A second look at minsup points and the existence of pure Nash equilibria. Adib Bagh Departments of Economics and Mathematics University of Kentucky.

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "A second look at minsup points and the existence of pure Nash equilibria. Adib Bagh Departments of Economics and Mathematics University of Kentucky."

Transcription

1 A second look at minsup points and the existence of pure Nash equilibria Adib Bagh Departments of Economics and Mathematics University of Kentucky. Abstract. We prove the existence of pure strategy Nash equilibria under very weak conditions of lower semi-continuity and quasi-concavity. Our results generalize previous results by Baye, Tian and Zhou as well as more recent results by Kim and Kum, Hou and Chang. We use the new results to establish the existence of pure strategy equilibria for games with discontinuous and non-quasiconcave payoffs such as probabilistic spatial voting games on the real line. Keywords. Transfer continuity, Transfer quasi-concavity, Payoff security, Minsup points, Nash equilibria, Probabilistic spatial voting games. JEL classification: C72,C62,C69 Corresponding Author: Adib Bagh Gatton College of Business and Economics, University of Kentucky, Lexington, KY, Tel: (859) ; Fax: (859)

2 1. Introduction The literature on minimax problems and their applications in game theory and economics is vast and expanding. It stretches from the work of Fan and Von Neuman in the fifties to recent papers on decision making under model uncertainty and robust control problems (Hansson and Sargent [8] and Willams [17]). Given a function f : X Y IR and a real number α, the existence of a minsup point ˆx X such that sup y Y f(ˆx, y) = min sup x X y Y f(x, y) α (1) is closely related to the existence of a pure strategy Nash equilibrium for a game whose aggregator function is f (see Tian [16], Baye et al [3], Chen and Zhou [18], Kim and Kum [12], and Chang [6]). 1 More generally, we can consider a collection C of functions from Y to X and look for a function ĉ C that solves sup y Y f(ĉ(y), y) = min sup c C y Y f(c(y), y). (2) This type of problems arises from a sequential game involving nature and a decision maker (an agent). Nature moves first by choosing a value y representing the state of the world. The agent has a set X of available actions and a collection C of implementable policies, where each policy is a function from Y to X that assigns to every possible state of the world y an action x X. The function f : X Y IR describes the loss the agent suffers when he takes action x and the state of the world is y. The problem in (2) can be interpreted as requiring the agent to choose, and to commit to, a specific policy before the realization of the state of the world in a manner that minimizes his maximum possible loss. It is often important to know whether or not the minimizer of (2) is constant over Y (i.e. whether or not the optimal policy requires the agent to commit to the same action x no matter what the state of the world is). One remarkable fact about establishing the existence of a simple (constant) policy solution for (2) is that such a result would imply that min sup x X y Y f(x, y) = min sup c C y Y f(c(y), y) (3) 1 We us the term minsup instead of minimax since the supremum need not be attained on Y. Note that for some authors such as Aubin [1], the definition of a minsup point includes additional requirements. 2

3 even when X can be strictly embedded within C (i.e. when C strictly contains all the constant functions from Y to X). In this paper, we establish the existence of a minsup point for f and a constant minimizer for (2) under two conditions. The first condition requires f to be majorized, in a very weak sense, by some function g. The second condition requires the function g to satisfy a very weak concavity condition. We generalize most of the current existence results of minimax points, including Theorem 3.1 in Chang [6], the most recent among such results. 2 We then obtain new existence results for pure strategy Nash equilibria in a large class of two-player games with discontinuous payoffs. Unlike the results of Baye et al [3] and Chang [6], our results do not require the construction of the aggregator function of the underlying game. This is important because imposing strong lower semi-continuity and concavity condtions on the individual payoff functions often does not translate into useful conditions on the aggregator function (see Ziad [19] for an example). We provide a number of applications that include probabilistic spatial voting games with two candidates, where the payoffs of the players are neither continuous nor quasi-concave. Our approach will actually allow us to numerically establish some important patterns regarding the equilibria platforms of the candidates. There are a number of alternative ways for tackling a game with discontinuous and non-quasi-concavity payoffs. One possible approach is to verify that the game is super modular, which requires the best reply functions of the game to satisfy certain monotonicity conditions. This, in turn, requires the payoff of every player to be upper semi-continuous (in the player s own strategy as well as in the strategies of the others). 3 A second approach, developed by Bich [4], requires the strategy set of the players to be convex and imposes conditions on the quasiconcave lower envelops of the payoff functions. Of course, there are games where the strategy sets are not convex, the payoffs are not upper semi-continuous, or the quasi-concave lower envelops of payoff functions cannot be easily calculated. For such games, the approach we follow in this paper will be more appropriate. We start the paper by reviewing basic definitions in Section 2. We present our main results in section 3. Finally, in Sections 4 and 5, we provide some concrete applications. 2 An exception would be the minimax existence results that do not require the set Y to have a linear structure as in Kalmoun and Riahi [11]. 3 The same is true for the approach of Nishimura and Friedman [13]. 3

4 2. Preliminaries In this section, we introduce the notation and the definitions that will be used throughout the paper. Henceforth, let X be a topological space and let Y be a subset of a topological vector space. 4 We denote by n the standard unit simplex in IR n, and for every λ n, we define I(λ) = {k {1,, n} λ k 0}, which is simply the collection of indices where λ has a non-zero component. We remind the reader of the following definition of the lower level set of a function. Definition 1 Given a function h from a set U to IR and given an α IR, the α-lower level sets of h is the set lev α h = {z U h(z) α}. The lower semi-continuous closure in x of a function f : X Y IR is defined in the following manner. Definition 2 Let W(x) be the collection of all open sets containing x X. The lower closure of f : X Y IR in x is defined by f x (x, y) = sup W W(x) inf x W f(x, y). It is clear from the definition that for any y Y, f x (, y) is lower semi-continuous in x, and that f x (x, y) f(x, y) for any (x, y) X Y. Thus, we now have the following lemma whose proof follows immediately from the lower semi-continuity of f x Lemma 1 For every α and every y Y, the set lev α f x (, y) = {x X f x (x, y) α is closed in X. The following notion of lower semi-continuity was introduced in Tian [16]. Definition 3 A function f : X Y IR is transfer lower continuous in x at α IR, if for any (x, y) X Y, f(x, y) > α implies the existence of ŷ Y and the existence of a neighborhood W of x such that f(x, ŷ) > α for all x W. The most important feature of the above notion is the connection between the lower level sets of f and the lower level sets of f x. Lemma 2 f is transfer lower continuous in x at α, then for any y Y, there exists ŷ Y such that lev α f x (, ŷ) lev α f(, y). 4 When X is a subset of topological space U, we can simply equip X with the relative topology it inherits from U. 4

5 Proof. Suppose x lev α f(, y). This implies that f(x, y) > α. Hence, by transfer lower continuity, there exists ŷ and neighborhood W (x) of x such that f(x, ŷ) > α for all x W (x), and therefore f x (x, ŷ) > α and x lev α f x (, ŷ). Payoff security is another notion of lower semi-continuity that was introduced by Reny [14] in a game theoretic setting. Definition 4 The function f : X Y IR is payoff secure in x, if for every (x, y) X Y and every ε > 0, there exists ŷ Y and a neighborhood W of x such that f(x, ŷ) f(x, y) ε, for all x W. Payoff security and transfer lower continuity are closely related via the following Lemma. Lemma 3 The function f : X Y IR is payoff secure in x, if and only if f is transfer lower continuous in x at any α. Proof. Suppose f is transfer lower continuous in x for all α. Then, for any (x, y) X Y and any ε > 0, f is transfer continuous at in x at f(x, y) ε, and therefore the existence of neighborhood W (x) and y Y such that f(x, ŷ) > f(x, y) ε for all x W (x). Hence, f is payoff secure. Now suppose f is payoff secure and f(x, y) > α. Let ε be such that f(x, y) ε > α. The payoff security of f implies the existence of neighborhood W (x) and y Y such that f(x, ŷ) > f(x, y) ε > α for all x W (x). Hence, f is transfer lower continuous at α. We also have the following property of payoff secure functions in terms of their lower level sets. Lemma 4 If f is payoff secure in x, then for every α, y Y levα f x (, y) = y Y levα f(, y). Proof. The fact that f x f implies that, for every α and every y, lev α f(, y) lev α f x (, y). The payoff security of f implies (via Lemmas 2 and 3) that for every α and every y, there exists ŷ Y such lev α f x (, ŷ) lev α f(, y), which implies that lev α f x (, y) lev α f(, y). y Y The conclusion of the Lemma follows immediately. The following notion of concavity is a very minor variation on the notion of 0-pair-concavity introduced by Chang [6]. 5

6 Definition 5 A function g : X Y IR is α-pair-concave in y, if for every finite collection {y 1,, y n } in Y, there exists a continuous function ϕ from n to X such that for any λ n, we have ϕ(λ) i I(λ) levα g(, y i ). 3. Main results As we claimed in the introduction, our first theorem generalizes the current existence results of minimax points. Theorem 1 Consider a function f : X Y IR and a fixed α IR. Assume the following: (i) there exists a function g : X Y IR such that for every y Y, there exists ŷ Y and a closed set F (y) X such that lev α g(, ŷ) F (y) lev α f(, y) (ii) there exists a finite collection of points K 0 Y such that y K 0 F (y) is compact Assume further that for every finite collection of point {y 1,, y n } in Y, there exists a function ϕ : n X such that (iii) for every i {1,, n}, the set G i = {λ n ϕ(λ) F (y i )} is closed in n (iv) for any λ n, we have ϕ(λ) lev α g(, y i ). i I(λ) Note that unlike similar results in Chang [6], Baye et al [3], and Tian [16], the above theorem does not impose an explicit continuity conditions on f. Instead, condition (i) requires f to be majorized, in a very weak sense, by some function g. In fact, as a result of Lemmas 2 and 3, condition (i) is weaker than requiring f to be transfer lower continuous in x at α, and hence it also weaker than requiring f to payoff secure in x. Condition (iv) by itself is weaker than α- pair-concavity in y since condition (iv) above does not require ϕ to be continuous. As we will see 6

7 from the proof of Theorem 1, the combination of (iii) and (iv) provides, in essence, the weakest conditions that will guarantee that the set y K levα g(, y) for any finite subset K of Y. We will also demonstrate in a subsequent corollary that the above theorem generalizes the results of Chang [6], and therefore it also generalizes similar results of Hou [10], Baye et al [3], and Tian [16]. It is possible to introduce conditions (iii) and (iv) as a separate and new notion of transfer quasiconcavity. However, we choose not do so since the literature is already cluttered with such notions (diagonal quasi-concavity, α-diagonal quasi-concavity, C-quasi-concavity, 0-pair-concavity). Proof of Theorem 1. Clearly, y Y F (y) implies y Y levα f(, y), and hence there exists ˆx X such that sup y Y f(ˆx, y) α. Therefore, we only need to show that y Y We define, for every y Y, the following set A 0 = F (y), y K 0 F (y). where K 0 is the finite set in assumption (ii). We also define, for every y Y, the set A(y) = F (y) A 0. For every y, A(y) is a closed subset of A 0. We now show that for every finite set K Y, y K F (y), which in turn implies, via the finite intersection property of closed subsets of a compact set, that y Y F (y) and we are done. Let K be some finite collection of points {y 1,, y n } in Y. By assumption (iii), for every i {1,, n}, there exists a function ϕ such that is closed in n. G i = {λ n ϕ(λ) F (y i )} Furthermore, assumptions (i) and (iv) of implies that for any indexing set {i 1,, i J } that is subset of {1,, n}, and for any λ n such that λ con{e i1,..., e ij }, we have and hence ϕ(λ) lev α g(, ŷ i1 ) lev α g(, ŷ ij ), ϕ(λ) G i1 G ij. (6) 7

8 We now have demonstrated that the collection of sets G 1,, G n satisfies all the assumptions of the KKM theorem (see Appendix A), and therefore n i=1 G i. Hence, y K F (y). Since K was an arbitrary finite subset of Y, this completes the proof. Corollary 1 Let f : X Y IR be transfer lower continuous in x at α. Assume that there is finite subset K 0 Y such that y K 0 lev α f(, y) is compact. Assume further that for every finite collection {y 1,, y n } in Y, there exists a function ϕ : n X such that (i) for every i, the set G i = {λ n f x (ϕ(λ), y i ) α} is closed. (ii) for any λ n, we have ϕ(λ) lev α f(, y i ) i I(λ) Then, there exists ˆx X such that sup y Y f(ˆx, y) α Proof. Take g = f x, F (y) = lev α f x (, y), and apply Lemma 2 and Theorem 1. Note that Lemma 2 also implies that if there is a finite K 0 such that y K 0 lev α f(, y) is compact, then there is a finite K such that y K 0 lev α f(, y) is also compact. As we indicated earlier, we also obtain Theorem 3.1 in Chang [6] a corollary of Theorem 1. Corollary 2 Let f : X Y IR be transfer lower continuous in x at α. Assume there is a finite collection of point K Y such that y K levα f(, ŷ) is compact. Then, there exists ˆx X such that sup y Y f(ˆx, y) α, if and only f is α-pair-concave in y. Proof. The α-pair-concave in y, the lower semi-continuity of f x in x, and the continuity of ϕ imply, for any {y 1,, y n }, the existence of ϕ satisfying conditions (i) and (ii) of Corollary 1. Hence, one direction of the claim follows from Corollary 1. The other direction of the claim is obtained by simply taking ϕ(λ) ˆx for all λ n and using the fact that f x f. Combining Corollary 1 with Lemma 3, we obtain a corollary which will be useful in establishing the existence of a constant solution satisfying (3). Corollary 3 Consider a function payoff secure f : X Y IR in x and a fixed α IR. Assume there is a finite set K 0 Y such that y Y levα f(, y) is compact. Assume further that for any 8

9 collection {y 1,, y n } of points in Y, there exists a function ϕ satisfying conditions (i) and (ii) of Corollary 1 at α. Then, there exists ˆx X such that sup y Y f(ˆx, y) α. Proof. Apply Corollary 1 to f x to obtain the existence of a point ˆx X such that sup y Y f x (ˆx, y) α. By Lemma 4, this implies that sup y Y f(ˆx, y) α. Our next theorem provides conditions that guarantee the existence of a constant function that is a minimizer of problem (2) in the introduction. Theorem 2 Consider a collection C of functions from Y to a compact space X. For each c C, let α c = sup y Y f(c(y), y), and let α = inf c C α c. Assume (a) f is payoff secure in x (b) for every c C, such that for every finite collection {y 1,, y n } in Y, there exists a function ϕ : n IR such that conditions (i) and (ii) of Corollary 1 hold at α = f(c(y c ), y c ) for some y c Y. Then, there exists ˆx X such that sup f(ˆx, y) α. (7) y Y Proof. Consider a sequence of functions c n and corresponding sequence of {α cn } of decreasing real numbers such that α < α cn+1 < α cn, and α cn α. For each y Y and each α cn, consider the set lev αcn f x (, y). Due to the lower semi-continuity of f x in x, and for every y Y and every α cn, lev αcn f x (, y) is a closed and compact subset of X. The function f is payoff secure in x, and by Lemma 3, it is transfer lower continuous at α cn. Condition (b), implies that conditions (i) of (ii) of Corollary 1 hold at f(c n (y cn ), y cn ), and hence they also hold at α cn. Therefore, Corollary 1 implies that, for every n 1, that the set y Y levαcn f x (, y) is not empty. Furthermore, these sets are compact and nested. In particular, for every n 1 we have Therefore, lev αcn f x (, y) lev αc n+1 f x (, y). y Y y Y ( lev αcn f x (, y)), n 1 y Y and there exists ˆx X such that sup y Y f x (ˆx, y) α, and by Lemma 4, sup y Y f(ˆx, y) α. 9

10 In the above proof, if the collection C contains the constant function ĉ(y) ˆx (or if it contains all constant functions), then clearly ĉ satisfies (2). Example 1: Let X = Y = [0, 1] and consider the function f : [0, 1] Y IR defined by 0 when ψ(x) < y, f(x, y) = 5 when ψ(x) = y and when y = 0, 10 when ψ(x) > y and y 0, where ψ is a function from [0, 1] to [0, 1] with ψ(x) = 0 for some x [0, 1]. The function f is payoff secure. Furthermore, for any function c : Y [0, 1] and for any {y 1,, y n } in Y, f satisfies condition (b) of Theorem 2 (take ϕ(λ) x). Therefore, Theorem 2 implies that ˆx such that sup f(ˆx, y) = inf y sup c C y where C is the collection of all functions from Y onto [0, 1]. 4. Applications f(c(y), y), Theorem 1 immediately leads to yet another characterization of the existence of pure strategy equilibria à al Baye et al, Hou, and Chang. Consider a game G with I players each with strategy set X i U where U is a Hausdorff topological vector space. Let X = I i=1 X i be the strategy set of the game, and let u i : X IR be the payoff of player i. Let x i denote the moves of all players other than player i. We define an aggregator function U : X X IR as U(x, y) = I i=1 [u i(y i, x i ) u i (x)]. By the construction of U, a point x X is minsup of U, if and only if it is a pure Nash equilibrium of G. Therefore, by applying Theorem 1 to U, we obtain Theorem 3 Let U : X X IR be the aggregator function of a game defined above, and assume there exists a finite set K 0 Y such y K 0 lev 0 U(, y) is compact. Assume that there exists a function V : X X such that for every y Y, there exists ŷ Y and closed set F (y) such that lev 0 V (, ŷ) F (y) lev 0 U(, y). Assume further that for every {y 1,, y n }, there exists a function ϕ : n X such (i) for every i {1,, n}, the set G i = {λ n ϕ(λ) F (y i )} 10

11 is closed in n (ii) for λ n, we have ϕ(λ) lev α V (, y i ). i I(λ) Then, the game G has a pure strategy equilibrium. We can also use Theorem 1 to provide conditions for the existence of pure Nash equilibria that can be imposed directly on the individual payoff functions rather than on the aggregator function of the game. As we mentioned in the introduction, this is important since properties such as transfer lower continuity and transfer quasi-concavity might hold for each payoff function, and yet fail to hold for the aggregator function. Theorem 4 Consider a two-player game defined on X 1 X 2. For every player i, assume there exists a function g i : X i X i IR and a real number α i such that for every x i, exist a closed set F (x i ) and a point ˆx i such that (i) lev α i g i (ˆx i, ) F (x i ) lev α i u i (x i, ) (ii) there exists a finite collection of points K 0 X i such that x K 0 F (x) is compact and nonempty Moreover, assume that for each i {1, 2}, for every finite collection {y 1,, y n } in X i, there exists a function ϕ i : X i such that (iii) for every k {1,, n}, the set G k = {λ n ϕ i (λ) F (y k )} is closed in n (iv) for any λ n, we have Assume further that ϕ i (λ) lev α g i (y k, ). k I(λ) (v) u 1 (x 1, x 2 ) + u 2 (x 2, x 1 ) α 1 + α 2 for any (x 1, x 2 ) X 1 X 2. Then, the game G has a pure strategy Nash equilibrium (x 1, x 2 ) which solves the system of equations u 1 (x 1, x 2 ) = α 1 and u 2 (x 1, x 2 ) = α 2. Proof. By Theorem 1, there exists x 1 and x 2 such that sup u 1 (x 1, x 2) α 1 and sup u 2 (x 1, x 2 ) α 2, x 1 X 1 x 2 X 2 11

12 Hence, by assumption (v), we have and Hence, which implies and therefore, Thus sup x 2 X 2 [α 1 + α 2 u 1 (x 1, x 2 )] α 2 α 1 + α 2 + sup x 2 X 2 [ u 1 (x 1, x 2 )] α 2 α 1 α 2 + inf u 1 (x 1, x 2 ) α 2, x 2 X 2 inf x 2 X 2 u 1 (x 1, x 2 ) α 1, u 1 (x 1, x 2) = sup u 1 (x 1, x 2) = inf u 1 (x 1, x 2 ). x 1 X 1 x 2 X 2 u 1 (x 1, x 2) = sup x 1 X 1 u 1 (x 1, x 2) The same exact argument can be used to show that u 2 (x 2, x 1) = sup x 2 X 2 u 2 (x 2, x 1 ), and (x 1, x 2 ) is a pure strategy Nash equilibrium. Moreover, u 1 (ˆx 1, x 2) α 1 and u 2 (x 2, x 1) α 2 and u 1 (x 1, x 2) + u 2 (x 2, x 1) α 1 + α 2. The last three inequalities imply that u 1 (x 1, x 2 ) = α 1 and u 2 (x 2, x 1 ) = α 2. Note that Theorems 3 and 4 impose no convexity or compactness conditions on the strategy sets. Note further, that Theorem 4 does not require the game to be a zero-sum game. 5 In the next section, we apply Theorem 4 to voting games. 5 More generally, Theorem 4 does not require the game to be reciprocally upper semi-continuous (Reny [14]). 12

13 5. Pure strategy Equilibrium in PSVM Probabilistic Spatial Voting Models (PSVM) are essentially Hotelling models of spatial competition between candidates where the voters ideal platforms are randomly distributed over a subset of the real line. As an application to the results of the previous section, we consider the following PSVM model that leads to a game with discontinuous and non-quasi-concave payoffs. Consider two candidates RED and BLUE. Both candidates simultaneously announce their platforms as two points in the interval [0, 1]. We assume full commitment to the announced policies. The probability that candidate RED wins the elections, when RED and BLUE respectively announce the platforms (r, b), is given by the function P (a, b), and thus the probability of BLUE winning is 1 P (r, b). We further assume that the candidates can derive the function P given the information they have about the voters. For example, suppose there exists a pivotal voter (a median voter for example) such that a candidate wins the election, if and only if this candidate gets the vote of this pivotal voter. The function P can then represent a situation where the candidates view the location of the ideal platform of the pivotal voter as a random variable with values in [0, 1]. Three minimal assumptions are commonly imposed on P (see Ball [2], Hansson and Stuart [9]): A1) 0 < P (r, b) < 1 A2) P (r, b) = 1 P (b, r) A3) For r < b, P (r, b) is non-decreasing in r and non-decreasing in b, and for b < r, P is nonincreasing in r and non-increasing in b The monotonicity assumption A3 says that if a candidate moves his platform closer to his opponent s, then he will not decrease his chances of winning the election. Similarly, if he moves his platform away from the his opponent s strategy, he will not increase his chances for winning the elections. Ball [2] pointed out that a function P satisfying A1-A3 is either constant with value 1 2 over all of [0, 1] [0, 1], or it is discontinuous on the diagonal of [0, 1] [0, 1]. In other words, in any interesting application of this model, the function P is discontinuous on the diagonal. Therefore, we can simply assume that the probability of RED winning is given by the function of the form 13

14 f(r, b) when r < b, P (r, b) = 1 2 when r = b = z, g(r, b) when r > b. We also assume voters have single-peaked utility functions, and we assume that the location of the ideal point (the peak of the utility function) of the median voter is a random variable with a uniform distribution of the interval [0, 1]. This setting yields a winning probability function for RED of the following form (see section 4 of Ball [2]) r+b 2 when r < b, P (r, b) = 1 2 when r = b = z, 1 r+b 2 when r > b. It is clear that the function P described above satisfies conditions A1 through A3. Assume further that both candidates have mixed motives in the sense that they care about winning the office and about the policy that will be implemented by the winner. More specifically, we assume that in addition to the utilities of winning K R and K B, candidates have respectively utilities of u R (z) and u B (z) when the policy z [0, 1] is implemented regardless to who wins the elections. Therefore, the expected payoffs of the candidates are U R (r, b) = P (r, b)[u R (r) + K R ] + (1 P (r, b))u R (b) and U B (b, r) = (1 P (r, b))[u B (b) + K B ] + P (r, b)u B (r). Or alternatively, U R (r, b) = P (r, b)[u R (r) + K R u R (b)] + u R (b) and U B (b, r) = P (r, b))[u B (r) u B (b) K B ] + u B (b) + K B. Note that when either K A or K B is not zero, the discontinuity in P (r, b) leads to a discontinuity in the payoff functions of the candidates. Finally, let u B (z) = a B z 1, u R (z) = a R z and K R = K B = K. 14

15 Using the setting of our previous section, the payoffs of RED and BLUE can be expressed as r+b 2 ( r + b + K) + a R b when r < b, U R (r, b) = 1 2 K + a R z when r = b = z, (1 r+b 2 )( r + b + K) + a R b when r > b. (1 r+b 2 )(r b K) + a B + b 1 + K when b < r, U B (b, r) = 1 2 K + a B + z 1 when r = b = z, r+b 2 (r b K) + a B + b 1 + K when b > r. The existence of mixed strategy equilibria for the voting games discussed above was investigated by Ball [2], Saporiti [15], and Duggan [7] among others. In this paper, however, we are only interested in the existence of pure strategy equilibrium for such games. (8) (9) When u 1 = u 2 0, K > 0 and candidates care only about winning the election, it is straight forward to show that assumptions A1-A3 imply that (r, b ) = (0.5, 0.5) is the only pure strategy equilibrium for our game. This is the so-called platforms convergence result where both candidates choose the policy corresponding to the expected location of the median voter (recall in our model 0.5 is the expected location of the median voter). When the candidates don t care about winning per say and they only care about the policy that will be implemented by the winner (i.e. K = 0), the platforms convergence result does not hold (see Hansson and Stuart [9]). Moreover, when K = 0, the payoff of both candidates are in fact continuous everywhere. As the value of K starts to increase above zero, a discontinuity is introduced to the candidates payoffs. Furthermore, given a value of K, and for some values of b and a, the functions U R (, b) and U B (, r) may fail to be quasi-concave. As Saporiti [15] pointed out, this lack of quasi-concavity can potentially lead to the non-existence of pure strategy equilibria despite the fact that the voting games under consideration are in fact better reply secure. More specifically, Theorem 3.1 in Reny [14] and related results in Carmona [5], two important tools in establishing the existence of pure strategy equilibria in better reply secure games, cannot be applied due to the lack of quasi-concavity. Note also that the functions U R and U B are not diagonal quasi-concave à la Baye et al (Definition 2 in Baye et al [3]), and therefore, their results cannot be applied here. Furthermore, the second order conditions 2 U R (r,b) r 2 0 and 2 U B (r,b) b 2 0 hold only almost everywhere on [0, 1]. In fact, they don t hold at points where x = y because these partial derivatives are not defined at such points. Therefore, it is not possible to find an equilibrium for this game 15

16 by constructing the best reply functions of the players using first order conditions. The problem with such approach is that the first order (necessary) conditions for the maximizers of the function U R (, b) and U B (, r) may no longer be sufficient if the second order conditions fail at a single point (see Section B in the appendix for an example). 6 Therefore, we establish the existence of a pure strategy equilibrium using Theorem 4. Let U R be the lower semi-continuous closure of U R in b. The functions U R and U R are different only at points of discontinuity where r = b = z 0.5. Moreover, from (8), we can see that any such point, we either have lim b z U R (z, b) > U(z, z), or we have lim b z + U R (z, b) > U(z, z). Hence, for every r [0, 1], and for any α, there exists ˆr [0, 1] such that lev α U R (ˆr, ) lev α U R (r, ). (10) Letting F (r) = lev α U R (ˆr, b), we can claim that assumptions (i), and (ii) of Theorem 4 hold for any α. For any collection {r 1,, r n }, there exists ϕ : n [0, 1] such that conditions (iii) and (iv) of Theorem 4 hold for α 1 = a R + 0.5(K 1) (see Appendix C for details). Similarly, we can show that U B also satisfies assumptions (i) through (iv) of Theorem 4 for α 2 = a B + 0.5(K 1). Moreover, straight forward calculations shows that U R + U B α 1 + α 2. (11) Hence, by Theorem 4, the game has a pure strategy Nash equilibrium. Furthermore, Theorem 4 provides us with a systematic method to find these equilibria. For K = 0, α 1 = a R and α 2 = a B. We start by solving the system U R (r, b) = a R U B (b, r) = a B, and among all the solutions that we find, we look for points (r, b ) where sup U R (r, b ) a R and r [0,1] sup U B (b, r ) a B. b [0,1] 6 This suggests that the approach for finding pure Nash equilibria taken in section 3.2 in [15] and the approach taken in [2] for constructing the best reply functions are both incomplete. More specifically, footnote 10 in [2] and footnote 19 in [15] are incorrect because the second derivative inequalities in these footnotes hold almost every where instead of holding everywhere. 16

17 The leads to the equilibrium (r, b ) = (0, 1) (independent of a R and a B ), and as expected we have an extreme divergence of platforms. Hence, we obtain the same results of Hansson and Stuart [9] but without any differentiability assumptions on the function P. For 0 < K < 1, repeating the same process leads to an equilibrium at (r, b ) = (0.5K, 1 0.5K). For example, when K = 0.5, (r, b ) = (0.25, 0.75) is an equilibrium. For K 1, the point (r, b ) = (0.5, 0.5) is an equilibrium, and the platforms for both candidates are the same. These result provide a concrete demonstration of the-convergence-of-platforms results when candidates office motivation surpasses a certain threshold. We emphasize again that unlike the results of Baye et al [3], Tian [16], and Chang [6], our proof does not require the construction of the aggregator function of the game. Moreover, the same proof works when the strategy set of each candidate is a finite (discrete) subset of the real line instead of the entire interval [0, 1]. Assuming that the location of the median vote is uniformly distributed simplifies our calculations to obtain (8) and (9) but it is not essential for the application of Theorem 4. The same is true for the specific functional forms we used for u R and u B. The only critical assumption is assuming K R = K B = K. When K R K B, we may not be able verify the assumptions of Theorem 4. In fact, Saporiti [15] suggests that when the difference between K R and K B is large enough, pure strategy equilibria will fail to exist. 17

18 REFERENCES REFERENCES References [1] Jean-Pierre Aubin. Mathematical Methods of Game and Economic Theory. Dover, [2] R. Ball. Discontinuity and non-existence of equilibirum in the probabilistic spatial voting model. Social Choice and and Welfare, 16: , [3] Michael Baye, Guoqiang Tian, and Jianxin Zhou. Characterization of the existence of equilibria in games with discontinuous and non-quasiconcave payoffs. Review of Economic Studies, 60: , [4] Philip Bich. Existence of pure nash equilibria in discontinuous and non quasiconcave games. International Journal of Game Theory, 38: , [5] G. Carmona. An existence result for dicontinuous games. Journal of Economic Theory, 144: , [6] Shiow-Yu Chang. Inequalities and nash equilibria. Nonlinear Analysis, 73: , [7] J. Duggan. Equilibrium existence for zero sum games and spatial models of elections. Games and Economic Behavior, 60:52 74, [8] L.P. Hansen and T. J. Sargent. Robust control and model uncertainty. American Economic Review, 91:60 66, [9] I. Hansson and C. Stuart. Voting competitions with interested politicians: Paltforms do not converge to the prefrences of the median voter. Public choice, 44: , [10] Ji-Cheng Hou. Characterization of the existence of pure strategy nash equilibrium. Applied Mathematics Letters, 22: , [11] E. Kalmoun and H. Riahi. Topological kkm theorems and generalized vector equilibira on g-connvex spaces with applications. 129: , Proceedings of the American Mathematical Soceity, 18

19 REFERENCES REFERENCES [12] W. K. Kim and S. Kum. Existence of nash equilibria with c-convexity. Nonlinear Analysis, 63: , [13] K. Nishimura and J. Friedman. Existence of nash equilibrium in n person games without quasi-concavity. International Economic Review, 22: , [14] Philip Reny. On the existence of equilibrium in discontinuous games. Econometrica, 167: , [15] Alejandro Saporiti. Existence and uniquness of nash equilibrium in electoral competition game: The hybrid case. Journal of Public Economic Theory, 10: , [16] Guoqiang Tian. Generalization of the fkkm theorem and the ky fan minimax inequality, with applications to maximal elements, price equilibrium, and complementarrity. Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, 170: , [17] N. Williams. Robust control. New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, [18] Jian Xin Zhou and Goong Chen. Diagonal convexity conditions for problems in convex analysis and quasi-variational inequalities. The Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, 132: , [19] A. Ziad. A counterexample to 0-diagonal quasiconcavity in a minimax inequality. Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications, 22: ,

20 REFERENCES REFERENCES Appendix A. The KKM Theorem Theorem A1. Let m denote the standard simplex in IR m, and let e k be the vector of m corresponding to the vector in IR m with one in the kth component and zeros everywhere else. Consider m subsets F i of the simplex m such that for (i) each F i is closed (i) for any J m and any face of of m of the form con{e i0, e i1,, e ij } is contained in the union F i0 Fi1 FiJ Then, the set m i=1 F i is not empty. For an excellent reference on the connection between KKM lemma, the classic Key Fan inequality, and the Brouwer and Kakutani fixed point theorems, see the appendix of [1] B. Lack of sufficiency when the second order condition fails at a single point The following example illustrates the difficulty in establishing best reply functions for the game PSVM in Section 4. Example B1: Consider the following function f : IR IR Clearly, the condition d2 f dx 2 f(x) = { x 2 when x < 1 x when x 1 < 0 holds everywhere except at the point x = 1, and yet the (only) critical point x = 0 obtained via the first order condition df dx = 0, is not a maximum. C. The functions U R and U B satisfy the assumptions of Theorem 1. The first panel in the Figure C.1 below shows a region in [0, 1] [0, 1] where U R (r, b) α 1. In particular, using (8) and simple constrained maximization techniques, we can easily show that when 1 2 b 1, 0 r 1 2, and r + b 1, we have U R(r, b) α 1. Similarly, when 1 2 r 1, 0 b 1 2, and r + b 1, we also have U R (r, b) α 1. Consider the function c : [0, 1] [0, 1] defined as c(z) = 1 z. For any finite collection {r 1,, r n }, and any λ n, let ϕ(λ) = c(λ 1 r 1 + +λ n r n ), then the continuity of ϕ, the lower semi-continuity of U R in b, and Lemma 1, imply that for any 20

21 REFERENCES REFERENCES k {1,, n}, the set G k = {λ n ϕ(λ) lev α 1 U R (r k, )} is closed in n. Furthermore, the first panel of Figure C1 implies that for any r in the convex hull of {r 1,, r n }, we have which implies that for λ n, min k I(λ) U R(r k, c( r)) α 1, ϕ(λ) k I(λ) lev α 1 U R (r k, ). A similar argument using the second panel in Figure C1 can be used to show that U B satisfies the conditions of Theorem 1 at α 2. b b α α α r 1 2 U R 1 2 U B α r Fig. C1 21

Could Nash equilibria exist if the payoff functions are not quasi-concave?

Could Nash equilibria exist if the payoff functions are not quasi-concave? Could Nash equilibria exist if the payoff functions are not quasi-concave? (Very preliminary version) Bich philippe Abstract In a recent but well known paper (see [11]), Reny has proved the existence of

More information

Minimax Inequalities and Related Theorems for Arbitrary Topological Spaces: A Full Characterization

Minimax Inequalities and Related Theorems for Arbitrary Topological Spaces: A Full Characterization Minimax Inequalities and Related Theorems for Arbitrary Topological Spaces: A Full Characterization Guoqiang Tian Department of Economics Texas A&M University College Station, Texas 77843 Abstract This

More information

Existence of Equilibria in Games with Arbitrary Strategy Spaces and Preferences: A Full Characterization

Existence of Equilibria in Games with Arbitrary Strategy Spaces and Preferences: A Full Characterization Existence of Equilibria in Games with Arbitrary Strategy Spaces and Preferences: A Full Characterization Guoqiang Tian Department of Economics Texas A&M University College Station, Texas 77843, USA and

More information

Power Sharing and Electoral Equilibrium

Power Sharing and Electoral Equilibrium Power Sharing and Electoral Equilibrium Alejandro Saporiti January 14, 2013 Abstract We study a model of consensual democracies, where two political parties compete for policy influence in an electoral

More information

Constructive Proof of the Fan-Glicksberg Fixed Point Theorem for Sequentially Locally Non-constant Multi-functions in a Locally Convex Space

Constructive Proof of the Fan-Glicksberg Fixed Point Theorem for Sequentially Locally Non-constant Multi-functions in a Locally Convex Space Constructive Proof of the Fan-Glicksberg Fixed Point Theorem for Sequentially Locally Non-constant Multi-functions in a Locally Convex Space Yasuhito Tanaka, Member, IAENG, Abstract In this paper we constructively

More information

On the Existence of Price Equilibrium in Economies with Excess Demand Functions

On the Existence of Price Equilibrium in Economies with Excess Demand Functions On the Existence of Price Equilibrium in Economies with Excess Demand Functions Guoqiang Tian Abstract This paper provides a price equilibrium existence theorem in economies where commodities may be indivisible

More information

Existence of Equilibrium in Minimax Inequalities, Saddle Points, Fixed Points, and Games without Convexity Sets

Existence of Equilibrium in Minimax Inequalities, Saddle Points, Fixed Points, and Games without Convexity Sets Existence of Equilibrium in Minimax Inequalities, Saddle Points, Fixed Points, and Games without Convexity Sets Rabia Nessah CNRS-LEM (UMR 8179) IESEG School of Management 3 rue de la Digue F-59000 Lille

More information

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Econ Theory Bull DOI 10.1007/s40505-016-0100-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Wei He 1 Nicholas C. Yannelis 1 Received: 7 February 2016 / Accepted:

More information

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester Mark Fey Department of Political Science University of Rochester

More information

On the existence of Nash equilibrium in discontinuous games

On the existence of Nash equilibrium in discontinuous games Econ Theory (2016) 61:515 540 DOI 10.1007/s00199-015-0921-8 RESEARCH ARTICLE On the existence of Nash equilibrium in discontinuous games Rabia Nessah 1 Guoqiang Tian 2 Received: 12 May 2015 / Accepted:

More information

NEW MAXIMUM THEOREMS WITH STRICT QUASI-CONCAVITY. Won Kyu Kim and Ju Han Yoon. 1. Introduction

NEW MAXIMUM THEOREMS WITH STRICT QUASI-CONCAVITY. Won Kyu Kim and Ju Han Yoon. 1. Introduction Bull. Korean Math. Soc. 38 (2001), No. 3, pp. 565 573 NEW MAXIMUM THEOREMS WITH STRICT QUASI-CONCAVITY Won Kyu Kim and Ju Han Yoon Abstract. In this paper, we first prove the strict quasi-concavity of

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

Essential equilibria in normal-form games

Essential equilibria in normal-form games Journal of Economic Theory 145 (2010) 421 431 www.elsevier.com/locate/jet Note Essential equilibria in normal-form games Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau 1 Department of Economics, Rutgers University, 75 Hamilton

More information

--Manuscript Draft-- without Convexity and Compactness Assumptions. IESEG School of Management Lille, FRANCE. Guoqiang Tian, Ph.D.

--Manuscript Draft-- without Convexity and Compactness Assumptions. IESEG School of Management Lille, FRANCE. Guoqiang Tian, Ph.D. Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications Existence of Solution of Minimax Inequalities, Equilibria in Games and Fixed Points without Convexity and Compactness Assumptions --Manuscript Draft-- Manuscript

More information

Chapter 9. Mixed Extensions. 9.1 Mixed strategies

Chapter 9. Mixed Extensions. 9.1 Mixed strategies Chapter 9 Mixed Extensions We now study a special case of infinite strategic games that are obtained in a canonic way from the finite games, by allowing mixed strategies. Below [0, 1] stands for the real

More information

On the Existence of Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibria

On the Existence of Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibria On the Existence of Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibria Pavlo Prokopovych a,1 and Nicholas C. Yannelis b a Kyiv School of Economics, 1 Ivana Mazepy, Kyiv 01010, Ukraine b Department of Economics, Tippie College

More information

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Political Economics. Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich. Summer term / 37

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Political Economics. Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich. Summer term / 37 1 / 37 Political Economics Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich Summer term 2010 4 / 37 Table of contents 1 Introduction(MG) 2 Preferences and voting (MG) 3 Voter turnout (MG) 4 Electoral competition (SÜ)

More information

On the existence of price equilibrium in economies with excess demand functions

On the existence of price equilibrium in economies with excess demand functions Econ Theory Bull (2016) 4:5 16 DOI 10.1007/s40505-015-0091-7 RESEARCH ARTICLE On the existence of price equilibrium in economies with excess demand functions Guoqiang Tian 1 Received: 15 September 2015

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny* Draft notes October 2011 http://home.uchicago.edu/~preny/papers/bigseqm.pdf Abstract:

More information

The Folk Theorem for Finitely Repeated Games with Mixed Strategies

The Folk Theorem for Finitely Repeated Games with Mixed Strategies The Folk Theorem for Finitely Repeated Games with Mixed Strategies Olivier Gossner February 1994 Revised Version Abstract This paper proves a Folk Theorem for finitely repeated games with mixed strategies.

More information

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models 14.773 Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models Daron Acemoglu MIT February 7 and 12, 2013. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 2 and 3 February

More information

Applied Mathematics Letters

Applied Mathematics Letters Applied Mathematics Letters 25 (2012) 974 979 Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Applied Mathematics Letters journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/aml On dual vector equilibrium problems

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 1 [1] In this problem (see FT Ex. 1.1) you are asked to play with arbitrary 2 2 games just to get used to the idea of equilibrium computation. Specifically, consider the

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 25, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Uniqueness of a Pure Nash Equilibrium for Continuous Games Reading: Rosen J.B., Existence

More information

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Chiaki Hara April 5, 2004 Abstract We give a theorem on the existence of an equilibrium price vector for an excess

More information

Equilibrium Equivalence under Expected Plurality and Probability of Winning Maximization

Equilibrium Equivalence under Expected Plurality and Probability of Winning Maximization Equilibrium Equivalence under Expected Plurality and Probability of Winning Maximization INCOMPLETE: ONE SECTION MISSING John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

On Semicontinuity of Convex-valued Multifunctions and Cesari s Property (Q)

On Semicontinuity of Convex-valued Multifunctions and Cesari s Property (Q) On Semicontinuity of Convex-valued Multifunctions and Cesari s Property (Q) Andreas Löhne May 2, 2005 (last update: November 22, 2005) Abstract We investigate two types of semicontinuity for set-valued

More information

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem Set 2: s Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem 1. (a) Prove that a closed subset of a complete metric space is complete. (b) Prove that a closed subset of a compact metric space is compact. (c) Prove that

More information

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities NUPRI Working Paper 2016-03 Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities Takuya Iimura, Toshimasa Maruta, and Takahiro Watanabe October, 2016 Nihon University Population Research Institute http://www.nihon-u.ac.jp/research/institute/population/nupri/en/publications.html

More information

A LITTLE REAL ANALYSIS AND TOPOLOGY

A LITTLE REAL ANALYSIS AND TOPOLOGY A LITTLE REAL ANALYSIS AND TOPOLOGY 1. NOTATION Before we begin some notational definitions are useful. (1) Z = {, 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, }is the set of integers. (2) Q = { a b : aεz, bεz {0}} is the set

More information

Fixed Point Theorems

Fixed Point Theorems Fixed Point Theorems Definition: Let X be a set and let f : X X be a function that maps X into itself. (Such a function is often called an operator, a transformation, or a transform on X, and the notation

More information

Optimization and Optimal Control in Banach Spaces

Optimization and Optimal Control in Banach Spaces Optimization and Optimal Control in Banach Spaces Bernhard Schmitzer October 19, 2017 1 Convex non-smooth optimization with proximal operators Remark 1.1 (Motivation). Convex optimization: easier to solve,

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

Jensen s inequality for multivariate medians

Jensen s inequality for multivariate medians Jensen s inequality for multivariate medians Milan Merkle University of Belgrade, Serbia emerkle@etf.rs Given a probability measure µ on Borel sigma-field of R d, and a function f : R d R, the main issue

More information

Product differences and prices

Product differences and prices Product differences and prices Claude d Aspremont, Jean Jaskold Gabszewicz and Jacques-François Thisse Abstract Under assumptions following Hotelling s 1929 paper Stability in Competition, the possibility

More information

Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018

Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018 Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Ec 181 KC Border Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018 Topic 7: Quasiconvex Functions I 7.1 Level sets of functions For an extended real-valued

More information

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem MS&E 336 Lecture 8: Supermodular games Ramesh Johari April 30, 2007 In this lecture, we develop the theory of supermodular games; key references are the papers of Topkis [7], Vives [8], and Milgrom and

More information

Fixed Point Theorems 1

Fixed Point Theorems 1 John Nachbar Washington University in St. Louis October 10, 2017 1 Overview Fixed Point Theorems 1 Definition 1. Given a set X and a function f : X X, x X is a fixed point of f iff f(x ) = x. Many existence

More information

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games Joel Sobel April 4, 2016 Abstract This paper extends Milgrom and Robert s treatment of supermodular games in two ways. It points out that

More information

Smooth Calibration, Leaky Forecasts, Finite Recall, and Nash Dynamics

Smooth Calibration, Leaky Forecasts, Finite Recall, and Nash Dynamics Smooth Calibration, Leaky Forecasts, Finite Recall, and Nash Dynamics Sergiu Hart August 2016 Smooth Calibration, Leaky Forecasts, Finite Recall, and Nash Dynamics Sergiu Hart Center for the Study of Rationality

More information

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis 1 Convex sets Both convex sets and functions have general importance in economic theory, not only in optimization. Given two points x; y 2 R n and 2 [0; 1]; the weighted

More information

Brouwer Fixed-Point Theorem

Brouwer Fixed-Point Theorem Brouwer Fixed-Point Theorem Colin Buxton Mentor: Kathy Porter May 17, 2016 1 1 Introduction to Fixed Points Fixed points have many applications. One of their prime applications is in the mathematical field

More information

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting 14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting Daron Acemoglu MIT September 6 and 11, 2017. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2 September 6

More information

The general programming problem is the nonlinear programming problem where a given function is maximized subject to a set of inequality constraints.

The general programming problem is the nonlinear programming problem where a given function is maximized subject to a set of inequality constraints. 1 Optimization Mathematical programming refers to the basic mathematical problem of finding a maximum to a function, f, subject to some constraints. 1 In other words, the objective is to find a point,

More information

Convex Functions and Optimization

Convex Functions and Optimization Chapter 5 Convex Functions and Optimization 5.1 Convex Functions Our next topic is that of convex functions. Again, we will concentrate on the context of a map f : R n R although the situation can be generalized

More information

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2017 Lecture 7 Tuesday July 25, 2017

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2017 Lecture 7 Tuesday July 25, 2017 Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2017 Lecture 7 Tuesday July 25, 2017 Section 2.9. Connected Sets Definition 1 Two sets A, B in a metric space are separated if Ā B = A B = A set in a metric space is connected

More information

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2)

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2) Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2) Haifeng Huang University of California, Merced Best response functions: example In simple games we can examine

More information

Coalitional Equilibria of Strategic Games

Coalitional Equilibria of Strategic Games Coalitional Equilibria of Strategic Games Rida Laraki To cite this version: Rida Laraki. Coalitional Equilibria of Strategic Games. cahier de recherche 2009-42. 2009. HAL Id: hal-00429293

More information

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games journal of economic theory 82, 267276 (1998) article no. ET982418 Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games Atsushi Kajii* Institute of Policy and Planning Sciences, University of Tsukuba, 1-1-1

More information

Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal

Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal Ali Kakhbod Demosthenis Teneketzis November 13, 2017 arxiv:1001.3896v4 [cs.gt] 9 Feb 2012 Abstract Within the context of games on networks S. Goyal

More information

Full characterizations of minimax inequality, fixed point theorem, saddle point theorem, and KKM principle in arbitrary topological spaces

Full characterizations of minimax inequality, fixed point theorem, saddle point theorem, and KKM principle in arbitrary topological spaces J. Fixed Point Theory Appl. 19 (2017) 1679 1693 DOI 10.1007/s11784-016-0314-z Published online September 22, 2016 c Springer International Publishing 2016 Journal of Fixed Point Theory and Applications

More information

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games Daron Acemoglu and Martin Kaae Jensen Abstract We provide general comparative static results for large finite and infinite-dimensional aggregative games.

More information

EC3224 Autumn Lecture #03 Applications of Nash Equilibrium

EC3224 Autumn Lecture #03 Applications of Nash Equilibrium Reading EC3224 Autumn Lecture #03 Applications of Nash Equilibrium Osborne Chapter 3 By the end of this week you should be able to: apply Nash equilibrium to oligopoly games, voting games and other examples.

More information

SOME ELEMENTARY GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CONVEX ANALYSIS. A. Granas M. Lassonde. 1. Introduction

SOME ELEMENTARY GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CONVEX ANALYSIS. A. Granas M. Lassonde. 1. Introduction Topological Methods in Nonlinear Analysis Journal of the Juliusz Schauder Center Volume 5, 1995, 23 37 SOME ELEMENTARY GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CONVEX ANALYSIS A. Granas M. Lassonde Dedicated, with admiration,

More information

Approval Voting: Three Examples

Approval Voting: Three Examples Approval Voting: Three Examples Francesco De Sinopoli, Bhaskar Dutta and Jean-François Laslier August, 2005 Abstract In this paper we discuss three examples of approval voting games. The first one illustrates

More information

15 Real Analysis II Sequences and Limits , Math for Economists Fall 2004 Lecture Notes, 10/21/2004

15 Real Analysis II Sequences and Limits , Math for Economists Fall 2004 Lecture Notes, 10/21/2004 14.102, Math for Economists Fall 2004 Lecture Notes, 10/21/2004 These notes are primarily based on those written by Andrei Bremzen for 14.102 in 2002/3, and by Marek Pycia for the MIT Math Camp in 2003/4.

More information

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago

More information

Mechanism design and allocation algorithms for energy-network markets with piece-wise linear costs and quadratic externalities

Mechanism design and allocation algorithms for energy-network markets with piece-wise linear costs and quadratic externalities 1 / 45 Mechanism design and allocation algorithms for energy-network markets with piece-wise linear costs and quadratic externalities Alejandro Jofré 1 Center for Mathematical Modeling & DIM Universidad

More information

Game Theory. Greg Plaxton Theory in Programming Practice, Spring 2004 Department of Computer Science University of Texas at Austin

Game Theory. Greg Plaxton Theory in Programming Practice, Spring 2004 Department of Computer Science University of Texas at Austin Game Theory Greg Plaxton Theory in Programming Practice, Spring 2004 Department of Computer Science University of Texas at Austin Bimatrix Games We are given two real m n matrices A = (a ij ), B = (b ij

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand KC Border Revised Fall 2011; Winter 2017 Preferences For the purposes of this note, a preference relation

More information

Volume 31, Issue 3. Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal

Volume 31, Issue 3. Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal Volume 31, Issue 3 Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal Ali Kakhbod University of Michigan, Ann Arbor Demosthenis Teneketzis University of Michigan, Ann Arbor Abstract Within the context

More information

Strategic Uncertainty and Equilibrium Selection in Discontinuous Games.

Strategic Uncertainty and Equilibrium Selection in Discontinuous Games. Strategic Uncertainty and Equilibrium Selection in Discontinuous Games. Philippe Bich October 21, 2016 Abstract We introduce the new concept of prudent equilibrium to model strategic uncertainty, and prove

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION

THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION HALUK ERGIN AND TODD SARVER Abstract. Suppose (i) X is a separable Banach space, (ii) C is a convex subset of X that is a Baire space (when endowed

More information

Hannu Salonen Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games. Aboa Centre for Economics

Hannu Salonen Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games. Aboa Centre for Economics Hannu Salonen Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games Aboa Centre for Economics Discussion paper No. 85 Turku 2013 The Aboa Centre for Economics is a joint initiative of the economics departments of

More information

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES DUSTIN HEDMARK Abstract. A study of the conditions under which a topological space is metrizable, concluding with a proof of the Nagata Smirnov

More information

UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND Department of Economics Economics 754 Topics in Political Economy Fall 2005 Allan Drazen. Exercise Set I

UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND Department of Economics Economics 754 Topics in Political Economy Fall 2005 Allan Drazen. Exercise Set I UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND Department of Economics Economics 754 Topics in Political Economy Fall 005 Allan Drazen Exercise Set I The first four exercises are review of what we did in class on 8/31. The next

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.oc] 1 Apr 2013

arxiv: v1 [math.oc] 1 Apr 2013 Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Existence of equilibrium for multiobjective games in abstract convex spaces arxiv:1304.0338v1 [math.oc] 1 Apr 2013 Monica Patriche University of Bucharest

More information

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions By Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago Paper can be found at https://sites.google.com/site/philipjreny/home/research

More information

Game Theory and its Applications to Networks - Part I: Strict Competition

Game Theory and its Applications to Networks - Part I: Strict Competition Game Theory and its Applications to Networks - Part I: Strict Competition Corinne Touati Master ENS Lyon, Fall 200 What is Game Theory and what is it for? Definition (Roger Myerson, Game Theory, Analysis

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Part 1. Static games of complete information Chapter 3. Mixed strategies and existence of equilibrium Ciclo Profissional 2 o Semestre / 2011 Graduação em Ciências Econômicas

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

Online Appendix: Optimal Retrospective Voting

Online Appendix: Optimal Retrospective Voting Online Appendix: Optimal Retrospective Voting Ethan Bueno de Mesquita 1 Amanda Friedenberg 2 The notation and setup will be as in the main text, with the following exceptions: Let x l : Ω R be a random

More information

Existence of Optima. 1

Existence of Optima. 1 John Nachbar Washington University March 1, 2016 Existence of Optima. 1 1 The Basic Existence Theorem for Optima. Let X be a non-empty set and let f : X R. The MAX problem is f(x). max x X Thus, x is a

More information

Mathematics 530. Practice Problems. n + 1 }

Mathematics 530. Practice Problems. n + 1 } Department of Mathematical Sciences University of Delaware Prof. T. Angell October 19, 2015 Mathematics 530 Practice Problems 1. Recall that an indifference relation on a partially ordered set is defined

More information

Electoral Competition with Privately Informed Candidates. (Preliminary)

Electoral Competition with Privately Informed Candidates. (Preliminary) Electoral Competition with Privately Informed Candidates (Preliminary) Dan Bernhardt Department of Economics University of Illinois 1206 S. Sixth Street Champaign, IL 61820 John Duggan Department of Political

More information

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Mehmet Barlo Nuh Aygun Dalkiran February 10, 2014 Abstract We provide necessary and sufficient conditions for epsilon ex post implementation. Our analysis extends Bergemann

More information

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Shiran Rachmilevitch April 22, 2016 Abstract ɛ-equilibrium allows for worse actions to be played with higher probability than better actions. I introduce

More information

Journal of Inequalities in Pure and Applied Mathematics

Journal of Inequalities in Pure and Applied Mathematics Journal of Inequalities in Pure and Applied Mathematics http://jipam.vu.edu.au/ Volume 2, Issue 1, Article 12, 2001 ON KY FAN S MINIMAX INEQUALITIES, MIXED EQUILIBRIUM PROBLEMS AND HEMIVARIATIONAL INEQUALITIES

More information

An asymptotic ratio characterization of input-to-state stability

An asymptotic ratio characterization of input-to-state stability 1 An asymptotic ratio characterization of input-to-state stability Daniel Liberzon and Hyungbo Shim Abstract For continuous-time nonlinear systems with inputs, we introduce the notion of an asymptotic

More information

EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS. Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel. 1. Introduction

EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS. Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel. 1. Introduction Topological Methods in Nonlinear Analysis Journal of the Juliusz Schauder Center Volume 16, 2000, 339 349 EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

Berge s Maximum Theorem

Berge s Maximum Theorem Berge s Maximum Theorem References: Acemoglu, Appendix A.6 Stokey-Lucas-Prescott, Section 3.3 Ok, Sections E.1-E.3 Claude Berge, Topological Spaces (1963), Chapter 6 Berge s Maximum Theorem So far, we

More information

Continuity of equilibria for two-person zero-sum games with noncompact action sets and unbounded payoffs

Continuity of equilibria for two-person zero-sum games with noncompact action sets and unbounded payoffs DOI 10.1007/s10479-017-2677-y FEINBERG: PROBABILITY Continuity of equilibria for two-person zero-sum games with noncompact action sets and unbounded payoffs Eugene A. Feinberg 1 Pavlo O. Kasyanov 2 Michael

More information

Math 118B Solutions. Charles Martin. March 6, d i (x i, y i ) + d i (y i, z i ) = d(x, y) + d(y, z). i=1

Math 118B Solutions. Charles Martin. March 6, d i (x i, y i ) + d i (y i, z i ) = d(x, y) + d(y, z). i=1 Math 8B Solutions Charles Martin March 6, Homework Problems. Let (X i, d i ), i n, be finitely many metric spaces. Construct a metric on the product space X = X X n. Proof. Denote points in X as x = (x,

More information

Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom

Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom Abstract: This paper gives a non-fixed point theoretic proof of equilibrium existence when the excess demand function of an exchange

More information

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3 Analysis Math Notes Study Guide Real Analysis Contents Ordered Fields 2 Ordered sets and fields 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts 2 Metric Spaces 3 Metric Spaces 3 Definitions 4 Separability

More information

Mathematical Economics - PhD in Economics

Mathematical Economics - PhD in Economics - PhD in Part 1: Supermodularity and complementarity in the one-dimensional and Paulo Brito ISEG - Technical University of Lisbon November 24, 2010 1 2 - Supermodular optimization 3 one-dimensional 4 Supermodular

More information

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY H. JEROME KEISLER AND YENENG SUN Abstract. An atomless probability space (Ω, A, P ) is said to have the saturation property for a probability measure µ on

More information

The Existence of Perfect Equilibrium in Discontinuous Games

The Existence of Perfect Equilibrium in Discontinuous Games Games 20, 2, 235-256; doi:0.3390/g2030235 Article OPEN ACCESS games ISSN 2073-4336 www.mdpi.com/journal/games The Existence of Perfect Equilibrium in Discontinuous Games Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau Department

More information

Analysis III Theorems, Propositions & Lemmas... Oh My!

Analysis III Theorems, Propositions & Lemmas... Oh My! Analysis III Theorems, Propositions & Lemmas... Oh My! Rob Gibson October 25, 2010 Proposition 1. If x = (x 1, x 2,...), y = (y 1, y 2,...), then is a distance. ( d(x, y) = x k y k p Proposition 2. In

More information

Metric Spaces and Topology

Metric Spaces and Topology Chapter 2 Metric Spaces and Topology From an engineering perspective, the most important way to construct a topology on a set is to define the topology in terms of a metric on the set. This approach underlies

More information

Game theory lecture 4. September 24, 2012

Game theory lecture 4. September 24, 2012 September 24, 2012 Finding Nash equilibrium Best-response or best-reply functions. We introduced Nash-equilibrium as a profile of actions (an action for each player) such that no player has an incentive

More information

Stability of efficient solutions for semi-infinite vector optimization problems

Stability of efficient solutions for semi-infinite vector optimization problems Stability of efficient solutions for semi-infinite vector optimization problems Z. Y. Peng, J. T. Zhou February 6, 2016 Abstract This paper is devoted to the study of the stability of efficient solutions

More information

Banach-Alaoglu theorems

Banach-Alaoglu theorems Banach-Alaoglu theorems László Erdős Jan 23, 2007 1 Compactness revisited In a topological space a fundamental property is the compactness (Kompaktheit). We recall the definition: Definition 1.1 A subset

More information