The measurement of welfare change

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The measurement of welfare change"

Transcription

1 The measurement of welfare change Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal Bhaskar Dutta Department of Economics, University of Warwick This version: December 21, 2018 Abstract. We propose a class of measures of welfare change that are based on the generalized Gini social welfare functions. We analyze these measures in the context of a second-order dominance property that is akin to generalized Lorenz dominance as introduced by Shorrocks (1983) and Kakwani (1984). Because we consider welfare differences rather than welfare levels, the requisite equivalence result involves affine welfare functions only, as opposed to the entire class of strictly increasing and strictly S-concave welfare indicators. Thus, our measures are associated with those members of the generalized-gini class that are strictly increasing and strictly S-concave. Moving from second-order dominance to first-order dominance does not change this result significantly: for most intents and purposes, the generalized Ginis remain the only strictly increasing and strictly S-concave measures that are equivalent to this first-order dominance condition phrased in terms of welfare change. Our final result provides a characterization of our measures of welfare change in the spirit of Weymark s (1981) original axiomatization of the generalized Gini welfare functions. Journal of Economic Literature Classification No.: D31. Keywords: Income inequality; welfare change; dominance criteria; generalized Ginis. We thank Dirk Van de gaer, Horst Zank and two referees for comments. Financial support from the Fonds de Recherche sur la Société et la Culture of Québec is gratefully acknowledged.

2 1 Introduction Kolm (1969), Atkinson (1970) and Sen (1973) have provided the basic framework within which the modern approach to the measurement of inequality has developed. This approach explicitly endows measures of inequality with a normative interpretation. This is done by deriving inequality indices from social welfare functions defined on income distributions. Each index so constructed inherits the distributional judgments embodied in the social welfare function from which it is obtained. A reduction in inequality results in an increase in social welfare provided mean income remains unchanged. Since the underlying social welfare functions are supposed to be ordinal, the derived measures of inequality are also ordinal. Hence, they can be used only to compare levels of inequality associated with the income distributions of, say, two countries, or of the same country at two points of time. However, it is also of considerable interest to ask questions such as Has country A been more successful than country B in reducing inequality over the last decade? A related but slightly different task is to compare the change in social welfare in country A to that of country B during a given period of time. Since the two countries may have a large difference in the rates of growth and since social welfare depends both on the size and the distribution of the cake, it may, in fact, be more appropriate to focus on comparisons of changes in social welfare. While this is the focus of this paper, we will also discuss briefly how to address the issue of comparing changes in the level of inequality. These are such natural questions that it is surprising that the existing literature has not posed them. We conjecture that this may be the case because the ordinal framework of Kolm, Atkinson and Sen does not accommodate comparisons of welfare changes. A comparison of changes in levels of social welfare requires us to step out of the ordinal framework since the ranking of differences of welfare is not preserved under ordinal transformations of the welfare function. That is why we assume in this paper that the social welfare function has cardinal significance. This allows us to define a measure, V, of the change in social welfare between two income distributions, say x 0 and x 1. Furthermore, it is meaningful to compare levels of V (x 0, x 1 ) and V (y 0, y 1 ). Having defined this measure of welfare change V, we pursue two lines of inquiry. The first of these constitutes our main contribution. The generalized Gini welfare functions as introduced by Mehran (1976) and Weymark (1981) constitute the entire class of linear functions of individual incomes that are increasing along the line of equality, anonymous and weakly inequality averse. Although we restrict attention to a subclass of these functions by imposing strict increasingness and strict S-concavity, we refer to our measures as the generalized Ginis. Strict S-concavity (see Marshall and Olkin, 1979) is equivalent to the conjunction of anonymity and the well-established strict transfer principle that can be traced back to Pigou (1912) and Dalton (1920). The strict Pigou-Dalton transfer principle requires welfare (and hence equality) to go up when there is a transfer of income from a richer person to someone who is poorer without reversing their relative ranks in the distribution. Of course, the comparison of levels of welfare change can vary depending on which member of the class of generalized Ginis is used. Since there are no firm ethical reasons for preferring one generalized Gini function over another, it may not always be possible to arrive at unambiguous comparisons. So, we ask the question whether it is 1

3 possible to define a dominance condition which, if satisfied, guarantees that the comparison of levels of welfare change give the same answer for all of the generalized Gini welfare functions. This question has, of course, been asked in the context of income inequality. Following Kolm (1969) and Atkinson (1970), Dasgupta, Sen and Starrett (1973) proved the most general such result by showing that if two distributions have the same mean income, then the social welfare associated with income distribution x is higher than that of y according to any strictly S-concave welfare function if and only if the Lorenz curve of x lies everywhere above that of y. Thus, there is a precise dominance result for equality levels that corresponds to the class of strictly S-concave welfare functions. Shorrocks (1983) and Kakwani (1984) independently extended this result so as to be able to compare welfare levels of income distributions which do not have the same mean incomes. They scaled up the Lorenz curve of an income distribution by its mean income to obtain the generalized Lorenz curve, and showed that generalized Lorenz dominance of income distribution x over another distribution y also provides a necessary and sufficient condition for unambiguous welfare comparisons. That is, x has higher social welfare than y for all strictly increasing and strictly S-concave welfare functions if and only if its generalized Lorenz curve lies everywhere above that of y. We too use generalized Lorenz curves in our analysis of comparisons of welfare change, but adapt them for our purpose. Consider any income distribution x for a population of size n where individual incomes have been ranked in increasing order, so that x i x i+1 for all i from 1 to n 1. Then, the generalized Lorenz curve of x is obtained by plotting the cumulative incomes of the lowest k income levels against k for all k from 1 to n. Suppose now that there are two pairs of income distributions (x 0, x 1 ) and (y 0, y 1 ) (all of population size n) indicating how income distributions have changed in countries A and B. Suppose also that all individual incomes have been arranged in increasing order. Then, we compare the sums of the cumulative differences between x 0 and x 1, and between y 0 and y 1. Put differently, we focus not on the generalized Lorenz curves themselves, but on the sums of the vertical differences between x 0 and x 1, and between y 0 and y 1. Our principal result is that the welfare change between x 0 and x 1 is at least as large as that between y 0 and y 1 for all generalized Gini differences if and only if the curve corresponding to the cumulative sums of differences between x 0 and x 1 lies everywhere above that of the corresponding curve for the (y 0, y 1 ) distributions. Of course, this dominance is equivalent to second-order dominance of the difference between the x vectors and the y vectors. We then ask whether first-order dominance of the difference between the (ranked) x vectors over the difference between the (ranked) y vectors will imply unambiguous welfare change comparisons for a larger class of welfare functions. Clearly, this class would then contain the generalized Gini welfare functions since firstorder dominance implies second-order dominance. However, we show the surprising result that even when there is first-order dominance in this sense, there are numerous pairs of distributions for which unambiguous welfare comparisons are possible only within the set of linear measures of welfare change. So, once strict increasingness and strict S-concavity are imposed, we are back to the generalized Ginis. Therefore, our result implies that first-order dominance does not buy very much that second-order dominance does not already give us. On the one hand, this demonstrates that unambiguous comparisons of welfare change are 2

4 very hard to make. At the same time, however, this observation can be used as a forceful argument in favor of the generalized Gini welfare functions and their associated measures of welfare change. As a secondary task, we specify some appealing axioms or properties of V and characterize the class of welfare change measures that are based on the generalized Gini welfare functions. Our proof closely follows that of Weymark (1981), the principal difference being that our axioms are imposed on the measure of welfare change rather than on the welfare function. In addition, our axioms are also slightly different allowing for a shorter proof. 2 Measures of welfare change Suppose that there are n 2 individuals in a society. A measure of welfare change is a function V : R 2n + R and we interpret V (x 0, x 1 ) as an indicator of the improvement (or deterioration) associated with moving from last period s income distribution x 0 R n + to the current distribution x 1 R n +. Our objective is to find a class of functions V that can be expressed in terms of a difference in welfare levels. That is, we require V to possess the following property. Welfare difference compatibility. There exists a function W : R n + R such that, for all x 0, x 1 R n +, V (x 0, x 1 ) = W (x 1 ) W (x 0 ). (1) The fundamental objective of our contribution is to examine the possibility of measuring differences in social welfare. Thus, welfare difference compatibility is an indispensable axiom that lies at the center of our approach. It is based on the (normative) assumption that an index of welfare change is well-defined. We assume throughout that V satisfies a plausible monotonicity property. Strict monotonicity. V is strictly increasing in x 1. It follows immediately that if V is strictly monotonic and a function W as in (1) exists, this function W must be strictly increasing. Moreover, using (1) and the strict increasingness of W, it follows that V is strictly decreasing in x 0. Anonymity requires that the individuals in a society be treated impartially, paying no attention to their identities. The strict transfer principle is an essential equity requirement that ensures welfare (and equality) to increase as a consequence of a rank-preserving progressive transfer. As is well-known, the conjunction of anonymity and the strict transfer principle is equivalent to strict S-concavity. To introduce this property formally, we require another definition. An n n matrix D is doubly stochastic if its entries are non-negative and all row sums and column sums are equal to one. We require V to be strictly S-concave in its second argument. Strict S-concavity in the second argument. For all x 0, x 1 R n + and for all doubly stochastic n n matrices D, V (x 0, Dx 1 ) V (x 0, x 1 ) and, if Dx 1 is not a permutation of x 1, this inequality is strict. 3

5 Clearly, if a function W as in (1) exists, it must be strictly S-concave if V is strictly S-concave in its second argument. Moreover, the conjunction of welfare difference compatibility and the strict S-concavity of V in its second argument implies that V is strictly S-convex in its first argument (strict S-convexity is obtained if the inequality in the definition of strict S-concavity is reversed). The set of bottom-first-ordered permutations of the elements of R n + is given by Let B = {x R n + x 1... x n }. A = {α R n ++ α 1 >... > α n }. A welfare function W is a generalized Gini welfare function if there exists a parameter vector α = (α 1,..., α n ) A and a number δ R such that, for all x R n +, W (x) = n α i x i + δ (2) where x B is a bottom-first-ordered permutation of x. Thus, the weights α i are assigned to the positions in an income distribution, where higher incomes receive lower weights in order to ensure that the resulting welfare function respects the strict transfer principle. Because we focus on welfare differences in this paper, the above formulation differs slightly from Weymark s (1981); he does not include an additive constant in his definition of the generalized Ginis. Clearly, this modification does not affect any of the welfare comparisons carried out by means of W. The corresponding generalized Gini measure of welfare change is given by n n V (x 0, x 1 ) = α i x 1 i α i x 0 i (3) for all (x 0, x 1 ) R 2n +. The measure of welfare change associated with the parameter vector α A is denoted by V α. The class of all generalized Gini measures of welfare change is given by V G = {V α α A}. Because we restrict attention to anonymous measures of welfare and welfare change, it involves no loss of generality to assume that x is bottom-first ordered. 3 Dominance properties To simplify notation, we define x i = x 1 i x 0 i and y i = y 1 i y 0 i for all i {1,..., n} for all bottom-first-ordered income distributions x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1 B. The following dominance property is a welfare-change adaptation of the generalized Lorenz criterion; see Shorrocks (1983). 4

6 Second-order dominance. For all x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1 B, (x 0, x 1 ) second-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ) if and only if ( x i y i ) 0 for all k {1,..., n}. Our objective is to derive a condition on any two pairs of distributions (x 0, x 1 ) and (y 0, y 1 ) that will enable us to state that the welfare change between (x 0, x 1 ) is greater or smaller than the welfare change between (y 0, y 1 ) for all measures of welfare change in the class V G. So, we want to rule out cases where there are two parameter vectors α, α A such that V α (x 0, x 1 ) V α (y 0, y 1 ) and V α (x 0, x 1 ) < V α (y 0, y 1 ). The following lemma provides a condition that prevents such reversals. Lemma 1. For all x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1 B, if and only if V (x 0, x 1 ) V (y 0, y 1 ) for all V V G α i ( x i y i ) 0 for all k {1,... n} and for all α A. (4) Proof. Sufficiency of (4) follows from the definition of the elements of V G. To prove necessity, let V α (x 0, x 1 ) V α (y 0, y 1 ) for some α A. Therefore, by definition n α i ( x i y i ) 0. Suppose there exists a k < n such that α i ( x i y i ) < 0. Let c > 1 and define a vector α c A as follows. For all i {1,..., n}, { αi c αi if i k, = 1 α c i if i > k. Clearly, α c A for all c > 1, and there exists c sufficiently large such that n αi c ( x i y i ) < 0, that is, V α c (y 0, y 1 ) > V α c (x 0, x 1 ). This shows that if (4) is not satisfied, then there are two measures of welfare change in V G which differ in their ranking of the pairs (x 0, x 1 ) and (y 0, y 1 ), a contradiction that completes the proof. We prove one more lemma before stating the equivalence result regarding second-order dominance. 5

7 Lemma 2. Let x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1 B and suppose that (x 0, x 1 ) second-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ). Then, for all α A and for all k {1,..., n}, α i ( x i y i ) α k ( x i y i ). Proof. Clearly, the claim is true for k = 1. By way of induction, suppose that it is true for all k < k. Then it follows that Hence, k 1 k 1 α k ( x k y k ) + α i ( x i y i ) α k ( x k y k ) + α k 1 ( x i y i ). α i ( x i y i ) α k ( x i y i ) since α k 1 > α k because α A and k 1 ( x i y i ) 0 because (x 0, x 1 ) second-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ). The following theorem is our main result. Theorem 1. For all x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1 B, V (x 0, x 1 ) V (y 0, y 1 ) for all V V G if and only if (x 0, x 1 ) second-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ). Proof. Suppose first that (x 0, x 1 ) second-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ). Then, by definition, ( x i y i ) 0 for all k {1,..., n}. (5) Take any α A. Then the inequality α 1 ( x 1 y 1 ) 0 follows from setting k = 1 in (5) and the fact that α 1 > 0. Suppose that, for some K {2,..., n}, α i ( x i y i ) 0 for all k {1,..., K 1}. We want to show that K α i ( x i y i ) 0. 6

8 By (5) and Lemma 2, K α i ( x i y i ) α K ( x i y i ) 0. Since α A was chosen arbitrarily, this inequality together with Lemma 1 establishes that V (x 0, x 1 ) V (y 0, y 1 ) for all V V G. Now suppose that V (x 0, x 1 ) V (y 0, y 1 ) for all V V G. We need to show that (x 0, x 1 ) second-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ). In view of Lemma 1, it is sufficient to prove that if (4) is satisfied, then (x 0, x 1 ) second-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ). Pick any α A. Then, α i ( x i y i ) 0 for all k {1,..., n}. Clearly, x 1 y 1 since α 1 > 0. Let K {2,..., n} and assume that ( x i y i ) 0 for all k {1,..., K 1}. Suppose that Multiplying by α K > 0, we obtain K ( x i y i ) < 0. K α K ( x i y i ) < 0. (6) Let ε R ++ and define α ε A as follows. For all i {1,..., n}, { αi ε αk + (K i)ε if i < K, = α i if i K. From (4), we know that But (6) implies lim ε 0 K αi ε ( x i y i ) 0 for all ε R ++. K αi ε ( x i y i ) = α K K ( x i y i ) < 0, a contradiction to (4) that completes the proof of the theorem. 7

9 A comparison with the result obtained by Shorrocks (1983) illustrates the impact of considering welfare differences rather than welfare levels. Because of the linearity inherent in difference comparisons, not all strictly increasing and strictly S-concave welfare functions have to agree in order to obtain an equivalence result but only those among them that are affine that is, those corresponding to the generalized Ginis. Thus, as established in the above theorem, welfare functions other than the generalized Ginis cannot be employed in an equivalence result that involves our second-order dominance condition. This raises the question of whether a more stringent dominance definition can accommodate a more general class of functions. For instance, we may want to impose a first-order dominance property for welfare differences, defined as follows. Again, we assume that, without loss of generality, the income distributions x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1 are in B, and x i and y i are defined as above. First-order dominance. For all x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1 B, (x 0, x 1 ) first-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ) if and only if x i y i 0 for all i {1,..., n}. Because first-order dominance implies second-order dominance, the generalized Gini measures of welfare change are compatible with this dominance property. There may be additional measures that can be accommodated in the first-order case but, as illustrated below, all of them must be based on linear measures as well. Let F be a class of measures of welfare change. If the members of F are to be compatible with the first-order dominance criterion, it must be the case that if (x 0, x 1 ) first-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ), then V (x 0, x 1 ) V (y 0, y 1 ) for all V F or, in terms of the underlying welfare functions W, W (x 1 ) W (x 0 ) W (y 1 ) W (y 0 ). (7) Consider x 1, y 0 B and let x 0 = y 1 = (x 1 + y 0 )/2, that is, the distributions x 0 and y 1 are both equal to the arithmetic mean of x 1 and y 0. Therefore, by definition, x i y i = (x 1 i x 0 i ) (y 1 i y 0 i ) = 0 for all i {1,..., n}. Because x 0 = y 1 = (x 1 + y 0 )/2, (7) requires that W (x 1 ) W (x 0 ) = W (y 1 ) W (y 0 ) W (x 1 ) W (x 0 ) = W (x 0 ) W (y 0 ) 2W (x 0 ) = W (x 1 ) + W (y 0 ) ( 1 W 2 x1 + 1 ) 2 y0 = 1 2 W (x1 ) W (y0 ), a condition that, along with strict increasingness, requires W to be a strictly increasing affine function within the bottom-first-ordered subspace of R n +. This, in turn, means that 8

10 the associated measure of welfare change is linear. Because the only increasing functions with that property other than the generalized Ginis are such that the parameter vectors α do not respect the inequalities that define membership in A, it follows that these additional functions fail to satisfy strict S-concavity. Thus, for numerous pairs of income distributions, even this first-order dominance condition does not allow for measures other than the generalized Ginis if this fundamental equity property is to be retained. We conclude this section with an observation that follows from Theorem 1. Consider the question of making similar unambiguous comparisons of changes in the level of inequality, where the measure of inequality is derived from a social welfare function according to the approach by Kolm, Atkinson and Sen alluded to in the introduction. Take two pairs of income distributions (x 0, x 1 ) and (y 0, y 1 ) each with the same (positive) mean income. Let Z(x 0, x 1 ) = I(x 1 ) I(x 0 ) be a measure of inequality change, analogous to V. Suppose, moreover, that I(x) = 1 x e µ(x), where µ(x) is mean income and x e is the equally-distributed-equivalent income corresponding to the income distribution x and the welfare function W. That is, x e is implicitly defined by W (x e,..., x e ) = W (x). The index I has an intuitive normative interpretation: it measures the percentage shortfall of the equally-distributed-equivalent income from average income, where this shortfall is attributable to the presence of inequality in the income distribution under consideration. Let I G be the class of inequality measures that are derived from the class of generalized Gini welfare functions, and let Z G be the set of measures of inequality change that represent the difference of inequality levels where the inequality index is some member of I G. In view of Theorem 1, the following result is immediate. Theorem 2. For all x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1 B with the same mean income, Z(x 0, x 1 ) Z(y 0, y 1 ) for all Z Z G if and only if (x 0, x 1 ) second-order dominates (y 0, y 1 ). Note that since we restrict the four distributions to have the same mean income, we could also state the above theorem in terms of second-order dominance of the vertical differences in the Lorenz curves. 4 Related literature In a seminal paper on the measurement of tax progressivity, Kakwani (1977) proposes the following measure P of tax progressivity P = 1 t (G G ) t 9

11 where G and G are the Gini coefficients of before and after-tax income distribution and t is the average tax rate. Kakwani s approach differs from ours because he focuses on a specific measure of inequality and, therefore, there is no counterpart to the dominance approach which forms the centerpiece of our contribution. However, there is a commonality since differences in the aggregate (inequality versus social welfare) are compared. Jenkins and Van Kerm (2006) also discuss the measurement of change in inequality as measured by the single-parameter Ginis. They use the difference in the levels of the inequality measures in the two periods as their index of inequality change. Thus, their approach is (implicitly) based on an assumption that parallels welfare difference compatibility. Letting G s denote a single-parameter Gini, the measure of inequality change is given by G s (x 1 ) G s (x 0 ), just as our measure of welfare change is W (x 1 ) W (x 0 ). Thus, our fundamental assumption is mirrored in earlier work. Beyond this commonality, however, our contribution and that of Jenkins and Van Kerm diverge: they treat the requisite class of measures as given and examine the decomposition of inequality change, whereas we allow our measures to be general at the beginning and narrow down the class by imposing a dominance requirement. Growth incidence curves have been used by various authors (such as Ravallion and Chen, 2003, and Son, 2004) to measure the effect of growth on the distribution of incomes. A cumulative growth incidence curve shows the difference between the initial income of those individuals who start out among the p poorest and the income of the p poorest individuals in the terminal distribution. Since an individual may not be occupying the same rank in the initial and terminal distributions of income, this implies that our paper as well as some of the literature on growth incidence curves impose a double anonymity condition (a label suggested by a referee) because the identities of the individuals do not matter in either the initial or terminal distributions. As we do, Ravallion and Chen (2003) and Son (2004) discuss first-order dominance and second-order dominance of one growth incidence curve over another. In that setting, second-order dominance means that the cumulative growth incidence curve of the first distribution is everywhere above that of the second. However, dominance comparisons that involve growth incidence curves do not shed much light on the comparison of welfare differences across different growth paths. The following example illustrates this observation. Let n = 3 and consider the distributions x 0 = (5, 10, 20) and x 1 = (10, 15, 25). The associated cumulative growth incidence curve is given by (1, 2, 3 ). Now consider the distributions y 0 = (2, 5, 8) and y 1 = (4, 8, 10) with the cumulative growth incidence curve 3 7 (1, 5, 7 ). It follows that the growth incidence curve for y second-order dominates that for 7 15 x. If welfare is given by the generalized Gini with parameters (3, 2, 1), we obtain W (x 1 ) W (x 0 ) = 30 and W (y 1 ) W (y 0 ) = 14. Clearly, dominance in terms of growth incidence curves may not translate into welfare difference dominance when the initial distributions of income are not identical. Bourguignon (2011) also proposes a new dominance criteria in the context of growth incidence curves. A crucial difference between his approach and ours is that he considers non-anonymous growth incidence curves by allowing changes in the ranks of individuals to matter. Clearly, keeping track of rank changes can be very important in many 10

12 circumstances Bourguignon himself mentions the measurement of income mobility. For the question we pose, however, it appears to be natural to assume our version of S-concavity (and hence anonymity). This is because we focus on measuring (aggregate) welfare change as opposed to obtaining a measure that aggregates individual income differences. More precisely, our starting point is a pair of income distributions x 0 (the incomes in the previous period) and x 1 (the distribution in the current period). We then ask the following question: what can we conclude regarding the properties of a measure of welfare change V that can be expressed as the difference between the welfare in the current period W (x 1 ) and the welfare in the previous period W (x 0 )? It is natural to assume that any period s welfare function is anonymous surely social welfare cannot depend on who gets what income. Once anonymity is imposed on the welfare function in one period, double anonymity is an inevitable consequence. Capéau and Ooghe (2007) study an extended notion of generalized Lorenz dominance by introducing a non-negative parameter r. For any two distributions x, y B, they define r-extended generalized Lorenz dominance of x over y by the criterion (1 + r) k i (x i y i ) for all k {1,..., n}. They then establish an equivalence result involving a subclass of the generalized Ginis that is parameterized using the same value r as in the dominance criterion. Thus, Capéau and Ooghe (2006) also link (a subclass of) the generalized Ginis to a notion of generalized Lorenz dominance but they do so in terms of levels rather than differences. 5 A characterization We conclude this paper by providing a characterization of the generalized Gini measures of welfare change. There clearly is a strong resemblance to Weymark s (1981) axiomatization but some arguments in his proof can be simplified here because our list of axioms is slightly different from his. In addition to welfare difference compatibility, strict monotonicity and strict S-concavity in the second argument, we use the following two properties that are well-established in the context of welfare functions. They continue to have strong intuitive appeal when formulated for a measure of welfare change. Positive linear homogeneity is a standard requirement for welfare functions that can be expressed analogously as a property of a measure of welfare change. Positive linear homogeneity. For all x 0, x 1 R n + and for all λ R ++, V (λx 0, λx 1 ) = λv (x 0, x 1 ). Our final axiom is an independence condition that is restricted to income distributions in which all incomes are ranked from lowest to highest. Recall that B is the set of bottomfirst-ordered permutations of the elements of R n +. The welfare function analogue of following property appears in Weymark (1981, p. 418). 11

13 Weak independence of income source. For all x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1, z B, V (x 0 + z, x 1 + z) V (y 0 + z, y 1 + z) V (x 0, x 1 ) V (y 0, y 1 ). (8) This axiom implies that W has the corresponding property as defined in Weymark (1981). Using (1), it follows that (8) is equivalent to W (x 1 + z) W (x 0 + z) W (y 1 + z) W (y 0 + z) W (x 1 ) W (x 0 ) W (y 1 ) W (y 0 ) for all x 0, x 1, y 0, y 1, z B. Setting x 0 = y 0, this simplifies to W (x 1 + z) W (y 1 + z) W (x 1 ) W (y 1 ) for all x 1, y 1, z B, which is Weymark s (1981) condition. We can now state the result of this section. Theorem 3. A measure of welfare change V satisfies welfare difference compatibility, strict monotonicity, strict S-concavity in the second argument, positive linear homogeneity and weak independence of income source if and only if V is a generalized Gini measure of welfare change with a corresponding generalized Gini welfare function W. Proof. That the generalized Gini measures of welfare change satisfy the axioms of the theorem statement is straightforward to verify. Conversely, suppose that V is a measure of welfare change satisfying the axioms. By anonymity (which follows from strict S-concavity in the second argument), it is sufficient to show that (2) and (3) are true for bottom-first-ordered permutations of the requisite income distributions. As mentioned in the text, the welfare function W (which exists as a consequence of welfare difference compatibility) inherits the properties of strict increasingness, strict S-concavity and weak independence of income source suitably formulated for welfare functions. We now show that the restriction of W to bottom-first-ordered permutations must be an increasing transformation of a strictly increasing linear function. Because we assume that V satisfies positive linear homogeneity, the argument used in the proof of Weymark s (1981) Theorem 3 can be simplified. To do so, we first prove that the restriction of any level set of W to B is a convex set. Let z, z B be in the same level set of W so that W (z) = W (z ). Using (1) and the positive linear homogeneity of V, it follows that W (z) = W (z ) V (z, z ) = 0 V (λz, λz ) = 0 W (λz) = W (λz ) for all λ R ++. Letting θ (0, 1), it follows that W (z) = W (z ) W ((1 θ)z) = W ((1 θ)z ). (9) Adding θz to both (1 θ)z and (1 θ)z, weak independence of income source implies that W ((1 θ)z) = W ((1 θ)z ) W (θz + (1 θ)z) = W (z) = W (θz + (1 θ)z ) 12

14 and, combined with (9), we obtain W (z) = W (z ) W (z) = W (θz + (1 θ)z ) for all z, z B in the same level set of W and for all θ (0, 1), which implies that the requisite level set is convex. Because W is strictly increasing, it follows that the restriction of W to B is an increasing transformation of a strictly increasing linear function. Thus, there exist β 1,..., β n R ++ and an increasing function φ: R + R such that, for all x B, ( n ) W (x) = φ β i x i. (10) By strict S-concavity and because the elements of B are bottom-first-ordered, it follows that β 1 >... > β n. By anonymity, ( n W (x) = φ β i x i ) for all x R n +. Using (10) and noting that, for any p, q R +, two distributions x and y can be chosen so that n β i x 0 i = p and n β i x 1 i = q, positive linear homogeneity requires that φ(λq) φ(λp) = λ(φ(q) φ(p)) (11) for all p, q R + and for all λ R ++. Setting p > 0, q = 0 and λ = 1/p in (11), it follows that φ(0) φ(1) = (φ(0) φ(p))/p and, solving for φ(p), we obtain φ(p) = (φ(1) φ(0))p + φ(0) = γp + δ where γ = φ(1) φ(0) is positive because φ is increasing and δ = φ(0) is a real number. Therefore, φ is an increasing affine function and, setting α i = γβ i for all i {1,..., n}, it follows that α 1 >... > α n and W (x) = n α i x i + δ for all x R n +. Using welfare difference compatibility, we obtain V (x 0, x 1 ) = n α i x 1 i n α i x 0 i for all (x 0, x 1 ) R 2n +. 13

15 6 Concluding remarks The dominance properties employed in this paper are quite forceful because they apply to income differences and, therefore, lead to criteria that are linear or affine within the set of bottom-first-ordered distributions. However, this is inevitable in view of the observation that the subject matter under examination is the possibility of measuring welfare change. A related question is whether there may be dominance concepts that lead to additively separable welfare functions of the form W (x) = n U(x i) for all x R n + with a strictly increasing and strictly concave function U : R + R. This is an interesting issue but unlikely to be answered in the context of the measurement of welfare change. Our notion of second-order dominance is not suitable because it results in criteria that are linear within the bottom-first-ordered subspace of R n + but not additively separable. Analogously, the traditional property of generalized Lorenz dominance is too weak because it permits any strictly increasing and strictly S-concave welfare function. Defining a dominance property that corresponds to additive separability is a task that is by no means obvious to us but constitutes a useful proposal beyond the scope of the welfare-difference approach analyzed here. In order to establish a dominance criterion that allows for welfare changes to be compared across societies with different population sizes, one possible approach consists of replicating the requisite societies and employing the dominance criterion that corresponds to the larger population. Specifically, if we have pairs of distributions (x 0, x 1 ) R 2n + and (y 0, y 1 ) R 2m + where n m, we can consider an m-fold replication of (x 0, x 1 ) and an n-fold replication of (y 0, y 1 ) and apply the dominance criterion for population size nm to the replicated distributions. Of course, implicit in such a procedure which is also suggested by Shorrocks (1983) is some suitable notion of a principle of population, ensuring that such replications do not distort welfare-change-relevant features of the original distributions. This observation leads us to the single-parameter Ginis, which are characterized by Donaldson and Weymark (1980) by means of the principle of population. A similar variable-population result that employs a recursivity property characterizes the single-sequence Ginis; see Bossert (1990). In analogy to our characterization that parallels Weymark s (1981) axiomatization, these variable-population extensions can be adjusted to our setting so as to apply to measures of welfare change. References Atkinson, A.B. (1970), On the measurement of inequality, Journal of Economic Theory 2, Bossert, W. (1990), An axiomatization of the single-series Ginis, Journal of Economic Theory 50, Bourguignon, F. (2011), Non-anonymous growth incidence curves, income mobility and social welfare dominance, Journal of Economic Inequality 9,

16 Capéau, B. and E. Ooghe (2007), On comparing heterogeneous populations: Is there really a conflict between welfarism and a concern for greater equality in living standards?, Mathematical Social Sciences 53, Dalton, H. (1920), The measurement of the inequality of incomes, Economic Journal 30, Dasgupta, P., A. Sen and D. Starrett (1973), Notes on the measurement of inequality, Journal of Economic Theory 6, Donaldson, D. and J.A. Weymark (1980), A single-parameter generalization of the Gini indices of inequality, Journal of Economic Theory 22, Jenkins, S.P. and P. Van Kerm (2006), Trends in income inequality, pro-poor income growth, and income mobility, Oxford Economic Papers 58, Kakwani, N.C. (1977), Measurement of tax progressivity: An international comparison, Economic Journal 87, Kakwani, N.C. (1984), Welfare ranking of income distributions, in R.L. Basman and G.F. Rhodes, eds., Advances in Econometrics, Vol. 3, JAI Press, Greenwich, Kolm, S.-Ch. (1969), The optimal production of social justice, in J. Margolis and S. Guitton, eds., Public Economics, Macmillan, London, Marshall, A.W. and I. Olkin (1979), Inequalities: Theory of Majorization and Its Applications, Academic Press, New York. Mehran, F. (1976), Linear measures of income inequality, Econometrica 44, Pigou, A.C. (1912), Wealth and Welfare, Macmillan, London. Ravallion, M. and S. Chen (2003), Measuring pro-poor growth, Economics Letters 78, Shorrocks, A.F. (1983), Ranking income distributions, Economica 50, Sen, A. (1973), On Economic Inequality, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Son, H.H. (2004), A note on pro-poor growth, Economics Letters 82, Weymark, J.A. (1981), Generalized Gini inequality indices, Mathematical Social Sciences 1,

Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation

Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation 2004-10 Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation BOSSERT, Walter D'AMBROSIO, Conchita Département de sciences économiques Université de Montréal Faculté des arts et des sciences C.P. 6128, succursale

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Stochastic Dominance

Stochastic Dominance GREQAM Centre de la Vieille Charité 2 rue de la Charité 13236 Marseille cedex 2, France Stochastic Dominance by Russell Davidson email: Russell.Davidson@mcgill.ca Department of Economics McGill University

More information

PRESENTATION ON THE TOPIC ON INEQUALITY COMPARISONS PRESENTED BY MAG.SYED ZAFAR SAEED

PRESENTATION ON THE TOPIC ON INEQUALITY COMPARISONS PRESENTED BY MAG.SYED ZAFAR SAEED PRESENTATION ON THE TOPIC ON INEQUALITY COMPARISONS PRESENTED BY MAG.SYED ZAFAR SAEED Throughout this paper, I shall talk in terms of income distributions among families. There are two points of contention.

More information

by John A. Weymark Working Paper No. 03-W14R July 2003 Revised January 2004 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS VANDERBILT UNIVERSITY NASHVILLE, TN 37235

by John A. Weymark Working Paper No. 03-W14R July 2003 Revised January 2004 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS VANDERBILT UNIVERSITY NASHVILLE, TN 37235 THE NORMATIVE APPROACH TO THE MEASUREMENT OF MULTIDIMENSIONAL INEQUALITY by John A. Weymark Working Paper No. 03-W14R July 2003 Revised January 2004 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS VANDERBILT UNIVERSITY NASHVILLE,

More information

Measurement of Inequality and Social Welfare

Measurement of Inequality and Social Welfare January 16, 218 Ranking income distribution and Lorenz curves: Partial and complete orderings (i) Partial orderings: Stochastic and inverse stochastic dominance, Lorenz dominance (ii) Complete orderings:

More information

Rolf Aaberge and Magne Mogstad

Rolf Aaberge and Magne Mogstad Discussion Papers No. 623, June 2010 Statistics Norway, Research Department Rolf Aaberge and Magne Mogstad Robust Inequality Comparisons Abstract: This paper is concerned with the problem of ranking Lorenz

More information

GROWTH AND INCOME MOBILITY: AN AXIOMATIC ANALYSIS

GROWTH AND INCOME MOBILITY: AN AXIOMATIC ANALYSIS XXIII CONFERENZA CRISI ECONOMICA, WELFARE E CRESCITA Pavia, Aule Storiche dell Università, 19-20 settembre 2011 GROWTH AND INCOME MOBILITY: AN AXIOMATIC ANALYSIS FLAVIANA PALMISANO società italiana di

More information

Measuring rank mobility with variable population size

Measuring rank mobility with variable population size Measuring rank mobility with variable population size Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal, Canada walter.bossert@videotron.ca Burak Can Department of Economics, Maastricht

More information

A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition

A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition Working Paper Series A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition Walter Bossert Burak Can Conchita D Ambrosio ECINEQ WP 2016-424 ECINEQ 2016-424 December 2016 www.ecineq.org

More information

Measuring Economic Insecurity

Measuring Economic Insecurity Measuring Economic Insecurity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal walterbossert@umontrealca Conchita D Ambrosio Università di Milano-Bicocca, DIW Berlin and Econpubblica,

More information

CIRPÉE Centre interuniversitaire sur le risque, les politiques économiques et l emploi

CIRPÉE Centre interuniversitaire sur le risque, les politiques économiques et l emploi CIRPÉE Centre interuniversitaire sur le risque, les politiques économiques et l emploi Cahier de recherche/working Paper 06-34 Poverty, Inequality and Stochastic Dominance, Theory and Practice: Illustration

More information

An axiomatization of the mixed utilitarian-maximin social welfare orderings

An axiomatization of the mixed utilitarian-maximin social welfare orderings An axiomatization of the mixed utilitarian-maximin social welfare orderings Walter Bossert and Kohei Kamaga November 16, 2018 Abstract We axiomatize the class of mixed utilitarian-maximin social welfare

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

Household Heterogeneity and Inequality Measurement

Household Heterogeneity and Inequality Measurement Household Heterogeneity and Inequality Measurement Alain Trannoy EHESS, Greqam-Idep, Marseille 4 th Canazei Winter School 1 Three allocation problems To cope with the problems raised by the fact that the

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Poverty measures and poverty orderings

Poverty measures and poverty orderings Statistics & Operations Research Transactions SORT 31 2) July-December 27, 169-18 ISSN: 1696-2281 www.idescat.net/sort Statistics & Operations Research c Institut d Estadística de Transactions Catalunya

More information

MEASURING THE SOCIO-ECONOMIC BIPOLARIZATION PHENOMENON

MEASURING THE SOCIO-ECONOMIC BIPOLARIZATION PHENOMENON 2 MEASURING THE SOCIO-ECONOMIC BIPOLARIZATION PHENOMENON Abstract Ştefan ŞTEFĂNESCU * The present paper emphasizes the differences between the Gini concentration coefficient [3] and a new bipolarization

More information

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montréal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown, Montréal QC H3C 3J7, Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343

More information

Single-plateaued choice

Single-plateaued choice Single-plateaued choice Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7, Canada walter.bossert@umontreal.ca and Hans Peters

More information

Discussion Papers. Satya R. Chakravarty, Conchita D Ambrosio and Pietro Muliere. Target Shortfall Orderings and Indices

Discussion Papers. Satya R. Chakravarty, Conchita D Ambrosio and Pietro Muliere. Target Shortfall Orderings and Indices Discussion Papers Satya R. Chakravarty, Conchita D Ambrosio and Pietro Muliere Target Shortfall Orderings and Indices Berlin, March 2003 Opinions expressed in this paper are those of the author and do

More information

DECOMPOSITION OF NORMALIZATION AXIOM IN THE MEASUREMENT OF POVERTY: A COMMENT. Nanak Kakwani. Nanak Kakwani is a Senior Fellow at WIDER.

DECOMPOSITION OF NORMALIZATION AXIOM IN THE MEASUREMENT OF POVERTY: A COMMENT. Nanak Kakwani. Nanak Kakwani is a Senior Fellow at WIDER. DECOMPOSITION OF NORMALIZATION AXIOM IN THE MEASUREMENT OF POVERTY: A COMMENT Nanak Kakwani Nanak Kakwani is a Senior Fellow at WIDER. - 2 - DECOMPOSITION OF NORMALIZATION AXIOM IN THE MEASUREMENT OF POVERTY:

More information

Multidimensional inequality comparisons

Multidimensional inequality comparisons Multidimensional inequality comparisons Jean-Yves Duclos, David E. Sahn and Stephen D. Younger February 5, 29 Abstract Keywords:. JEL Classification:. Institut d Anàlisi Econòmica (CSIC), Barcelona, Spain,

More information

The Measurement of Inequality, Concentration, and Diversification.

The Measurement of Inequality, Concentration, and Diversification. San Jose State University From the SelectedWorks of Fred E. Foldvary 2001 The Measurement of Inequality, Concentration, and Diversification. Fred E Foldvary, Santa Clara University Available at: https://works.bepress.com/fred_foldvary/29/

More information

Inequality and Envy. Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert. London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg

Inequality and Envy. Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert. London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg Inequality and Envy Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg DARP 88 December 2006 The Toyota Centre Suntory and Toyota International Centres for Economics and Related

More information

Inequality, poverty and redistribution

Inequality, poverty and redistribution Inequality, poverty and redistribution EC426 http://darp.lse.ac.uk/ec426 17 February 2014 Issues Key questions about distributional tools Inequality measures what can they tell us about recent within-country

More information

! 2005 "# $% & !! "#! ,%-)./*(0/ #1 %! 2*- 3434%*1$ * )#%'(*- % *

! 2005 # $% & !! #! ,%-)./*(0/ #1 %!  2*- 3434%*1$ * )#%'(*- % * ! 2005 www.ecineq.org "# $% & '(#!! "#! "# $%&'()*+ ++,%-)./*(0/ #1 %! * )#%'(*- % * 2*- 3434%*1$ 1 Introduction Henri Theil s book on information theory (Theil 1967) provided a landmark in the development

More information

The greatest unhappiness of the least number

The greatest unhappiness of the least number The greatest unhappiness of the least number Walter Bossert Centre Interuniversitaire de Recherche en Economie Quantitative (CIREQ) P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada e-mail: walter.bossert@videotron.ca

More information

Extrapolated Social Preferences

Extrapolated Social Preferences Extrapolated Social Preferences Maya Eden World Bank July 17, 2017 Abstract This paper proposes a simpler interpretation of Harsanyi s impartial observer idea. It postulates an impartiality axiom with

More information

ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES

ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES On procedures for measuring deprivation and living standards of societies in a multi-attribute framework Prasanta K. Pattanaik Department of Economics, University

More information

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada walter.bossert@videotron.ca

More information

Ethically Robust Comparisons of Bidimensional Distributions with an Ordinal Attribute

Ethically Robust Comparisons of Bidimensional Distributions with an Ordinal Attribute Ethically Robust Comparisons of Bidimensional Distributions with an Ordinal Attribute Nicolas Gravel Patrick Moyes November 9, 2011 Abstract We provide foundations for robust normative evaluation of distributions

More information

An Atkinson Gini family of social evaluation functions. Abstract

An Atkinson Gini family of social evaluation functions. Abstract An Atkinson Gini family of social evaluation functions Abdelkrim Araar CIRPEE and PEP, Universite Laval, Canada Jean Yves Duclos CIRPEE and Departement d'economique, Universite Laval, Canada Abstract We

More information

Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons

Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons Preliminary version - Please do not distribute Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons Kristof Bosmans a Luc Lauwers b Erwin Ooghe b a Department of Economics, Maastricht University, Tongersestraat

More information

Unit-Consistent Decomposable Inequality Measures: Some Extensions

Unit-Consistent Decomposable Inequality Measures: Some Extensions WORKING PAPER SERIES NOVEMBER 2005 WORKING PAPER No. 05-02 Unit-Consistent Decomposable Inequality Measures: Some Extensions by Buhong Zheng DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF COLORADO AT DENVER AND

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

Robust inequality comparisons

Robust inequality comparisons J Econ Inequal (211) 9:353 371 DOI 1.17/s1888-1-9163-y Robust inequality comparisons Rolf Aaberge Magne Mogstad Received: 1 February 21 / Accepted: 25 November 21 / Published online: 31 December 21 The

More information

Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism

Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism 2004-03 Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism BLACKORBY, Charles BOSSERT, Walter DONALDSON, David Département de sciences économiques Université de Montréal Faculté des arts et des sciences C.P. 6128, succursale

More information

Ranking distributions of an ordinal attribute

Ranking distributions of an ordinal attribute Ranking distributions of an ordinal attribute Nicolas Gravel, Brice Magdalou and Patrick Moyes Keywords: ordinal, qualitative, health, inequality, Hammond transfers, increments, dominance JEL codes: C81,

More information

The Impossibility of a Just Pigouvian

The Impossibility of a Just Pigouvian Working Paper Series The Impossibility of a Just Pigouvian Casilda Lasso de la Vega Christian Seidl ECINEQ WP 2007 69 ECINEQ 2007-69 May 2007 www.ecineq.org The Impossibility of a Just Pigouvian Casilda

More information

Evaluating Dimensional and Distributional Contributions to Multidimensional Poverty

Evaluating Dimensional and Distributional Contributions to Multidimensional Poverty Evaluating Dimensional and Distributional Contributions to Multidimensional Poverty Social Choice and Welfare Conference 2014, Boston College Sabina Alkire James E. Foster OPHI, Oxford George Washington

More information

Multi-profile intertemporal social choice: a survey

Multi-profile intertemporal social choice: a survey Multi-profile intertemporal social choice: a survey Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343

More information

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty*

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* journal of economic theory 75, 194204 (1997) article no. ET962280 On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* Elchanan Ben-Porath Tel-Aviv University, Ramit-Aviv, 69 978 Tel-Aviv, Israel; and Northwestern

More information

Comparing Societies with Different Numbers of Individuals on the Basis of Their Average Advantage

Comparing Societies with Different Numbers of Individuals on the Basis of Their Average Advantage Comparing Societies with Different Numbers of Individuals on the Basis of Their Average Advantage Nicolas Gravel, Thierry Marchant, and Arunava Sen 1 Introduction At an abstract level, one can view the

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

Inequality Measures and the Median:

Inequality Measures and the Median: Inequality Measures and the Median: Why inequality increased more than we thought by Frank A. Cowell STICERD London School of Economics Houghton Street London, W2CA 2AE, UK f.cowell@lse.ac.uk and Emmanuel

More information

Transfers Principles in a Generalized Utilitarian Framework

Transfers Principles in a Generalized Utilitarian Framework Transfers Principles in a Generalized Utilitarian Framework Mickaël Beaud Lameta Université Montpellier I Stéphane Mussard Lameta Université Montpellier I Marc Dubois Lameta Université Montpellier I Abstract

More information

On Income and Utility Generalised Transfer Principles in a. Welfarist-Paretian Separable Framework. Marc DUBOIS Stéphane MUSSARD

On Income and Utility Generalised Transfer Principles in a. Welfarist-Paretian Separable Framework. Marc DUBOIS Stéphane MUSSARD Groupe de Recherche en Économie et Développement International Cahier de recherche / Working Paper 15-09 On Income and Utility Generalised Transfer Principles in a Welfarist-Paretian Separable Framework

More information

Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems

Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems Lars Ehlers Bettina Klaus This Version: March 2004 Abstract We study a simple model of assigning indivisible objects (e.g., houses, jobs, offices, etc.)

More information

Ranking income distributions: a rank-dependent and needs-based approach

Ranking income distributions: a rank-dependent and needs-based approach Ranking income distributions: a rank-dependent and needs-based approach Ida Petrillo July 25, 217 Abstract This paper provides a normative framework to assess social welfare within a rankdependent and

More information

Conciliating absolute and relative poverty: Income poverty measurement with two poverty lines.

Conciliating absolute and relative poverty: Income poverty measurement with two poverty lines. Conciliating absolute and relative poverty: Income poverty measurement with two poverty lines. Benoit Decerf May 16, 2018 Abstract I study income poverty indices in a framework considering two poverty

More information

Pro poor growth : a partial ordering approach

Pro poor growth : a partial ordering approach MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Pro poor growth : a partial ordering approach Sandip Sarkar Indian Statistical Institute Kolkata 9. May 2014 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/55851/ MPRA Paper

More information

Winter School, Canazei. Frank A. Cowell. January 2010

Winter School, Canazei. Frank A. Cowell. January 2010 Winter School, Canazei Frank A. STICERD, London School of Economics January 2010 Meaning and motivation entropy uncertainty and entropy and inequality Entropy: "dynamic" aspects Motivation What do we mean

More information

On the decomposition of the Gini index: An exact approach

On the decomposition of the Gini index: An exact approach On the decomposition of the Gini index: An exact approach Abdelkrim Araar 13th January 2004 Abstract The decomposition of inequality indices across household groups is useful to judge the importance of

More information

Social Welfare Functions for Sustainable Development

Social Welfare Functions for Sustainable Development Social Welfare Functions for Sustainable Development Thai Ha-Huy, Cuong Le Van September 9, 2015 Abstract Keywords: criterion. anonymity; sustainable development, welfare function, Rawls JEL Classification:

More information

Market Demand Elasticity and Income Inequality

Market Demand Elasticity and Income Inequality Market Demand Elasticity and Income Inequality The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Published Version Accessed

More information

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus. Testing Revealed Preference Theory, I: Methodology The revealed preference theory developed last time applied to a single agent. This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices

More information

A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition

A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal, Canada walter.bossert@videotron.ca Burak Can Department

More information

Discussion Paper Series

Discussion Paper Series INSTITUTO TECNOLÓGICO AUTÓNOMO DE MÉXICO CENTRO DE INVESTIGACIÓN ECONÓMICA Discussion Paper Series Lower bounds and recursive methods for the problem of adjudicating conflicting claims Diego Domínguez

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

Adjusting the HDI for Inequality: An Overview of Different Approaches, Data Issues, and Interpretations

Adjusting the HDI for Inequality: An Overview of Different Approaches, Data Issues, and Interpretations Adjusting the HDI for Inequality: An Overview of Different Approaches, Data Issues, and Interpretations Milorad Kovacevic Statistical Unit, HDRO HDRO Brown bag Seminar, September 28, 2009 1/33 OBJECTIVES:

More information

Working Paper No. 2010/74 Poverty and Time Walter Bossert, 1 Satya R. Chakravarty, 2 and Conchita d Ambrosio 3

Working Paper No. 2010/74 Poverty and Time Walter Bossert, 1 Satya R. Chakravarty, 2 and Conchita d Ambrosio 3 Working Paper No. 2010/74 Poverty and Time Walter Bossert, 1 Satya R. Chakravarty, 2 and Conchita d Ambrosio 3 June 2010 Abstract We examine the measurement of individual poverty in an intertemporal context.

More information

Unit-consistency and polarization of income distributions

Unit-consistency and polarization of income distributions Working Paper Series Unit-consistency and polarization of income distributions M a Casilda Lasso de la Vega Ana Urrutia Henar Díez ECINEQ WP 2008 100 ECINEQ 2008-100 November 2008 www.ecineq.org Unit-consistency

More information

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences in Expected Utility Alejandro Francetich Department of Decision Sciences and IGIER Bocconi University, Italy March 7, 204 Abstract Many choice-theoretic

More information

On Comparing Heterogenous Populations: is there really a Conflict between the Pareto Criterion and Inequality Aversion?

On Comparing Heterogenous Populations: is there really a Conflict between the Pareto Criterion and Inequality Aversion? On Comparing Heterogenous Populations: is there really a Conflict between the Pareto Criterion and Inequality Aversion? by Bart CAPEAU Erwin OOGHE Public Economics Center for Economic Studies Discussions

More information

Ranking by Rating. Yves Sprumont. February 22, 2016

Ranking by Rating. Yves Sprumont. February 22, 2016 Ranking by Rating Yves Sprumont February 22, 2016 Abstract Each item in a given collection is characterized by a set of possible performances. A (ranking) method is a function that assigns an ordering

More information

THE EXTENDED ATKINSON FAMILY: THE CLASS OF MULTIPLICATIVELY DECOMPOSABLE INEQUALITY MEASURES, AND SOME NEW GRAPHICAL PROCEDURES FOR ANALYSTS

THE EXTENDED ATKINSON FAMILY: THE CLASS OF MULTIPLICATIVELY DECOMPOSABLE INEQUALITY MEASURES, AND SOME NEW GRAPHICAL PROCEDURES FOR ANALYSTS THE EXTENDED ATKINSON FAMILY: THE CLASS OF MULTIPLICATIVELY DECOMPOSABLE INEQUALITY MEASURES, AND SOME NEW GRAPHICAL PROCEDURES FOR ANALYSTS LASSO DE LA VEGA, Mª Casilda 1 and URRUTIA, Ana 2 1 (for correspondence

More information

Dynamic Fairness: Mobility, Inequality, and the Distribution of Prospects

Dynamic Fairness: Mobility, Inequality, and the Distribution of Prospects Dynamic Fairness: Mobility, Inequality, and the Distribution of Prospects Baochun Peng 1 The Hong Kong Polytechnic University Haidong Yuan The Chinese University of Hong Kong Abstract This paper clarifies

More information

Dynamic Fairness: Mobility, Inequality, and the Distribution of Prospects

Dynamic Fairness: Mobility, Inequality, and the Distribution of Prospects Dynamic Fairness: Mobility, Inequality, and the Distribution of Prospects Baochun Peng 1 The Hong Kong Polytechnic University Haidong Yuan The Chinese University of Hong Kong Abstract This paper clarifies

More information

Poverty, Inequality and Growth: Empirical Issues

Poverty, Inequality and Growth: Empirical Issues Poverty, Inequality and Growth: Empirical Issues Start with a SWF V (x 1,x 2,...,x N ). Axiomatic approaches are commen, and axioms often include 1. V is non-decreasing 2. V is symmetric (anonymous) 3.

More information

Distribution Neutral Fiscal Policy with Distorting Taxes and Transfers

Distribution Neutral Fiscal Policy with Distorting Taxes and Transfers Distribution Neutral Fiscal Policy with Distorting Taxes and Transfers Sugata Marjit Centre for Training and Research in Public Finance and Policy Centre for Studies in Social Sciences, Calcutta, India

More information

The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach

The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach Koichi Tadenuma Faculty of Economics, Hitotsubashi University Kunitachi, Tokyo 186-8601, Japan Email: tadenuma@econ.hit-u.ac.jp

More information

The Non-Existence of Representative Agents

The Non-Existence of Representative Agents The Non-Existence of Representative Agents Matthew O. Jackson and Leeat Yariv November 2015 Abstract We characterize environments in which there exists a representative agent: an agent who inherits the

More information

Measuring Health Inequality and Health Opportunity

Measuring Health Inequality and Health Opportunity Measuring Health Inequality and Health Opportunity Buhong Zheng Department of Economics University of Colorado at Denver and HSC Denver, CO, USA buhong.zheng@cudenver.edu August 2006 Abstract: The paper

More information

Chapter 6: Economic Inequality

Chapter 6: Economic Inequality Chapter 6: Econoic Inequality We are interested in inequality ainly for two reasons: First, there are philosophical and ethical grounds for aversion to inequality per se. Second, even if we are not interested

More information

The decomposability of simple orthogonal arrays on 3 symbols having t + 1 rows and strength t

The decomposability of simple orthogonal arrays on 3 symbols having t + 1 rows and strength t The decomposability of simple orthogonal arrays on 3 symbols having t + 1 rows and strength t Wiebke S. Diestelkamp Department of Mathematics University of Dayton Dayton, OH 45469-2316 USA wiebke@udayton.edu

More information

Index-Number Tests and the Common-Scaling Social Cost-of-Living Index 1

Index-Number Tests and the Common-Scaling Social Cost-of-Living Index 1 Index-Number Tests and the Common-Scaling Social Cost-of-Living Index 1 David Donaldson and Krishna Pendakur February 2010 Abstract For a change in prices, the common-scaling social cost-of-living index

More information

WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION

WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION Prerequisites Almost essential Welfare: Basics Welfare: Efficiency WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell July 2017 1 Social Welfare Function Limitations

More information

Infinite Utilitarianism: More Is Always Better*

Infinite Utilitarianism: More Is Always Better* Infinite Utilitarianism: More Is Always Better* Luc Lauwers Center for Economic Studies, K.U.Leuven Peter Vallentyne Department of Philosophy, University of Missouri-Columbia Economics and Philosophy 20

More information

Sharing a Polluted River

Sharing a Polluted River Sharing a Polluted River Debing Ni School of Management University of Electronic Science and Technology of China Chengdu, Sichuan, P.R. China, 610054 Yuntong Wang Department of Economics University of

More information

A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM. Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE. Introduction

A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM. Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE. Introduction A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE Abstract. In this paper we deal with a fair division model concerning compensation among individuals endowed

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

Utilitarian resource allocation

Utilitarian resource allocation Utilitarian resource allocation Albin Erlanson and Karol Szwagrzak March 19, 2014 Extended Abstract Keywords: Claims; Indivisible objects; Consistency; Resource-monotonicity JEL classification: D70, D63,

More information

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Social Choice Theory Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Social choice theory MWG, Chapter 21. JR, Chapter 6.2-6.5. Additional

More information

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72 Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056 JEL code: D71, D72 Maastricht research school of Economics of TEchnology and ORganizations Universiteit Maastricht

More information

Cahier CONSISTENT RELATIONS. Walter BOSSERT

Cahier CONSISTENT RELATIONS. Walter BOSSERT Cahier 03-2006 CONSISTENT RELATIONS Walter BOSSERT Le Centre interuniversitaire de recherche en économie quantitative (CIREQ) regroupe des chercheurs dans les domaines de l'économétrie, la théorie de la

More information

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Sean Horan, Martin J. Osborne, and M. Remzi Sanver December 24, 2018 Abstract May

More information

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from Topics in Data Analysis Steven N. Durlauf University of Wisconsin Lecture Notes : Decisions and Data In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from The Data:

More information

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1 Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1 David Pérez-Castrillo 2 Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona David Wettstein 3 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev April 2005 1 We gratefully

More information

::ON MULTIDIMENSIONAL INEQUALITY WITH VARIABLE HOUSEHOLD WEIGHT

::ON MULTIDIMENSIONAL INEQUALITY WITH VARIABLE HOUSEHOLD WEIGHT ::ON MULTIDIMENSIONAL INEQUALITY WITH VARIABLE HOUSEHOLD WEIGHT ERNESTO SAVAGLIO 52 RIUNIONE SIE TEMA: PIL, benessere e felicità, Povertà e distribuzione del reddito PRELIMINARY DRAFT Abstract. The present

More information

Using Markov Chains To Model Human Migration in a Network Equilibrium Framework

Using Markov Chains To Model Human Migration in a Network Equilibrium Framework Using Markov Chains To Model Human Migration in a Network Equilibrium Framework Jie Pan Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Saint Joseph s University Philadelphia, PA 19131 Anna Nagurney School

More information

Deep Linear Networks with Arbitrary Loss: All Local Minima Are Global

Deep Linear Networks with Arbitrary Loss: All Local Minima Are Global homas Laurent * 1 James H. von Brecht * 2 Abstract We consider deep linear networks with arbitrary convex differentiable loss. We provide a short and elementary proof of the fact that all local minima

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 0/06 CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY by Indraneel Dasgupta July 00 DP 0/06 ISSN 1360-438 UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM

More information

CIRPÉE Centre interuniversitaire sur le risque, les politiques économiques et l emploi

CIRPÉE Centre interuniversitaire sur le risque, les politiques économiques et l emploi CIRPÉE Centre interuniversitaire sur le risque, les politiques économiques et l emploi Cahier de recherche/working Paper 03-41 Bi-Polarization Comparisons Jean-Yves Duclos Damien Échevin Octobre/October

More information

The Role of Inequality in Poverty Measurement

The Role of Inequality in Poverty Measurement The Role of Inequality in Poverty Measurement Sabina Alkire Director, OPHI, Oxford James E. Foster Carr Professor, George Washington Research Associate, OPHI, Oxford WIDER Development Conference Helsinki,

More information

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS Gopakumar Achuthankutty 1 and Souvik Roy 1 1 Economic Research Unit, Indian Statistical Institute, Kolkata Abstract In line with the works

More information

The New Palgrave: Separability

The New Palgrave: Separability The New Palgrave: Separability Charles Blackorby Daniel Primont R. Robert Russell 1. Introduction July 29, 2006 Separability, as discussed here, refers to certain restrictions on functional representations

More information

A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem

A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem Sofia Moroni and Jeroen Swinkels April, 23 Abstract We provide a class of counter-examples to existence in a simple moral hazard problem

More information

On Measuring Growth and Inequality. Components of Changes in Poverty. with Application to Thailand

On Measuring Growth and Inequality. Components of Changes in Poverty. with Application to Thailand On Measuring Growth and Inequality Components of Changes in Poverty with Application to Thailand decomp 5/10/97 ON MEASURING GROWTH AND INEQUALITY COMPONENTS OF POVERTY WITH APPLICATION TO THAILAND by

More information

ECON 361 Assignment 1 Solutions

ECON 361 Assignment 1 Solutions ECON 361 Assignment 1 Solutions Instructor: David Rosé Queen s University, Department of Economics Due: February 9th, 2017 1. [22] Poverty Measures: (a) [3] Consider a distribution of income over a sample

More information