1 Introduction. Retrieved Labour obtained 27.6% of the vote in the 1983 election, down 9 points from their 1980 defeat.

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "1 Introduction. Retrieved Labour obtained 27.6% of the vote in the 1983 election, down 9 points from their 1980 defeat."

Transcription

1 Tactical Extremism Jon X. Eguia Department of Economics, Michigan State University and Department of Economics, University of Bristol Francesco Giovannoni Department of Economics, University of Bristol Abstract We provide an instrumental, rational choice theory of extreme campaign platforms. By adopting an extreme platform, a party foregoes some probability of winning the current election. However, the party also builds credibility as the one most capable of delivering an alternative poliy. If voters become disatisfied with the status quo, they will then turn to the party that had adopted an extreme policy and kept it in opposition.

2 Introduction Political parties occasionally choose extreme candidates who seem destined to lose. In the US, following their defeat in the 960 Presidential election, the Republican party chose the extreme right-winger Barry Goldwater as their 964 candidate. Goldwater lost in a landslide election. In the UK, following their defeat in the 979 General election, the Labour party veered left under Michael Foot. Their socialist manifesto for the 983 election under Michael Foot was famously described as the longest suicide note in history. In the 983 election, Foot led Labour to their worst electoral result since 98. In 05, following their second consecutive election defeat, Labour again selected a candidate from the far left: Jeremy Corbyn. Traditional spatial explanations Downs 959 suggest that parties should follow the median. If a leftright-leaning party loses, under traditional models of two-party competition, one infers that the party was located too far to the leftright for the median s taste, and one predicts that in the next election the party will correct this mistake by moderating positions, selecting policies closer to the center. One may wonder why the Republicans in 964, or Labour in and 05, responded to defeat by doubled down and becoming more extreme. Non-instrumental theories would account these choices as expressive see for instance Brennan and Hamlin 998. Purist partisan factions Roemer 009, ch. 8 have preferences that depend on the platform embraced by their party, and not by the political outcome. Extreme policy platforms are more satisfying to these factions, even if they spell electoral doom. We suggest an alternative, purely instrumental, explanation with testable empirical implications. We argue that even offi ce-motivated parties that care only about winning elections, under some circumstances, have incentives to choose an extreme policy that makes them lose the most immediate election. The reason is that there are more elections after the most immediate one. Choosing an extreme policy is akin to leaving the ground fallow for a year: in the short term it leads to a loss, but in the long term it makes the ground more fertile and increases future yields. We argue that choosing an extreme policy has a similar effect. It allows the party to gain competence in such an alternative policy, and in expectation it delivers better electoral results in subsequent elections. Parties can have different skills at implementing particular policies Krasa and Polborn 00, 0, 06. Put differently, party valence can be policy specific. Suppose that an incumbent party has gained greater policy-valence at the status quo policy favored by the median voter. We can say that this incumbent party owns the issue Petrocik 996. Now consider the options available to the opposition party. It could try to compete on the same issue by selecting the same status quo policy. But given that the incumbent has a policy-valence advantage on this policy, the party is not likely to win. Alternatively, the opposition party can go an explore an alternative policy, which we label extreme simply because it is outside the mainstream. This extreme policy is less liked by voters, so choosing it reduces the probability that the opposition party wins the election. To convey the argument in its most stark case, assume that choosing the extreme policy makes the opposition lose the election with certainty. By choosing a new alternative policy position, the opposition party invests time and resources into developing and perfecting proposals on this policy position. These position-specific investments make the opposition party more competent on this alternative position. It is then able to produce higher quality proposals. As in Hirsch and Shotts 005, let a proposal be defined by two quantities: its ideological position as in traditional spatial models and its quality. Quality is a valence characteristic that all voters appreciate. By repeatedly investing on a particular policy position, a party gains the ability to generate proposals of higher quality on this position. It may also allow the party, if it perseveres in choosing the alternative policy after the electoral defeat, to gain credibility as the party that will deliver this alternative. An opposition party that embraces an alternative position will eventually own this position if it perseveres in holding it. It will have the policy-specific advantage in this alternative policy position. Suppose that the implemented policy is the mainstream one and the country suffers a negative shock. Perhaps the economy does not perform as well as expected. If the median voter becomes disillusioned with the status quo policy, Goldwater DW-Nominate score of 0.67 locates him among the 3% most conservative senators in the history of the US Senate see Carroll, Lewis, Lo, McCarty, Poole and Rosenthal on voteview.com, updated September 05. He lost 6% to 38%. The quote is by Labour MP Kauffman. See Mann, Nyta Foot s message of hope to left. BBC News. Retrieved Labour obtained 7.6% of the vote in the 983 election, down 9 points from their 980 defeat.

3 she might conclude that it is not the right policy, and that a new one is needed. And the opposition party will have an alternative ready, one in which it has invested over time so it built a policy-specific valence advantage. Therefore, extremism can help to win future elections by positioning the party as the party that is most capable of delivering a high quality alternative policy. The party surrenders competition over who can best provide policy x today, by investing in policy y, becoming the best at policy y, and hoping that voters will want y at a future election. We expect a party to choose this tactical extremism under the following circumstances: -the party is currently out of power, and it is regarded as less competent or less trustworthy or both in delivering policies at the currently mainstream position. -the consensus in favor of the currently preferred, mainstream policy position is weaker. Returning to our examples, the Republicans in 964 and Labor in 983 were out of power and faced popular opponents such as Johnson and Thatcher. If they perceived their chances of victory competing at the center to be small, then they had greater incentives to try an alternative. Labour chose the left-leaning Michael Foot in 980, at the tail-end of the stagflation crises of the 970s. GDP growth per capita was lower in the years preceding the election of Foot than at any other time from the Great Depression in the 930s to the Great Recession in We conjecture that Labour hoped that further crises would make voters turn away from capitalism and seek an alternative in the 983 election. By choosing Foot, Labour would have been ready to deliver such an alternative. Tactical extremism sometimes pays off, other times it does not. Barry Goldwater s defeat set the stage for the rise of conservatism Perlstein 009 and was followed by a sequence of conservative victories in several states, capped with the ascension of another conservative Reagan to the presidency in 980. On the other hand, Foot s extremism flopped: the British economy rebounded in the early 980s, the UK won the Falklands Malvinas War and Thatcher became more popular. Labour backtracked, ditching its investment in socialism as a sunk cost, and returning to compete and to lose throughout the 980s on centrist ground. Extremism is the best course of action for a party only in rare circumstances, so we expect tactical extremism to be observed only rarely. It is more likely to emerge in periods of greater upheaval, in which the previously mainstream orthodox policies have been called into question, such as following the 99 Depression, leading to tactical extremism in the 930s; following the 970s stagflation, and following the Great Recession. These or future shocks to the orthodoxy can make a policy experiment more appealing for parties with low-valence at the currently orthodox policy. These parties will be tempted to embrace an alternative and invest in it, hoping that additional negative shocks further sink the popularity of the orthodox policy and that voters follow the party to the policy alternative. Our theory formalizes these intuitions. The rest of the paper is structured as follows. In Section we introduce a simple model which we analyze in Section 3. We discuss and interpret our results in a concluding Section 4. We relegate most of our proofs to an Appendix. The Model Consider a two-period model of electoral competition with two purely offi ce-motivated parties and one strategic representative voter. In each of the two periods, parties E and M compete for election. Both parties seek to maximize the sum of the probabilities of being elected over the two periods. We consider a policy space with only two policies: {, }, where represents the orthodox or mainstream policy, and an alternative or unorthodox policy that we call extreme. In each period t {, }, before the election, the two parties simultaneously choose a policy. We denote with x j t {, } the policy choice of party j {E, M} in period t, while x t = x E t, x M t denotes the policy profile chosen by the two parties in period t. Once a policy profile is chosen, the voter chooses one of the 3 Inflation-adjusted GDP growth per capita in the UK from 973 to 980 was less than %. Since 945, the only other span of more than four years of such low growth occured from 007 to 04..., and once again Labour has chosen a candidate from its extreme left. Source of the data: UK Offi ce of National Statistics, GDP average per head, Chained Volume Measures CVM market prices

4 two parties. The winning party implements her chosen platform as period t. Let x W t { } x E t, x M t denote the policy of the winning party. The voter cares about the state of the economy. Assuming that there is an underlying state of nature θ {, } that determines which policy delivers a better economic outcome. In each period t, the economy performs better if x W t = θ than if x W t = θ. The true realization of θ is never observed by any of the players, but in period t = it is common knowledge that Pr θ = = p >. We therefore refer to platform as the mainstream platform and as the extreme platform because ex-ante policy is most likely to be the policy that generates a better economic outcome. Since θ {, }, we refer to policy θ as the correct policy and θ as the wrong one. The economy is also subject to temporary external shocks in each period, which are independent of policies. Let ω t {, } denote the period t external shock. We assume that true realizations of ω and ω are never observed by any of the players, but it is common knowledge that these two random variables are independent across the two periods and identically distributed with Pr ω t = = q >, so we interpret ω t = as a normal state, and ω t = as a negative shock. A third component that affects the performance of the economy is the competence of the party in government at executing its policy. Whether an implemented policy is the right one x W t = θ or the wrong one x W t = θ given the state, if it is implemented competently, the economic output is increased by c 0,. We assume that party M, the mainstream party, starts the game with greater competence at the mainstream policy, and it owns the issue, in the sense that it maintains a valence advantage on this policy position as long as it continues to advocate for it. Formally, for each party j {E, M}, let c j xj denote the competence or valence advantage of party j in period over policy x j, and let cj xj, xj denote the period competence of party j on policy x j, given xj. We assume that cm = c, c M, = c and c M, = 0, whereas c E = c E, = c E, = 0. On the other hand, the extreme policy position is open territory, up for grabs in the sense that it is not owned by any party. A party that invests on it for two periods in a row gains greater competence on it. Formally, c j = cj, = 0 and cj = cj, = c for each j {E, M}. Notice the deliberate asymmetry in the model: the mainstream party M starts the game with a valence advantage over the extremist E over the mainstream policy. Party M owns this policy position. Party E can only acquire a credibility advantage if she consistently pick the extreme policy and M does not imitate her. 4 The economic utility that the voter obtains from electing party j in the first period is: θx j + ω + c j xj and the economic utility that the voter obtains from electing party h in the second period is, θx h + ω + c h x h, x h. In addition, we assume that a random variable ɛ t represents the voter s idiosyncratic preference for party M, as a stochastic party valence characteristic in each period. This shock captures non-policy attributes such as charisma or attractiveness of the candidate. We assume that ɛ and ɛ are i.i.d. distributed as uniforms on, and private information to the voter, so that they are not observed by the parties. It is convenient to define π t = θx W t + ω t. The voter s utility from choosing party j in the first period is vθ, w, x j = π + c j xj + I j=mε, where I j=m is an indicator function equal to one if j = M and zero if j = E. The voter s utility from choosing party j in the second period is vθ, w, x j, xj = π + c j xj, xj + I j=mε. 4 The fact that we allow the possibility that M can match E s credibility over the extremist platform is simply there to make it harder, in principle, for E to choose the extremist policy over a version of the assumption where M cannot do that. Choosing the latter version of our assumption would obviously make our results no easier to obtain. It actually turns out that in equilibrium M will never choose policy - in the first period and so either version leads to the same results. 4

5 We assume that in each period, the voter maximizes her period s utility, voting for the candidate that delivers a higher expected utility in this period. We also assume that in each period, after the winning party is determined and her platform implemented, π t is commonly observed by all players. 3 Analysis In this section, we describe equilibrium behavior. We relegate all formal statements and their proofs to the appendix. Throughout, we assume that in either period, if M is indifferent between two platforms, she chooses the mainstream one. We begin with the second period. We determine updated beliefs about the true state θ given the events of the first period. If the first period economic outcome is one that could only have been achieved by the correct policy if π = or only by the wrong one if π = platform, then the correct policy becomes known: if π =, θ = x W, whereas if π =, then θ = x W Lemma. If the correct policy becomes known, both parties propose it in the second period. Intermediate economic outcomes π = 0 lead to continuing uncertainty about which policy is correct. If the updated beliefs that the correct policy is the mainstream one are suffi ciently high or suffi ciently low, then both parties will choose accordingly, but because the asymmetry in credibility we have introduced in the model, it also also possible that when these beliefs are not so clear-cut, then one party will choose the mainstream policy and the other the extremist one. Because M has an advantage on the mainstream policy, if the parties do choose different policy, it must be party M that chooses the mainstream policy and party E that chooses the extremist one Lemma. So, in summary Remark Policy choices in the second period. If the outcome from the first period generates beliefs such that it is unlikely or impossible that the mainstream policy is the correct one, then this will lead both parties to choose the extremist policy, while if the beliefs imply that the mainstream policy is likely or certain to be the correct one, then both parties will choose the mainstream policy. For intermediate beliefs, the extremist party chooses the extremist policy and the mainstream party choosing the mainstream policy. Given a first period outcome with remaining uncertainty about the correct policy π = 0, the updated beliefs on which policy is correct depend on p prior that the mainstream policy is correct, on q probability of no external negative shock, and on which policy was implemented in the first-period. Lemmas 3-6. In particular, subject to an outcome with lingering uncertainty, If the mainstream policy is implemented in the first period, the beliefs that the correct policy is the mainstream one will be increasing in p and decreasing in q. A mediocre first period outcome means that either the policy choice was wrong or the winning party was unlucky ω =. A higher value of p makes it more likely that the mediocre outcome was due to back luck on the state ω while a higher value of q makes it more likely that the mediocre outcome was due to bad policy. If the extreme policy is implemented in the first period, then the beliefs that the extreme is the correct policy will be increasing in both p and q. Now, it s the extremist policy that has delivered a mediocre outcome and both a higher value of p and a higher value of q make it more likely that the mediocre outcome was due to a bad policy choice. Consider now the first election. The voter votes for M if and only if E[v θ, w, x M ] E[v θ, w, x E ], where E[v] denotes the expectation of v with respect to ω and θ. Detailed results are in Lemma 7, summarized here 5

6 Remark Voter s choice in the first election. If the two parties choose the same policy, then the voter s decision depends only on her idiosyncratic preferences shock and on the policy-specific competence advantage of each party. In particular If both choose the mainstream platform, then M has an advantage and wins with probability + c. If both choose the extremist platform, then neither party has an advantage and M wins with probability. If the two parties choose diff erent platforms, then the voter s decision also depends on the probability p that is the correct policy. In particular If M choose the mainstream platform while E chooses the extremist platform then the probability that M wins is min c + 4p 3 ; If E choose the mainstream platform while M chooses the extremist platform then the probability that M wins is max 5 4p; 0 One simple but crucial observation is that if we consider the first period game in isolation, it is a dominant strategy for E to choose the mainstream policy. Thus the only possible rationale for E choose the extreme platform is to sacrifice some probability of winning in the first period to build a competence advantage on the extremist policy so as to get a higher probability of winning in the second period. Using the same logic, it is also easy to see that M has no incentive to choose the extremist policy Lemma 8. M already enjoys an advantage on the mainstream platform which is also more likely to be the correct one. Choosing the extremist policy in the first period yields no short or long term gain for M. This means that in the first period, only two possible equilibrium profiles may emerge: both parties go mainstream or M goes mainstream while E goes extreme. We describe the conditions under which each of the two possibilities obtain. We focus on the case in which the mainstream policy always wins in the first period election. This makes choosing an extremist policy for E as diffi cult as possible. That is, this is the hardest case for the tactical extremism phenomenon that we want to describe. Remark 3 First period policy proposals Propositions and simplified. Assume p 5 8 c 4. The mainstream policy is implemented in the first period. M always chooses the mainstream policy in the first period while there exist a function ĉp, q and a function q p where and ĉp, q = p q+ if q q p +4p q if q p < q p if q > p q p = 9 p 4p 48p + 08p 48p 3 + 6p p such that E chooses an extremist platform in the first period if and only if c ĉp, q. 5 Further, ĉ is increasing in p and decreasing resp. increasing in q whenever q p < q p resp. otherwise, while q is increasing in p. The portion of space p, q, c above the surface in the figure below is the set of parameter values for which E will select an extremist policy in the first period. Our results partitions the space of possible parameter values in three possible regions. 5 In the appendix, proposition is stated quite differently and in its proof we discuss show how to obtain this simplification. 6

7 Figure : cp,q. In the first region, q is smaller than q p. This means that in the second period, even if the mainstream policy delivered a mediocre outcome in the first period, all players have suffi ciently strong beliefs that the mainstream policy is the correct one that both parties will propose it in the second period. Thus, if the outcome from the mainstream policy is good or mediocre, then going extreme in the first period does not pay off. Only if c is suffi ciently large and p not too large, E is willing to choose the extremist platform gambling that the outcome will be bad. If that happens and it is more likely to happen the lower p is, having invested on the extremist policy from the first period will pay off for E in the second period, when both parties will go extreme.. In the second region, q is larger than p. Now, in the second period, if the mainstream policy delivers a mediocre outcome in the first period, all players blame the policy itself for the outcome, and both parties go extreme in the second period. Thus, going extreme in the first period pays off in the second whenever the first period outcome from the mainstream policy is bad or mediocre. So, again if c is suffi ciently large but not necessarily as large as in the previous case and p small enough but not necessarily as small as in the previous case then investing on the extremist policy is profitable for E. 3. In the third region q is between q p and p. The intuition here is similar to the one in the previous case, except that when the outcome is mediocre, parties will split their proposals, with M choosing the mainstream and E choosing to go extremist. As already discussed above, this will happen because M has an advantage on the mainstream policy that E doesn t have and given that there is suffi cient uncertainty about what is the correct policy, this uncertainty is suffi cient to generate the split. A first period investment on an extreme policy pays off for E if the first period outcome from the mainstream policy is bad or mediocre. So, again if c is suffi ciently large and p small enough then investing on the extremist policy is profitable for E. In all three regions, E makes an extreme proposal in the first period if c is suffi ciently high and p is suffi ciently low, because an increase in c increases the benefits resp. losses from having a competence advantage resp. disadvantage, which pushes E away from the mainstream policy. Whereas, an increase in p makes the mainstream policy more reliable or, equivalently, the extremist one less reliable. How q influences E s choice between mainstream and extremist proposals is more ambiguous. In particular, conditional on q being in the first two regions so that it is suffi ciently large or suffi ciently small, an extremist 7

8 proposal is less likely as q increases, while when q is in the third region then an extremist proposal is more likely as q increases. These can be explained as a combination of two effects. The first effect is the direct effect of an increase in q on first period outcomes. In all regions, an increase in q makes it less likely, from the first period s perspective that an outcome favorable to the extremist choice will occur. For example, if q is suffi ciently small to be in the first region, then a marginal increase will make it a little bit more likely that the outcome is either good or at least mediocre, and in those cases being an extremist in the first period does not pay. 6 If q is in the second or third region, a marginal increase in q will make it a little bit more likely that the outcome is good. 7 The second is the effect of an increase in q on the probability that the pivotal voter in the second period will vote for E. In the first and second region, this effect does not apply because both parties choose the same platform. In the third region, however, M chooses the mainstream policy and E chooses the extremist policy. A marginal increase in q therefore, will change the pivotal voter s beliefs in favor of the extremist policy. Thus our comparative statics results obtain because the second effect is suffi ciently strong in the third region to overcome the first effect. In the other two regions, only the first effect obtains. The figure below plots ĉ p, q for fixed p. E chooses the extremist policy in the first period in the shaded region. The vertical dotted lines represent q p and p respectively. Think of a situation where q is very close to the lower bound / and where E is indifferent between choosing a mainstream or an extremist policy in the first period. In the figure, we are at the point where the horizontal dotted line touches the vertical axis, at ĉ p,. In this situation, since q is very low, all players still believe that a mediocre outcome is not the mainstream platform s fault. Keeping c and p constant at ĉ p, and p respectively, but letting q increase, this remains the case but the probability that a bad outcome occurs also decreases and so E now prefers to choose the mainstream policy. At some point, q is large enough that conditional on a mediocre outcome, E switches to an extremist policy while M keeps choosing the mainstream one in the second period. In the figure, we are crossing the first vertical dashed line which represents q p. As q increases further, beliefs conditional on a mediocre outcome become more and more favorable for the extremist policy and so the incentive to go extremist in the first period as well for E increase until at some point, E decides to do it and enters the shaded region. Eventually, q will be high enough that conditional on a mediocre outcome, M will also switch to the extremist policy in the second period. In the figure, this is the second vertical dashes line which represents p. Now, as q increases, because the two parties are choosing the same platform, all that matters is that an increase in q makes a good outcome more favorable but it s effect conditional on bad or mediocre outcomes does not matter. So, the incentive to choose an extremist policy starts to reduce again. The next figure shows how the three regions change as a function of p: the higher curves represent higher values p and shows how, as p increases the space of values of c, q for which E goes extreme in the first period, becomes smaller. 6 The probability that the outcome is either mediocre or good is p q = p + q p which is increasing in q. 7 The probability that the outcome is good is. Thus, whichever region we are in, the probability of obtaining first period outcomes that favor extremism, is decreasing in q. 8

9 0.5 c q^p q p 9

10 c q 4 Discussion We identify conditions under which an offi ce-motivated political party chooses an extremist policy that causes it to lose an election. Namely, the party must face a disadvantage if it competes on mainstream ideas; the party must be able to acquire a policy-specific valence advantage on an alternative extreme policy; and there must be suffi cient uncertainty in the mind of the electorate about the virtues of the mainstream policy. The idea is that if a party takes an extreme position that is currently unpopular and loses, and the economic outcome under the implemented mainstream policies is bad, voters may then infer that it is time for a new policy. If so, the party that had previously invested in a non-mainstream policy will be better positioned to deliver such an alternative. It follows that extremism is more likely to arise at a time of crisis, when it is more likely that the economic outcome under mainstream policy will be unsatisfactory to voters. Our binary policy space represents a stark contrast between competing policy prescriptions. We see this policy choice as a reduced-form encapsulation of competing political ideologies. Our interpretation of a mainstream policy is the set of economic policies that are applied in most OECD countries, with IMF, World Bank, ECB and Federal Reserve support, centered around a broad consensus that central banks ought to be independent of political control, that private property rights help competitive markets function, that fiscal responsibility is desirable, that free trade generates growth, that inflation targeting should be taken seriously, etc. We think of the parameter p as the probability that such orthodox policies are correct. This underlying value of p may also be different across countries. The whole package of the Washington consensus may not be as appropriate in certain developing countries as it is in others. We interpret p as largely stable over time, but major events can affect it. For instance, the collapse of the Communist bloc in the late 980s would suggest that the capitalist orthodoxy was a better policy prescription. On the other hand, the controversies 0

11 surrounding the policy responses to the Great Recession in the years following 007 show that p is not one, and doubts about the wisdom of austerity, budget balances, and defaulting on the national debt persists. Extremism is more likely to develop when the consensus on the mainstream weakens, so an economic failure is more likely to be blamed on failed policies than on bad luck. Parameter q represents the probability that the non-policy factors that affect the economy are normal. Any possible negative shock that may derail a country s economy regardless of the economic policies implemented in the country would be captured in the probability q. This term includes both country-specific effects, such as the probability of a violent outbreak in unstable countries, or a fall in commodity prices in countries that rely on the export of a given commodity. It also includes the possibility of contagion from a worldwide economic crisis that generates unavoidable negative spillovers due to a contraction of trade, loss of confidence in financial markets, etc. If a negative shock is very unlikely q very high, then the incentives to go extreme increase in the probability of a negative shock decreasing in q because a negative economic outcome would be interpreted as a failure of the mainstream policy. On the other hand, if the negative shock is suffi ciently likely, the comparative static reverses as a disappointing economic outcome would not be blamed on the policy, but on the likely negative shock. We have modelled the incentive for choosing an extreme policy through parameter c, which is the reward for investing on a new policy away from the mainstream. We have interpreted c as an acquired policy-specific valence, obtained as the party becomes more competent on this policy position and is able to generate higher quality policies on this position. Our main intuition is that tactical extremism arises when a party that finds it diffi cult to compete on mainstream policies can adopt an alternative policy in which it gains an advantage, in hopes that a negative economic shock discredits the mainstream policy. This incentive to go extreme is reinforced through other channels that we have not considered. Relax the strong assumption of commitment to any policy proposal. In reality, parties may find it diffi cult to commit to a new policy: reactionary elements within the party will object and fight to row back the changes, so that even if it wins, the party may not implement its policy proposal. If a party has always stood on an ideological position, and it suddenly reverses itself and proposes something entirely different, its proposals may simply not be credible. It may take time to acquire this credibility. In particular, suppose that if a party proposes a new policy, voters treat its platform as stochastic, assigning some weight to its past position in the previous election, and some to the new proposal. If so, a new incentive for tactical extremism arises: a party that proposes an alternative policy position in period and insists on that position in period is more credible in period than a party newly arrived at this position. So a party that is disadvantaged at the mainstream position has an additional incentive to relocate early to an extreme, hoping to become a credible alternative, that voters follow later, after they become disillusioned with the mainstream. The competence and credibility channels reinforce each other: a party chooses tactical extremism, forgoing a small chance to win the current election on mainstream grounds, in order to build an advantage to fight the next election on an alternative policy position. This strategy pays off if the economic outcome in the first period after the mainstream policy is implemented turns out to be negative, thus discrediting the mainstream policy, and inducing voters to seek an alternative. Tactical extremism allows a party to become the new home for these voters, and to win the next election and is more likely to develop when the consensus on the mainstream weakens, so an economic failure is more likely to be blamed on failed policies than on bad luck. [An Alternative Interpretation with naive more gullible voters, that by investing in extreme candidate can change perception of p, would lead to the same thing]. 5 Appendix Some conventions. Let p be the posterior belief, after the economic output π is realized, that the state is θ =. For each candidate J {E, M}, for each second period policy profile x {, } and for each p [0, ], let u V J x E, x M, x E, x M, p be the expected second period utility for the voter from voting for candidate J given x E, x M, and p.

12 Lemma If π =, then p {0, } and x = x W, x W. If π =, then p {0, } and x = x W, x W. Proof. π = reveals that θ = x W with probability one. So if x W = then p = 0 and x =,, while if x W = then p = and x =,. π = reveals that θ = x W with probability one. So if x W = then p = and x =,, while if x W = then p = 0 and x =,. Lemma x =, is not part of any pure strategy equilibrium. Proof. Suppose that x =, occurred in any pure strategy equilibrium. If the probability of victory for M in this equilibrium is not strictly greater than, M deviates to x = ; if it is strictly greater, then E deviates to Lemma 3 If x =, and π = 0, then p =, if, if + p q,, and x is equal to + p q, + 4] c, + p q [ + c 4,. Proof. Given x =,, x W = and π = 0 imply that either θ = and ω = with probability or θ = and ω = with probability p q. So p =, which is strictly greater than because p, q,. + p q u V E,,,, p = p p + c and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε then Pr[M wins,,,, p ] = Pr[ε c, ] = c Whereas, u V E,,,, p = p p + c and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε then Pr[M wins,,,, p ] = Pr[p + ε p + c] = Pr[ε 4p + c, ] = + 4p c = 4p 3 c Therefore, based on M s incentives,, is a mutual best response only if 4p 3 c c or equivalently only if p. But p > as noted above, so, cannot be sustained. We have just established that if p >, M prefers x =, to x =,. Obviously, M will always prefer x =, to x =, see Lemma and so M always chooses platform. Since u V E,,,, p = p p and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε then Pr[M wins,,,, p ] = Pr[ε 0, ] = It follows that E prefers x =, to x =, if and only 4p 3 c, or equivalently, p + c 4. Thus, an equilibrium with x =, exists if and only if p, + 4] c and one with x =, exists if and only if [ + c 4, ].

13 Lemma 4 If x =,, x W p q = and π = 0, then p = p q+ 0,, and x is equal to, if, if, if p q p q+ 0, 4 c, p q p q+ [ c 4, + 4] c, p q p q+ [ + c 4,. If x =,, x W = and π = 0, then p = + p q 0,, and x is equal to, if, if + p q p, + 4 c, + p q [ + c 4,. Proof. Given x =,, then x W = and π = 0 imply that either θ = and ω = with probability p q or θ = and ω = with probability. So p = p q p q+. u V E,,,, p = p p + c and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε thus Pr[M wins,,,, p ] = Pr[ε c, ] = c Whereas, u V E,,,, p = p p + c and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε + c thus Pr[M wins,,,, p ] = Pr[p + ε + c p + c] = Pr[ε 4p, ] = + 4p = 4p 3 Therefore, x M = is a best response to x E = if and only if 4p 3 c or equivalently if only if p c 4, and if it holds with equality M deviates by our indifference assumption. Since M has greater incentives to deviate from, than E, it follows that x =, is a second period mutual best response if and only if p < c 4. We have just established that if p c 4, M prefers x =, to x =,. Since u V E,,,, p = p p and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε + c so Pr[M wins,,,, p ] = Pr[ε c, ] = + c and it follows that E prefers x =, to x =, if and only 4p 3 + c, or equivalently, p + c 4. Thus, an equilibrium with x =, exists if and only if p c 4, + 4] c and one with x =, exists if and only if [ + c 4, ]. If we consider the situation where x =,, x W = and π = 0 imply that either θ = and ω = with probability or θ = and ω = with probability p q. Then p = and the second period best responses are as stated by an analogous + p q proof, with the corresponding p cutoffs, but noting that q > implies p > p. 3

14 Lemma 5 If x =,, x W p q = and π = 0, then p = p q+ 0,. If x =,, x W and π = 0, then p = + p q. In either case, x is equal to =, if p 0,,, or, if p =,, if p,. Proof. Given x =,, x W = and π = 0 imply that either θ = and ω = with probability p q p q or θ = and ω = with probability. Then p = p q+. Given x =,, x W = and π = 0 imply that either θ = and ω = with probability or θ = and ω = with probability p q. In the second period, neither party has an advantage, so the equilibrium consists of x E = x M = if p <, xe, x M {,,, } if p =, and xe = x M = if p >, where our indifference assumption on M rules out the other two options for p =. Lemma 6 If x =, and π = 0, then p = p q p q+, and x is equal to, if, if, if p q p q+ 0, 4 c, p q p q+ [ c 4, ], p q p q+ [, ]. Proof. Given x =,, x W = and π = 0 imply that either θ = and ω = with probability p q or θ = and ω = with probability. So p = p q p q+. u V E,,,, p = p p and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε thus Pr[M wins,,,, p ] = Pr[ε 0, ] = Whereas, u V E,,,, p = p p and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε + c so Pr[M wins,,,, p ] = Pr[p + ε + c p ] = Pr[ε 4p c, ] = + 4p + c = 4p 3 + c Therefore, x M = is a best response to x E = if and only if 4p 3 + c or equivalently if only if p c 4, and if it holds with equality M deviates by our indifference assumption. Since M has greater incentives to deviate from, than E, it follows that x =, is a second period mutual best response if and only if p < c 4. We have just established that if p c 4, M prefers x =, to x =,. Since u V E,,,, p = p p and u V M,,,, p = p p + ε + c 4

15 so Pr[Mwins,,,, p ] = Pr[ε c, ] = + c and it follows that E prefers x =, to x =, if and only 4p 3 + c + c, or equivalently, p. Thus, an equilibrium with x =, exists if and only if p c 4, ] and one with x =, exists if and only if [ + c 4, ]. Lemma 7 For any combination of first period platforms x = x E, x M then the following gives the first period pivotal voter s decision to vote M and probabilities of M winning x = x Vote M iff: Pr[M wins], ε > c + c, ε > 0 [ c + 4p 3, ε > c 4p if < p < c [ if p c 5, ε > 4p 4p if < p < ] if p 5 8 ] Proof. Note that we use this repeatedly that for any λ R, if λ Pr[ε > λ] = λ if λ [, ] 0 λ >.. We have four cases.. Case x =,. The voter utilities are: so that she will vote for M whenever u V M x E, x M, p = ε + c + p q = ε + c + p + q, and u V E x E, x M, p = p + q, ε + c > 0 ε > c. and so Pr ε > c = + c.. Case x =,. Then u V M x E, x M, p = ε + p q p q = ε p q, and u V E x E, x M, p = p q so the voter will vote for M whenever ε > 0, which occurs with probability. 3. Case x =,. Then u V M x E, x M, p = ε + c + p q = ε + c + p + q, and u V E x E, x M, p = p q, 5

16 and thus u V M x E, x M, p u V E x E, x M, p = ε + c + p + q + p q so that the voter will vote for M whenever and by, or equivalently, 4. Case x =,. Then { Pr[ε > c 4p] = ε + c + 4p > 0 = ε + c + 4p, ε > c 4p, if c 4p 4p + c 3 if c 4p [, ] { 4p + c 3 Pr[ε > c 4p] = if p [, 5 8 ] c 4 p [ 5 8 c 4, ] u V M x E, x M, p = ε p q and u V E x E, x M, p = p + q so u V M x E, x M, p u V E x E, x M, p = ε 4p + } }. 3 so the voter votes for M if and only if ε > 4p and by, { 5 Pr[ε > 4p ] = 4p if 4p [ ] 0, 0 if 4p } 4 or equivalently, { 5 Pr[ε > c 4p] = 4p if p, p [ 5 8, ] }. 5 Lemma 8 Strategy x M = strictly dominates x M =. Proof. Given x M =, P x E, x M + c strictly greater if E chooses xe =. If x =, then in the second period election, M can obtain at least a probability of winning in the second period by choosing the same platform as E, while if x =, then M can guarantee to obtain at least c by choosing the same platform as E. The table below summarizes a lower bound on M s utility: x E = x E = x M = + c + EP, P, + EP, with P, > + c, EP, and EP, c. So, P, + EP, > is a lower bound on M s total utility choosing x M =. Now, consider the choice of x M =. If E chooses x E = then the probability of M winning will be since no party has an advantage whereas if E chooses x E = the probability of M winning will be strictly smaller than since no party has an advantage and p >. If x =, then E can always guarantee herself at least a probability of winning in the second period by choosing the same platform as M, but this means that M can never get more than probability of winning in the second period. If x =, then E can always guarantee herself at least a probability of winning in the second period by choosing the same platform as M, but this means that M can never get more than probability of winning in the second period. The table below summarizes an upper bound on M s utility: x E = x E = x M = P, + EP, + EP, 6

17 with P, <, EP, and EP,. So, an upper bound on M s utility is + EP, which is less than the lower bound with with x M =. Proposition In any equilibrium, there exist functions Q p, c, Q p, c and Q p, c such that x =, whenever c 5 and { p, min Q p, c, q max Q p, c,, p or c > 5 and and x =, otherwise. p, min Q p, c, q max Q p, c,, q, p, min Q p, c, q Proof. We begin our proof by defining the functions below q + = + c p + cp ; q = c p cp ; and q = + c p cp Let P t be the equilibrium probability that M wins the election in period t, given x. Also, let ϕ = 4p + c 3. Then we have the following Lemma 9 If x =,, E[P ] = P = + c, and + p + q c if q p + p + q c + p q if q p, q+ + c if q > q+. If x =, and p 5 8 c 4, E[P ] = P =, and + p + q c if q q + p + q c + p q if q q, q + + c if q > q+. Finally, if x =, and p, 5 8 c 4, P = ϕ E[P [,, x ]] ϕ + p + q c + p q + ϕ q p c + p + q 3 if q, q and p < + c 4 ϕ + p + q c + ϕ + c p + if q, q and p > + c 4 ϕ + p + q c + p q + ϕ + c p + if q max{q, q }, q + ϕ + c + ϕ + c p + if q q +, 7

18 Proof. We consider the two cases x =, and x =, separately.. Suppose first x =,. From Lemma 6, P, = + c, and xw =. With probability, we observe π =, and then x =, and the probability that M wins the second election is + c. With probability p q, we observe π =, and then x =, and the probability that M wins the second election is. Finally, with probability p q + p q, we observe π = 0 and then from Lemma 6 and by studying the properties of q + we obtain the first column and the conditions in the following table: x P, + c if q p, p q, 4 p q+ 3 + c if q p, q+., if q > q + For the probabilities, the first and third row are immediate. For the second row, 6 So, M wins if which occurs with probability u V M x E, x M, p = ε + c + p q p q = ε + c + p + q, and u V E x E, x M, p = p q p q = q p. ε c p, c + 4p = 4p 3 c p q = 4 p q c. Thus, if q p, the expected utility for M in the second period is + c + p q + p q + p q + c = + cp + q ; if q p, q +, the expected utility for M in the second period is + c + p q + p q + p q p q 4 p q c = + cp + q q p; and if q q +, the expected utility for M in the second period is + c + p q + p q + p q = + c.. Suppose now x =,. Unfortunately, in this case we have eight separate subcases for different parameter p, q, c values in the parameter space,, 0,..a. Consider first three subcases corresponding to p 5 8 c 4. In this case, xw = so P = and p q we obtain posterior p, 0 = p q+. With probability, we observe π =, and then x =, and the probability that M wins the second election is + c. With probability p q, we observe π =, and then x =, and the probability that M wins the second election is c. Finally, with probability p q+ p q, we observe π = 0 and then we have three subcases depending on {q, c}, and 8

19 from Lemma 4 and by studying the properties of q and q + we obtain the first column and the conditions in the following table: x P, + c if q < q. p q, 4 p q+ 3 if q [q, q + 7 ],, c if q > q+. So, if p 5 8 c 4 and q < q, the expected utility for M in the nd period is = + c + c + p q c p q + = p + q c + ; c + [p q + p q] + c p q if p 5 8 c 4 and q [q, q + ], the expected utility for M in the nd period is + c + p q c p q + p q + p q 4 p q + 3 = + p + q c + p q; and if p 5 8 c 4 and q > q+, the expected utility for M in the nd period is + c = + c = + c. + p q c + c + p q + p q c.b. Now consider the five subcases in which p, 5 8 c 4. Then x W can be + or. Note u V E,, p = p p = p u V M,, p = p p + ε + c = p + ε + c u V M,, p u V E,, p = 4p + ε + c so Pr[M wins,, p] = Pr[ε c 4p, ] = + c + 4p = 4p + c 3. So, with probability 4p + c 3, xw = and then, subject to x W =, as noted in the proof for case.a., E[u M x =,, x W = + p + q c if q < q. + p + q c + p q if q [q, q + ], + c if q > q+. 9

20 On the other hand, with probability 5 4p c, xw = and then, subject to x W = : π x Probability {, + c} [, ] p q., if q q {0, c}, if q q + p q, {, + c},., 8 where p, 0 = + p q and the x outcome given π {0, c} is by by studying the properties of q and Lemma 4. Notice that the probability that M wins in the second period as a function of x given x =, is P [,,, ] = c, P [,,, ] = + c and given π {0, c}, P [,,, ] = Pr[ε + p > p ] = Pr[ε > 4p ] = 4p 3 = 4 + p q 3. So, subject to x W winning for M : =, we can update Table 8 to include expected second period utility probability of π P [,, x ] Probability {, + c} [ c p q. 4 {0, c} + p q 3 if q q ], 9 + p q, + c if q q {, + c} + c. Aggregating probabilities over all three events, we can calculate the expected probability of winning, not conditioning on π, as If q q, then P [,, x ] = p q c + + p q 4 + p q c = q p c + p + q 3, whereas if q q, then P [,, x ] is equal to = p q c = + c p +, + p q + c Recalling that q q +, and aggregating probabilities over the events x w = and x w =, we now have five subcasesas described in the lemma P [,, x ] if q 4p + c 3 + p + q c + 5 4p c q p c + p + q 3, min{q, q } 4p + c 3 + p + q c + p q + 5 4p c q p c + p + q 3 q, q 4p + c 3 + p + q c + 5 4p c + c p + q, q 4p + c 3 + p + q c + p q + 5 4p c + c p + max{q, q }, q + 4p + c 3 + c + 5 4p c + c p + q +, We can partition c, p, q space according lemma 9. We have nine potential regions: 0

21 . If q q +, then, will be preferred when or + c + + c ϕ + ϕ + c + ϕ + c p + q q = c cp ϕ + 4cp + cp. If p > + 4 c c or and q p, q + then, will be preferred when + c + + p + q c + p q ϕ + ϕ + p + q c + p q + ϕ + c p + q q = c + p + 3cp + ϕ 4p + 6cp + cp c + ϕ + c 3cp 3. If p > + c 4 and q q, p then, will be preferred when or + c + + p + q c ϕ + ϕ + p + q c + p q + ϕ + c p + q q 3 = c + p + 3cp + ϕ 6cp + cp c + ϕ + c 3cp 4. If p > + c 4 and q, q then, will be preferred when or 5. If + c 4 > p > + 4 c c or + c + + p + q c ϕ + ϕ + p + q c + ϕ + c p + q q 4 = c + 4cp + ϕ 6cp + c 4p ϕ + c 3p and q q, p then, will be preferred when + c + + p + q c ϕ + ϕ + p + q c + p q q q 3 + ϕ + c p +

22 6. If + c 4 > p > + 4 c c and q, q then, will be preferred when or 7. If < p < + 4 c c or + c + + p + q c ϕ + ϕ + p + q c + p q 8. If < p < + 4 c c or + ϕ q p c + p + q 3 q q 5 = c cp 3 ϕ + c 4p + 4cp + 5 cp + 4ϕ and q q, q + then, will be preferred when + c + + p + q c + p q ϕ + ϕ + p + q c + p q q q + ϕ + c p + and q p, q then, will be preferred when + c + + p + q c + p q ϕ + ϕ + p + q c + p q + ϕ q p c + p + q 3 q q 6 = c cp 3 ϕ + c + 4cp + 5 cp + 4 4ϕ 9. If < p < + 4 c c and q, p then, will be preferred when or + c + + p + q c ϕ + ϕ + p + q c + p q q q 5 + ϕ q p c + p + q 3 We can summarize all of this by saying that the dashed lines actually don t matter, so effectively, the c, p, q is partitioned in six areas. If q q +, then, will be preferred when q q. If q max p, q, q + then, will be preferred when q q 3. If q max q, q, p then, will be preferred when q q 3 4. If q, q then, will be preferred when q q 4 5. If q, minq, p then, will be preferred when q q 5 6. If q p, q then, will be preferred when q q 6 Although we also have the following that we provide without proof available upon request:

23 Lemma 0 If q p, q then q q 6. which implies that the restriction q q 6 is redundant. So now write { q if q q Q p, c = +, q if q max p, q, q + { q3 if q max q Q p, c =, q, p q 5 if q, minq, p Q p, c = q 4 then we get the result in the proposition if we note that case 4. above requires that q p, c = q 4 p, c for p > 4 + c 4 and this requires that c > 5 as claimed above. Finally, we get Remark 3 in the main text by noting that if ϕ = then q = q = Q p, c = 4c cp q 3 = q 5 = Q p, c = + 4p 4c cp q 4 = Q p, c = 4c cp c p and the result just follows by expressing these as a function of c. Proposition Q p, c and Q p, c are decreasing in p and increasing in c while Q p, c is increasing in p and decreasing in c. Proof. Simple inspection shows this to be true for the case p 5 8 c 4 where ϕ = and so q = q = Q p, c = 4c cp q 3 = q 5 = Q p, c = + 4p 4c cp q 4 = Q p, c = 4c cp c p Consider now the case p < 5 8 c 4 where ϕ = 4p + c 3.. dq dp dq dc = = d d pc +3p 8p 4c+ p cp dp pc +3p 8p 4c+ p cp dc = p c c cp < c c cp < 0 = p + c p c p > 0. As we know dq 6c dp = + 96c + 56 p + 3c 3 + c 64c 30 p + 4c 4 4c 3 59c + 44c c + 6p + 6cp + 4c p 0cp c 0 3

Tactical Extremism. NICEP Working Paper: Jon X. Eguia Francesco Giovannoni

Tactical Extremism. NICEP Working Paper: Jon X. Eguia Francesco Giovannoni NICEP Working Paper: 207-06 Tactical Extremism Jon X. Eguia Francesco Giovannoni Nottingham Interdisciplinary Centre for Economic and Political Research https://nicep.nottingham.ac.uk/ School of Politics,

More information

Tactical Extremism. October 11, Abstract. We provide an instrumental theory of extreme campaign platforms. By adopting

Tactical Extremism. October 11, Abstract. We provide an instrumental theory of extreme campaign platforms. By adopting Tactical Extremism Jon X. Eguia Francesco Giovannoni October, 207 Abstract We provide an instrumental theory of extreme campaign platforms. By adopting an extreme platform, a previously mainstream party

More information

The Importance of the Median Voter

The Importance of the Median Voter The Importance of the Median Voter According to Duncan Black and Anthony Downs V53.0500 NYU 1 Committee Decisions utility 0 100 x 1 x 2 x 3 x 4 x 5 V53.0500 NYU 2 Single-Peakedness Condition The preferences

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

Spatial Competition Between Two Candidates of Different Quality: The Effects of Candidate Ideology and Private Information 1

Spatial Competition Between Two Candidates of Different Quality: The Effects of Candidate Ideology and Private Information 1 Spatial Competition Between Two Candidates of Different Quality: The Effects of Candidate Ideology and Private Information 1 Enriqueta Aragones Thomas R. Palfrey 3 May 005 1 Aragones acknowledges financial

More information

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers joint work with Frederic Murphy Climate Policy and Long Term Decisions-Investment and R&D, Bocconi University, Milan,

More information

Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case

Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case Mariagiovanna Baccara Leeat Yariv August 19, 2012 1 Introduction In this Appendix we study the information sharing application analyzed

More information

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals Liping Tang Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh PA 15213, USA Abstract. Crawford and Sobel s Cheap Talk model [1] describes an information

More information

Political Cycles and Stock Returns. Pietro Veronesi

Political Cycles and Stock Returns. Pietro Veronesi Political Cycles and Stock Returns Ľuboš Pástor and Pietro Veronesi University of Chicago, National Bank of Slovakia, NBER, CEPR University of Chicago, NBER, CEPR Average Excess Stock Market Returns 30

More information

Tactical Extremism. Jon X. Eguia Francesco Giovannoni. Discussion Paper 18 / June 2018

Tactical Extremism. Jon X. Eguia Francesco Giovannoni. Discussion Paper 18 / June 2018 Tactical Extremism Jon X. Eguia Francesco Giovannoni Discussion Paper 8 / 70 8 June 208 Department of Economics University of Bristol Priory Road Complex Bristol BS8 TU United Kingdom Tactical Extremism

More information

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lecture 8. Institutional Change and Democratization

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lecture 8. Institutional Change and Democratization 14.773 Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lecture 8. Institutional Change and Democratization Daron Acemoglu MIT March 5, 2013. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lecture 8 March 5,

More information

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication. National University of Singapore June 5, 2018

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication. National University of Singapore June 5, 2018 When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication Ying Chen Johns Hopkins University Atara Oliver Rice University National University of Singapore June 5, 2018 Main idea In many communication

More information

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Political Economics. Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich. Summer term / 37

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Political Economics. Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich. Summer term / 37 1 / 37 Political Economics Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich Summer term 2010 4 / 37 Table of contents 1 Introduction(MG) 2 Preferences and voting (MG) 3 Voter turnout (MG) 4 Electoral competition (SÜ)

More information

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013 Uncertainty Michael Peters December 27, 20 Lotteries In many problems in economics, people are forced to make decisions without knowing exactly what the consequences will be. For example, when you buy

More information

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication Work in Progress Ying Chen Johns Hopkins University Atara Oliver Rice University March 19, 2018 Main idea In many communication situations,

More information

ANSWER KEY 2 GAME THEORY, ECON 395

ANSWER KEY 2 GAME THEORY, ECON 395 ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 95 PROFESSOR A. JOSEPH GUSE (1) (Gibbons 1.6) Consider again the Cournot duopoly model with demand given by the marginal willingness to pay function: P(Q) = a Q, but this time

More information

Learning from Others Outcomes

Learning from Others Outcomes Learning from Others Outcomes Alexander Wolitzky MIT BFI, July 21, 2017 Wolitzky (MIT) Learning from Others Outcomes BFI, July 21, 2017 1 / 53 Introduction Scarcity of Cost-Saving Innovation Development

More information

C31: Game Theory, Lecture 1

C31: Game Theory, Lecture 1 C31: Game Theory, Lecture 1 V. Bhaskar University College London 5 October 2006 C31 Lecture 1: Games in strategic form & Pure strategy equilibrium Osborne: ch 2,3, 12.2, 12.3 A game is a situation where:

More information

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Voter Turnout Agency GIP SIP Rent seeking Partisans. 7. Special-interest politics

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Voter Turnout Agency GIP SIP Rent seeking Partisans. 7. Special-interest politics 7. Special-interest politics Motivation Why do some groups in society receive more generous support than other (e.g. farmers)? Homogeneity in interests which allows more efficient organization of lobby

More information

Estimating Dynamic Games of Electoral Competition to Evaluate Term Limits in U.S. Gubernatorial Elections: Online Appendix

Estimating Dynamic Games of Electoral Competition to Evaluate Term Limits in U.S. Gubernatorial Elections: Online Appendix Estimating Dynamic Games of Electoral Competition to Evaluate Term Limits in U.S. Gubernatorial Elections: Online ppendix Holger Sieg University of Pennsylvania and NBER Chamna Yoon Baruch College I. States

More information

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Gagan Ghosh Bingchao Huangfu Heng Liu October 19, 2017 (PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE: COMMENTS WELCOME) Abstract We study wars of attrition between two bidders who

More information

Economics 3012 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 20, 2006

Economics 3012 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 20, 2006 Economics 301 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 0, 006 Lecture 11 Topics Problem Set 9 Extensive Games of Imperfect Information An Example General Description Strategies and Nash Equilibrium Beliefs

More information

Game theory lecture 4. September 24, 2012

Game theory lecture 4. September 24, 2012 September 24, 2012 Finding Nash equilibrium Best-response or best-reply functions. We introduced Nash-equilibrium as a profile of actions (an action for each player) such that no player has an incentive

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach)

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach) UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2015 Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach) Block 4 Jul 31 and Aug 1, 2015 Auction results Herd behavior and

More information

A political-economy model of taxation and government expenditures with differentiated candidates

A political-economy model of taxation and government expenditures with differentiated candidates A political-economy model of taxation and government expenditures with differentiated candidates Stefan Krasa Mattias Polborn May 9, 2009 Abstract e develop a model of political competition between two

More information

Game Theory: Spring 2017

Game Theory: Spring 2017 Game Theory: Spring 207 Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss Plan for Today We have seen that every normal-form game has a Nash equilibrium, although

More information

Mutual Optimism in the Bargaining Model of War

Mutual Optimism in the Bargaining Model of War Mutual Optimism in the Bargaining Model of War Mark Fey Kristopher W. Ramsay December 19, 2016 Abstract Mutual optimism is often considered an explanation for war, but recent research has challenged that

More information

Political Economy of Transparency

Political Economy of Transparency Political Economy of Transparency Raphael Galvão University of Pennsylvania rgalvao@sas.upenn.edu November 20, 2017 Abstract This paper develops a model where short-term reputation concerns guide the public

More information

Module 16: Signaling

Module 16: Signaling Module 16: Signaling Information Economics (Ec 515) George Georgiadis Players with private information can take some action to signal their type. Taking this action would distinguish them from other types.

More information

Entry under an Information-Gathering Monopoly Alex Barrachina* June Abstract

Entry under an Information-Gathering Monopoly Alex Barrachina* June Abstract Entry under an Information-Gathering onopoly Alex Barrachina* June 2016 Abstract The effects of information-gathering activities on a basic entry model with asymmetric information are analyzed. In the

More information

Chapter Three. Hypothesis Testing

Chapter Three. Hypothesis Testing 3.1 Introduction The final phase of analyzing data is to make a decision concerning a set of choices or options. Should I invest in stocks or bonds? Should a new product be marketed? Are my products being

More information

Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan

Discussion of Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan Stephen Morris IUB Stern Workshop March 2017 Basic Question Some policy ingredients:

More information

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models 14.773 Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models Daron Acemoglu MIT February 7 and 12, 2013. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 2 and 3 February

More information

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2)

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2) Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2) Haifeng Huang University of California, Merced Best response functions: example In simple games we can examine

More information

The New Keynesian Model: Introduction

The New Keynesian Model: Introduction The New Keynesian Model: Introduction Vivaldo M. Mendes ISCTE Lisbon University Institute 13 November 2017 (Vivaldo M. Mendes) The New Keynesian Model: Introduction 13 November 2013 1 / 39 Summary 1 What

More information

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 1 Modelling incomplete information So far, we have studied games in which information was complete,

More information

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information:

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: Signalling Games In general, a dynamic game of incomplete information is any extensive form game in which at least one player is uninformed about some

More information

SPATIAL VOTING (MULTIPLE DIMENSIONS)

SPATIAL VOTING (MULTIPLE DIMENSIONS) SPATIAL VOTING (MULTIPLE DIMENSIONS) 1 Assumptions Alternatives are points in an n-dimensional space. Examples for 2D: Social Issues and Economic Issues Domestic Spending and Foreign Spending Single-peaked

More information

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007 Costly Expertise Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz Current Version: December, 007 In many environments expertise is costly. Costs can manifest themselves in numerous ways, ranging from the time that is required

More information

Economic Policies of Heterogeneous Politicians

Economic Policies of Heterogeneous Politicians Economic Policies of Heterogeneous Politicians ODILON CÂMARA Marshall School of Business, University of Southern California January 27, 2012 Abstract This paper studies how a politician s preferences and

More information

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting 14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting Daron Acemoglu MIT September 6 and 11, 2017. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2 September 6

More information

Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation

Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation Roland Bénabou Jean Tirole. Review of Economic Studies 2003 Bénabou and Tirole Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation 1 / 30 Motivation Should a child be rewarded for passing

More information

Misinformation. March Abstract

Misinformation. March Abstract Misinformation Li, Hao University of British Columbia & University of Toronto Wei Li University of British Columbia & University of California, Riverside March 2010 Abstract We model political campaigns

More information

Deviant Behavior in Monetary Economics

Deviant Behavior in Monetary Economics Deviant Behavior in Monetary Economics Lawrence Christiano and Yuta Takahashi July 26, 2018 Multiple Equilibria Standard NK Model Standard, New Keynesian (NK) Monetary Model: Taylor rule satisfying Taylor

More information

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class.

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class. Political Economy of Institutions and Development: 14.773 Problem Set 1 Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class. Answer Questions 1-3. handed in. The other two questions are for practice and are not

More information

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection Geethanjali Selvaretnam Abstract This model takes into consideration the fact that depositors

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory COMP323 Introduction to Computational Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Paul G. Spirakis Department of Computer Science University of Liverpool Paul G. Spirakis (U. Liverpool) Introduction to Game

More information

Endogenous Information Choice

Endogenous Information Choice Endogenous Information Choice Lecture 7 February 11, 2015 An optimizing trader will process those prices of most importance to his decision problem most frequently and carefully, those of less importance

More information

Econ 325: Introduction to Empirical Economics

Econ 325: Introduction to Empirical Economics Econ 325: Introduction to Empirical Economics Chapter 9 Hypothesis Testing: Single Population Ch. 9-1 9.1 What is a Hypothesis? A hypothesis is a claim (assumption) about a population parameter: population

More information

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lecture 8. Institutional Change and Democratization

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lecture 8. Institutional Change and Democratization 14.773 Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lecture 8. Institutional Change and Democratization Daron Acemoglu MIT March 6, 2018. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lecture 8 March 6,

More information

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium For an important class of extensive games, a solution concept is available that is simpler than sequential equilibrium, but with similar properties. In a Bayesian extensive

More information

Strategic Abuse and Accuser Credibility

Strategic Abuse and Accuser Credibility 1 / 33 Strategic Abuse and Accuser Credibility HARRY PEI and BRUNO STRULOVICI Department of Economics, Northwestern University November 16th, 2018 Montréal, Canada 2 / 33 Motivation Many crimes/abuses

More information

Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 2: Nash Equilibria and Examples

Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 2: Nash Equilibria and Examples Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 2: Nash Equilibria and Examples February 24, 2011 Summary: We introduce the Nash Equilibrium: an outcome (action profile) which is stable in the sense that no player

More information

1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty

1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty 1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty Sofarwehaveassumedawayaggregatefluctuations (i.e., business cycles) in our description of the incomplete-markets economies with uninsurable idiosyncratic risk

More information

Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica

Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica Barcelona Economics Working Paper Series Working Paper nº 60 Electoral Competition Between Two Candidates of Different Quality: The Effects of Candidate Ideology

More information

Endogenous information acquisition

Endogenous information acquisition Endogenous information acquisition ECON 101 Benhabib, Liu, Wang (2008) Endogenous information acquisition Benhabib, Liu, Wang 1 / 55 The Baseline Mode l The economy is populated by a large representative

More information

Fiscal Rules and Discretion under Self-Enforcement

Fiscal Rules and Discretion under Self-Enforcement Fiscal Rules and Discretion under Self-Enforcement Marina Halac and Pierre Yared Columbia University May 2018 Motivation Countries impose rules to constrain governments policy decisions Fiscal rules in

More information

arxiv: v2 [cs.ni] 8 Apr 2014

arxiv: v2 [cs.ni] 8 Apr 2014 Network Non-Neutrality on the Internet: Content Provision Under a Subscription Revenue Model Mohammad Hassan Lotfi ESE Department University of Pennsylvania Philadelphia, PA, 1910 lotfm@seas.upenn.edu

More information

Coordination and Continuous Choice

Coordination and Continuous Choice Coordination and Continuous Choice Stephen Morris and Ming Yang Princeton University and Duke University December 2016 Abstract We study a coordination game where players choose what information to acquire

More information

Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanisms

Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanisms Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanisms Jonathan Levin 1 Economics 285 Market Design Winter 2009 1 These slides are based on Paul Milgrom s. onathan Levin VCG Mechanisms Winter 2009 1 / 23 Motivation We consider

More information

Probability and Statistics

Probability and Statistics Probability and Statistics Kristel Van Steen, PhD 2 Montefiore Institute - Systems and Modeling GIGA - Bioinformatics ULg kristel.vansteen@ulg.ac.be CHAPTER 4: IT IS ALL ABOUT DATA 4a - 1 CHAPTER 4: IT

More information

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I Lecture 11 Instructor: Tommaso Nannicini Teaching Fellow: Jeremy Bowles Harvard University November 9, 2017 Overview * Today s lecture Dynamic games of incomplete

More information

Source: US. Bureau of Economic Analysis Shaded areas indicate US recessions research.stlouisfed.org

Source: US. Bureau of Economic Analysis Shaded areas indicate US recessions research.stlouisfed.org Business Cycles 0 Real Gross Domestic Product 18,000 16,000 (Billions of Chained 2009 Dollars) 14,000 12,000 10,000 8,000 6,000 4,000 2,000 1940 1960 1980 2000 Source: US. Bureau of Economic Analysis Shaded

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

Fairness and Redistribution: Response

Fairness and Redistribution: Response Fairness and Redistribution: Response By ALBERTO ALESINA, GEORGE-MARIOS ANGELETOS, AND GUIDO COZZI This paper responds to the comment of Di Tella and Dubra (211). We first clarify that the model of Alesina

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibrium Refinements Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game... subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium Play starting

More information

MA Macroeconomics 4. Analysing the IS-MP-PC Model

MA Macroeconomics 4. Analysing the IS-MP-PC Model MA Macroeconomics 4. Analysing the IS-MP-PC Model Karl Whelan School of Economics, UCD Autumn 2014 Karl Whelan (UCD) Analysing the IS-MP-PC Model Autumn 2014 1 / 28 Part I Inflation Expectations Karl Whelan

More information

Partisan Politics and Aggregation Failure with Ignorant Voters

Partisan Politics and Aggregation Failure with Ignorant Voters Partisan Politics and Aggregation Failure with Ignorant Voters Faruk Gul and Wolfgang Pesendorfer Princeton University June 2006 Abstract We analyze a Downsian model of candidate competition with two modifications.

More information

Design Patent Damages under Sequential Innovation

Design Patent Damages under Sequential Innovation Design Patent Damages under Sequential Innovation Yongmin Chen and David Sappington University of Colorado and University of Florida February 2016 1 / 32 1. Introduction Patent policy: patent protection

More information

UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND Department of Economics Economics 754 Topics in Political Economy Fall 2005 Allan Drazen. Exercise Set I

UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND Department of Economics Economics 754 Topics in Political Economy Fall 2005 Allan Drazen. Exercise Set I UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND Department of Economics Economics 754 Topics in Political Economy Fall 005 Allan Drazen Exercise Set I The first four exercises are review of what we did in class on 8/31. The next

More information

Communication and Voting with Double-Sided Information

Communication and Voting with Double-Sided Information Communication and Voting with Double-Sided Information Ulrich Doraszelski Hoover Institution Dino Gerardi Yale University Francesco Squintani University of Rochester March 2002 An earlier version of this

More information

EC3224 Autumn Lecture #03 Applications of Nash Equilibrium

EC3224 Autumn Lecture #03 Applications of Nash Equilibrium Reading EC3224 Autumn Lecture #03 Applications of Nash Equilibrium Osborne Chapter 3 By the end of this week you should be able to: apply Nash equilibrium to oligopoly games, voting games and other examples.

More information

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Attila Ambrus, Eduardo M. Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada December 3, 011 1 Monotonicity of the set of pure-strategy equilibria

More information

Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan Question 1 (duopoly games with imperfect information)

Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan Question 1 (duopoly games with imperfect information) Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan 200 Good luck!!! Question (duopoly games with imperfect information) Consider a duopoly game in which the inverse demand function is linear where it is positive

More information

Supplementary Appendix for Informative Cheap Talk in Elections

Supplementary Appendix for Informative Cheap Talk in Elections Supplementary Appendix for Informative Cheap Talk in Elections Navin Kartik Richard Van Weelden October 19, 2017 Abstract This Supplementary Appendix formalizes two extensions of the baseline model discussed

More information

Known Unknowns: Power Shifts, Uncertainty, and War.

Known Unknowns: Power Shifts, Uncertainty, and War. Known Unknowns: Power Shifts, Uncertainty, and War. Online Appendix Alexandre Debs and Nuno P. Monteiro May 10, 2016 he Appendix is structured as follows. Section 1 offers proofs of the formal results

More information

Static Information Design

Static Information Design Static Information Design Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Frontiers of Economic Theory & Computer Science, Becker-Friedman Institute, August 2016 Mechanism Design and Information Design Basic Mechanism

More information

The Value of Sharing Intermittent Spectrum

The Value of Sharing Intermittent Spectrum The Value of Sharing Intermittent Spectrum R. erry, M. Honig, T. Nguyen, V. Subramanian & R. V. Vohra Abstract We consider a model of Cournot competition with congestion motivated by recent initiatives

More information

Information Choice in Macroeconomics and Finance.

Information Choice in Macroeconomics and Finance. Information Choice in Macroeconomics and Finance. Laura Veldkamp New York University, Stern School of Business, CEPR and NBER Spring 2009 1 Veldkamp What information consumes is rather obvious: It consumes

More information

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

Limit pricing models and PBE 1 EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Limit pricing models and PBE 1 1 Model Consider an entry game with an incumbent monopolist (Firm 1) and an entrant (Firm ) who analyzes whether or not to join the

More information

Costly Voting: Voter Composition and Turnout

Costly Voting: Voter Composition and Turnout Costly Voting: Voter Composition and Turnout Jannet Chang Department of Economics, Virginia Tech October, 004 Abstract Given voting is costly, we analyze under what conditions rational agents vote and

More information

Chapter 12: Model Specification and Development

Chapter 12: Model Specification and Development Chapter 12: Model Specification and Development Chapter 12 Outline Model Specification: Ramsey REgression Specification Error Test (RESET) o RESET Logic o Linear Demand Model o Constant Elasticity Demand

More information

Fall 2017 Recitation 10 Notes

Fall 2017 Recitation 10 Notes 14.770-Fall 017 Recitation 10 Notes Arda Gitmez December 8, 017 Today: Why incentives can backfire Holmstrom and Milgrom s multitasking model (1991, JLEO) Two papers by Benabou and Tirole (003, REStud

More information

Blocking Development

Blocking Development Blocking Development Daron Acemoglu Department of Economics Massachusetts Institute of Technology October 11, 2005 Taking Stock Lecture 1: Institutions matter. Social conflict view, a useful perspective

More information

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics. Puri cation 1 Stephen Morris Princeton University July 2006 1 This survey was prepared as an entry for the second edition of the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. In a mixed strategy equilibrium of

More information

14.461: Technological Change, Lecture 3 Competition, Policy and Technological Progress

14.461: Technological Change, Lecture 3 Competition, Policy and Technological Progress 14.461: Technological Change, Lecture 3 Competition, Policy and Technological Progress Daron Acemoglu MIT September 15, 2016. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Competition, Policy and Innovation September 15, 2016.

More information

V. The Speed of adjustment of Endogenous Variables and Overshooting

V. The Speed of adjustment of Endogenous Variables and Overshooting V. The Speed of adjustment of Endogenous Variables and Overshooting The second section of Chapter 11 of Dornbusch (1980) draws on Dornbusch (1976) Expectations and Exchange Rate Dynamics, Journal of Political

More information

4- Current Method of Explaining Business Cycles: DSGE Models. Basic Economic Models

4- Current Method of Explaining Business Cycles: DSGE Models. Basic Economic Models 4- Current Method of Explaining Business Cycles: DSGE Models Basic Economic Models In Economics, we use theoretical models to explain the economic processes in the real world. These models de ne a relation

More information

Online Appendix for Sourcing from Suppliers with Financial Constraints and Performance Risk

Online Appendix for Sourcing from Suppliers with Financial Constraints and Performance Risk Online Appendix for Sourcing from Suppliers with Financial Constraints and Performance Ris Christopher S. Tang S. Alex Yang Jing Wu Appendix A: Proofs Proof of Lemma 1. In a centralized chain, the system

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

MA Macroeconomics 3. Introducing the IS-MP-PC Model

MA Macroeconomics 3. Introducing the IS-MP-PC Model MA Macroeconomics 3. Introducing the IS-MP-PC Model Karl Whelan School of Economics, UCD Autumn 2014 Karl Whelan (UCD) Introducing the IS-MP-PC Model Autumn 2014 1 / 38 Beyond IS-LM We have reviewed the

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Summer 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the four areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory A, (III) game theory B, and (IV) psychology & economics). Be sure

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key EconS 50 - Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam # - Answer Key 1. Revenue comparison in two auction formats. Consider a sealed-bid auction with bidders. Every bidder i privately observes his valuation

More information

Do Shareholders Vote Strategically? Voting Behavior, Proposal Screening, and Majority Rules. Supplement

Do Shareholders Vote Strategically? Voting Behavior, Proposal Screening, and Majority Rules. Supplement Do Shareholders Vote Strategically? Voting Behavior, Proposal Screening, and Majority Rules Supplement Ernst Maug Kristian Rydqvist September 2008 1 Additional Results on the Theory of Strategic Voting

More information

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden 1 Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning Jason R. Marden Abstract A learning rule is completely uncoupled if each player s behavior is conditioned only on his own realized

More information

Electoral Politics with Policy Adjustment Costs

Electoral Politics with Policy Adjustment Costs Electoral Politics with Policy Adjustment Costs Peter Evangelakis 1 Job Market Paper March 27, 2017 Abstract: Politicians and voters sometimes make decisions that conflict with their ideological position.

More information

What do you do when you can t use money to solve your problems?

What do you do when you can t use money to solve your problems? Markets without money What do you do when you can t use money to solve your problems? Matching: heterosexual men and women marrying in a small town, students matching to universities, workers to jobs where

More information

Cycles in Public Opinion and the Dynamics of Stable Party Systems

Cycles in Public Opinion and the Dynamics of Stable Party Systems Cycles in Public Opinion and the Dynamics of Stable Party Systems Sandro Brusco Jaideep Roy October 1, 2015 Abstract We study a dynamic model of elections where many parties may enter or exit political

More information

Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. On-Line Appendix

Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. On-Line Appendix Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness On-Line Appendix Jérôme Dugast Thierry Foucault August 30, 07 This note is the on-line appendix for Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. It contains

More information