Fairness and the proportionality principle

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Fairness and the proportionality principle"

Transcription

1 Fairness and the proportionality principle Alexander W. Cappelen and Bertil Tungodden November 12, 2016 Abstract How should income be distributed in a way that respects both the egalitarian ideal that inequalities due to differences in opportunities should be eliminated and the liberal ideal that people should be free to pursue their own idea of the good life without interference from society? We show that reasonable interpretations of the egalitarian and the liberal ideal characterize what we refer to as the generalized proportionality principle. This principle states that an individual should have the share of total income that he or she would have had if everyone had the same opportunities and these opportunities were given by the average of the pre-tax income functions of all individuals in society. We argue that a redistribution mechanism based on this principle would eliminate unfair inequalities and preserve fair inequalities, and discuss when the generalized proportionality principle is equivalent to the simple proportionality principle. 1 Introduction Inequalities in earned income are a result of differences in both the opportunities people have and the choices they make. A theory of distributive justice needs to address how society should handle such inequalities. The liberal Both authors: Norwegian School of Economics, Bergen, Norway. alexander.cappelen@nhh.no and bertil.tungodden@nhh.no. We have received extremely useful comments and suggestions from two anonymous referees. The project was financed by support from the Research Council of Norway, research grant and administered by The Choice Lab. 1

2 egalitarian theories of distributive justice answer this question by combining the egalitarian ideal that inequalities due to differences in opportunities should be eliminated and the liberal ideal that people should be free to pursue their own idea of the good life without interference from society (see among others Dworkin, 1981; Arneson, 1989; Cohen, 1989; Le Grand, 1991; Roemer, 1993, 1996, 1998; Fleurbaey, 1994, 1995a-d, 2008; Bossert, 1995; Bossert and Fleurbaey, 1996; Iturbe-Ormaetxe, 1997; Sprumont, 1997; Boadway et al., 2002; Cappelen and Tungodden, 2002, 2003, 2006, 2009; Tungodden, 2005; Luttens, 2010; and Fleurbaey and Maniquet, 2011). In line with liberal egalitarian theories of justice, recent papers in behavioral economics have shown that a majority of people seem to accept income inequalities as fair if they reflect differences in choices, but reject income inequalities due to luck (Konow, 1996, 2000, 2001; Frohlich et al., 2004; Cappelen et al., 2007, 2010, 2013, 2014). A key challenge for a liberal egalitarian redistribution mechanism is how to eliminate income inequalities due to differences in opportunities and at the same time preserve income inequalities due to choice. An answer to this challenge, with a history going back to Aristotle, is provided by the proportionality principle. Applied to income distribution, this principle is commonly interpreted as saying that income should be distributed proportionally to individual effort. An appealing feature of the proportionality principle is that it eliminates income inequalities between individuals who choose the same effort level. A less appealing feature of this principle, as we demonstrate in this paper, is that it may violate the liberal ideal that society should be neutral with respect to how individuals choose to live their lives. However, we show that the generalized proportionality principle, closely related to principles suggested by Bossert (1995) and Konow (1996), satisfies both the egalitarian ideal of equalization and the liberal ideal of neutrality. 1 We argue that a liberal egalitarian redistribution mechanism must satisfy two basic requirements, a liberal requirement and an egalitarian requirement. In the formulation of these requirements, we refer to factors within individual control as effort and factors beyond individual control as talent. 2 First, we argue that the egalitarian ideal is captured by the requirement of equalization for equal effort, which states that the share of the total income that a 1 Our work is inspired by Iturbe-Ormaetxe (1997) and Sprumont (1977), who study related redistribution mechanisms. 2 See Fleurbaey and Maniquet (2011) for an excellent survey of alternative interpretations of liberal egalitarianism in the social choice literature. 2

3 person receives should only depend on the person s chosen level of effort and not on the talent profile in society. Second, we argue that the liberal ideal of neutrality is captured by the requirement of no equalization for uniform distribution of talent, which implies that there should be no redistribution between individuals at different effort levels if there is a uniform distribution of talent across effort levels. This requirement captures the intuition that any redistribution between individuals who make different choices must be justified by reference to differences in the distribution of talent among those who make different choices. We show that these two requirements jointly characterize the generalized proportionality principle. This principle states that each individual s fair share of the total income in any given situation is determined by considering a hypothetical situation which is identical to the actual situation with respect to the distribution of effort, but where everyone has the same opportunities and these opportunities are given by the average of the pre-tax income function of all members of society. The generalized proportionality principle assigns a share of the total income to each individual that is equal to this person s share of the total income in the hypothetical situation. In his seminal contribution to the analysis of liberal egalitarian justice, John Roemer often assumes that the distribution of effort is the same at all talent levels and he discusses what would constitute a liberal egalitarian distribution when the effort level of each individual is unobservable (Roemer 1993, 1998). In this paper we consider what would be the liberal egalitarian distribution in a first best setting where both talent and effort levels are observable, and we argue that the generalized egalitarian principle follows from attractive formulations of the liberal and egalitarian ideals even without assuming that effort is uniformly distributed within each talent group. The paper is organized as follows: Section 2 presents the basic framework, while Section 3 introduces the formal liberal and egalitarian requirements. In Section 4, we characterize the generalized proportionality principle, and in Section 5 we provide a formal analysis of how it relates to the simple proportionality principle. Section 6 provides some concluding remarks. In an online appendix, we report some further results on how the conditions used in the paper relate to other liberal and egalitarian conditions. 3

4 2 The basic framework Consider a population N = {1,..., n}, n 2, where each person i is characterized by his talent level, a T i, and effort level, a E i. 3 Let Ω E = {e 1, e 2...} be the set of possible effort levels and Ω T = {t 1, t 2...} be the set of possible talent levels, where Ω E, Ω T R. 4 Each individual can thus be represented by a vector a i = (a T i, a E i ) Ω = Ω E Ω T, where the pre-tax income function, f : Ω R ++, is assumed to be strictly increasing in effort and talent. 5 A society can be characterized by a vector a = (a 1,..., a n ) Ω N, where Ω N = Ω Ω... Ω is the set of possible characteristics profiles of society. Let Ω E (a), Ω T (a) be the effort levels and talent levels present in a, and a E and a T be the vectors of effort levels and talent levels in a. We now define the average population pre-tax income at effort level e j in a as g(e j, a T ) i N f(ej, a T i )/N, which is equal to what would have been the average income in a population with talent profile a T if everyone exercised effort level e j. In the core part of the paper we assume restricted domain richness, i.e., we assume that for any situation a there exists another situation ã established by permuting the effort levels in a such that the talent composition is the same at each effort level in ã. To formalize this domain restriction, let N j (a) be the set of individuals who choose effort level e j Ω E (a), i.e., N j (a) = {i N a E i = e j } and n j (a) be the cardinality of this set. Further, let E(a) represent the distribution of effort in a, i.e. the vector consisting of the fraction of the population exercising each possible effort level. We can now define restricted domain richness as follows: Restricted Domain Richness. The set of possible characteristics profiles of society is given by Ω N = {a Ω N there exists ã Ω N, where a T = ã T, 3 We thus focus on cases where talent and effort are unidimensional, but it is straightforward to extend the main analysis to the multidimensional cases. Further, this formal framework also presupposes that we can clearly distinguish between talent and effort, which may not always be the case in practice where some factors affecting income (for example education) may be shaped by both talent and effort. 4 Our results do not depend on the set of possible effort and talent levels being the set of real numbers. All the results in the paper can be established as long as there is more than one element in Ω E, Ω T. 5 In this framework, all effort levels are available for all talent levels. One might argue that for some interpretations of effort, low talented people have a more restricted set of available effort levels than high talented people. 4

5 E(a) = E(ã), and i N j (ã) f(ã i) n j (ã) = g(e j, ã T ) for all j Ω E (ã)}. This should be a straightforward assumption to make when studying redistribution in large societies, and nothing of importance seems to be lost by restricting the domain in this way. Since the aim of our analysis is to describe what constitutes a fair income distribution, we assume that people s choice of effort is insensitive to the ex post distribution of income. This implies that all allocations of income will be Pareto-optimal (as long as we assume that people have self-interested preferences and a positive marginal utility of income). We pay attention only to information about effort and talent levels when choosing among Paretooptimal allocations, and thus our object of study is a redistribution mechanism, F : Ω N R n, that for any distribution of talent and effort assigns a post-tax income to each person in society. We assume that F satisfies the no-waste condition i N F i(a) = i N f(a i), a Ω N. 3 The two ideals Liberal egalitarianism aims to combine an egalitarian ideal and a liberal ideal. In our framework, the egalitarian ideal implies that people should not be held responsible for their talent, while the liberal ideal implies that society should be neutral with respect to what effort level people choose to exercise. The basic moral intuition underlying the egalitarian ideal is that inequalities due to talent are unfair and should be eliminated. A very weak interpretation of this ideal is the minimal condition demanding that people who make the same choices in a particular situation face the same consequences (Bossert and Fleurbaey, 1996; Fleurbaey, 2008; Fleurbaey and Maniquet, 2011). In other words, if a low talented and a high talented person exercise the same level of effort in a particular situation, then they should end up with the same post-tax income. This condition, however, is silent about which factors should affect how we share total income more generally. For example, consider two situations, a and ā, that only differ in the effort levels of two individuals l and k being permuted. The minimal condition places no restriction on how the distribution of total income changes when we move from one of these situations to the other. It is consistent with giving nothing to l in a and everything to k in ā, even though the effort level exercised by 5

6 l in a is the same as the effort level exercised by k in ā and, importantly, the overall effort profiles are the same in the two situations. Hence, it is consistent with letting the share received by any particular person depend on whether he is a low talented person or a high talented person. This clearly shows that there is a need for a stronger condition to capture the egalitarian ideal. We argue that the appropriate way of capturing the egalitarian ideal is to require that the share of total income that a person receives in any particular situation only should depend on the effort profile in this situation. Clearly, whether it is a talented or less talented that is exercising any particular level of effort will be important in determining total income, but it should not be relevant for how the total income is distributed among individuals. In particular, if the effort profile is the same in two situations, then the share of the total income given to an individual exercising a particular effort level in one of the situations should be equal to the share of the total income given to another individual exercising the same effort level in the other situation. Formally, this requirement can be captured by the following condition. 6 Equalization for Equal Effort (EEE). For any a, ã Ω N and k, l N, if a T = ã T, E(a) = E(ã), and ã E l = a E k, then F l (ã) = F k(a) i N f(ã i) i N. f(a i) It follows straightforwardly that if a redistribution mechanism satisfies EEE, then it also satisfies the weaker demand that people who make the same choices in a particular situation should face the same consequences. The liberal ideal addresses the question of how income should be distributed between individuals who exercise different levels of effort; i.e., what is a fair inequality between individuals who make different choices? In a situation where people only differ with respect to their effort and not with respect to their talent, the liberal ideal has a straightforward interpretation. If everyone has the same talent, then there is no reason for a liberal society to redistribute between individuals since any difference in pre-tax income is only a result of a difference in choices. The liberal ideal then requires that we should preserve the pre-tax income inequality (Bossert and Fleurbaey, 1996; Fleurbaey, 2008; Fleurbaey and Maniquet, 2011). But how should we interpret the liberal ideal in situations where people differ in their talent? We argue that there is an attractive strengthening 6 In an online appendix, we discuss the relationship between the conditions introduced in this section and alternative formulations of the egalitarian and the liberal ideal. 6

7 of the minimal liberal requirement that captures the essence of the liberal ideal more generally: there should be no redistribution between individuals at different effort levels in situations where the average pre-tax income at any chosen effort level is equal to the average population pre-tax income at this effort level. This would be the case if there is a uniform distribution of talent across all chosen effort levels (or if the average pre-tax income at any effort level is equal to what would have been the case if there were a uniform distribution of talent at all effort levels). We can formalize this requirement as follows: No Equalization for Uniform Distribution of Talent (NEUDT). For any a Ω N : if i N j (a) f(a i)/n j (a) = g(e j, a T ) for all e j Ω E (a), then i N j (a) F i(a) = i N j (a) f(a i) for all e j Ω E (a). NEUDT implies that any redistribution between individuals at different effort levels must be justified on the basis of differences in the talent composition at the different effort levels. In particular, if the distribution of talent is the same across all chosen effort levels, then the liberal ideal of neutrality requires no redistribution between effort levels. 4 The generalized proportionality principle We will now show that the egalitarian ideal and the liberal ideal jointly characterize the generalized proportionality principle. F GP k (a) = g(ae k,at ) i N g(ae i,at ) i N f(a i), k N, a Ω n. According to the generalized proportionality principle, the fair share of the total income a person should receive in a given situation should be equal to the share of the total income that the person would have earned in a hypothetical situation where everyone exercised the same effort as in the actual situation, but where the pre-tax income function of each person is given by g(e j, a). In other words, a person s fair share of the total income is determined by considering the counterfactual situation where everyone has the same opportunities, and these opportunities are given by the average of the pre-tax income function of all members of society. The generalized proportionality principle is egalitarian in the sense that the share of the total income that an individual receives only depends on the 7

8 effort profile, E(a), and not on how talent is distributed across effort levels. The generalized proportionality principle is liberal in the sense that it does not view any choice as more or less deserving and only redistributes income in order to eliminate inequalities that result from an unequal distribution of non-responsibility factors. It turns out that the generalized proportionality principle is closely related to EEE and NEUDT. Proposition 1: Given restricted domain richness, a redistribution mechanism F satisfies EEE and NEUDT iff F = F GP. Proof. The if-part is trivial, and thus we only show the only-if-part (1) Consider any a Ω N and k N, where a E k = ek. By restricted domain richness we know that there exists ã Ω N such that a T = ã T, E(a) = E(ã), and i N j (ã) f(ã i)/n j (ã) = g(e j, ã T ), e j Ω E (ã), and m N such that ã E m = a E k. (2) By (1) and EEE, F k (a) i N f(a i) = Fm(ã) i N f(ã i). (3) By (1) and NEUDT, i N k (ã) F i(ã) = i N k (ã) f(ã i). By EEE, F m (ã) = F i (ã), i N k. Hence, F m (ã) = 1 n k (ã) i N k (ã) f(ã i). (4) From (2) and (3), we find that F k (a) = i N k (ã) f(ã i) 1 n k (ã) i N f(ã i) i N f(a i). 1 From the definition of ã in (1), it follows that n k (ã) i N k (ã) f(ã i) = g(e k, ã T ) and i N f(ã i) = i N g(ãe i, ã T ). Thus, the result follows by noticing that g(e k, a T ) = g(e k, ã T ) and i N g(ãe i, ã T )= i N g(ae i, ã T ). Within a more general domain, there are also other redistribution mechanisms consistent with EIEE and NEUDT. In particular, the class of subgroup solidarity mechanisms proposed by Cappelen and Tungodden (2002, 2003) satisfies both these requirements. 5 The simple proportionality principle In applying the idea of proportionality to fairness, the more traditional approach has been to adopt a straightforward version of the proportionality 8

9 principle, where each person receives a share of the total income that is proportional to his or her share of the total effort exercised in society (Konow 1996, 2000, 2001; Cappelen et al., 2007, 2013). F P k (a) = ae k i N ae i i N f(a i), k N, a Ω N. Given the popularity of the basic proportionality principle, it is interesting to study both in which economic environments it is an appealing approach and its shortcomings as a general principle of fairness. It follows straightforwardly that Fk P satisfies the egalitarian idea as formulated in EEE, but it is less likely to satisfy the liberal ideal Consider the following weak version of the liberal requirement (Bossert and Fleurbaey, 1996; Fleurbaey, 2008; Fleurbaey and Maniquet, 2011), which is restricted to situations where everyone has the same talent. No Equalization for Uniform Talent (NEUT): For all a Ω N, if a T j = a T k, j, k N, then F i(a) = f(a i ), i N. The proportionality principle is only consistent with NEUT in an economic environment where pre-tax income is proportional to effort. 7 Proposition 2: The redistribution mechanism F P f(e j,t k ) = f(el,t k ) for all e j, e l Ω E and for all t k Ω T. e j e l satisfies NEUT iff Proof. The if-part. (1) Consider any a Ω N, j N, and t j Ω T, where a T i = a T j = t j, i N. By assumption, f(a E i, t j ) = ae i a E j i N ae i i N a E i a E j The only-if part. a E j f(a E j, t j ), i N. Hence, F P j (a) = f(a E j, t j ) = f(a E j, t j ), and thus NEUT is satisfied. (2) Suppose that there exist e j, e l Ω E and t j Ω T such that f(ej,t j ) e j f(e l,t j ). Consider any a Ω N, where a T e l i = t j, i N and for some r, s N, 7 It follows straightforwardly that NEUDT implies NEUT. 9

10 a E r = e j and a E s = e l. By NEUT, F i (a) = f(a E i, t), i N. Hence, Fr(a) F s(a) = f(ar). However, F r P (a) = ae f(a s) Fs P r f(ar) (a) a E s f(a s), and thus the supposition is violated. The restriction of the economic environment in Proposition 2, however, is not sufficient to make the basic proportionality principle in line with our preferred interpretation of the liberal ideal (NEUDT). This will only be the case if we impose the further restriction that the average pre-tax income at each effort level is proportional to effort. Proposition 3: The redistribution mechanism Fk P satisfies NEUDT iff g(e j,a T ) = g(el,a T ) for all e j, e l Ω E and for all a Ω N. e j e l Proof. The if-part. (1) Consider any a Ω N, where i N j (a) f(a i)/n j (a) = g(e j, a T ), e j Ω E (a). By assumption, g(e i, a T ) = ei g(e j, a T ), e i Ω E (a), and e j by definition, i N f(a i) = i N g(ae i, a T ). Hence, i N j (a) F i P (a) = n j (a)g(e j, a T ) = i N j (a) f(a i), e j Ω E (a), and the result follows. The only-if-part. (4) Suppose that for some a Ω N and e r, e s Ω E (a), g(er,a T ) Consider some ã Ω N, where n r (ã) = n s (ã) and all j Ω E (ã). It now follows that i N r (ã) F i P (ã) i N s (ã) F i P er = (ã) (5) From the supposition, it follows that g(er,a T ) it follows that the result follows. i N r (ã) F i P (ã) i N i N r (ã) f(ã i) s (ã) F i P (ã) i N s (ã) f(ã i) g(es,a T ). e r e s i N j (ã) f(ã i) = g(e j, ã) for n j (ã) e s and g(e s,a T ) er i N r (ã) f(ã i) i N s (ã) f(ã i) = g(er,a T ) g(e s,a T ). e s, and hence from (1). But this violates NEUDT, and It follows directly that the generalized proportionality principle is equivalent to the basic proportionality principle when the average pre-tax income at each effort level is proportional to effort. Proposition 4: Given restricted domain richness, Fk P for all j, l Ω E (a), where e j > 0, g(ej,a) = g(el,a). e j e l GP (a) = Fk (a) iff 10

11 Proof. The proof follows from combining Proposition 1 and Proposition 3 and the fact that Fk P satisfies EEE. The basic proportionality principle is attractive because of its simplicity, and it has the appealing feature of satisfying EEE. However, unless we operate in an economic environment where the pre-tax income function is multiplicative, f(a i ) = h(a T i )a E i, which is often the case in experimental studies of fairness, the principle violates what we consider an attractive interpretation of the liberal ideal of neutrality. 6 Conclusion An important point of departure for the axiomatic approach to liberal egalitarian ethics is the impossibility result established in Bossert (1995) and Bossert and Fleurbaey (1996), which shows a potential conflict between the egalitarian ideal and the liberal ideal. A standard response to this result has been to argue that we have to make a trade-off between these two ideals in liberal egalitarian justice (Fleurbaey, 2008). In this paper, however, we argue that the standard minimal interpretations of the egalitarian ideal and the liberal ideal are too weak and too strong, respectively. The minimal egalitarian requirement is too weak because it does not rule out that people s talent determines how the income is distributed; the minimal liberal requirement is too strong because it restricts redistribution in situations where redistribution could be justified by appealing to differences in talent. By strengthening the egalitarian requirement and weakening the liberal requirement, not only do we avoid the impossibility result, but we also characterize a unique liberal egalitarian position, the generalized proportionality mechanism. While this principle has been suggested previously, it has not been given a convincing characterization and it has received far less attention than for example the egalitarian equivalent mechanism and the conditional egalitarian mechanism proposed by Bossert and Fleurbaey (1996). Even if we have shown that there is a way to combine the egalitarian ideal and the liberal ideal in theory, there might still be a tension between these ideals in the design of redistributive policies. Policies aimed at equalizing opportunities will typically involve redistribution between individuals who pursue different ideas of the good life. To illustrate, consider a tax system that redistributes income from those with high income to those with low 11

12 income. Such a progressive tax system would reduce income inequalities due to differences in income opportunities (including talent), but it would at the same time reduce income inequalities between individuals who have the same income opportunities, but who have chosen to pursue different ideas of the good life (including exercising different levels of effort). This problem is unavoidable in practical policy since information required to implement the generalized proportionality mechanism typically is unavailable to tax authorities. A characterization of the liberal egalitarian ideal is still important, since it can be used as a standard for evaluating redistributive policies, including tax policies. Almås et al. (2011) show how the generalized proportionality principle can be used to measure unfair inequality in a population, both pre-tax and post-tax, and demonstrate that such an approach may give a very different picture of the development in a country than more standard inequality measures. This paper has been concerned with the normative question of what constitutes a just redistribution mechanism. However, it is also interesting to ask the positive question of which principle of justice motivates individuals when they make decisions that have distributive implications. In previous research (Cappelen et al. 2007, 2010, 2013, 2014), we have shown that a large majority of people make a distinction between income inequalities due to choice and income inequalities due to luck. Typically, we have focused on economic environments where the pre-tax income function is multiplicative, which implies that the generalized proportionality principle and the simple proportionality coincide. An interesting question for further behavioral research would be to study more complex environments, where the simple proportionality principle has important shortcomings. More research is also needed to understand which inequalities people find fair when individuals make choices on an unlevel playing field, i.e., in situations where the consequences of an individual s choices partly are determined by circumstances beyond individual control. References [1] Almås, I., A. Cappelen, J. T. Lind, E. Ø. Sørensen, and B. Tungodden (2011) Measuring unfair inequality. Theory and evidence from Norwegian data, Journal of Public Economics, 95 :

13 [2] Arneson, R. (1989) Equality and equal opportunity for welfare, Philosophical Studies, 56: [3] Boadway, R., M. Marchand, P. Pestieau, and M. del Mar Racionero (2002) Optimal redistribution with heterogeneous preferences for leisure, Journal of Public Economic Theory, 4 : [4] Bossert, W. (1995) Redistribution mechanisms based on individual characteristics, Mathematical Social Sciences, 29 : [5] Bossert, W. and M. Fleurbaey (1996) Redistribution and compensation, Social Choice and Welfare, 13 : [6] Cappelen, A., A. Drange Hole, E. Ø. Sørensen, and B. Tungodden (2007) The Pluralism of Fairness Ideals: An Experimental Approach, American Economic Review, 97 : [7] Cappelen, A. T., Eichele, K. Hughdahl, K. Specht, E. Ø. Sørensen, and B. Tungodden (2014) Equity theory and fair inequality: a neuroeconomic study, Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 111 : [8] Cappelen, A., J. Konow, E. Ø. Sørensen, and B. Tungodden (2013) Just luck: An experimental study of risk taking and fairness, American Economic Review, 103 : [9] Cappelen, A., E. Ø. Sørensen, and B. Tungodden (2010) Responsibility for what? Fairness and individual responsibility, European Economic Review, 54 : [10] Cappelen, A. and B. Tungodden (2002) Responsibility and Reward, Finanzarchiv, 59 : [11] Cappelen, A. and B. Tungodden (2003) Reward and responsibility: How should we be affected when others change their effort, Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 2 : [12] Cappelen, A. and B. Tungodden (2006) A liberal egalitarian paradox, Economics and Philosophy, 22 : [13] Cappelen, A. and B. Tungodden (2009) Rewarding effort, Economic Theory, 39 :

14 [14] Cohen, G.A. (1989) On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, Ethics, 99 : [15] Dworkin, R. (1981) What is equality? Part 2: equality of resources, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10 : [16] Fleurbaey, M. (1994) On fair compensation, Theory and Decision, 36 : [17] Fleurbaey, M. (1995a) Equal opportunity or equal social outcome?, Economics and Philosophy, 11 : [18] Fleurbaey, M. (1995b) The requisites of equal opportunity, in Social Choice, Welfare, and Ethics, Barnett W.A., Moulin H., Salles M., and Schofield N. (eds), Cambridge University Press: [19] Fleurbaey, M. (1995c) Three solutions for the compensation problem, Journal of Economic Theory, 65 : [20] Fleurbaey, M. (1995d) Equality and responsibility, European Economic Review, 39: [21] Fleurbaey, M. (2008) Fairness, Responsibility and Welfare, Oxford University Press. [22] Fleurbaey, M. and F. Maniquet (2011) Compensation and responsibility, in Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, Arrow K.J., Sen A., and Suzumura K. (eds) vol. II : [23] Frohlich N.J., Oppenheimer, A. Kurki (2004) Modeling other-regarding preferences and an experimental test, Public Choice, 119 : [24] Iturbe-Ormaetxe, I. (1997) Redistribution and Individual Characteristics, Review of Economic Design, 3 : [25] Konow, J. (1996) A Positive Theory of Economic Fairness, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 31 : [26] Konow, J. (2000) Fair Shares: Accountability and Cognitive Dissonance in Allocation Decisions, American Economic Review, 90 :

15 [27] Konow, J. (2001) Fair and Square: The Four Sides of Distributive Justice, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 46 : [28] Le Grand, J. (1991) Equity and Choice, HarperCollins. [29] Luttens, R.I. (2010) Minimal Rights Based Solidarity, Social Choice and Welfare, 34 : [30] Roemer, J. (1993) A pragmatic theory of responsibility for the egalitarian planner, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 22 : [31] Roemer, J. (1996) Theories of Distributive Justice, Harvard University Press. [32] Roemer, J. (1998) Equality of Opportunity, Harvard University Press. [33] Sprumont, Y. (1997) Balanced egalitarian redistribution of income, Mathematical Social Sciences, 33 : [34] Tungodden, B. (2005) Responsibility and redistribution, Social Choice and Welfare, 24 :

A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM. Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE. Introduction

A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM. Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE. Introduction A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE Abstract. In this paper we deal with a fair division model concerning compensation among individuals endowed

More information

Economic Policy and Equality of Opportunity

Economic Policy and Equality of Opportunity Economic Policy and Equality of Opportunity Sang Yoon (Tim) Lee 1 Ananth Seshdari 2 1 University of Mannheim 2 University of Wisconsin October 25, 2014 Normative Ethics and Welfare Economics Redistributive

More information

No-envy in Queueing Problems

No-envy in Queueing Problems No-envy in Queueing Problems Youngsub Chun School of Economics Seoul National University Seoul 151-742, Korea and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627, USA E-mail: ychun@plaza.snu.ac.kr

More information

Responsibility sensitive egalitarianism and optimal linear income taxation

Responsibility sensitive egalitarianism and optimal linear income taxation Responsibility sensitive egalitarianism and optimal linear income taxation Erik Schokkaert,DirkVandegaer, Frank Vandenbroucke, Roland Iwan uttens December 2003 Abstract We compute optimal linear taxes

More information

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: Preference Aggregation, Judgment Aggregation, Graph Aggregation Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss

More information

Extrapolated Social Preferences

Extrapolated Social Preferences Extrapolated Social Preferences Maya Eden World Bank July 17, 2017 Abstract This paper proposes a simpler interpretation of Harsanyi s impartial observer idea. It postulates an impartiality axiom with

More information

ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES

ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES On procedures for measuring deprivation and living standards of societies in a multi-attribute framework Prasanta K. Pattanaik Department of Economics, University

More information

Compensation and Responsibility

Compensation and Responsibility Compensation and Responsibility Marc Fleurbaey and François Maniquet March 1999; revised August 2005 1 Introduction Many distributive issues involve situations of unequal endowments that call for compensating

More information

Axiomatic bargaining. theory

Axiomatic bargaining. theory Axiomatic bargaining theory Objective: To formulate and analyse reasonable criteria for dividing the gains or losses from a cooperative endeavour among several agents. We begin with a non-empty set of

More information

Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism

Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism 2004-03 Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism BLACKORBY, Charles BOSSERT, Walter DONALDSON, David Département de sciences économiques Université de Montréal Faculté des arts et des sciences C.P. 6128, succursale

More information

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice Susumu Cato Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo, Japan Society for the Promotion of Science Research Fellow First Version: January 10, 2007

More information

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

Can everyone benefit from innovation? Can everyone benefit from innovation? Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi June 16, 2017 Abstract We study a resource allocation problem with variable technologies, and ask if there is an allocation

More information

Optimal Insurance of Search Risk

Optimal Insurance of Search Risk Optimal Insurance of Search Risk Mikhail Golosov Yale University and NBER Pricila Maziero University of Pennsylvania Guido Menzio University of Pennsylvania and NBER November 2011 Introduction Search and

More information

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty*

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* journal of economic theory 75, 194204 (1997) article no. ET962280 On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* Elchanan Ben-Porath Tel-Aviv University, Ramit-Aviv, 69 978 Tel-Aviv, Israel; and Northwestern

More information

EX ANTE VERSUS EX POST EQUALITY OF OPPORTUNITY

EX ANTE VERSUS EX POST EQUALITY OF OPPORTUNITY XXII CONFERENZA NUOVE FRONTIERE DELL INTERVENTO PUBBLICO IN UN MONDO DI INTERDIPENDENZA Pavia, Università, 20-21 settembre 2010 EX ANTE VERSUS EX POST EQUALITY OF OPPORTUNITY MARC FLEURBAEY, VITO PERAGINE

More information

Fairness motivation in bargaining: a matter of principle

Fairness motivation in bargaining: a matter of principle Theory Dec. (2014) 77:125 151 DOI 10.1007/s18-013-9392-1 Fairness motivation in bargaining: a matter of principle Sigbjørn Birkeland Bertil Tungodden Published online: 12 September 2013 Springer Science+Business

More information

Infinite Utilitarianism: More Is Always Better*

Infinite Utilitarianism: More Is Always Better* Infinite Utilitarianism: More Is Always Better* Luc Lauwers Center for Economic Studies, K.U.Leuven Peter Vallentyne Department of Philosophy, University of Missouri-Columbia Economics and Philosophy 20

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

Sense of impartiality. Abstract

Sense of impartiality. Abstract Sense of impartiality Jean Fernand Nguema LAMETA Université Montpellier UFR Sciences Economique Abstract The distribution of indivisible good in a society has social implications on individual behavior.

More information

Equality of Opportunity

Equality of Opportunity Equality of Opportunity and School Financing Structure Juan Rios January 4, 2017 Juan Rios Equality of Opportunity January 4, 2017 1 / 20 Motivation (I) 1 Normative Principles: Compensation Principle:

More information

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Bettina Klaus This Version: April 2010 Previous Versions: November 2007 and December 2008 Abstract We consider one-to-one matching

More information

Characterizing Welfare-egalitarian Mechanisms with Solidarity When Valuations are Private Information

Characterizing Welfare-egalitarian Mechanisms with Solidarity When Valuations are Private Information Characterizing Welfare-egalitarian Mechanisms with Solidarity When Valuations are Private Information Duygu Yengin December 1, 2011 Abstract In the problem of assigning indivisible goods and monetary transfers,

More information

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Bettina Klaus Working Paper 09-072 Copyright 2007, 2008 by Bettina Klaus Working papers are in draft form. This working paper is distributed

More information

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Social Choice Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Summer term 2017 Version: March 15, 2018 CONTENTS Remarks 1 0 Introduction 2 1 The Case of 2 Alternatives 3 1.1 Examples for social choice rules............................

More information

Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion

Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion José Carlos R. Alcantud and María D. García-Sanz Universidad de Salamanca, Spain 17. December

More information

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta,

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Lorenz dominance and non-welfaristic redistribution

Lorenz dominance and non-welfaristic redistribution Lorenz dominance and non-welfaristic redistribution Roland Iwan Luttens and Dir Van de gaer February 2004 Abstract Given the decision to implement a non-welfaristic redistribution scheme, we analyze which

More information

Piercing the Veil of Ignorance

Piercing the Veil of Ignorance Piercing the Veil of Ignorance Shachar Kariv UC Berkeley William R. Zame UCLA September 15, 2008 Abstract Theories of justice in the spirit of Harsanyi and Rawls argue that fair-minded people should aspire

More information

Sharing a Polluted River

Sharing a Polluted River Sharing a Polluted River Debing Ni School of Management University of Electronic Science and Technology of China Chengdu, Sichuan, P.R. China, 610054 Yuntong Wang Department of Economics University of

More information

The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach

The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach Koichi Tadenuma Faculty of Economics, Hitotsubashi University Kunitachi, Tokyo 186-8601, Japan Email: tadenuma@econ.hit-u.ac.jp

More information

Second Welfare Theorem

Second Welfare Theorem Second Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2015 Lecture 18, November 2 Outline 1 Second Welfare Theorem From Last Class We want to state a prove a theorem that says that any Pareto optimal allocation is (part

More information

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1. INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 41, No. 2, May 2000 SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel In this article we consider

More information

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montréal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown, Montréal QC H3C 3J7, Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343

More information

The Review of Economic Studies, Ltd.

The Review of Economic Studies, Ltd. The Review of Economic Studies, Ltd. Oxford University Press http://www.jstor.org/stable/2297086. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.

More information

On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation

On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation Ismail Saglam Ipek University 4 May 2016 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/71090/

More information

Measurement of Inequality and Social Welfare

Measurement of Inequality and Social Welfare January 16, 218 Ranking income distribution and Lorenz curves: Partial and complete orderings (i) Partial orderings: Stochastic and inverse stochastic dominance, Lorenz dominance (ii) Complete orderings:

More information

Nash Bargaining in Ordinal Environments

Nash Bargaining in Ordinal Environments Nash Bargaining in Ordinal Environments By Özgür Kıbrıs April 19, 2012 Abstract We analyze the implications of Nash s (1950) axioms in ordinal bargaining environments; there, the scale invariance axiom

More information

Welfare Egalitarianism under Uncertainty

Welfare Egalitarianism under Uncertainty Welfare Egalitarianism under Uncertainty Sinan Ertemel y October 29, 2014 Abstract This paper studies ranking allocations in economic environments where the endowments are state contingent. Social orderings

More information

Inequality and Envy. Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert. London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg

Inequality and Envy. Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert. London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg Inequality and Envy Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg DARP 88 December 2006 The Toyota Centre Suntory and Toyota International Centres for Economics and Related

More information

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations 14.452 Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations Daron Acemoglu MIT November 20, 2018 Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Economic Growth Lecture 8 November 20, 2018 1 / 46 Growth with Overlapping Generations

More information

Combining Equity and Efficiency. in Health Care. John Hooker. Joint work with H. P. Williams, LSE. Imperial College, November 2010

Combining Equity and Efficiency. in Health Care. John Hooker. Joint work with H. P. Williams, LSE. Imperial College, November 2010 Combining Equity and Efficiency in Health Care John Hooker Carnegie Mellon University Joint work with H. P. Williams, LSE Imperial College, November 2010 1 Just Distribution The problem: How to distribute

More information

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada walter.bossert@videotron.ca

More information

A Note On Comparative Probability

A Note On Comparative Probability A Note On Comparative Probability Nick Haverkamp and Moritz Schulz Penultimate draft. Please quote from the published version (Erkenntnis 2012). Abstract A possible event always seems to be more probable

More information

The Repugnant Conclusion on Realistic Choice Sets

The Repugnant Conclusion on Realistic Choice Sets The Repugnant Conclusion on Realistic Choice Sets by Leslie Shiell May 005 University of Ottawa Department of Economics 00 Wilbrod Street Ottawa, Canada phone (613) 56-5800 x1693 fax (613) 56-5999 email:

More information

The measurement of welfare change

The measurement of welfare change The measurement of welfare change Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal walter.bossert@videotron.ca Bhaskar Dutta Department of Economics, University of Warwick B.Dutta@warwick.ac.uk

More information

Liberal Egalitarianism and the Harm Principle

Liberal Egalitarianism and the Harm Principle MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Liberal Egalitarianism and the Harm Principle Michele Lombardi and Kaname Miyagishima and Roberto Veneziani University of Glasgow, Waseda University, Queen Mary University

More information

1. The Problem. Table 1

1. The Problem. Table 1 1 A Possibility Theorem on Aggregation Over Multiple Interconnected Propositions Christian List 1 forthcoming in Mathematical Social Sciences Abstract. Drawing on the so-called doctrinal paradox, List

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from Topics in Data Analysis Steven N. Durlauf University of Wisconsin Lecture Notes : Decisions and Data In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from The Data:

More information

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Sean Horan, Martin J. Osborne, and M. Remzi Sanver December 24, 2018 Abstract May

More information

Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra

Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra Wonki Jo Cho Biung-Ghi Ju June 27, 2018 Abstract We study the problem of determining memberships to the groups in a Boolean algebra. The Boolean algebra is composed

More information

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2015

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2015 Computational Social Choice: Spring 2015 Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss 1 Plan for Today Last time we introduced the axiomatic method for

More information

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Mantas Radzvilas July 2017 Abstract In 1986 David Gauthier proposed an arbitration scheme

More information

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice Marion Hourdequin Companion Website Material Chapter 4 Companion website by Julia Liao and Marion Hourdequin ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS: FROM THEORY TO PRACTICE

More information

A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency

A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency Richard Bradley Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method London School of Economics and Political Science February 24, 2015

More information

On Income and Utility Generalised Transfer Principles in a. Welfarist-Paretian Separable Framework. Marc DUBOIS Stéphane MUSSARD

On Income and Utility Generalised Transfer Principles in a. Welfarist-Paretian Separable Framework. Marc DUBOIS Stéphane MUSSARD Groupe de Recherche en Économie et Développement International Cahier de recherche / Working Paper 15-09 On Income and Utility Generalised Transfer Principles in a Welfarist-Paretian Separable Framework

More information

Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory

Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory Maximilian Kasy Department of Economics, Harvard University 1 / 53 Takeaways for this part of class 1. A general framework to think about what makes a

More information

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra

More information

WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION

WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION Prerequisites Almost essential Welfare: Basics Welfare: Efficiency WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell July 2017 1 Social Welfare Function Limitations

More information

Introduction to General Equilibrium

Introduction to General Equilibrium Introduction to General Equilibrium Juan Manuel Puerta November 6, 2009 Introduction So far we discussed markets in isolation. We studied the quantities and welfare that results under different assumptions

More information

Household Heterogeneity and Inequality Measurement

Household Heterogeneity and Inequality Measurement Household Heterogeneity and Inequality Measurement Alain Trannoy EHESS, Greqam-Idep, Marseille 4 th Canazei Winter School 1 Three allocation problems To cope with the problems raised by the fact that the

More information

Moral hazard in teams

Moral hazard in teams Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Moral hazard in teams KC Border November 2004 These notes are based on the first part of Moral hazard in teams by Bengt Holmström [1], and fills in the gaps

More information

Expertise and Complexity in the Social and Engineering Sciences: An Extended Sen s Theorem

Expertise and Complexity in the Social and Engineering Sciences: An Extended Sen s Theorem Expertise and Complexity in the Social and Engineering Sciences: An Extended Sen s Theorem Donald G. Saari Institute for Mathematical Behavioral Sciences University of California Irvine, CA 92617-5100

More information

Prospect Theory and the Wisdom of the Inner Crowd

Prospect Theory and the Wisdom of the Inner Crowd Prospect Theory and the Wisdom of the Inner Crowd Stephan Hartmann July 23, 2017 Abstract We give a probabilistic justification of the shape of one of the probability weighting functions used in Prospect

More information

Trade, Inequality and Costly Redistribution

Trade, Inequality and Costly Redistribution Trade, Inequality and Costly Redistribution Pol Antràs Alonso de Gortari Oleg Itskhoki Harvard Harvard Princeton ILO Symposium September 2015 1 / 30 Introduction International trade raises real income

More information

Çağatay Kayı, Eve Ramaekers. An Impossibility in Sequencing Problems RM/08/040. JEL code: D63, C72

Çağatay Kayı, Eve Ramaekers. An Impossibility in Sequencing Problems RM/08/040. JEL code: D63, C72 Çağatay Kayı, Eve Ramaekers An Impossibility in Sequencing Problems RM/08/040 JEL code: D63, C72 Maastricht research school of Economics of TEchnology and ORganizations Universiteit Maastricht Faculty

More information

Volume 35, Issue 4. Group contests and technologies. Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University

Volume 35, Issue 4. Group contests and technologies. Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University Volume 35, Issue 4 Group contests and technologies Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University Abstract We study the role of returns of scale of the technology on the characterization of

More information

Strategy-proof and fair assignment is wasteful

Strategy-proof and fair assignment is wasteful Strategy-proof and fair assignment is wasteful Giorgio Martini June 3, 2016 I prove there exists no assignment mechanism that is strategy-proof, non-wasteful and satisfies equal treatment of equals. When

More information

Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation

Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation 2004-10 Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation BOSSERT, Walter D'AMBROSIO, Conchita Département de sciences économiques Université de Montréal Faculté des arts et des sciences C.P. 6128, succursale

More information

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad Unlinked llocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One ad Chiaki Hara Faculty of Economics and Politics, University of Cambridge Institute of Economic Research, Hitotsubashi University pril 16,

More information

CORE DISCUSSION PAPER 2014/24. Fair allocation of disputed properties

CORE DISCUSSION PAPER 2014/24. Fair allocation of disputed properties 2014/24 Fair allocation of disputed properties Biung-Ghi Ju and Juan Moreno-Ternero DISCUSSION PAPER Center for Operations Research and Econometrics Voie du Roman Pays, 34 B-1348 Louvain-la-Neuve Belgium

More information

Fairness and Redistribution: Response

Fairness and Redistribution: Response Fairness and Redistribution: Response By ALBERTO ALESINA, GEORGE-MARIOS ANGELETOS, AND GUIDO COZZI This paper responds to the comment of Di Tella and Dubra (211). We first clarify that the model of Alesina

More information

Globalization, Inequality and Welfare

Globalization, Inequality and Welfare Globalization, Inequality and Welfare Pol Antràs Harvard University Alonso de Gortari Harvard University Oleg Itskhoki Princeton University Harvard - September 7, 2016 Antràs, de Gortari and Itskhoki Globalization,

More information

Distribution Neutral Fiscal Policy with Distorting Taxes and Transfers

Distribution Neutral Fiscal Policy with Distorting Taxes and Transfers Distribution Neutral Fiscal Policy with Distorting Taxes and Transfers Sugata Marjit Centre for Training and Research in Public Finance and Policy Centre for Studies in Social Sciences, Calcutta, India

More information

Characterizations of Pareto-efficient, fair, and strategy-proof allocation rules in queueing problems

Characterizations of Pareto-efficient, fair, and strategy-proof allocation rules in queueing problems Characterizations of Pareto-efficient, fair, and strategy-proof allocation rules in queueing problems Çağatay Kayı and Eve Ramaekers For updated version: http://troi.cc.rochester.edu/ ckyi/kr2006.pdf This

More information

Redistribution Mechanisms for Assignment of Heterogeneous Objects

Redistribution Mechanisms for Assignment of Heterogeneous Objects Redistribution Mechanisms for Assignment of Heterogeneous Objects Sujit Gujar Dept of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India sujit@csa.iisc.ernet.in Y Narahari Dept

More information

The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice *

The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice * The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice * by Nick Baigent Institute of Public Economics, Graz University nicholas.baigent@kfunigraz.ac.at Fax: +44 316 3809530

More information

Session 4: Money. Jean Imbs. November 2010

Session 4: Money. Jean Imbs. November 2010 Session 4: Jean November 2010 I So far, focused on real economy. Real quantities consumed, produced, invested. No money, no nominal in uences. I Now, introduce nominal dimension in the economy. First and

More information

UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS

UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS Strategy-Proofness versus Efficiency in Exchange Economies: General Domain Properties and Applications Biung-Ghi Ju Paper

More information

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Susumu Cato January 17, 2006 Abstract In actual life, we face the opportunity of many choices, from that opportunity set, we have to choose from different alternatives.

More information

1 Surplus Division. 2 Fair Distribution (Moulin 03) 2.1 Four Principles of Distributive Justice. Output (surplus) to be divided among several agents.

1 Surplus Division. 2 Fair Distribution (Moulin 03) 2.1 Four Principles of Distributive Justice. Output (surplus) to be divided among several agents. 1 Surplus Division 2 Fair Distribution (Moulin 03) Output (surplus) to be divided among several agents. Issues: How to divide? How to produce? How to organize? Plus: adverse selection, moral hazard,...

More information

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions Shurojit Chatterji, Remzi Sanver and Arunava Sen May 2010 Paper No. 07-2010 ANY OPINIONS EXPRESSED ARE THOSE OF THE AUTHOR(S) AND

More information

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory Eric Pacuit Department of Philosophy University of Maryland, College Park pacuit.org epacuit@umd.edu March 4, 2014 Eric Pacuit 1 Competing desiderata

More information

In this article, we show that total act utilitarianism can be derived

In this article, we show that total act utilitarianism can be derived consequentialism to utilitarianism 403 FROM CONSEQUENTIALISM TO UTILITARIANISM* In this article, we show that total act utilitarianism can be derived from a set of axioms that are (or ought to be) acceptable

More information

TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective.

TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective. TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective Author(s) Sakamoto, Norihito Citation Issue 2011-08 Date Type Technical Report Text Version publisher URL http://hdl.handle.net/10086/19289 Right Hitotsubashi University

More information

Public Provision of Scarce Resources when Preferences are Non-Linear

Public Provision of Scarce Resources when Preferences are Non-Linear Public Provision of Scarce Resources when Preferences are Non-Linear Katharina Huesmann February 13, 2017 Abstract This paper considers the problem of assigning an indivisible good of limited availability

More information

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS AN EFFICIENCY CHARACTERIZATION OF PLURALITY SOCIAL CHOICE ON SIMPLE PREFERENCE DOMAINS Biung-Ghi Ju University of Kansas

More information

Fleurbaey-Michel Conjecture on Equitable weak Paretian Social Welfare Order

Fleurbaey-Michel Conjecture on Equitable weak Paretian Social Welfare Order Fleurbaey-Michel Conjecture on Equitable weak Paretian Social Welfare Order Ram Sewak Dubey Department of Economics, Uris Hall, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY 14853, USA Abstract The paper examines the

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Todd Davies Symbolic Systems Program Stanford University joint work with Raja Shah, Renee Trochet, and Katarina Ling Decision

More information

Rules for Aggregating Information

Rules for Aggregating Information Rules for Aggregating Information Christopher P. Chambers and Alan D. Miller May 1, 2010 Abstract We present a model of information aggregation in which agents information is represented through partitions

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World Brown University Department of Economics Working Paper No. 2007-12 Allan M. Feldman Department of Economics, Brown University

More information

A Gini approach to inequality of opportunity: evidence from the PSID

A Gini approach to inequality of opportunity: evidence from the PSID A Gini approach to inequality of opportunity: evidence from the PSID Antonio Abatemarco Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche e Statistiche - Università di Salerno Via Ponte Don Melillo - 84084 - Fisciano

More information

Behavioral predictions and hypotheses for "An experimental test of the deterrence hypothesis"

Behavioral predictions and hypotheses for An experimental test of the deterrence hypothesis Behavioral predictions and hypotheses for "An experimental test of the deterrence hypothesis" Hannah Schildberg-Hörisch a, Christina Strassmair b a Institute for Empirical Research in Economics, Department

More information

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ). University of California, Davis Date: August 24, 2017 Department of Economics Time: 5 hours Microeconomics Reading Time: 20 minutes PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION FOR THE Ph.D. DEGREE Please answer any three

More information

WORKING PAPER N Compensating the dead? Yes we can!

WORKING PAPER N Compensating the dead? Yes we can! WORKING PAPER N 2010-34 Compensating the dead? Yes we can! Marc Fleurbaey Marie-Louise Leroux Grégory Ponthière JEL Codes: D63, D71, I18, J18 Keywords: compensation, longevity, mortality, fairness, redistribution

More information

The Non-Existence of Representative Agents

The Non-Existence of Representative Agents The Non-Existence of Representative Agents Matthew O. Jackson and Leeat Yariv November 2015 Abstract We characterize environments in which there exists a representative agent: an agent who inherits the

More information

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice http://selod.ensae.net/m1 Paris School of Economics (selod@ens.fr) September 27, 2007 Notations Consider an individual (agent) facing a choice set X. Definition (Choice set, "Consumption set") X is a set

More information

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics Public Economics: Chapter 9 1 Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics Objectives of this chapter Public Economics: Chapter 9 2 Read Atkinson & Stiglitz (1980,

More information

Multidimensional Welfare Aggregation * CHRISTIAN LIST. 1. Introduction

Multidimensional Welfare Aggregation * CHRISTIAN LIST. 1. Introduction 1 Multidimensional Welfare Aggregation * CHRISTIAN LIST Nuffield College, Oxford OX1 1NF, U.K.; E-mail christian.list@nuffield.oxford.ac.uk Accepted subject to revision by Public Choice Revised 3 December

More information