiom. The immediate purpose will be to prove that the

More information

Souslin s Hypothesis

Souslin s Hypothesis Michiel Jespers Souslin s Hypothesis Bachelor thesis, August 15, 2013 Supervisor: dr. K.P. Hart Mathematical Institute, Leiden University Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Trees 2 3 The -Principle 7 4 Martin

More information

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence Arthur W. Apter Department of Mathematics Baruch College of CUNY New York, New York 10010 USA and The CUNY Graduate Center, Mathematics 365 Fifth

More information

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS TOM CUCHTA 1. Introduction This paper was written as a final project for the 2013 Summer Session of Mathematical Logic 1 at Missouri S&T. We intend to present a short discussion

More information

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial Young Set Theory Workshop 2010, Raach, Austria. The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial Justin Tatch Moore 1 Notes taken by Giorgio Venturi In these notes we will present an exposition of the Proper Forcing

More information

Restricted versions of the Tukey-Teichmüller Theorem that are equivalent to the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem

Restricted versions of the Tukey-Teichmüller Theorem that are equivalent to the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem Restricted versions of the Tukey-Teichmüller Theorem that are equivalent to the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem R.E. Hodel Dedicated to W.W. Comfort on the occasion of his seventieth birthday. Abstract We

More information

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d Fields October 24, 2012 Notation If A and B are subsets of N let denote the equivalence relation defined by A B if and only if A B is finite. Let [A]

More information

INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING

INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 43, No. 2, 2013, 185-189 INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING Boris Šobot 1 Abstract. An inseparable sequence is an almost disjoint family A ξ : ξ < ω 1 of subsets of ω such that for

More information

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS DIEGO ANDRES BEJARANO RAYO Abstract. We expand on and further explain the work by Malliaris and Shelah on the cofinality spectrum by doing

More information

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER ALAN DOW AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We construct a model in which the splitting number is large and every ultrafilter has a small subset with no pseudo-intersection.

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

Title Covering a bounded set of functions by Author(s) Kada, Masaru Editor(s) Citation Topology and its Applications. 2007, 1 Issue Date 2007-01 URL http://hdl.handle.net/10466/12488 Rights c2007 Elsevier

More information

arxiv:math/ v2 [math.nt] 3 Dec 2003

arxiv:math/ v2 [math.nt] 3 Dec 2003 arxiv:math/0302091v2 [math.nt] 3 Dec 2003 Every function is the representation function of an additive basis for the integers Melvyn B. Nathanson Department of Mathematics Lehman College (CUNY) Bronx,

More information

Cardinality and ordinal numbers

Cardinality and ordinal numbers Cardinality and ordinal numbers The cardinality A of a finite set A is simply the number of elements in it. When it comes to infinite sets, we no longer can speak of the number of elements in such a set.

More information

Maximum union-free subfamilies

Maximum union-free subfamilies Maximum union-free subfamilies Jacob Fox Choongbum Lee Benny Sudakov Abstract An old problem of Moser asks: how large of a union-free subfamily does every family of m sets have? A family of sets is called

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

Adam Kwela. Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS. Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12)

Adam Kwela. Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS. Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12) Adam Kwela Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12) Opiekun pracy: Piotr Zakrzewski 1. Introduction We study property (S),

More information

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM ALAN DOW AND TODD EISWORTH Abstract. We show that the Continuum Hypothesis is consistent with all regular spaces of hereditarily countable π-character being C-closed. This

More information

SOME NEW EXAMPLES OF INFINITE IMAGE PARTITION REGULAR MATRICES

SOME NEW EXAMPLES OF INFINITE IMAGE PARTITION REGULAR MATRICES #A5 INTEGERS 9 (29) SOME NEW EXAMPLES OF INFINITE IMAGE PARTITION REGULAR MATRIES Neil Hindman Department of Mathematics, Howard University, Washington, D nhindman@aolcom Dona Strauss Department of Pure

More information

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008 Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008 Closed sets We have been operating at a fundamental level at which a topological space is a set together

More information

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET 1. THE AXIOM OF FOUNDATION Early on in the book (page 6) it is indicated that throughout the formal development set is going to mean pure set, or set whose elements,

More information

The seed order. Gabriel Goldberg. October 11, 2018

The seed order. Gabriel Goldberg. October 11, 2018 The seed order Gabriel Goldberg October 11, 2018 arxiv:1810.04284v1 [math.lo] 9 Oct 2018 Abstract e study various orders on countably complete ultrafilters on ordinals that coincide and are wellorders

More information

A CONVERSATION BETWEEN MODEL THEORY AND GRAPH THEORY

A CONVERSATION BETWEEN MODEL THEORY AND GRAPH THEORY A CONVERSATION BETWEEN MODEL THEORY AND GRAPH THEORY ISABELLA SCOTT Abstract. In general terms, Ramsey Theory studies the properties of structures that are preserved under taking partitions, and covers

More information

Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1

Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1 22M:132 Fall 07 J. Simon Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1 Chapter 1 contains material on sets, functions, relations, and cardinality that

More information

On a Question of Maarten Maurice

On a Question of Maarten Maurice On a Question of Maarten Maurice Harold Bennett, Texas Tech University, Lubbock, TX 79409 David Lutzer, College of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA 23187-8795 May 19, 2005 Abstract In this note we give

More information

Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms

Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms Topology and its Applications 154 (2007) 277 281 www.elsevier.com/locate/topol Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms Masaru Kada Graduate School of Science, Osaka Prefecture

More information

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2010) 916 922 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Cardinal characteristics and

More information

REALCOMPACTNESS IN MAXIMAL AND SUBMAXIMAL SPACES.

REALCOMPACTNESS IN MAXIMAL AND SUBMAXIMAL SPACES. REALCOMPACTNESS IN MAXIMAL AND SUBMAXIMAL SPACES. FERNANDO HERNÁNDEZ-HERNÁNDEZ, OLEG PAVLOV, PAUL J. SZEPTYCKI, AND ARTUR H. TOMITA Abstract. We study realcompactness in the classes of submaximal and maximal

More information

MONOCHROMATIC VS. MULTICOLORED PATHS. Hanno Lefmann* Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Emory University. Atlanta, Georgia 30332, USA

MONOCHROMATIC VS. MULTICOLORED PATHS. Hanno Lefmann* Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Emory University. Atlanta, Georgia 30332, USA MONOCHROMATIC VS. MULTICOLORED PATHS Hanno Lefmann* Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Emory University Atlanta, Georgia 30322, USA and School of Mathematics Georgia Institute of Technology

More information

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS Topology Proceedings Vol 17, 1992 COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS PETER J. NYIKOS, BORIS SHAPIROVSKIĬ, ZOLTÁN SZENTMIKLÓSSY AND BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ One of the classical separation axioms of topology

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE ALAN DOW AND ISTVÁN JUHÁSZ Abstract. A space has σ-compact tightness if the closures of σ-compact subsets determines the topology. We consider a dense

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES

COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES Karin DLASKA, Nurettin ERGUN and Maximilian GANSTER Abstract In this paper we introduce the class of countably S-closed spaces which lies between the familiar classes of S-closed

More information

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1.

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1. Chapter 3 Sequences Both the main elements of calculus (differentiation and integration) require the notion of a limit. Sequences will play a central role when we work with limits. Definition 3.. A Sequence

More information

FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES

FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES ALAN DOW AND RODRIGO HERNÁNDEZ-GUTIÉRREZ Abstract. We give a partial solution to a question by Alas, Junqueria and Wilson by proving that under PFA the one-point

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

REPRESENTABLE BANACH SPACES AND UNIFORMLY GÂTEAUX-SMOOTH NORMS. Julien Frontisi

REPRESENTABLE BANACH SPACES AND UNIFORMLY GÂTEAUX-SMOOTH NORMS. Julien Frontisi Serdica Math. J. 22 (1996), 33-38 REPRESENTABLE BANACH SPACES AND UNIFORMLY GÂTEAUX-SMOOTH NORMS Julien Frontisi Communicated by G. Godefroy Abstract. It is proved that a representable non-separable Banach

More information

STEVO TODORCEVIC AND JUSTIN TATCH MOORE

STEVO TODORCEVIC AND JUSTIN TATCH MOORE June 27, 2006 THE METRIZATION PROBLEM FOR FRÉCHET GROUPS STEVO TODORCEVIC AND JUSTIN TATCH MOORE 1. Introduction Let us begin this paper by recalling the following classical metrization theorem of Birkhoff

More information

ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES

ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES Submitted to the Annals of Probability ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES By Mark J. Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph B. Kadane, Carnegie

More information

The Rudin-Keisler ordering of P-points under b = c

The Rudin-Keisler ordering of P-points under b = c The Rudin-Keisler ordering of P-points under b = c arxiv:1803.03862v3 [math.lo] 3 Jun 2018 Andrzej Starosolski June 5, 2018 Abstract M. E. Rudin proved under CH that for each P-point there exists another

More information

arxiv: v3 [math.ac] 29 Aug 2018

arxiv: v3 [math.ac] 29 Aug 2018 ON THE LOCAL K-ELASTICITIES OF PUISEUX MONOIDS MARLY GOTTI arxiv:1712.00837v3 [math.ac] 29 Aug 2018 Abstract. If M is an atomic monoid and x is a nonzero non-unit element of M, then the set of lengths

More information

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT VERA FISCHER Abstract. In this talk we will consider three properties of iterations with mixed (finite/countable) supports: iterations of arbitrary length preserve ω 1, iterations

More information

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets Countable and Uncountable Sets The concept of countability will be important in this course

More information

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages 113-132 A FAMILY OF TREES WITH NO UNCOUNTABLE BRANCHES MIRNA DŽAMONJA AND JOUKO VÄÄNÄNEN Abstract. We construct a family of 2 ℵ 1 trees of size ℵ 1 and

More information

by Harold R. Bennett, Texas Tech University, Lubbock, TX and David J. Lutzer, College of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA

by Harold R. Bennett, Texas Tech University, Lubbock, TX and David J. Lutzer, College of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA The β-space Property in Monotonically Normal Spaces and GO-Spaces by Harold R. Bennett, Texas Tech University, Lubbock, TX 79409 and David J. Lutzer, College of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA 23187-8795

More information

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH JIN DU Abstract. Fontanella [2] showed that if κ n : n < ω is an increasing sequence of supercompacts and ν = sup n κ n, then the strong tree property holds

More information

Non-conglomerability for countably additive measures that are not -additive* Mark Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph Kadane CMU

Non-conglomerability for countably additive measures that are not -additive* Mark Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph Kadane CMU Non-conglomerability for countably additive measures that are not -additive* Mark Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph Kadane CMU Abstract Let be an uncountable cardinal. Using the theory of conditional

More information

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY About the Class Evaluation. Final grade will be based 25%, 25%, 25%, 25%, on homework, midterm 1, midterm 2, final exam. Exam dates. Midterm 1: Oct 4. Midterm 2:

More information

THE NON-URYSOHN NUMBER OF A TOPOLOGICAL SPACE

THE NON-URYSOHN NUMBER OF A TOPOLOGICAL SPACE THE NON-URYSOHN NUMBER OF A TOPOLOGICAL SPACE IVAN S. GOTCHEV Abstract. We call a nonempty subset A of a topological space X finitely non-urysohn if for every nonempty finite subset F of A and every family

More information

Forcing notions in inner models

Forcing notions in inner models Forcing notions in inner models David Asperó Abstract There is a partial order P preserving stationary subsets of! 1 and forcing that every partial order in the ground model V that collapses asu ciently

More information

Remarks on continuum cardinals on Boolean algebras

Remarks on continuum cardinals on Boolean algebras Math. Log. Quart. 58, No. 3, 159 167 (2012) / DOI 10.1002/malq.201110064 Remarks on continuum cardinals on Boolean algebras J. Donald Monk Department of Mathematics, University of Colorado, Boulder, CO

More information

2 RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 We thank the referee for a number of useful comments. We need the following result: Theorem 0.1. [2]

2 RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 We thank the referee for a number of useful comments. We need the following result: Theorem 0.1. [2] CHARACTERIZING! 1 AND THE LONG LINE BY THEIR TOPOLOGICAL ELEMENTARY REFLECTIONS RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 Abstract. Given a topological space hx; T i 2 M; an elementary submodel of

More information

Houston Journal of Mathematics. c 2013 University of Houston Volume 39, No. 3, Dedicated to the memory of Mikhail Misha Matveev

Houston Journal of Mathematics. c 2013 University of Houston Volume 39, No. 3, Dedicated to the memory of Mikhail Misha Matveev Houston Journal of Mathematics c 2013 University of Houston Volume 39, No. 3, 2013 ON THE HAUSDORFF NUMBER OF A TOPOLOGICAL SPACE MADDALENA BONANZINGA Communicated by Yasunao Hattori Dedicated to the memory

More information